United States v. Nichols , 784 F.3d 666 ( 2015 )


Menu:
  •                                                                                       FILED
    United States Court of Appeals
    PUBLISH                                   Tenth Circuit
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS                             April 15, 2015
    Elisabeth A. Shumaker
    FOR THE TENTH CIRCUIT                               Clerk of Court
    _________________________________
    UNITED STATES OF AMERICA,
    Plaintiff - Appellee,
    v.                                                             No. 14-3041
    LESTER RAY NICHOLS,
    Defendant - Appellant.
    _________________________________
    ORDER
    _________________________________
    Before BRISCOE, Chief Judge, KELLY, LUCERO, HARTZ, TYMKOVICH,
    GORSUCH, HOLMES, MATHESON, BACHARACH, PHILLIPS, MCHUGH, and
    MORITZ, Circuit Judges.
    _________________________________
    This matter is before the court on the appellant’s Petition for Rehearing En Banc.
    We also have a response from the government. Upon consideration of the implicit request
    for panel rehearing contained in the petition, the request is denied by a majority of the
    original panel members.
    The en banc petition was also transmitted to all of the judges of the court who are
    in regular active service. Upon review, a poll was called, and a majority of the active
    judges voted to deny the en banc suggestion. Consequently, that request is likewise
    denied. Judges Lucero, Gorsuch, Matheson and Moritz would grant the en banc petition.
    Judges Lucero and Gorsuch have written separately in dissent from the denial of
    the petition.
    Entered for the Court
    ELISABETH A. SHUMAKER, Clerk
    2
    14-3041, United States v. Nichols (Lucero, J., dissenting from the denial of rehearing
    en banc)
    I dissent from the denial of rehearing en banc because a recent Eighth Circuit
    decision creates a circuit split regarding the applicability of SORNA’s notice provisions
    to offenders who leave the country. Compare United States v. Lunsford, 
    725 F.3d 859
    ,
    860 (8th Cir. 2013), with United States v. Murphy, 
    664 F.3d 798
    , 799 (10th Cir. 2011). I
    continue to hold the view that Murphy was incorrectly decided for the reasons stated in
    my dissent from that case. See id. at 804-08 (Lucero, J., dissenting). Correcting this
    circuit split is a matter of exceptional importance given the express purpose of Congress
    in enacting SORNA to remedy “a wide disparity among State registration requirements
    and notification obligations for sex offenders.” H.R. Rep. No. 109-218(I), at 23 (2005).
    The facts of Lunsford and this case illustrate why our current jurisprudence runs
    directly against the stated intent of Congress. In both cases, the appellants moved
    directly from the Kansas City metropolitan area to the Philippines. Lunsford had lived in
    the Missouri side of the metropolis and was not required to update his Missouri
    registration to reflect his move out of the country. Lunsford, 725 F.3d at 860. But
    Nichols, who had lived just across the river in Kansas, was brought back to the United
    States and sentenced to prison for failing to update his Kansas registration. United States
    v. Nichols, 
    775 F.3d 1225
    , 1227 (10th Cir. 2014). We have simply replaced a “wide
    disparity among State registration requirements” with a wide disparity among Circuit
    registration requirements. In doing so, we thwart the intent of Congress and needlessly
    complicate an already complicated law.
    Additionally, I agree with Judge Gorsuch that the Constitution demands something
    more than an “intelligible principle” when Congress delegates its power to define crimes
    to the executive branch agency charged with prosecuting those crimes. Moreover, I agree
    that it is questionable whether SORNA even includes an “intelligible principle” to guide
    the Attorney General’s discretion to apply SORNA’s provisions to pre-Act offenders. I
    would address this issue in en banc rehearing as well.
    2
    No. 14-3041, United States v. Nichols
    GORSUCH, Circuit Judge, dissenting from the denial of rehearing en banc.
    A circuit split lingers here. First to approach the question, this circuit
    interpreted 
    42 U.S.C. § 16913
     as requiring sex offenders to notify authorities if
    they plan to leave the country. United States v. Murphy, 
    664 F.3d 798
    , 801-02
    (10th Cir. 2011). In a later opinion the Eighth Circuit gave thoughtful
    consideration to this interpretation of the statute but came to the opposite view.
    United States v. Lunsford, 
    725 F.3d 859
    , 861-82 (8th Cir. 2013); see also Murphy,
    664 F.3d at 805 (Lucero, J., dissenting). In denying rehearing today to reconsider
    this court’s position in light of Lunsford’s learning, we leave those who seek a
    resolution of the circuit split to travel other avenues. Murphy and Lunsford
    articulate both sides of the split admirably and there’s no need for further
    amplification here, only resolution somewhere.
    Beyond this matter of statutory interpretation, though, lies a constitutional
    question that deserves more notice. If the separation of powers means anything, it
    must mean that the prosecutor isn’t allowed to define the crimes he gets to
    enforce. Yet, that’s precisely the arrangement the Sex Offender Registration and
    Notification Act purports to allow in this case and a great many more like it. In
    § 16913(d), Congress left it to the Attorney General to decide whether and on
    what terms sex offenders convicted before the date of SORNA’s enactment should
    be required to register their location or face another criminal conviction. So
    unusual is this delegation of legislative authority that to find an analogue you
    might have to look back to the time Congress asked the President to devise a code
    of “fair competition” for the poultry business — a delegation of legislative
    authority the Supreme Court unanimously rejected and Justice Cardozo called
    “unconfined and vagrant,” a “delegation running riot.” A.L.A. Schechter Poultry
    Corp. v. United States, 
    295 U.S. 495
    , 551, 553 (1935) (Cardozo, J., concurring).
    Even then you could be excused for thinking the delegation before us a good deal
    less cooped or caged than that one. After all, it doesn’t just grant some alphabet
    soup agency the power to write rules about the chicken trade. It invests in the
    nation’s chief prosecutor the authority to devise a criminal code governing a half-
    million people.
    When it comes to sex offenders convicted after SORNA’s enactment, the
    statute is exquisitely detailed. It divides those persons into three tiers based on
    the seriousness of their offense. 
    42 U.S.C. § 16911
    . It specifies which sex
    offenses place offenders in which tiers. 
    Id.
     It requires tier I offenders to register
    their location for 15 years; tier II offenders to do so for 25 years; and tier III
    offenders to carry on registering for life. 
    Id.
     § 16915. It explains what conditions
    merit reducing the registration period. Id. § 16915(b)(1). On and on it goes for
    22 pages.
    But none of this automatically applies to Mr. Lester Nichols and others
    convicted of sex offenses before the Act’s passage. Instead, when it comes to
    past offenders, the Act says just this:
    2
    The Attorney General shall have the authority to specify the applicability of
    the requirements of this subchapter to sex offenders convicted before the
    enactment of this chapter . . . and to prescribe rules for registration of any
    such sex offender. 
    42 U.S.C. § 16913
    (d).
    Yes, that’s it.
    As the government acknowledges, this language leaves the Attorney
    General free to do nothing: the law “does not require the Attorney General to act
    within a certain time frame or by a date certain; it does not require him to act at
    all.” Brief for the United States at 23-24, Reynolds v. United States, 
    132 S. Ct. 975
     (2012) (No. 10-6549). Alternatively, “[u]nder his delegated authority in
    Subsection (d), the Attorney General could” require all past offenders to register
    or “require some but not all to register.” Id. at 24-25. Or, alternatively still, he
    could require those forced to register to “comply with some but not all of the
    registration requirements” applicable to future offenders in order to adapt the law
    as he thinks best for past offenders. Id. After all, the statute grants the Attorney
    General authority to specify the applicability not of the Act as a whole, one way
    or another, but to specify the applicability of each of the various “requirements”
    contained within the Act — and Congress well knew the difference. Compare 
    42 U.S.C. § 16912
    (b) (explaining that the Attorney General shall “interpret and
    implement this subchapter”), with 
    id.
     § 16913(d) (providing the Attorney General
    authority “to specify the applicability of the requirements of this subchapter”).
    Even then, the Attorney General remains free to “change his mind at any given
    3
    time or over the course of different administrations.” Brief for the United States,
    supra, at 23-24. Given all this, it’s perhaps unsurprising how many circuits and
    commentators have observed that the degree of discretion invested in the Attorney
    General here is vast.1 It is so vast, in fact, that some (including the government
    itself) once suggested a narrower interpretation of § 16913(d) would make more
    sense of the statute. See id.; Reynolds, 
    132 S. Ct. at 986
     (Scalia, J., dissenting).
    A majority of the Supreme Court, however, carefully considered and
    rejected any alternative reading and made plain that, as a matter of statutory
    interpretation, SORNA’s retroactive application hinges on the Attorney General.
    The Court explained that Congress chose this course as its solution for the many
    “problems” associated with trying “to apply [SORNA’s] registration requirements
    to pre-Act offenders” who were at the time subject to a “patchwork of pre-
    existing state systems.” Reynolds, 
    132 S. Ct. at 981
    . The power delegated to the
    1
    See, e.g., United States v. Rickett, 535 F. App’x 668, 673 (10th Cir. 2013)
    (“As written, § 16913(d) gives the Attorney General discretion to decide whether
    and how SORNA should be applied retroactively.”); United States v. DeJarnette,
    
    741 F.3d 971
    , 981 (9th Cir. 2013) (“[W]e see no reason to assume that the
    Attorney General was mandated to apply all of SORNA’s registration
    requirements to all pre-Act offenders.”); United States v. Johnson, 
    632 F.3d 912
    ,
    923 (5th Cir. 2011) (“This language is not ambiguous. Following the plain
    meaning rule, this phrase delegates to the Attorney General the decision of
    whether and how the SORNA registration requirements apply to offenders with
    pre-enactment convictions.”); United States v. Madera, 
    528 F.3d 852
    , 858 (11th
    Cir. 2008) (“Subsection (d) . . . granted the Attorney General unfettered discretion
    to determine both how and whether SORNA was to be retroactively applied.”);
    see also Steven G. Calabresi & Gary Lawson, The Rule of Law as a Law of Law,
    
    90 Notre Dame L. Rev. 483
    , 485 (2014); Reem Sadik, Comment, Passing the
    Torch but Sailing too Close to the Wind, 6 Legis. & Pol’y Brief 295, 298 (2014).
    4
    Attorney General, the Court said, is sort of like a directive telling the
    Commissioner of Major League Baseball that he has “the authority to specify the
    applicability” of a stringent minor league drug testing policy to major league
    players: “we should think that the minor league policy would not apply unless
    and until the Commissioner so specified” whether and how it should be applied to
    meet the needs of a similar but different league. 
    Id.
     As written, the statute
    demonstrates Congress thought that past offenders could “warrant[] different
    federal registration treatment” than future offenders. 
    Id.
     Even among pre-Act
    offenders, the statute contemplates the possibility of “different federal registration
    treatment of different categories of pre-Act offenders.” 
    Id.
     In short, Congress
    thought it a “desirable solution” to ask “the Department of Justice . . . to examine
    these pre-Act offender problems” and specify “new registration requirements” for
    them. 
    Id.
    The Court acknowledged that a statute investing so much authority in the
    Attorney General inevitably raises with it separation of powers questions. But,
    the Court said, it would leave those questions for another day. 
    Id.
     Justices Scalia
    and Ginsburg went further, expressing concern that the law “sail[s] close to the
    wind.” 
    Id. at 986
     (Scalia, J., dissenting). The day to decide the constitutional
    question the Court left open is now upon us. And, as it turns out, the statute
    doesn’t just sail close to the wind. It sails right into it.
    5
    *
    Article I § 1 provides that “[a]ll legislative powers herein granted shall be
    vested in a Congress of the United States.” U.S. Const. art. I, § 1. Many times
    over and in cases stretching back to the founding the Supreme Court has held that
    this language limits the ability of Congress to delegate its legislative power to the
    Executive. See Whitman v. Am. Trucking Ass’ns, 
    531 U.S. 457
     (2001). There’s
    ample evidence, too, that the framers of the Constitution thought the
    compartmentalization of legislative power not just a tool of good government or
    necessary to protect the authority of Congress from encroachment by the
    Executive but essential to the preservation of the people’s liberty. As Madison
    put it, “[n]o political truth is . . . stamped with the authority of more enlightened
    patrons of liberty” than the separation of powers because “[t]he accumulation of
    all powers, legislative, executive, and judiciary in the same hands . . . may justly
    be pronounced the very definition of tyranny.” The Federalist No. 47, at 298
    (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961). By separating the lawmaking and
    law enforcement functions, the framers sought to thwart the ability of an
    individual or group to exercise arbitrary or absolute power. And by restricting
    lawmaking to one branch and forcing any legislation to endure bicameralism and
    presentment, the framers sought to make the task of lawmaking more arduous
    still. These structural impediments to lawmaking were no bugs in the system but
    the point of the design: a deliberate and jealous effort to preserve room for
    6
    individual liberty. See, e.g., Dep’t of Transp. v. Ass’n of Am. Railroads, 
    135 S. Ct. 1225
    , 1237 (2015) (Alito, J., concurring) (“The principle that Congress cannot
    delegate away its vested power exists to protect liberty.”).
    Without a doubt, the framers’ concerns about the delegation of legislative
    power had a great deal to do with the criminal law. The framers worried that
    placing the power to legislate, prosecute, and jail in the hands of the Executive
    would invite the sort of tyranny they experienced at the hands of a whimsical
    king. Their endorsement of the separation of powers was predicated on the view
    that “[t]he inefficiency associated with [it] serves a valuable” liberty-preserving
    “function, and, in the context of criminal law, no other mechanism provides a
    substitute.” Rachel E. Barkow, Separation of Powers and the Criminal Law, 
    58 Stan. L. Rev. 989
    , 1011-17, 1031 (2006).
    So it is that “to abandon openly the nondelegation doctrine [would be] to
    abandon openly a substantial portion of the foundation of American representative
    government.” Gary Lawson, Delegation and Original Meaning, 
    88 Va. L. Rev. 327
    , 332 (2002). Neither is it so much that bureaucrats might do a “bad job as
    our effective legislators” as that “they are neither elected nor reelected, and are
    controlled only spasmodically by officials who are.” John Hart Ely, Democracy
    and Distrust 131 (1980). 2
    2
    For other excellent works along these and related lines, see Philip
    Hamburger, Is Administrative Law Unlawful? 377 (2014); Bogdan Iancu,
    Legislative Delegation: The Erosion of Normative Limits in Modern
    7
    Of course all this invites the question: how do you know an impermissible
    delegation of legislative authority when you see it? By its own telling, the Court
    has had a hard time devising a satisfying answer. See, e.g., Wayman v. Southard,
    23 U.S. (10 Wheat) 1, 42 (1825) (“[T]he precise boundary of this power is a
    subject of delicate and difficult inquiry. . . .”). But the difficulty of the inquiry
    doesn’t mean it isn’t worth the effort. After all, at stake here isn’t just the
    balance of power between the political branches who might be assumed capable
    of fighting it out among themselves. At stake is the principle that the scope of
    individual liberty may be reduced only according to the deliberately difficult
    processes prescribed by the Constitution, a principle that may not be fully
    vindicated without the intervention of the courts. And “[a]bdication of
    responsibility is not part of the constitutional design.” Clinton v. City of New
    York, 
    524 U.S. 417
    , 452 (1998) (Kennedy, J., concurring). 3
    Constitutionalism 222 (2012); Martin Redish, The Constitution as Political
    Structure 16 (1995); David Schoenbrod, Power Without Responsibility 181
    (1993); Ernest Gellhorn, Returning to First Principles, 
    36 Am. U. L. Rev. 345
    ,
    352 (1987); Paul Gewirtz, The Courts, Congress, and Executive Policy-Making:
    Notes on Three Doctrines, 
    40 Law & Contemp. Probs. 46
    , 49-65 (1976); Marci A.
    Hamilton, Representation and Nondelegation: Back to Basics, 
    20 Cardozo L. Rev. 807
    , 822 (1999); Carl McGowan, Congress, Court, and Control of Delegated
    Power, 
    77 Colum. L. Rev. 1119
    , 1127-30 (1977); Bernard Schwartz, Of
    Administrators and Philosopher-Kings: The Republic, The Laws, and Delegations
    of Power, 
    72 Nw. U. L. Rev. 443
    , 457 (1978); Nadine Strossen, Delegation as a
    Threat to Liberty, 
    20 Cardozo L. Rev. 861
    , 861 (1999).
    3
    See also, e.g., Ass’n of Am. Railroads, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1237
     (Alito, J.,
    concurring) (“[T]he inherent difficulty of line-drawing is no excuse for not
    enforcing the Constitution.”); 
    id. at 1246
     (Thomas, J., concurring in the
    8
    Besides, putting the pieces together it turns out we do know a few things.
    We know, for example, that Congress can leave “details” to the Executive.
    Congress can’t punt to the President the job of devising a competition code for
    the chicken industry. Schechter Poultry, 
    295 U.S. at 531
    . Such widely applicable
    rules governing private conduct must be enacted by the Legislature. But once
    Congress enacts a detailed statutory scheme on its own — once it says, for
    example, that margarine manufacturers must pay a tax and place a stamp on their
    packages showing the tax has been paid — Congress may leave to the President
    “details” like designing an appropriate tax stamp. In re Kollock, 
    165 U.S. 526
    ,
    533 (1897); see also, e.g., Currin v. Wallace, 
    306 U.S. 1
    , 15 (1939); United States
    v. Shreveport Grain & Elevator Co., 
    287 U.S. 77
    , 85 (1932).
    Of course, defining what qualifies as a detail is itself no detail. But
    whether or not something fairly denominated a detail is involved, we also know
    Congress may pass legislation the operation of which is conditioned on a factual
    finding by the President. So, for example, Congress may direct the President to
    lift a statutorily imposed trade embargo against Great Britain if he determines as a
    judgment) (explaining that enforcing the separation of powers “is no less
    important for its difficulty”); Louis L. Jaffe, An Essay on Delegation of
    Legislative Power, 
    47 Colum. L. Rev. 561
    , 577 (1947) (“[N]early every doctrine
    of constitutional limitation has been attacked as vague. Essentially the charges go
    to the institution of judicial review as we have it rather than specifically to the
    delegation doctrine.”); Antonin Scalia, A Note on the Benzene Case, Reg., July-
    Aug. 1980, at 25, 28 (“So even with all its Frankenstein-like warts, knobs, and
    (concededly) dangers, the unconstitutional delegation doctrine is worth hewing
    from the ice.”).
    9
    factual matter that it is no longer violating the United States’s neutrality. See
    Cargo of the Brig Aurora v. United States, 
    11 U.S. 382
    , 388 (1813); see also, e.g.,
    Marshall Field & Co. v. Clark, 
    143 U.S. 649
    , 692-93 (1892). That’s clearly no
    trivial question the President may answer. But answer it he may so long as a
    clear legislative consequence follows from his factual finding.
    While these are the most traditional delegation tests — is it a detail? do we
    have a clear legislative consequence hinging on a factual finding? — in more
    recent times the Court has gone further, allowing legislation to stand so long as it
    contains an “intelligible principle” to guide the exercise of Executive discretion.
    J.W. Hampton, Jr. & Co. v. United States, 
    276 U.S. 394
    , 409 (1928). How
    intelligible the “intelligible principle” must be to pass muster is much debated. 4
    But we know, by way of example, that Congress may ask the EPA to set national
    air quality standards which are “requisite to protect the public health” subject to
    “an adequate margin of safety” because, as used in the statute, the term
    “requisite” demands a standard neither higher nor lower than necessary to meet
    4
    See, e.g., Ass’n of Am. Railroads, 
    135 S. Ct. at 1246
     (Thomas, J.,
    concurring in the judgment); Mistretta v. United States, 
    488 U.S. 361
    , 415-17
    (1989) (Scalia, J., dissenting); David Schoenbrod, The Delegation Doctrine:
    Could the Court Give It Substance?, 
    83 Mich. L. Rev. 1223
    , 1224 (1985) (“Since
    the early part of this century, the Court has said in essence that a statute may be
    vague so long as it is either not too vague or no vaguer than necessary.”);
    Lawson, supra, at 329 (asserting that the Court has “found intelligible principles
    where less discerning readers find gibberish”); see also supra n.2 (additional
    authorities discussing this question).
    10
    the legislatively directed objective of protecting the public health with an
    adequate margin of safety. Whitman, 
    531 U.S. at 473, 476
    .
    Still, the Court has never expressly held that an intelligible principle alone
    suffices to save a putative delegation when the criminal law is involved. See
    Touby, 500 U.S. at 165-66. To be sure, the Court has applied the intelligible
    principle test to regulations that may be enforceable through criminal penalties.
    See, e.g., United States v. O’Hagan, 
    521 U.S. 642
    , 695 n.10 (1997); Yakus v.
    United States, 
    321 U.S. 421
    , 424-25 (1944). But the Court hasn’t endorsed the
    test in anything like the situation we face — legislation leaving it to the nation’s
    top prosecutor to specify whether and how a federal criminal law should be
    applied to a class of a half-million individuals. In fact, the Court has repeatedly
    and long suggested that in the criminal context Congress must provide more
    “meaningful[]” guidance than an “intelligible principle.” Touby, 500 U.S. at 166;
    Fahey v. Mallonee, 
    332 U.S. 245
    , 249-50 (1947); see also, e.g., United States v.
    Robel, 
    389 U.S. 258
    , 272-73 (1967) (Brennan, J., concurring); Barenblatt v.
    United States, 
    360 U.S. 109
    , 140 n.7 (1959) (Black, J., dissenting); cf. United
    States v. Grimaud, 
    220 U.S. 506
    , 517 (1911); United States v. Eaton, 
    144 U.S. 677
    , 687-88 (1892).
    It’s easy enough to see why a stricter rule would apply in the criminal
    arena. The criminal conviction and sentence represent the ultimate intrusions on
    personal liberty and carry with them the stigma of the community’s collective
    11
    condemnation — something quite different than holding someone liable for a
    money judgment because he turns out to be the lowest cost avoider. See, e.g.,
    Henry M. Hart, Jr., The Aims of the Criminal Law, 23 Law & Contemp. Prob. 401,
    404 (1958); William J. Stuntz, Substance, Process, and the Civil-Criminal Line, 
    7 J. Contemp. Legal Issues 1
    , 26 (1996). Indeed, the law routinely demands clearer
    legislative direction in the criminal context than it does in the civil and it would
    hardly be odd to think it might do the same here. See, e.g., Whitman v. United
    States, 
    135 S. Ct. 352
    , 353 (2014) (Scalia, J., statement respecting the denial of
    certiorari). When it comes to legislative delegations we’ve seen, too, that the
    framers’ attention to the separation of powers was driven by a particular concern
    about individual liberty and even more especially by a fear of endowing one set of
    hands with the power to create and enforce criminal sanctions. And might not
    that concern take on special prominence today, in an age when federal law
    contains so many crimes — and so many created by executive regulation — that
    scholars no longer try to keep count and actually debate their number? See John
    C. Coffee, Jr., Does “Unlawful” Mean “Criminal”?: Reflections on the
    Disappearing Tort/Crime Distinction in American Law, 
    71 B.U. L. Rev. 193
    , 216
    (1991) (estimating that over 300,000 federal criminal regulations are on the
    books).
    Recently, the Supreme Court has suggested what a more “meaningful”
    standard might look like in the criminal context. See Touby, 500 U.S. at 166-67.
    12
    Its discussion came in the course of a challenge to the Controlled Substances Act
    — legislation permitting the Attorney General to schedule various drugs as
    controlled substances, rendering their possession by unauthorized persons illegal.
    The Court allowed the law to stand, but instead of applying the intelligible
    principle test alone it proceeded to stress the presence and importance of certain
    specific statutory features. First, the Court explained, to schedule a drug as a
    controlled substance the Executive had to find that the drug posed an “imminent
    hazard” to public safety. Id. at 166. Second, when making that determination,
    the Court noted, the Executive had to consider the drug’s “history and current
    pattern of abuse,” “[t]he scope, duration, and significance of abuse,” and “[w]hat,
    if any, risk there is to the public health.” Id. Third, the law required a further
    factual finding that the drug in question “has a high potential for abuse,” “has no
    currently accepted medical use in treatment in the United States,” and “[t]here is
    a lack of accepted safety for use of the drug . . . under medical supervision.” Id.
    at 167.
    Here we see strains of a more traditional delegation jurisprudence, one
    permitting Congress to enact rules the operation of which is premised on the
    Executive’s factual findings. Indeed, distilling Touby to its essence, at least three
    “meaningful” limitations emerge: (1) Congress must set forth a clear and
    generally applicable rule (unauthorized persons may not possess the drug) that (2)
    hinges on a factual determination by the Executive (does the drug pose an
    13
    imminent hazard?) and (3) the statute provides criteria the Executive must employ
    when making its finding (does the drug in question currently have an accepted
    medical use?). These three criteria could easily be applied to most any delegation
    challenge in the criminal context and provide the more meaningful standard the
    Court has long sought. In fact, since Touby a number of courts of appeals have
    employed something very much like them when assessing delegation challenges
    to federal criminal statutes. See United States v. Amirnazmi, 
    645 F.3d 564
    , 576-
    77 (3d Cir. 2011); United States v. Dhafir, 
    461 F.3d 211
    , 216-17 (2d Cir. 2006);
    United States v. Arch Trading Co., 
    987 F.2d 1087
    , 1093-94 (4th Cir. 1993).
    *
    With that much guidance about delegation doctrine in hand, a few things
    come clear when we return to the statute before us. For one, it’s easy enough to
    see the similarities between our case and Schechter Poultry where the Court held
    Article I violated. Here as there Congress pointed to a problem that needed fixing
    and more or less told the Executive to go forth and figure it out. Meanwhile, it’s
    hard to see how ours might be likened to any of the cases turning away delegation
    challenges.
    True, some might try to pass off the question of SORNA’s applicability to
    past offenders as a mere “detail.” But the statute before us leaves the Attorney
    General with “unfettered discretion to determine both how and whether SORNA
    [is] to be retroactively applied” to a half-million individuals under threat of
    14
    criminal prosecution from his own deputies. Madera, 
    528 F.3d at 858
    . And
    however far you want to bend the boundaries of what qualifies as a “detail” it’s
    hard to see how that might qualify. Our case just isn’t anything like your
    grandfather’s tax stamp challenge.
    Fair enough, some might respond, but sex offenders are so unpopular that
    there’s little chance an Attorney General would do anything other than apply
    SORNA retroactively to the fullest extent possible. Maybe there is no legislative
    mandate — conditional or otherwise — requiring him to follow this course, but
    there might as well be. A reply along these lines seems a likely enough answer to
    the question what a politically attuned Attorney General would do when the hot
    potato is passed his way. But it also seems an unlikely answer to the question
    whether Congress may constitutionally pass the potato in the first place. After
    all, in a delegation challenge the question isn’t whether the Executive is likely to
    exercise the delegation in one way or another but whether Congress is empowered
    to delegate the decision at all. See Whitman, 
    531 U.S. at 472-73
     (“The very
    choice of which portion of the power to exercise . . . would itself be an exercise
    of the forbidden legislative authority.”). Indeed, the logic at play here would
    serve to ensconce even the most extreme and obviously unconstitutional
    delegations only because of a judicial intuition about contemporary political
    pressures. And not only do unelected judges make for notoriously poor political
    15
    pundits: ours is supposed to be an independent judiciary making decisions on the
    legal merits without respect to the vagaries of shifting political winds.
    Others still might claim an “intelligible principle” can be rummaged out of
    SORNA’s preamble — a provision that expresses Congress’s wish to “protect the
    public from sex offenders and offenders against children” by establishing “a
    comprehensive national system for the registration of those offenders.” 
    42 U.S.C. § 16901
    . But Supreme Court cases rejecting delegation challenges on intelligible
    principle grounds don’t usually rest on policy objectives voiced in a statute’s
    preamble. See, e.g., Panama Refining Co. v. Ryan, 
    293 U.S. 388
    , 417-19 (1935)
    (finding a statute’s general policy statement insufficient because the “general
    outline of policy contains nothing as to the circumstances or conditions in which”
    the delegation should be exercised, 
    id. at 417
    ). To be sure, the Court has
    sometimes gone so far as to suggest that Congress need only “clearly delineate[]
    the general policy” to guide an agency’s conduct. Mistretta, 
    488 U.S. at 372-73
    .
    But this language usually seems to cover situations in which the legislative grant
    of discretion is tied to specific statutory provisions that expressly direct the
    exercise of that discretion. See, e.g., 
    id. at 375-76
     (containing a direct link
    between discretion and direction); Yakus, 321 U.S. at 420-21 (same). Even in
    National Broadcasting Co. v. United States, 
    319 U.S. 190
     (1943), perhaps one of
    the most ambitious uses of the intelligible principle test, the Court interpreted the
    statute granting the Executive discretion to regulate radio in the “public interest”
    16
    as requiring him to exercise that discretion in ways that “encourage the larger and
    more effective use of radio.” 
    Id. at 216
    . Meanwhile, no comparable guidance
    exists here for § 16913(d) “specifie[s] no governing standard whatsoever.”
    Calabresi & Lawson, supra n.1, at 485.
    Requiring a direct statutory link between discretion and direction makes
    sense too. After all, as the Court has acknowledged in recent years, it is most
    assuredly wrong to assume that “whatever” seems to further a “statute’s primary
    objective must be the law.” Rodriguez v. United States, 
    480 U.S. 522
    , 526 (1987)
    (emphasis omitted). Legislation is the art of compromise and few (if any) statutes
    pursue a single preambulatory purpose without condition, subtlety, or exception.
    
    Id. at 525-26
    ; see also United States v. Rentz, 
    777 F.3d 1105
    , 1113 (10th Cir.
    2015) (en banc); John F. Manning, What Divides Textualists from Purposivists?,
    
    106 Colum. L. Rev. 70
    , 104 (2006). For precisely these reasons, when it comes to
    the business of statutory interpretation it is usually the more specific and not the
    more general or aspirational direction that controls. See, e.g., Radzanower v.
    Touche Ross & Co., 
    426 U.S. 148
    , 153 (1976).
    Our case illustrates the point. SORNA’s prefatory provision expressing the
    desire to protect children and create a nationwide registration requirement hardly
    establishes that the statute meant to do so always and in every particular without
    exception or at any cost. In fact, SORNA is replete with examples of compromise
    even when it comes to future offenders. Congress indicated that some future
    17
    offenders may be exempt from its registration requirements if they committed
    certain kinds of sex offenses but not others. 
    42 U.S.C. § 16911
    (5)(C), (7)(A),
    (7)(B), (8). Registration is required for life for some offenders but lesser periods
    for others. 
    Id.
     § 16915(a). These periods can be reduced on good behavior. Id.
    § 16915(b)(1). In these circumstances, it would seem strange to suppose that the
    statute’s prefatory statement of purpose — or, for that matter, provisions of the
    law discussing the treatment of future offenders — provides intelligible guidance
    for the Attorney General’s treatment of past offenders. Especially when Congress
    went on to address past offenders specifically, exempted them from the automatic
    application of any of the statute’s registration requirements, and left their
    treatment to the Attorney General.
    Separately but relatedly, the Supreme Court has instructed that under the
    intelligible principle test “the degree of agency discretion that is acceptable varies
    according to the scope of the power congressionally conferred.” Whitman, 
    531 U.S. at 475
    . Faint echos of detail doctrine can be found here: less direction may
    be required when Congress leaves it to the Executive to define what constitutes a
    “country elevator[]” and more may be required when Congress seeks to endow the
    Executive with the power to create regulations that affect the national economy.
    
    Id.
     So even assuming that a preamble detached from the provision granting
    discretion to the Executive might suffice to supply an intelligible principle in
    some circumstances, it certainly won’t always. And once again it’s hard to see
    18
    how the discretion conferred here is anything less than extraordinary — in its
    breadth (allowing the Attorney General to apply none, some, or all of SORNA’s
    requirements to none, some, or all past offenders), in its subject matter
    (effectively defining a new crime), in its chosen delegate (the nation’s top
    prosecutor), and in the number of people affected (half a million). All factors
    suggesting more, not less, guidance is required.
    Neither is it any answer to say that, though the Attorney General wants for
    any intelligible principle to guide him in deciding which requirements to impose
    on which past offenders, at least his discretion finds some boundaries in the
    statute (he cannot exceed the full application of all of SORNA’s requirements).
    Delegation doctrine teaches that Congress must set both the “boundaries” of the
    Executive’s discretion and supply an “intelligible principle” for the exercise of
    that discretion within those boundaries. Mistretta, 
    488 U.S. at 372-73
    . After all
    and again, the point of the delegation doctrine isn’t so much that some poor
    Executive agent tasked with the thankless job will necessarily perform poorly
    within the bounds and metes of the discretion set for him. It is that decoupling
    the exercise of his discretion so much from legislative direction deprives the
    people of the structural protections guaranteed by the first section of the first
    article of the Constitution.
    19
    There remains much less room still for debate about the proper outcome of
    this case when the “intelligible principle” test gives way to a more “meaningful”
    one in the criminal setting. After all, SORNA’s delegation contains none of the
    three factors that Touby found reassuring and that circuit courts have since used
    to assess delegation challenges in the criminal context. First, the statute provides
    no generally applicable rule for past offenders for the Attorney General to follow
    contingent only on specified factual findings. Rather, the Attorney General may
    apply all, some or none of the requirements of the Act however he sees fit.
    Second, the statute requires no factual findings of the Attorney General of any
    kind. Third, it offers no guidance about these non-existent factual findings.
    To be sure, Congress could have easily written a statute with such
    constraints, and to remedy the delegation problem here it might still. For
    example, Congress could have tasked the Attorney General with the job of
    determining what factors correlate with recidivism or present an unreasonable
    danger to the public and make his determinations based on those considerations.
    When deciding which past offenders should be required to register Congress
    could have required the Attorney General to examine, as well, factors like the
    recency of the violation; the nature of the sex offense; the number of past
    violations; the offender’s age, family, residential, or occupational circumstances;
    or the offender’s mental or physical health — or banned consideration of any of
    these factors. It’s easy to imagine all sorts of ways Congress might have
    20
    constrained — and might still constrain — the Attorney General’s discretion in
    ways parallel to Touby. But and by the government’s own admission, we have
    nothing of the kind here. And that leaves us well outside the ballpark when it
    comes to satisfying Touby’s test. Indeed, you might wonder if we are even on
    Yawkey Way. See Sadik, supra n.1, at 298 (arguing that SORNA fails Touby’s
    test).
    Delegation doctrine may not be the easiest to tease out and it has been some
    time since the Court has held a statute to cross the line. But it has also been some
    time since the courts have encountered a statute like this one — one that, if
    allowed to stand, would require the Judiciary to endorse the notion that Congress
    may effectively pass off to the prosecutor the job of defining the very crime he is
    responsible for enforcing. By any plausible measure we might apply that is a
    delegation run riot, a result inimical to the people’s liberty and our constitutional
    design.
    21
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 14-3041

Citation Numbers: 784 F.3d 666, 2015 U.S. App. LEXIS 6148, 2015 WL 1727385

Judges: Briscoe, Kelly, Lucero, Hartz, Tymkovich, Gorsuch, Holmes, Matheson, Bacharach, Phillips, McHugh, Moritz

Filed Date: 4/15/2015

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 11/5/2024

Authorities (22)

Department of Transportation v. Association of American ... , 135 S. Ct. 1225 ( 2015 )

Panama Refining Co. v. Ryan , 55 S. Ct. 241 ( 1935 )

United States v. Eaton , 12 S. Ct. 764 ( 1892 )

Fahey v. Mallonee , 332 U.S. 245 ( 1947 )

Whitman v. American Trucking Assns., Inc. , 121 S. Ct. 903 ( 2001 )

Reynolds v. United States , 132 S. Ct. 975 ( 2012 )

A. L. A. Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United States , 55 S. Ct. 837 ( 1935 )

Currin v. Wallace , 59 S. Ct. 379 ( 1939 )

United States v. Arch Trading Company , 987 F.2d 1087 ( 1993 )

united-states-v-rafil-dhafir-also-known-as-sealed-deft-1-maher-zagha , 461 F.3d 211 ( 2006 )

J. W. Hampton, Jr., & Co. v. United States , 48 S. Ct. 348 ( 1928 )

United States v. Grimaud , 31 S. Ct. 480 ( 1911 )

Barenblatt v. United States , 79 S. Ct. 1081 ( 1959 )

Clinton v. City of New York , 118 S. Ct. 2091 ( 1998 )

United States v. Madera , 528 F.3d 852 ( 2008 )

United States v. Amirnazmi , 645 F.3d 564 ( 2011 )

United States v. Johnson , 632 F.3d 912 ( 2011 )

National Broadcasting Co. v. United States , 63 S. Ct. 997 ( 1943 )

In Re Kollock , 17 S. Ct. 444 ( 1897 )

The Cargo of the Brig Aurora, Burn Side v. The United States , 3 L. Ed. 378 ( 1813 )

View All Authorities »