United States v. Heineman ( 2014 )


Menu:
  •                                                                                    FILED
    United States Court of Appeals
    Tenth Circuit
    PUBLISH
    September 15, 2014
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    Elisabeth A. Shumaker
    Clerk of Court
    TENTH CIRCUIT
    UNITED STATES OF AMERICA,
    Plaintiff - Appellee,
    v.                                                             No. 13-4043
    AARON MICHAEL HEINEMAN, a/k/a
    Aaron Heineman,
    Defendant - Appellant.
    APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT
    FOR THE DISTRICT OF UTAH
    (D.C. No. 2:11-CR-00432-DN-1)
    Benjamin McMurray, Assistant Federal Public Defender (Kathryn Nester, Federal Public
    Defender, with him on the briefs), District of Utah, Salt Lake City, Utah, for Defendant -
    Appellant.
    Elizabethanne C. Stevens, Assistant United States Attorney (David B. Barlow, United
    States Attorney, with her on the brief), District of Utah, Salt Lake City, Utah, for Plaintiff
    - Appellee.
    Before HARTZ, BALDOCK, and BACHARACH, Circuit Judges.
    HARTZ, Circuit Judge.
    Defendant Aaron Heineman was convicted after a bench trial on one count of
    sending an interstate threat. See 
    18 U.S.C. § 875
    (c). The district court found that he
    knowingly sent an e-mail that caused the recipient to reasonably fear bodily harm.
    Defendant argues that his conviction violated the First Amendment because the court did
    not also find that he intended the recipient to feel threatened. We have jurisdiction under
    
    28 U.S.C. § 1291
    . Agreeing with Defendant, we reverse and remand.1
    I.     BACKGROUND
    In 2010 and 2011 Defendant sent three e-mails espousing white supremacist
    ideology to a professor at the University of Utah. The first two e-mails did not contain
    threats, but the third made the professor fear for his safety and the safety of his family.
    Entitled “Poem,” Aplt. App., Vol. 1 at 89, it began by addressing the professor by his first
    name, and contained the following language:
    Come the time of the new revolution
    we will convene to detain you
    And slay you, by a bowie knife shoved up into the skull from your pig chin
    you choke, with blood flooding in your filthily treasonous throat!
    We put the noose ring around your neck
    and drag you as you choke and gasp
    1
    The concurrence suggests that because the issue we decide here is now before the
    United States Supreme Court, we should await that decision before resolving this case.
    We respectfully disagree. That decision may not be handed down until next June, and
    there is always the possibility that an unexpected problem with the case will cause the
    Supreme Court not to proceed with its review. True, Defendant is on probation and will
    not suffer as much in the interim as one who has been incarcerated. But probation is not
    an insignificant sanction, and Defendant may well be subject to various restrictions on his
    civil liberties as a result of his felony conviction.
    2
    The noose laid on the tree branch
    and the fate hath conferred justice for Treason
    You are a filthy traitor along the horde of anti-American and anti-Whitey
    comrades
    whose justice shall come to be delivered
    To fuck the traitors, for justice!
    fuck Mexico! fuck South America!
    Fuck your soul to Hell!
    Into the furnace pool of MexiShit as the filthily traitorous asshole and puta!
    
    Id. at 90
    . Law-enforcement officers traced the e-mail to Defendant through his e-mail
    address, which had the user name “siegheil_neocon.” 
    Id. at 91
    . When officers contacted
    him in writing, he responded immediately, “Is this about the email?” 
    Id.
     He was charged
    in the United States District Court for the District of Utah with one count of sending an
    interstate threat, in violation of 
    18 U.S.C. § 875
    (c).
    Before trial Defendant requested an instruction that “the government must prove
    that the defendant intended the communication to be received as a threat.” 
    Id. at 18
    . He
    asserted that he has Asperger’s Disorder, which impairs his “ability to understand how
    others will receive the things he says and does.” Aplt. Br. at 2. The district court
    declined the request. Defendant then moved to dismiss the charge, arguing that § 875(c)
    was facially unconstitutional if it did not require proof that “the defendant intended to
    place the hearer in fear of bodily harm or death.” Aplt. App., Vol. 1 at 28. After the
    court denied the motion, the parties agreed to a bench trial on stipulated facts so that
    Defendant could preserve his legal arguments. He renewed his objections at trial, and the
    court again rejected them. It found that the government had established that Defendant
    “knowingly transmitted a communication containing a threat to injure the person of
    3
    another,” id. at 91, and that the poem was a true threat because it “would cause a
    reasonable person to conclude that the sender . . . intended to cause bodily injury,” id. at
    93. The court did not determine whether Defendant intended the professor to feel
    threatened.
    II.    DISCUSSION
    Defendant was prosecuted under 
    18 U.S.C. § 875
    (c), which states in relevant part:
    “Whoever transmits in interstate or foreign commerce any communication containing . . .
    any threat to injure the person of another, shall be fined under this title or imprisoned not
    more than five years, or both.” The law in this circuit is settled, and the parties do not
    dispute, most of what must be proved to establish a violation of the statute. For example,
    the statement itself must be one that a reasonable person in the circumstances would
    understand “as a declaration of intention, purpose, design, goal, or determination to inflict
    [bodily injury] on another.” United States v. Viefhaus, 
    168 F.3d 392
    , 395 (10th Cir.
    1999); see 
    id. at 396
    ; United States v. Dysart, 
    705 F.2d 1247
    , 1256 (10th Cir. 1983).
    And “[i]t is not necessary to show that defendant intended to carry out the threat,”
    although the threat must be a serious one, “as distinguished from words as mere political
    argument, idle talk or jest.” Viefhaus, 
    168 F.3d at 395
     (internal quotation marks omitted).
    The issue on appeal is whether § 875(c) requires proof of an additional element—
    that the defendant intended the recipient to feel threatened. The statutory language
    contains no mens rea requirement, but as a statute that criminalizes speech, it “must be
    interpreted with the commands of the First Amendment clearly in mind. What is a threat
    4
    must be distinguished from what is constitutionally protected speech.” Watts v. United
    States, 
    394 U.S. 705
    , 707 (1969) (per curiam). Thus, we will read into § 875(c) any
    scienter necessary to satisfy the demands of the First Amendment.2 “We review
    2
    The concurrence suggests that we can avoid the constitutional question by
    construing the statute without reference to First Amendment requirements. We
    respectfully disagree. If we were writing on a clean slate, we would certainly want to try
    that approach first. In our view, however, circuit precedent forecloses that path. First,
    we read United States v.Viefhaus, 
    168 F.3d 392
     (10th Cir. 1999), as adopting an objective
    standard for the meaning of true threat. The opinion defines the term without including
    any requirement that the speaker intend the recipient to feel threatened. See 
    id.
     at
    395‒96. The discussion includes the following sentence in italics: “The question is
    whether those who hear or read the threat reasonably consider that an actual threat has
    been made.” 
    Id. at 396
     (emphasis omitted). The question is not whether the speaker
    viewed the statement as an actual threat.
    Moreover, we read United States v. Dysart, 
    705 F.2d 1247
     (10th Cir. 1983), as
    explicitly rejecting the interpretation of true threat advanced by the concurrence. We
    wrote: “Defendant Dysart claims that two errors afflict the jury instructions. First, he
    says the trial court erred in failing to charge that for conviction under § 871, it must be
    shown that Dysart intended the letter to be taken as a threat, even if he had no intention
    of carrying out the threat. Second, he contends the trial judge erred when he refused to
    give an instruction on the relevance of evidence of Dysart’s mental condition to the issue
    of Dysart’s ability to form the requisite intent. Neither contention is persuasive.” Id. at
    1255‒56 (emphasis added).
    The concurrence suggests that the instruction in Dysart actually contained the
    requirement requested by the defendant in that case. It points to the sentence in the
    instruction stating: “The term ‘threat’ means an avowed present determination or intent
    to injure presently or in the future.” Id. at 1256 (internal quotation marks omitted). But
    that sentence came after the sentence: “The question is whether those who hear or read
    the threat reasonably consider that an actual threat has been made.” Id. (internal
    quotation marks omitted). The avowed-present-determination language is explaining to
    the jury what it is that the listener must consider to have been communicated. That is, it
    is saying that the language uttered by the defendant must be reasonably considered as “an
    avowed present determination or intent to injure presently or in the future.” First, we
    define what it means for a statement to be an actual threat. Then we decide whether it is
    Continued . . .
    5
    questions of constitutional law de novo.” ClearOne Commc’ns, Inc. v. Bowers, 
    651 F.3d 1200
    , 1216 (10th Cir. 2011) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    Defendant contends that the Supreme Court’s opinion in Virginia v. Black, 
    538 U.S. 343
     (2003), compels us to adopt his position. But before we examine that opinion,
    we turn to, and reject, the claims of both parties that we are bound by circuit precedent to
    adopt their positions.
    The government points to four of our decisions. Two can be disposed of
    summarily. Viefhaus predated Black. Whatever it said, a circuit precedent cannot bind
    us to the extent that it is inconsistent with a later Supreme Court decision. See Currier v.
    Doran, 
    242 F.3d 905
    , 912 (10th Cir. 2001). And United States v. Wolff, 370 F. App’x
    888 (10th Cir. 2010), like all unpublished decisions of this court, is not binding
    precedent. See 10th Cir. R. 32.1(A).
    The government’s third case, Nielander v. Board of County Commissioners,
    
    582 F.3d 1155
     (10th Cir. 2009), is a post-Black precedent, but it did not address the issue
    before us. After successfully defending a state criminal-threat charge, Nielander brought
    a First Amendment retaliation claim in federal court under 
    42 U.S.C. § 1983
    . See 
    id.
     at
    1162–63. The district court granted summary judgment against Nielander on the ground
    that his statements (the alleged threats) leading to the alleged retaliation were not
    protected by the Constitution. See 
    id. at 1163
    . We affirmed. See 
    id.
     at 1165–66. We
    the speaker or a reasonable observer who must view the language of the statement as
    having that meaning. Dysart and Viefhaus state Tenth Circuit law that it is the observer.
    6
    held that even if Nielander’s statements were protected speech, the defendants were
    entitled to qualified immunity. See 
    id.
     at 1166–69. Two of the defendants had “merely
    provid[ed] the police with their account of events,” and had not brought any charges
    against Nielander. 
    Id. at 1166
    . As for the defendant police officer, we said that he was
    entitled to qualified immunity because the law was not clearly established that
    Nielander’s statements were not true threats. See 
    id.
     at 1167–69. Although we used a
    pre-Black definition of true threat that did not include an intent to instill fear, see 
    id. at 1167
    , we did not consider whether such intent was required, and we fail to see how our
    ultimate decision would have been affected if we had included that requirement because
    the evidence would have supported a reasonable belief that Nielander had that intent. See
    Brecht v. Abrahamson, 
    507 U.S. 619
    , 631 (1993) (“[S]ince we have never squarely
    addressed the issue, and have at most assumed the [standard], we are free to address the
    issue on the merits.”).
    The fourth case relied on by the government is United States v. Teague, 
    443 F.3d 1310
     (10th Cir. 2006). Teague was convicted of transmitting an interstate threat under
    
    18 U.S.C. § 875
    (c) after he sent a series of threatening e-mails to his former divorce
    attorney. See 
    id.
     at 1311–13. His defense at trial was that he had not intended a threat,
    but that his e-mails were meant instead to prod the attorney to take various actions, were
    meant humorously, or merely stated the biological truth that the attorney and his family
    were going to die. See 
    id.
     at 1312–13. On appeal he argued that the jury should have
    been instructed that he must have intended that his former attorney feel threatened and
    7
    not just that “he sent the e-mail with knowledge that a reasonable person would take the
    message as a threat.” 
    Id. at 1318
    . But Teague had not raised that argument in district
    court, so we reviewed only for plain error. See 
    id.
     Accordingly, he needed to show that
    the requirement of his additional element was “clear under current law.” 
    Id. at 1319
    (internal quotation marks omitted). Yet he conceded (incorrectly, as we shall see) that
    the Supreme Court had not spoken on the issue, and he acknowledged that this circuit had
    no controlling precedent and that the other circuits were split. See 
    id.
     We readily
    concluded that there was no plain error. See 
    id.
     The parties’ briefs did not cite Black, nor
    did our opinion. Teague could hardly stand as this court’s interpretation of Black.
    Defendant in turn relies on two of our decisions. One is United States v. Pinson,
    
    542 F.3d 822
     (10th Cir. 2008), which concerned a prosecution under 
    18 U.S.C. § 871
    (a)
    for threatening the life of the President. See 
    id. at 826
    . Pinson complained that the jury
    was instructed that an element of the offense was that he “understood and meant the
    words mailed as a threat.” 
    Id. at 832
     (internal quotation marks omitted). By making his
    intent an element, argued Pinson, the prosecution was enabled to put on prejudicial
    evidence of his state of mind. See 
    id. at 831
    . We affirmed the conviction. See 
    id. at 827
    .
    Some language in the opinion certainly supports Defendant’s argument. We said:
    The burden is on the prosecution to show that the defendant understood
    and meant his words as a threat, and not as a joke, warning, or hyperbolic
    political argument. But a threat violates the law even if the defendant had
    no actual intention, or even ability, to carry it out. . . . The proper question
    for the jury is whether the defendant meant his words as a threat and
    whether a reasonable person would so regard them. The instruction here
    conveyed at least the first element of that meaning. It does not imply that
    8
    the defendant must be shown to have intended to carry out the threat, but it
    does require that the defendant understood and meant his words to be a
    threat.
    
    Id. at 832
     (footnote omitted). But the opinion does not bind us in this case. It concerned
    a prosecution under 
    18 U.S.C. § 871
    (a), which, in contrast to § 875(c), explicitly requires
    that the offense be committed “knowingly and willfully”; and it did not purport to be
    stating a proposition of constitutional law. Pinson does not cite any authority (much less
    First Amendment decisions) for its language supporting Defendant, and it does not
    otherwise explain why (other than the statutory requirement) a defendant must mean his
    words to be a threat.
    The other case relied on by Defendant is United States v. Magleby, 
    420 F.3d 1136
    (10th Cir. 2005). Magleby had filed a motion under 
    28 U.S.C. § 2255
     to challenge his
    convictions of burning and conspiring to burn a cross, in violation of the civil rights of an
    interracial couple. See 
    id.
     at 1138–39. The success of one of his arguments turned on
    whether his appellate counsel had been ineffective for failing to challenge instructions on
    the elements of his offenses. In the course of the opinion we paraphrased Black as saying
    that a threat must have been made “with the intent of placing the victim in fear of bodily
    harm or death. An intent to threaten is enough.” 
    Id. at 1139
     (citation and internal
    quotation marks omitted). But our ruling on Magleby’s claim of ineffective assistance of
    appellate counsel hinged on the pre-Black law in effect at the time of his earlier appeal.
    See 
    id. at 1140
    . Any statement in the opinion regarding the meaning of Black was
    irrelevant to the opinion and therefore dictum. “[A] panel of this court . . . is not bound
    9
    by a prior panel’s dicta.” Thompson v. Weyerhaeuser Co., 
    582 F.3d 1125
    , 1129 (10th
    Cir. 2009) (brackets and internal quotation marks omitted).
    Thus, we are facing a question of first impression in this circuit: Does the First
    Amendment, as construed in Black, require the government to prove in any true-threat
    prosecution that the defendant intended the recipient to feel threatened? We conclude
    that it does.
    At issue in Black were three state-law convictions for cross burning (or attempted
    cross burning) with intent to intimidate. See Black, 
    538 U.S. at
    348–51. On an open field
    on private property, defendant Black had led a Ku Klux Klan rally that ended with the
    participants setting flame to a large cross 300 yards or so from a road, where passersby
    and neighbors could see it. See 
    id.
     at 348–49. In a separate incident, defendants Elliott
    and O’Mara had driven a truck into the yard of an African-American family that had
    recently moved into the neighborhood, planted a cross 20 feet from the house, and set it
    on fire. 
    Id. at 350
    .
    The three were convicted of violating a Virginia statute that provided: “It shall be
    unlawful for any person or persons, with the intent of intimidating any person or group of
    persons, to burn, or cause to be burned, a cross on the property of another, a highway or
    other public place,” and, “Any such burning of a cross shall be prima facie evidence of an
    intent to intimidate a person or group of persons.” 
    Id. at 348
     (internal quotation marks
    omitted). The Virginia Supreme Court held the statute facially unconstitutional for two
    reasons: (1) the statute “selectively cho[se] only cross burning because of its distinctive
    10
    message,” and was therefore a content-based distinction within the category of true
    threats, which was impermissible under R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, 
    505 U.S. 377
     (1992);
    and (2) the prima facie provision rendered it overbroad “because the enhanced probability
    of prosecution under the statute chills the expression of protected speech.” Black, 
    538 U.S. at 351
     (brackets and internal quotation marks omitted). It did not decide whether the
    prima facie provision was severable. See 
    id. at 363
    .
    The United States Supreme Court affirmed in part and reversed in part. We
    discuss the opinion at some length because, in our view, it has been misconstrued by
    some courts that we highly respect. Black devotes little attention to what is required for a
    threat to be a “true threat” not protected by the First Amendment, and its sentence
    defining true threat (which appears in the Court’s resolution of the R.A.V. issue) is
    somewhat ambiguous. Nevertheless, a careful review of the opinions of the Justices
    makes clear that a true threat must be made with the intent to instill fear.
    To resolve the R.A.V. issue, the Court, in an opinion by Justice O’Connor for
    herself and four other Justices, began by reiterating the fundamental protection of speech
    embodied in the First Amendment. “The hallmark of the protection of free speech is to
    allow free trade in ideas—even ideas that the overwhelming majority of people might
    find distasteful or discomforting.” 
    Id. at 358
     (internal quotation marks omitted). But it
    also noted that the Amendment “permits restrictions upon the content of speech in a few
    limited areas, which are of such slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit that
    may be derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and
    11
    morality.” 
    Id.
     at 358–59 (internal quotation marks omitted). As examples of permissible
    content-based restrictions, it included incitement to imminent breach of the peace,
    fighting words, and “true threats.” 
    Id.
     Critical to the resolution of our case, the Court
    then defined true threats, stating:
    True threats encompass those statements where the speaker means to
    communicate a serious expression of an intent to commit an act of unlawful
    violence to a particular individual or group of individuals. The speaker
    need not actually intend to carry out the threat. Rather, a prohibition on
    true threats protects individuals from the fear of violence and from the
    disruption that fear engenders, in addition to protecting people from the
    possibility that the threatened violence will occur. Intimidation in the
    constitutionally proscribable sense of the word is a type of true threat,
    where a speaker directs a threat to a person or group of persons with the
    intent of placing the victim in fear of bodily harm or death.
    
    Id.
     at 359–60 (emphasis added) (brackets, citations, and internal quotation marks
    omitted).
    Turning to the Virginia statute, the Court acknowledged that cross-burning is
    symbolic expression, and therefore governed by First Amendment principles. See 
    id. at 360
    . And it further acknowledged that R.A.V. held that even when a statute bans speech
    within an unprotected category (such as true threats), it ordinarily cannot discriminate by
    targeting only a subset of speech within the category. See 
    id.
     at 361–62. Thus, the
    ordinance in R.A.V. was invalidated because it banned “certain symbolic conduct,
    including cross burning, when done with the knowledge that such conduct would arouse
    anger, alarm or resentment in others on the basis of race, color, creed, religion or gender,”
    
    id. at 361
     (internal quotation marks omitted), but it did not cover, for example, “those
    12
    who wish to use fighting words in connection with other ideas—to express hostility, for
    example, on the basis of political affiliation, union membership, or homosexuality,” 
    id.
    (brackets and internal quotation marks omitted). R.A.V. did not hold, however, that
    prohibiting only a subset of “a proscribable area of speech” is always barred by the First
    Amendment. 
    Id.
     In particular, “the First Amendment permits content discrimination
    based on the very reasons why the particular class of speech at issue is proscribable.” 
    Id. at 362
     (ellipsis and internal quotation marks omitted). Thus, “[t]he Federal Government
    can criminalize only those threats of violence that are directed against the President since
    the reasons why threats of violence are outside the First Amendment have special force
    when applied to the person of the President.” 
    Id.
     (ellipses and internal quotation marks
    omitted). (But the government cannot ban “only those threats against the President that
    mention his policy on aid to inner cities.” 
    Id.
     (internal quotation marks omitted).)
    Accordingly, the Virginia statute’s “ban on cross burning carried out with intent to
    intimidate [was] fully consistent” with the dictates of R.A.V. because “burning a cross is a
    particularly virulent form of intimidation.” 
    Id. at 363
    .
    On the First Amendment overbreadth issue, there was no Court majority. Three
    Justices did not address the issue; they would have invalidated the Virginia statute under
    R.A.V. See Black, 
    538 U.S. at
    380–87 (Souter, J.). Of the remaining six, four (in an
    opinion by Justice O’Connor for those who formed the R.A.V.-issue majority except for
    Justice Scalia) would have held that the statute was rendered facially unconstitutional by
    the provision that “any such burning of a cross shall be prima facie evidence of an intent
    13
    to intimidate a person or group of persons.” 
    Id. at 363
     (brackets and internal quotation
    marks omitted) (O’Connor, J.). In their view, the flaw was that the provision “strip[ped]
    away the very reason why a State may ban cross burning with the intent to intimidate.”
    
    Id. at 365
    . The plurality explained:
    The prima facie evidence provision permits a jury to convict in every cross-
    burning case in which defendants exercise their constitutional right not to
    put on a defense. And even where a defendant like Black presents a
    defense, the prima facie evidence provision makes it more likely that the
    jury will find an intent to intimidate regardless of the particular facts of the
    case. The provision permits the Commonwealth to arrest, prosecute, and
    convict a person based solely on the fact of cross burning itself.
    
    Id.
     “[T]he act of cross burning may mean that a person is engaging in constititutionally
    proscribable intimidation,” it said, “[b]ut that same act may mean only that the person is
    engaged in core political speech.” 
    Id.
     Thus, the prima facie provision “ignore[d] all of
    the contextual factors that are necessary to decide whether a particular cross burning is
    intended to intimidate.” 
    Id. at 367
    . “The First Amendment,” concluded the plurality,
    “does not permit such a shortcut.” 
    Id.
    Justice Scalia, who was a member of the Court majority on the R.A.V. issue,
    dissented from the plurality on overbreadth. He disagreed with the plurality’s
    interpretation of the prima facie provision, contending that it permitted an inference of
    the requisite intent only if the defendant put on no rebuttal evidence. See 
    id.
     at 368–71
    (Scalia, J.). And he argued that (1) so construed, the statute was not unconstitutionally
    overbroad because it would be highly unlikely to lead to any convictions for
    constitutionally protected conduct; and (2) the plurality should not have assumed its own
    14
    construction of the prima facie provision but instead should have remanded to the
    Virginia Supreme Court for a definitive interpretation. See 
    id.
     at 371–79. He agreed,
    however, with setting aside Black’s conviction because the jury had been instructed that
    it could infer his intent from the act of cross-burning itself, so the jury may have ignored
    evidence showing no such intent. See 
    id.
     at 379–80.
    Finally, Justice Thomas would have upheld the statute, saying that cross-burning
    is not expressive conduct and the prima facie provision established a permissible
    inference. See 
    id.
     at 388–400.
    We read Black as establishing that a defendant can be constitutionally convicted of
    making a true threat only if the defendant intended the recipient of the threat to feel
    threatened. The majority of the Court said that “‘[t]rue threats’ encompass those
    statements where the speaker means to communicate a serious expression of an intent to
    commit an act of unlawful violence to a particular individual or group of individuals.”
    
    Id. at 359
    . When the Court says that the speaker must “mean[] to communicate a serious
    expression of an intent,” it is requiring more than a purpose to communicate just the
    threatening words. 
    Id.
     It is requiring that the speaker want the recipient to believe that
    the speaker intends to act violently. The point is made again later in the same paragraph
    when the Court applies the definition to intimidation threats: “Intimidation in the
    constitutionally proscribable sense of the word is a type of true threat, where a speaker
    directs a threat to a person or group of persons with the intent of placing the victim in fear
    of bodily harm or death.” 
    Id. at 360
     (emphasis added).
    15
    Moreover, the plurality’s overbreadth analysis is predicated on the understanding
    that the First Amendment requires the speaker to intend to place the recipient in fear.
    According to the plurality, at least one First Amendment flaw in the prima facie provision
    was that a jury could infer an “intent to intimidate” from the act of cross-burning itself.
    
    Id. at 363
    . The prima facie provision, wrote Justice O’Connor, “does not distinguish
    between a cross burning done with the purpose of creating anger or resentment and a
    cross burning done with the purpose of threatening or intimidating a victim.” 
    Id. at 366
    .
    But how could that be a First Amendment problem if the First Amendment is indifferent
    to whether the speaker had an intent to threaten? The First Amendment overbreadth
    doctrine does not say simply that laws restricting speech should not prohibit too much
    speech. It says that laws restricting speech should not prohibit too much speech that is
    protected by the First Amendment.
    True, Justice O’Connor’s overbreadth analysis was not adopted by a Court
    majority. But that portion of her opinion did not include an analysis of what the First
    Amendment requires to convict someone of a true threat. The plurality obviously
    assumed that the discussion of the R.A.V. issue had already established that an intent to
    threaten was required. The one Justice (Justice Scalia) who had departed from the rest of
    the R.A.V.-issue majority to dissent on overbreadth in no way challenged the underlying
    assumption by the plurality that the First Amendment required an intent to threaten. On
    the contrary, he agreed with the reversal of Black’s conviction on the ground that the
    instruction at his trial based on the prima facie provision could have led the jury to
    16
    convict without considering evidence that he had no intent to intimidate. See 
    id.
     at 379–
    801 (Scalia, J.). Thus, the overbreadth discussion confirms our reading of the definition
    of true threat in the discussion of the R.A.V. issue. We also note that Justice Souter’s
    opinion for the R.A.V.-issue dissenters also seems to have assumed that intent to instill
    fear is an element of a true threat required by the First Amendment. In support of the
    view that the Virginia statute could not survive First Amendment scrutiny, the opinion
    pointed out that the prima facie provision could encourage juries to convict despite weak
    evidence of an intent to intimidate. See 
    id.
     at 384–87 (Souter, J.).
    The Ninth Circuit has read Black as we do. See United States v. Bagdasarian, 
    652 F.3d 1113
    , 1116–18 (9th Cir. 2011); United States v. Cassel, 
    408 F.3d 622
    , 630–33 (9th
    Cir. 2005). It said that a “natural reading” of Black’s definition of true threats “embraces
    not only the requirement that the communication itself be intentional, but also the
    requirement that the speaker intend for his language to threaten the victim.” Cassel, 
    408 F.3d at 631
    . We also find some support from the Seventh Circuit. In United States v.
    Parr, 
    545 F.3d 491
    , 500 (7th Cir. 2008), it wrote: “It is possible that the Court was not
    attempting a comprehensive redefinition of true threats in Black; the plurality’s
    discussion of threat doctrine was very brief. It is more likely, however, that an entirely
    objective definition is no longer tenable.”
    Other circuits have declined to read Black as imposing a subjective-intent
    requirement. See United States v. Clemens, 
    738 F.3d 1
    , 9–12 (1st Cir. 2013) (on plain-
    error review); United States v. Elonis, 
    730 F.3d 321
    , 327–32 (3rd Cir. 2013), cert.
    17
    granted, 
    134 S. Ct. 2819
     (2014); United States v. White, 
    670 F.3d 498
    , 506–12 (4th Cir.
    2012); United States v. Jeffries, 
    692 F.3d 473
    , 477–81 (6th Cir. 2012), cert. denied, 
    134 S. Ct. 59
     (2013); United States v. Nicklas, 
    713 F.3d 435
    , 438–40 (8th Cir. 2013); United
    States v. Martinez, 
    736 F.3d 981
    , 986–88 (11th Cir. 2013). But the reasons for their
    conclusions do not persuade us.
    We discuss the opinion in Jeffries, 
    692 F.3d 473
    , because it expresses the various
    reasons for rejecting our reading of Black. To begin with, the Sixth Circuit said that
    Black had no need to impose a subjective-intent requirement because the Virginia statute
    already required that intent. It wrote:
    [Black] merely applies—it does not innovate—the principle that what is a
    threat must be distinguished from what is constitutionally protected speech.
    It says nothing about imposing a subjective standard on other threat-
    prohibiting statutes, and indeed had no occasion to do so: the Virginia law
    itself required subjective intent. The problem in Black thus did not turn on
    subjective versus objective standards for construing threats. It turned on
    overbreadth—that the statute lacked any standard at all. The prima facie
    evidence provision failed to distinguish true threats from constitutionally
    protected speech because it ignored all of the contextual factors that are
    necessary to decide whether a particular cross burning is intended to
    intimidate, and allowed convictions based solely on the fact of cross
    burning itself.
    Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 479–80 (emphasis added) (brackets, citations, and internal quotation
    marks omitted); accord Clemens, 738 F.3d at 11; Martinez, 736 F.3d at 986–87;
    Nicklas, 713 F.3d at 439–40; see Elonis, 730 F.3d at 330. But we do not read the
    plurality’s overbreadth analysis as Jeffries does. As described above, one of the
    predicates for the plurality’s overbreadth ruling was the Court’s view that a threat was
    18
    unprotected by the First Amendment only if the speaker intended to instill fear in the
    recipient. If the First Amendment does not require subjective intent, how could it
    invalidate the statute for allowing a jury to find subjective intent on improper or
    inadequate grounds? See Cassel, 
    408 F.3d at 631
     (Black’s overbreadth analysis made
    clear that “intent to threaten [is] the sine qua non of a constitutionally punishable threat”);
    White, 
    670 F.3d at 523
     (Floyd, J., dissenting) (“If the First Amendment did not impose a
    specific intent requirement, ‘Virginia’s statutory presumption was superfluous to the
    requirements of the Constitution, and thus incapable of being unconstitutional in the way
    that the majority understood it.’” (quoting Frederick Schauer, Intentions, Conventions,
    and the First Amendment: The Case of Cross-Burning, 
    55 Sup. Ct. Rev. 197
    , 217
    (2003))). Why would the First Amendment care how a jury goes about finding an
    element that is a matter of indifference to the Amendment? We cannot read the
    plurality’s overbreadth ruling as derived from a lack of standards simpliciter.
    Also, Jeffries did not read Black’s definition of true threat to include subjective
    intent. It said that Black’s language—“‘“True threats” encompass those statements where
    the speaker means to communicate a serious expression of an intent to commit an act of
    unlawful violence’”—conveys “only that a defendant ‘means to communicate’ when she
    knowingly says the words.” Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 480 (quoting Black, 
    538 U.S. at 359
    );
    accord Martinez, 736 F.3d at 987; Elonis, 730 F.3d at 329; White, 
    670 F.3d at
    508–09.
    Perhaps. There is certainly some ambiguity in the language quoted from Black about
    what the speaker must intend. But the natural reading is that the speaker intends to
    19
    convey everything following the phrase means to communicate, see Cassel, 
    408 F.3d at 631
    ; White, 
    670 F.3d at 522
     (Floyd, J., dissenting), rather than just to convey words that
    someone else would interpret as a “‘serious expression of an intent to commit an act of
    unlawful violence,’” Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 480. And later in the same paragraph of Black
    two sentences resolve any ambiguity. The sentence immediately after the quote is, “The
    speaker need not actually intend to carry out the threat.” Black, 
    538 U.S. at
    359–60. The
    proposition that the speaker need not intend to carry out the threat is a helpful
    qualification if there is a requirement that the defendant intend the victim to feel
    threatened. See White, 
    670 F.3d at 522
     (Floyd J., dissenting). But no such qualification
    is called for if the preceding sentence means that the only requisite mens rea is that the
    defendant “knowingly says the words.” Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 480. Once it is established
    that the sole requisite intent is to say the (threatening) words, no reasonable person (juror)
    would then need to be informed that the defendant need not intend to carry out the threat.
    If there is no requirement that the defendant intend the victim to feel threatened, it would
    be bizarre to argue that the defendant must still intend to carry out the threat.
    A later sentence in the paragraph is still more definitive about Black’s meaning.
    It says, “Intimidation in the constitutionally proscribable sense of the word is a type of
    true threat, where a speaker directs a threat to a person or group of persons with the intent
    of placing the victim in fear of bodily harm or death.” Black, 
    538 U.S. at 360
     (emphasis
    added). The Court was not referring to intimidation as defined by the Virginia statute or
    even as it might be defined by other statutes, but the meaning that is required by the First
    20
    Amendment. Jeffries did not dispute that this sentence means that intimidation cannot be
    proscribed unless the speaker utters the threatening words “with the intent of placing the
    victim in fear of bodily harm or death.” 692 F.3d at 480 (internal quotation marks
    omitted). Rather, it disposed of the sentence by saying that it only “shows that
    intimidation is one ‘type of true threat,’ a reality that does little to inform § 875(c), which
    prohibits all types of threats to injure a person.” Id.; accord Elonis, 730 F.3d at 329 n.4
    (“[T]his sentence explains when intimidation can be a true threat, and does not define
    when threatening language is a true threat.”); Martinez, 736 F.3d at 987 (“[T]he general
    class of true threats does not require such an inquiry . . . . After all, intimidation is but
    one type of true threat . . . . [E]xplicitly requiring subjective intent for one discrete type
    of true threat makes little sense if the Court intended all true threats to require such
    intent.”). Yet why should the First Amendment require a subjective intent for
    intimidation but not other true threats? See White, 
    670 F.3d at 522
     (Floyd, J., dissenting).
    Nothing in Black so much as hints at a reason for such a distinction. What is it about
    nonintimidation threats that makes them so much worse than threats of bodily harm or
    death that the First Amendment allows them to be prosecuted even when the speaker did
    not intend to instill fear? One would have thought the opposite—that there should be less
    First Amendment protection for threats of bodily harm or death. The sentence in Black
    about “intimidation” is best read as merely applying the propositions stated earlier in the
    paragraph to the specific statute before the Court.
    21
    Jeffries found further support for an objective standard in the rationale for denying
    First Amendment protection to true threats:
    While the First Amendment generally permits individuals to say what they
    wish, it allows government to “protect[ ] individuals” from the effects of
    some words—“from the fear of violence, from the disruption that fear
    engenders, and from the possibility that the threatened violence will occur.”
    R.A.V., 
    505 U.S. at 377, 388
    ; Black, 
    538 U.S. at 344
    . What is excluded
    from First Amendment protection—threats rooted in their effect on the
    listener—works well with a test that focuses not on the intent of the speaker
    but on the effect on a reasonable listener of the speech.
    692 F.3d at 480 (citations modified); accord Martinez, 736 F.3d at 987–88; Elonis, 730
    F.3d at 329–30. Well said. But to say that the effect on the listener supports a “threat”
    exception to the freedom of speech does not mean that no other considerations come into
    play. For example, it may be worth protecting speech that creates fear when the speaker
    intends only to convey a political message. As we understand Black, the Supreme Court
    has said as much. When the speaker does not intend to instill fear, concern for the effect
    on the listener must yield.
    In short, despite arguments to the contrary, we adhere to the view that Black
    required the district court in this case to find that Defendant intended to instill fear before
    it could convict him of violating 
    18 U.S.C. § 875
    (c).3
    3
    Of course, as stated by the First Circuit, “[I]t is rare that a jury would find that a
    reasonable speaker would have intended a threat under the particular facts of a case but
    that a competent defendant did not.” Blum v. Holder, 
    744 F.3d 790
    , 802 n.17 (1st Cir.
    2014) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    22
    III.   CONCLUSION
    We REVERSE Defendant’s conviction and REMAND for the district court to
    determine whether he intended his e-mail to be threatening.
    23
    United States v. Heineman, No. 13-4043
    BALDOCK, J., concurring in the judgment only.
    The interstate transmission of “any communication containing . . . any threat to injure
    the person of another” is a federal crime. 
    18 U.S.C. § 875
    (c). The question presented in this
    case is whether § 875(c) requires the Government to prove a defendant’s subjective intent
    to threaten. The court concludes the First Amendment requires such proof. But to my mind
    we should resolve this case without resorting to the First Amendment by simply construing
    the statute’s text.   Indeed, we are duty bound not to reach constitutional questions
    unnecessarily even if the parties ask us to do so. See Ulster Cnty. Court v. Allen, 
    442 U.S. 140
    , 154 (1979) (recognizing federal courts have a “strong duty to avoid constitutional issues
    that need not be resolved”). Accordingly, I respectfully decline to join the court’s opinion.
    I.
    In Clark v. Martinez, 
    543 U.S. 371
     (2005), the Supreme Court explained that “when
    deciding which of two plausible statutory constructions to adopt, a court must consider the
    necessary consequences of its choice.        If one of them would raise a multitude of
    constitutional problems, the other should prevail.” 
    Id.
     at 380–81. This is the canon
    of constitutional avoidance. The canon “is a tool for choosing between competing plausible
    interpretations of a statutory text, resting on the reasonable presumption that Congress
    did not intend the alternative which raises serious constitutional doubts.” 
    Id. at 381
    .
    Importantly, however, “[t]he canon of constitutional avoidance comes into play only when,
    after the application of ordinary textual analysis, the statute is found to be susceptible of
    more than one construction.” 
    Id. at 385
     (emphasis added). Therein lies the fundamental
    problem with this court’s opinion. The court undertakes no “ordinary textual analysis” of
    § 875(c), but simply states “[t]he statutory language contains no mens rea requirement” and
    proceeds to engage the Constitution from the outset. Court’s Op. at 4. After telling us
    it “will read into § 875(c) any scienter necessary to satisfy the demands of the First
    Amendment,” the court identifies the only question before us as whether “the First
    Amendment . . . requires the government to prove in any true-threat prosecution that the
    defendant intended the recipient to feel threatened.” Id. at 5, 10. The court undoubtedly
    applies the canon of constitutional avoidance prematurely, and perhaps unnecessarily.
    The Supreme Court’s recent grant of the petition for a writ of certiorari in United
    States v. Elonis, 
    730 F.3d 321
     (3d Cir. 2013), cert. granted, 
    134 S. Ct. 2819
     (2014), is telling.
    The only question raised in the petition (the same question this court insists on answering)
    is “[w]hether, consistent with the First Amendment . . . , conviction of threatening another
    person [in violation of 
    18 U.S.C. § 875
    (c)] requires proof of the defendant’s subjective
    intent to threaten . . . ; or whether it is enough to show that a ‘reasonable person’ would
    regard the statement as threatening . . . .” Petition for a Writ of Cert., Elonis, 
    2014 WL 645438
     (No. 13-983) (2014). Importantly, however, in its order granting the petition, the
    Court directed the parties to brief and argue an additional question: “Whether, as a matter
    of statutory interpretation, conviction of threatening another person under 
    18 U.S.C. § 875
    (c)
    requires proof of the defendant’s subjective intent to threaten.” Elonis, 134 S. Ct. at 2819.
    The Supreme Court’s order granting the petition in Elonis reinforces what Clark teaches us,
    namely that in interpreting § 875(c) we must first ask what its text requires rather than what
    2
    the Constitution demands. One need not be an oracle to understand what the Supreme Court
    first wants to know. And what the Supreme Court wants we should endeavor to provide.1
    II.
    This court says in footnote 2 of its opinion that two circuit precedents, namely our
    decisions in United States v. Dysart, 
    705 F.2d 1247
     (10th Cir. 1983), and United States v.
    Viefhaus, 
    168 F.3d 392
    , 395–96 (10th Cir. 1999), preclude us from deciding by way of
    ordinary textual analysis what sort of intent § 875(c) requires. Not so. We have never
    considered whether § 875(c) requires proof of a defendant’s subjective intent to threaten. We
    have never even once held the term “threat” as used elsewhere in the criminal code excludes
    a defendant’s subjective intent.
    Dysart involved a prosecution under 
    18 U.S.C. § 871
    , which proscribes threats against
    the President. To be sure, in Dysart the defendant argued “the trial court erred in failing to
    charge that for conviction under § 871, it must be shown that [the defendant] intended the
    letter to be taken as a threat.” Dysart, 705 F.2d at 1256. But a careful reading of Dysart
    1
    My initial response to the grant of certiorari in Elonis, given its nearly identical
    stature to this case, was to ponder whether we should decide this case now. Certainly, where
    a defendant is in custody, to delay a decision in favor of such defendant might be unfair
    notwithstanding a relevant grant of certiorari. But here, Defendant Heineman received a
    sentence of three years probation. Just last month, the district court reduced Defendant’s
    sentence to two years probation. United States v. Heineman, No. 11-CR-432-DN, Corrected
    Order at 1 (D. Utah Aug. 8, 2014). Defendant has approximately six months left to serve.
    Today’s judgment is no guarantee that Defendant will be free from state supervision anytime
    soon because the Government may choose to apply for certiorari or retry him. I see little
    need of rendering an opinion here when the Supreme Court had granted certiorari in another
    case that in all likelihood will resolve the matter before us. But because this court forces my
    hand, I too shall play my cards—for better or worse.
    3
    reveals we never held otherwise. Instead, we explained that § 871 “requires that the
    Government must prove a ‘true “threat”’, and the instructions given by the trial court met this
    requirement.” Id. at 1256 (internal citation omitted). Those instructions, in addition to
    stating that the recipient must reasonably perceive the communication as threatening,
    elsewhere defined the term “threat” as an “avowed present determination or intent to injure
    presently or in the future,” and required the prosecution to establish “a serious threat as
    distinguished from words as mere political argument, talk or jest.” Id. The instructions also
    required consideration of “the context in which [the words] were spoken,” not the context in
    which they were heard. Id. (emphasis added). In short, the instructions which we approved
    in Dysart included a subjective intent component: that the speaker intend his threat be taken
    seriously, as opposed to in jest.2
    In Viefhaus, by contrast, the defendant never argued 
    18 U.S.C. § 844
    (e), which
    proscribes bomb threats, requires proof of a defendant’s subjective intent to threaten. Rather,
    the defendant argued “his comments amounted only to ‘vulgar political speech’” protected
    by the First Amendment. Viefhaus, 
    168 F.3d at 395
    . We rejected that argument by
    distinguishing a “true threat” from political speech based on its effect on the listener, much
    like the Supreme Court did in Watts v. United States, 
    394 U.S. 705
     (1969). Importantly,
    2
    The court relies on Dysart’s rejection of the defendant’s subjective intent argument
    without ever acknowledging why we rejected that argument. We rejected that argument
    because the instructions as written already required proof of the defendant’s subjective intent
    to threaten. Specifically, we rejected the contention “that the instructions did not avoid the
    risk of conviction for a crude jest or expression of political hostility,” because that contention
    “is clearly untenable in light of the explicit guidance on that point found in the instructions.”
    Dysart, 705 F.2d at 1256.
    4
    Viefhaus never addressed whether § 844(e) lacks a subjective intent component. In fact, our
    words suggest otherwise:
    A “true threat” means “a serious threat as distinguished from words as mere
    political argument, idle talk or jest.” United States v. Leaverton, 
    835 F.2d 254
    ,
    257 (10th Cir. 1987). We have previously defined “threat” by referencing the
    language of Black’s Law Dictionary. See 
    id.
     at 256–57. We again rely on that
    definition, but elaborate on the meaning of “intent” as it is used in that
    definition. Thus, we define “threat” as a declaration of intention, purpose,
    design, goal, or determination to inflict punishment, loss, or pain on another,
    or to injure another or his property by the commission of some unlawful act.
    See Black’s Law Dictionary 1480 (6th ed. 1990); Webster’s Third New Int’l
    Dictionary (unabridged) 1176 (1993). It is not necessary to show that
    defendant intended to carry out the threat, nor is it necessary to prove he had
    the apparent ability to carry out the threat. The question is whether those who
    hear or read the threat reasonably consider that an actual threat has been
    made. It is the making of the threat and not the intention to carry out the threat
    that violates the law.
    Viefhaus, 
    168 F.3d at
    395–96 (emphasis in original).
    Similar to the definition we approved in Dysart, our definition of a “threat” in
    Viefhaus implicitly contains a subjective intent component. The italicized statement
    appearing in the original cannot be read in isolation from the remainder of the text and, in
    particular, the sentences immediately preceding and succeeding it. Taken in context, that
    statement merely expresses our (correct) view that a defendant need not intend to carry out
    the threat or even have the apparent ability to do so. In no sense does the italicized statement
    suggest the Government need not prove a defendant’s subjective intent to threaten as part of
    a § 844(e) prosecution.
    But regardless of how one chooses to read our precedents—lest any doubt remain—
    I am aware of no Supreme Court or Tenth Circuit decision that says a court’s interpretation
    5
    of a term in one statute binds its interpretation of the same term in a different statute. In
    Hackwell v. United States, 
    491 F.3d 1229
    , 1235 (10th Cir. 2007), we explained that “[w]hile
    there is no per se rule of statutory interpretation that identical words used in different statutes
    are intended to have the same meaning, we will nevertheless look at a statute’s relationship
    to other statutes to determine Congress’s intent.” (internal quotations omitted). See also
    Envtl. Def. v. Duke Energy Corp., 
    549 U.S. 561
    , 574 (2007). What this means for present
    purposes is that any construction we may have given the word “threat” in a statute other than
    § 875(c) is merely one facet of a comprehensive textual analysis of § 875(c), not an excuse
    to forego such analysis altogether. Plainly then, Tenth Circuit precedent does not preclude
    us from undertaking a textual analysis of § 875(c) in the first instance.
    III.
    As noted in the court’s opinion, a number of our sister circuits recently have addressed
    the meaning of § 875(c). See Court’s Op. at 17–18. Oddly enough, however, Judge Sutton
    is the only circuit judge to date to address the question the Supreme Court now wants
    answered. In his separate dubitante opinion in Jeffries, Judge Sutton asks why the circuit
    courts have routinely construed § 875(c) “through the prism of free-speech principles” and,
    in particular, the Supreme Court’s splintered decision in Virginia v. Black, 
    538 U.S. 343
    (2003), without first simply construing its text.3 United States v. Jeffries, 
    692 F.3d 473
    , 485
    3
    Judge Sutton also authored the Sixth Circuit’s opinion in Jeffries. Because the Sixth
    Circuit previously had held § 875(c) does not require proof of subjective intent, the court was
    required to address Jeffries’ argument that the First Amendment, via Black, invalidated all
    communicative-threat laws failing to do so. Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 483 (Sutton, J., dubitante).
    6
    (6th Cir. 2012) (Sutton, J., dubitante). “The statute should require first what the words say
    . . . .” Id. Only if our construction of § 875(c)’s text raises constitutional concerns need we
    ask what constitutional avoidance principles require.
    Judge Sutton’s dubitante opinion first addresses the wording of § 875(c), then its
    history, and finally background norms for construing criminal statutes.           That is, he
    undertakes an ordinary textual analysis of § 875(c). Applying these “conventional indicators
    of meaning,” id., Judge Sutton comes to but one conclusion: In a case such as this, where
    everyone agrees the intent element of § 875(c) contains an objective component, see Watts,
    
    394 U.S. at 708
    , courts need not rely on the First Amendment to interpret § 875(c) because
    the statute as written already requires the Government to prove a defendant’s subjective
    intent to threaten. Courts relying on Black to construe § 875(c) have placed the cart before
    the horse.
    As to the meaning of the word “threat” itself, Judge Sutton points out—
    Every relevant definition of the noun “threat” or the verb “threaten,” whether
    in existence when Congress passed the law (1932) or today, includes an intent
    component. “To declare (usually conditionally) one’s intention of inflicting
    injury upon” a person, says one dictionary. 11 Oxford English Dictionary 352
    (1st ed. 1933). “An expression of an intention to inflict loss or harm on
    another by illegal means, esp. when effecting coercion or duress of the person
    threatened,” says another. Webster’s New Int’l Dictionary 2633 (2d ed. 1955).
    “A communicated intent to inflict harm or loss on another,” says still another.
    Black’s Law Dictionary 1489 (7th ed. 1999). And so on: “An expression of
    intention to inflict pain, injury, evil, or punishment.” American Heritage
    Dictionary of the English Language 1801 (4th ed. 2000). And on: “An
    expression of intention to inflict something harmful.” Webster’s New College
    Dictionary 1149 (1995). And on: “A declaration of an intention or
    determination to inflict punishment, injury, etc., in retaliation for, or
    conditionally upon, some action or course.” Random House Unabridged
    Dictionary 1975 (2d ed. 1987).
    7
    ***
    If words matter, I am hardpressed to understand why these definitions do not
    resolve today’s case. These definitions, all of them, show that subjective intent
    is part and parcel of the meaning of a communicated “threat” to injure
    another.
    Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 483–84 (Sutton, J., dubitante) (internal brackets omitted) (emphasis
    added). In other words, the dictionary definition of the word “threat” connotes subjective
    intent. One may cause another to “feel threatened” through an act of mere jest or even
    negligence (an objective inquiry), but one cannot “threaten” another without intending to do
    so (a subjective inquiry).
    Of course, Judge Sutton’s definitional analysis is not immune from challenge. As
    Justice Frankfurter once commented: “All our work . . . is a matter of semantics.”4 Notably,
    for instance, when defining a “true threat” in Black, the Supreme Court added language to
    the aforementioned dictionary definitions, perhaps to emphasize that subjective intent was
    part and parcel of that phrase.5 Compare Black’s Law Dictionary 1489 (7th ed. 1999)
    4
    “All our work, our whole life is a matter of semantics, because words are the tools
    with which we work, the materials out of which laws are made . . . . Everything depends on
    our understanding of them.” William T. Coleman, Counsel for the Situation: Shaping the
    Law to Realize America’s Promise 78 (2010) (quoting Justice Frankfurter).
    5
    In Black, the Court explained that the reasons why the First Amendment does not
    shield “true threats” is to protect individuals “‘from the fear of violence’ and ‘from the
    disruption that fear engenders,’ in addition to protecting people ‘from the possibility that the
    threatened violence will occur.’” Black, 
    538 U.S. at 360
     (quoting R.A.V. vs. City of St. Paul,
    
    505 U.S. 375
    , 388 (1992)). The first two reasons lend themselves well to an objective intent
    standard that asks how a reasonable person would perceive the “threat.” The third reason,
    however, suggests the First Amendment may require the Government to prove subjective
    intent as part of any § 875(c) prosecution. If the culprit lacks a subjective intent to threaten,
    the possibility the threatened violence will occur seems at best rather remote.
    8
    (defining threat only as “[a] communicated intent to inflict harm”), with Black, 
    538 U.S. at 359
     (defining threat as “where the speaker means to communicate a serious expression of
    an intent to commit an act of unlawful violence . . . .” (emphasis added)). This arguably
    suggests dictionary definitions of a “threat” alone do not encompass the necessary subjective
    intent, or at least that the Supreme Court may not believe so. But, as Judge Sutton forcefully
    points out, any ambiguity in the dictionary definitions of “threat” is surely overcome by
    1) the history of § 875, which from the beginning possessed a subjective intent component,
    originally, the “intent to extort,” and 2) the background norms for construing criminal
    statutes, which “presume that intent [i.e. something more than negligence] is the required
    mens rea in criminal laws.” Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 484 (Sutton, J., dubitante).
    Judge Sutton’s analysis of the word “threat” as it appears in § 875(c) leads me to
    believe we too have placed the cart before the horse. At the very least, this court should tell
    us why Judge Sutton’s view does not carry the day when the Supreme Court seems to think
    it might.
    9