Forum for Academic & Institutional Rights v. Rumsfeld , 390 F.3d 219 ( 2004 )


Menu:
  •                                                                                                                            Opinions of the United
    2004 Decisions                                                                                                             States Court of Appeals
    for the Third Circuit
    11-29-2004
    Forum Academic v. Secretary Defense
    Precedential or Non-Precedential: Precedential
    Docket No. 03-4433P
    Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.villanova.edu/thirdcircuit_2004
    Recommended Citation
    "Forum Academic v. Secretary Defense" (2004). 2004 Decisions. Paper 104.
    http://digitalcommons.law.villanova.edu/thirdcircuit_2004/104
    This decision is brought to you for free and open access by the Opinions of the United States Court of Appeals for the Third Circuit at Villanova
    University School of Law Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in 2004 Decisions by an authorized administrator of Villanova
    University School of Law Digital Repository. For more information, please contact Benjamin.Carlson@law.villanova.edu.
    PRECEDENTIAL
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE THIRD CIRCUIT
    No. 03-4433
    FORUM FOR ACADEMIC AND INSTITUTIONAL
    RIGHTS, a New Jersey membership corporation;
    SOCIETY OF AM ERICAN LAW TEACHERS, INC.,
    a New York corporation; COALITION FOR EQUALITY, a
    Massachusetts association; RUTGERS GAY AND LESBIAN
    CAUCUS, a New Jersey association;
    PAM NICKISHER, a New Jersey resident; LESLIE
    FISCHER, a Pennsylvania resident; MICHAEL
    BLAUSCHILD, a New Jersey resident; ERW IN
    CHEMERINSKY, a California resident; SYLVIA LAW , a
    New York resident,
    Appellants
    v.
    DONALD H. RUMSFELD, in his capacity as U.S. Secretary
    of Defense; ROD PAIGE, in his capacity as U. S. Secretary of
    Education; ELAINE CHAO, in her capacity as U.S. Secretary
    of Labor; TOMMY THOMPSON, in his capacity as U.S.
    Secretary of Health and Human Services; NORMAN Y.
    MINETA, in his capacity as U.S. Secretary of Transportation;
    TOM RIDGE, in his capacity as U.S. Secretary of Homeland
    Security
    Appeal from the United States District Court
    for the District of New Jersey
    (D.C. Civil Action No. 03-cv-04433)
    District Judge: Honorable John C. Lifland
    Argued June 30, 2004
    Before: AMBRO, ALDISERT and STAPLETON,
    Circuit Judges
    (Opinion filed November 29, 2004 )
    E. Joshua Rosenkranz, Esquire (Argued)
    Timothy P. Wei, Esquire
    Sharon E. Frase, Esquire
    Heller, Ehrman, White & McAuliffe LLP
    120 West 45th Street, 20th Floor
    New York, NY 10036-4041
    Warrington S. Parker, III, Esquire
    Aaron M. Armstrong, Esquire
    Benjamin D. Hauser, Esquire
    Heller, Ehrman, White & McAuliffe LLP
    333 Bush Street
    San Francisco, CA 94104-2878
    Attorneys for Appellants
    2
    Peter D. Keisler
    Assistant Attorney General
    Christopher J. Christie
    United State Attorney
    Gregory G. Katsas (Argued)
    Deputy Assistant Attorney General
    Douglas N. Letter, Esquire
    Scott R. McIntosh, Esquire
    United States Department of Justice
    Civil Division, Appellate Staff
    601 D Street, N.W., Room 9550
    Washington, DC 20530
    George S. Leone, Esquire
    Office of the United States Attorney
    970 Broad Street, Room 700
    Newark, NJ 07102
    Attorneys for Appellees
    Paul M. Smith, Esquire (Argued)
    William M . Hohengarten, Esquire
    Daniel Mach, Esquire
    Jenner & Block, Suite 1200 South
    601 13th Street, N.W., 12th Floor
    Washington, DC 20005
    Philip G. Gallagher, Esquire
    Lawrence S. Lustberg, Esquire
    Jonathan L. Hafetz, Esquire
    Gibbons, Del Deo, Dolan, Griffinger & Vecchione
    3
    One Pennsylvania Plaza, 37th Floor
    New York, NY 10119
    Stuart D. Rosen, Esquire
    Bingham McCutchen
    One State Street
    Hartford, CT 06103
    Jonathan A. Kenter, Esquire
    Bingham McCutchen LLP
    399 Park Avenue
    New York, NY 10022
    Tyler M. Paetkau, Esquire
    Melissa J. Goldberg, Esquire
    Bingham McCutchen LLP
    Three Embarcadero Center
    San Francisco, CA 94111
    Walter E. Dellinger, III, Esquire (Argued)
    Pamela Harris, Esquire
    O’Melveny & M yers
    1625 Eye Street, N.W.
    Washington, DC 20006
    Hilary E. Ball, Esquire
    Sam Heldman, Esquire
    Gardner, Middlebrooks, Gibbons, Kittrell & Olsen
    2805 31st Street, N.W.
    Washington, DC 20008
    4
    David M. Rabban, Esquire
    University of Texas School of Law
    727 East Dean Keeton Street
    Austin, TX 78705
    Ann D. Springer, Esquire
    Donna R. Euben, Esquire
    American Association of University Professors
    1012 Fourteenth Street, N.W., Suite 500
    Washington, DC 20005
    John L. Moore, Jr., Esquire
    Louis J. Rouleau, Esquire
    Piper Rudnick LLP
    1200 Nineteenth Street, N.W.
    Washington, DC 20036
    E. O’Brien Kelley, Esquire
    Darren G. Gibson, Esquire
    Piper Rudnick LLP
    1251 Avenue of the Americas
    New York, NY 10020
    Attorneys for Amicus-Appellants
    Howard J. Bashman, Esquire (Argued)
    1250 Virginia Drive
    Suite 1000
    Fort Washington, PA 19034
    5
    Steven W . Fitschen, Esquire
    The National Legal Foundation
    2224 Virginia Beach Boulevard
    Suite 204
    Virginia Beach, VA 23454
    Attorneys for Amicus-Appellees
    OPINION OF THE COURT
    Ambro, Circuit Judge
    The Solomon Amendment, 
    10 U.S.C. § 983
    , requires
    the United States Department of Defense (“DOD”) to deny
    federal funding to institutions of higher education that
    prohibit military representatives access to and assistance for
    recruiting purposes. Last fall, the Forum for Academic and
    Institutional Rights, Inc. (“FAIR”), 1 an association of law
    1
    Joining FAIR in its preliminary injunction motion and in this
    appeal are: the Society for Law Teachers, Inc.; the Coalition for
    Equality; Rutgers Gay and Lesbian Caucus; law professors
    Erwin Chemerinsky and Sylvia Law; and law students Pam
    Nickisher, Leslie Fischer, Ph.D., and Michael Blauschild. For
    convenience, we refer to all plaintiff-appellants collectively as
    “FAIR.”
    6
    schools and law faculty, asked the United States District
    Court for the District of New Jersey to enjoin enforcement of
    the Solomon Amendment. The District Court denied FAIR’s
    motion. Forum for Academic & Institutional Rights, Inc. v.
    Rumsfeld, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d 269
     (D.N.J. 2003) (“FAIR”). On
    appeal, we hold that FAIR has demonstrated a likelihood of
    success on the merits of its First Amendment claims and that
    it is entitled to preliminary injunctive relief. Accordingly, we
    reverse.
    I.   Background Facts 2 and Procedural Posture
    A.        Law Schools’ Nondiscrimination Policies
    Law schools have long maintained formal policies of
    nondiscrimination that withhold career placement services
    from employers who exclude employees and applicants based
    on such factors as race, gender, and religion. In the 1970s law
    schools began expanding these policies to prohibit
    discrimination based on sexual orientation as well. In
    response to this trend the American Association of Law
    Schools (“AALS”) voted unanimously in 1990 to include
    sexual orientation as a protected category. As a result,
    2
    The facts on appeal are not in dispute. As the District Court
    noted, the Government did not challenge or supplement the
    factual assertions presented by FAIR in its motion for injunctive
    relief. FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at 277
    .
    7
    virtually every law school now has a comprehensive policy
    like the following:
    [The] School of Law is committed to a policy of
    equal opportunity for all students and graduates.
    The Career Services facilities of this school
    shall not be available to those employers who
    discriminate on the grounds of race, color,
    religion, national origin, sex, handicap or
    disability, age, or sexual orientation . . . .
    Before using any of the Career Services
    interviewing facilities of this school, an
    employer shall be required to submit a signed
    statement certifying that its practices conform to
    this policy.
    B.       Congress Passes the Solomon Amendment
    The United States military excludes servicemembers
    based on evidence of homosexual conduct and/or orientation.
    See 
    10 U.S.C. § 654.3
     Citing their nondiscrimination policies,
    3
    While the current statutory version of the military’s
    exclusionary policy has existed since 1993, National Defense
    Authorization Act for Fiscal Year 1994, Pub. L. No. 103-160, §
    571(a)(1), 
    107 Stat. 1547
    , 1670 (Nov. 30, 1993), the military has
    had formal regulatory policies excluding gays and lesbians since
    World War I and a practice of such exclusion since the
    8
    some law schools began in the 1980s refusing to provide
    access and assistance to military recruiters. This caught the
    attention of members of Congress. In 1994, Representative
    Gerald Solomon of New York sponsored an amendment to
    the annual defense appropriation bill that proposed to
    withhold DOD funding from any educational institution with
    a policy of denying or effectively preventing the military from
    obtaining entry to campuses (or access to students on
    campuses) for recruiting purposes. National Defense
    Authorization Act for Fiscal Year 1995, Pub. L. No. 103-337
    Revolutionary War. See, e.g., Articles of War of 1916, Pub. L.
    No. 242, art. 93, 
    39 Stat. 619
    , 664 (assault with intent to commit
    sodomy punishable by court martial); see generally Randy
    Shilts, Conduct Unbecoming: Gays & Lesbians in the U.S.
    Military 11–17 (1994).
    Under the current statute, a servicemember is separated
    from the military if it is found that he or she “engaged in . . . a
    homosexual act” or “stated that he or she is a homosexual” or
    “married or attempted to marry a person known to be of the
    same biological sex.” 
    10 U.S.C. § 654
    (b). It defines
    “homosexual” and “homosexual act” to include evidence
    demonstrating “a propensity or intent to engage in homosexual
    acts.” 
    Id.
     It also allows servicemembers to rebut findings of
    proscribed conduct with evidence of the lack of a propensity to
    engage in homosexual conduct, i.e., evidence of a heterosexual
    orientation. 
    Id.
     Law schools interpret the ban as conflicting
    with their policies against discrimination on the basis of sexual
    orientation.
    9
    § 558, 
    108 Stat. 2663
    , 2776 (1994).
    During debate in the House of Representatives,
    Representative Solomon urged the passage of his amendment
    “on behalf of military preparedness” because “recruiting is the
    key to an all-volunteer military.” 140 Cong. Rec. H3861
    (daily ed. May 23, 1994). He argued that it was hypocritical
    for schools to receive federal money while at the same time
    denying the military access to their campuses: “[T]ell[]
    recipients of Federal money at colleges and universities that if
    you do not like the Armed Forces, if you do not like its
    policies, that is fine. That is your [F]irst [A]mendment
    right[]. But do not expect Federal dollars to support your
    interference with our military recruiters.” 
    Id.
     The
    amendment’s co-sponsor, Representative Richard Pombo of
    California, said Congress needed to target “policies of
    ambivalence or hostility to our Nation’s armed services” that
    are “nothing less than a backhanded slap at the honor and
    dignity of service in our Nation’s Armed Forces.” 
    Id.
     at
    H3863. He urged his colleagues to “send a message over the
    wall of the ivory tower of higher education” that colleges’ and
    universities’ “starry-eyed idealism comes with a price. If they
    are too good—or too righteous—to treat our Nation’s military
    with the respect it deserves[,] then they may also be too good
    to receive the generous level of taxpayer dollars presently
    enjoyed by many institutions of higher education in America.”
    
    Id.
    10
    Other Representatives opposed the amendment,
    alleging violations of academic freedom and civil rights. See,
    e.g., 
    id.
     at H3862 (Rep. Dellums) (“We should not . . . chill or
    abridge privacy, speech, or conscience by threatening a
    college with a Federal funds termination because it chose for
    whatever reason to deny access to military recruiters . . . . We
    should not browbeat them . . . into becoming involuntary
    agents of Federal policy.”). In light of Vietnam War-era
    legislation, rarely invoked, that already granted the DOD
    discretion to withhold funding from colleges and universities
    that barred military recruiters, see Pub. L. No. 92-436, § 606,
    
    86 Stat. 734
    , 740 (1972), the DOD itself objected to the
    proposed amendment as “unnecessary” and “duplicative.” 140
    Cong. Rec. H3864 (Rep. Schroeder) (explaining the DOD’s
    position). The DOD also feared that withholding funds from
    universities could be potentially harmful to defense research
    initiatives. 
    Id.
     But the House voted for the amendment by a
    vote of 271 to 126. 
    Id.
     at H3865. Several months later the
    Senate approved the defense spending appropriations bill,
    including Representative Solomon’s amendment, and the
    “Solomon Amendment” ultimately became law.
    C.     Subsequent Amendments and Regulatory
    Interpretations
    In 1997 Congress amended the Solomon Amendment
    by expanding its penalty to include, in addition to DOD funds,
    funds administered by other federal agencies, including the
    11
    Departments of Transportation,4 Labor, Health and Human
    Services, and Education.5 Omnibus Consolidated
    Appropriations Act, 1997, Pub. L. No. 104–208, § 514(b),
    
    110 Stat. 3009
    –270 (1996). This amendment was recodified
    in another amendment in 1999. National Defense
    Authorization Act for Fiscal Year 2000, Pub. L. No. 106–65,
    § 549, 
    113 Stat. 512
    , 609–11 (1999). DOD regulations have
    clarified this expansion, penalizing an offending
    “subelement” of a college or university (i.e., a law school)
    that prohibits or effectively prevents military recruiting with
    the loss of federal funding from all of the federal agencies
    identified in the statute, while withholding from the offending
    subelement’s parent institution only DOD funds. 
    32 C.F.R. § 216.3
    (b)(1).
    The 1999 amendment also codified exceptions to the
    Solomon Amendment’s penalties for schools that (1) have
    ceased an offending policy or practice, or (2) have a
    longstanding religious-based policy of pacifism. § 549, 113
    4
    Department of Homeland Security funds later replaced
    Department of Transportation funds. Pub. L. No. 107-296,
    § 1704(b)(1), 
    116 Stat. 2314
     (2002).
    5
    A separate amendment cancelled the application of the
    Solomon Amendment to direct student aid. Department of
    Defense Appropriations Act of 2000, § 8120, Pub. L. No. 106-
    79, 
    113 Stat. 1212
    , 1260 (1999).
    12
    Stat. at 610(c) (codified at 
    10 U.S.C. § 983
    (c)). DOD
    regulations subsequently added a third exception for schools
    that provide military recruiters a degree of access equal to that
    provided to other recruiters. 
    32 C.F.R. § 216.4
    (c).
    Following the 1999 amendment, the DOD enforced the
    Solomon Amendment consistent with its terms. Only schools
    whose policies or practices “prohibit[ed], or in effect
    prevent[ed],” military representatives “from gaining entry to
    campuses, or access to students . . . on campuses for purposes
    of military recruiting,” were penalized. Thus, by merely
    allowing military recruiters to gain access to campuses, many
    law schools avoided the Solomon Amendment’s penalty while
    reaffirming their opposition to the military’s exclusionary
    employment policy by not providing them affirmative
    assistance in the manner provided to other recruiters. Harvard
    Law School, for example, allowed military recruiters on
    campus to recruit at the offices of its Veterans Association but
    did not volunteer its placement personnel to arrange
    interviews. Boston College Law School allowed military
    recruiters to conduct on-campus interviews, but kept their
    literature in the library rather than in the career services
    office. Until the fall of 2001, the DOD did not consider these
    and other similar “ameliorative measures” to violate the
    Solomon Amendment and expressed enthusiasm for the law
    schools’ cooperation with what it described as successful
    recruiting efforts. See FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at
    282 (citing
    record evidence).
    13
    But following the terrorist attacks in the United States
    in September 2001, the DOD began applying an informal
    policy of requiring not only access to campuses, but treatment
    equal to that accorded other recruiters. As evidence of this
    informal policy, a letter from the DOD’s Acting Deputy
    Undersecretary William J. Carr to Richard Levin, the
    President of Yale University, stated that universities are
    required “to provide military recruiters access to students
    equal in quality and scope to that provided to other
    recruiters.” 6 The same letter stated that the “DOD requires
    that there not be a substantial disparity in the treatment of
    military recruiters as compared to other potential employers.”
    This changed context meant that Yale’s willingness to let
    military recruiters use a room in Yale Law School’s building
    for interviews would not pass muster unless it also provided
    military recruiters with the same level of assistance from its
    career development office (arranging interviews, posting
    notices, etc.) provided to other recruiters. Furthermore, the
    DOD intimated that failure to comply would result in a loss to
    6
    In wording the new informal policy’s substantive
    requirement, the DOD borrowed language from the existing
    policy’s regulatory exception—32 C.F.R. 216.4(c) (exempting
    from Solomon Act compliance a law school that “presents
    evidence that the degree of access by military recruiters is at
    least equal in quality and scope to that afforded to other
    employers”).
    14
    Yale University not only of DOD funds, but of all federal
    funds (a penalty that is not consistent with the DOD’s existing
    regulations, under which the offending subelement’s parent
    institution is penalized with the loss of only DOD funds, see
    
    32 C.F.R. § 216.3
    (b)(1)).
    In another example, the DOD advised the University of
    Southern California Law School in 2002 that its past practice
    of accommodating military recruiters—providing them with
    standard employer information, referring them to the campus
    ROTC office for scheduling of interview office space, posting
    notices in the weekly newsletter for students, and making
    military recruitment materials available to students—would
    violate the Solomon Amendment unless its career services
    office invited military recruiters to participate in an off-
    campus job fair open to other employers. According to the
    DOD, anything less than equal treatment for military
    recruiters “sends the message that employment in the Armed
    Forces is less honorable or desirable than employment with
    other organizations”—a dangerous message to be sending “in
    today’s military climate.” In light of the millions of dollars at
    stake, every law school that receives federal funds had, by the
    2003 recruiting season, suspended its nondiscrimination
    policy as applied to military recruiters.
    This past summer Congress amended the Solomon
    Amendment to codify the DOD’s informal policy. Ronald W.
    Reagan National Defense Authorization Act for Fiscal Year
    15
    2005, Pub. L. No. 108–375, § 552, 
    118 Stat. 1811
    , 1911
    (2004). Now, under the terms of the statute itself, law schools
    and their parent institutions are penalized for preventing
    military representatives from gaining entry to campuses for
    the purpose of military recruiting “in a manner that is at least
    equal in quality and scope to the [degree of] access to
    campuses and to students that is provided to any other
    employer.” 
    10 U.S.C. § 983
    (b).
    D.     Current Litigation
    In September 2003, FAIR sued the DOD and the other
    federal departments whose funds are restricted under the
    Solomon Amendment, seeking on constitutional grounds a
    preliminary injunction enjoining enforcement of the statute
    and the then-existing (now codified) informal policy. The
    Government defendants moved to dismiss for lack of
    standing. The District Court denied both the motion to
    dismiss and FAIR’s motion for preliminary injunction. See
    FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at 296, 322
    . This appeal followed.
    II.   Jurisdiction
    Under 
    28 U.S.C. § 1331
    , a federal district court has
    original subject matter jurisdiction over an action for
    injunctive relief based on constitutional claims. Tenafly Eruv
    Ass’n v. Borough of Tenafly, 
    309 F.3d 144
    , 156 n.12 (3d Cir.
    16
    2002), cert. denied, 
    539 U.S. 942
     (2003).7 Our appellate
    jurisdiction exists under 
    28 U.S.C. § 1292
    (a)(1).
    III.   Analysis
    To obtain a preliminary injunction FAIR must establish
    (1) a reasonable likelihood of success on the merits, (2)
    irreparable harm absent the injunction, (3) that the harm to
    FAIR absent the injunction outweighs the harm to the
    Government of granting it, and (4) that the injunction serves
    7
    Standing must also be proper for subject matter jurisdiction
    to exist. See, e.g., Storino v. Borough of Point Pleasant Beach,
    
    322 F.3d 293
    , 296 (3d Cir. 2003); Charles Alan Wright &
    Arthur R. Miller et al., Federal Practice & Procedure § 3531
    (2d ed. 1984). The District Court held that FAIR had standing
    to seek a preliminary injunction against the Solomon
    Amendment, and the Government has conceded this issue on
    appeal. Acknowledging our continuing obligation to verify
    subject matter jurisdiction when it is in question, see, e.g., Exxon
    Mobil Corp. v. Saudi Basic Indus. Corp., 
    364 F.3d 102
    , 104 (3d
    Cir.), cert. granted on other grounds, No. 03-1696, 
    125 S. Ct. 310
     (2004), we affirm the District Court’s holding that FAIR’s
    standing was proper for the reasons it provided. FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at
    285–91.
    While the Government does not concede that the non-
    FAIR plaintiffs had standing, the presence of one plaintiff with
    standing is sufficient to satisfy that requirement. Bowsher v.
    Synar, 
    478 U.S. 714
    , 721 (1986).
    17
    the public interest. Tenafly Eruv Ass’n, 
    309 F.3d at 157
    .
    While we review a district court’s balancing of the
    preliminary injunction factors for abuse of discretion, we
    review “any determination that is a prerequisite to the
    issuance of an injunction . . . according to the standard
    applicable to that particular determination.” 
    Id. at 156
    (citations omitted). Thus, because the District Court’s ruling
    was based on its application of the First Amendment and
    other constitutional principles to the Solomon
    Amendment—issues of law to which a plenary standard of
    review applies— our review is plenary. 
    Id.
    A.     Unconstitutional Conditions Doctrine
    FAIR argues that the Solomon Amendment is an
    unconstitutional condition.8 Under the unconstitutional
    8
    Our dissenting colleague urges us to begin our analysis with
    the presumption that congressional statutes are constitutional.
    It is a fundamental canon of statutory construction that, when
    there are “‘two possible interpretations of a statute, by one of
    which it would unconstitutional and by the other valid, our plain
    duty is to adopt that which will save the Act.’” Rust v. Sullivan,
    
    500 U.S. 173
    , 190 (1991) (quoting Blodgett v. Holden, 
    275 U.S. 142
    , 148 (1927)). But in this case it is not argued that there are
    two possible constructions of the Solomon Amendment. The
    canons of statutory construction therefore do not apply.
    Moreover, “although a duly enacted statute normally carries
    with it a presumption of constitutionality, when a [statute]
    18
    conditions doctrine, the Government “may not deny a benefit
    to a person on a basis that infringes his constitutionally
    protected interests—especially, his interest in freedom of
    speech.” Perry v. Sindermann, 
    408 U.S. 593
    , 597 (1972). If
    Congress “could deny a benefit to a person because of his
    constitutionally protected speech or associations, his exercise
    of those freedoms would in effect be penalized and inhibited.”
    
    Id.
     Put another way, the Government may not propose a
    penalty to “produce a result which [it] could not command
    directly.” Speiser v. Randall, 
    357 U.S. 513
    , 526 (1958) (state
    could not condition property tax exemption on loyalty oath);
    see also Rosenberger v. Rectors & Visitors of the Univ. of Va.,
    
    515 U.S. 819
     (1995) (public university could not condition
    funds for student publications on their secular perspective);
    FCC v. League of Women Voters, 
    468 U.S. 364
     (1984) (FCC
    could not condition federal funds to radio stations on editorial
    content). Thus, if the law schools’ compliance with the
    Solomon Amendment compromises their First Amendment
    rights, the statute is an unconstitutional condition.9
    allegedly infringes on the exercise of [F]irst [A]mendment
    rights, the statute’s proponent bears the burden of establishing
    [its] constitutionality.” ACORN v. City of Frontenac, 
    714 F.2d 813
    , 817 (8th Cir. 1983) (citing Org. for a Better Austin v.
    Keefe, 
    402 U.S. 415
    , 419 (1971)).
    9
    As the District Court noted, the Supreme Court’s exception
    to the unconstitutional conditions doctrine for selective spending
    programs does not apply here. FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at
    19
    B.     First Amendment Analysis
    The First Amendment provides that “Congress shall
    make no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech.” U.S.
    Const. amend. I. This simple commandment plays out
    differently depending on the avenue of analysis. Two
    avenues applicable here are: (1) whether the law schools are
    “expressive associations” whose First Amendment right to
    disseminate their chosen message is impaired by the inclusion
    of military recruiters on their campuses; and (2) whether the
    law schools are insulated by free speech protections from
    being compelled to assist military recruiters in the expressive
    299–300. When the Government appropriates for a particular
    spending program, it may endorse one viewpoint over another
    by conditioning its spending on certain criteria. United States v.
    Am. Library Ass’n, 
    539 U.S. 194
    , 211 (2003) (providing library
    assistance funds to only those libraries who agree to block
    obscene Internet sites); Rust, 
    500 U.S. at
    192–93 (funding
    family planning services that eschew abortion counseling). In
    those cases, “the Government [was] not denying a benefit to
    anyone, but [was] instead simply insisting that public funds be
    spent for the purposes for which they were authorized.” Rust,
    
    500 U.S. at 196
    ; see also Am. Library Ass’n, 
    539 U.S. at 211
    .
    That exception does not apply in our case because the Solomon
    Amendment does not create a spending program; it merely
    imposes a penalty—the loss of general funds.
    20
    act of recruiting.10
    A violation of freedom of speech under either
    analytical approach draws down the curtain on Solomon
    Amendment enforcement unless the Government can
    establish that the statute withstands strict scrutiny. The levels
    of scrutiny applicable in the First Amendment context are
    crucial. A regulation that disrupts an expressive association
    or compels speech must be narrowly tailored to serve a
    compelling governmental interest, and must use the least
    restrictive means of promoting the Government’s asserted
    interest (here, recruiting talented lawyers). See infra Parts
    10
    FAIR also argues that the Solomon Amendment and the
    then-existing informal policy are void under the First
    Amendment’s vagueness doctrine because they provide
    insufficient notice as to what activities will trigger funding
    penalties. But the statutory amendment enacted during FAIR’s
    pending appeal, see supra Part I.C, has rendered moot both the
    challenge to the Solomon Amendment, see Black United Fund
    of N.J., Inc. v. Kean, 
    763 F.2d 156
    , 160 (3d Cir. 1985), and the
    challenge to the regulatory policy, see Prometheus Radio
    Project, Inc. v. FCC, 
    373 F.3d 372
    , 396 (3d Cir. 2004). The
    recent amendment to the Solomon Amendment does not,
    however, moot FAIR’s other challenges to it. See Northeastern
    Fla. Chapter of the Associated Gen. Contractors of Am. v. City
    of Jacksonville, 
    508 U.S. 656
    , 662 (1993) (stating that a
    challenge to a statute is not moot when the new version of it
    “disadvantages [appellants] in the same fundamental way”).
    21
    III.B.1(c), 2(e). Needless to say, this is an imposing barrier.
    The District Court, by contrast, emphasized a third
    potential theory of this case that invokes only intermediate
    scrutiny, i.e., whether the government action at issue furthers
    an important government interest that would be achieved less
    effectively without that action. The Court asked whether the
    law schools’ resistance to the Solomon Amendment is
    sufficiently communicative to bring it within the ambit of the
    First Amendment’s protection for “expressive conduct,” the
    suppression of which receives intermediate scrutiny under
    United States v. O’Brien, 
    391 U.S. 367
     (1968). See infra Part
    III.B.3(b). We emphasize at the outset that we need not
    decide this issue because we conclude that the Solomon
    Amendment violates the First Amendment by impeding the
    law schools’ rights of expressive association and by
    compelling them to assist in the expressive act of recruiting.
    Nonetheless, we explain briefly our conclusion that FAIR
    would prevail even under O’Brien’s less strict framework.
    1.     Expressive Association
    FAIR argues that the Solomon Amendment impairs
    law schools’ First Amendment rights under the doctrine of
    expressive association. The Supreme Court most recently
    addressed this doctrine in Boy Scouts of America v. Dale, 
    530 U.S. 640
     (2000). There the Court held that a state public
    accommodations law that prohibited discrimination based on
    22
    sexual orientation could not constitutionally be invoked to
    force the Boy Scouts to accept openly gay James Dale as an
    assistant scoutmaster. 
    Id. at 659
    . Central to its analysis was
    the deference it gave to the Boy Scouts’ “view of what would
    impair its expression,” which compelled the Court’s
    conclusion that Dale’s presence would “significantly burden
    the Boy Scouts’ desire to not ‘promote homosexual conduct
    as a legitimate form of behavior.’” 
    Id. at 653
     (citation
    omitted).
    Under Dale, the elements of an expressive association
    claim are (1) whether the group is an “expressive
    association,” (2) whether the state action at issue significantly
    affects the group’s ability to advocate its viewpoint, and (3)
    whether the state’s interest justifies the burden it imposes on
    the group’s expressive association. 
    Id.
     at 648–58; accord
    The Circle School v. Pappert, 
    381 F.3d 172
    , 181-82 (3d Cir.
    2004) (applying the Dale framework); Pi Lambda Phi
    Fraternity, Inc. v. Univ. of Pittsburgh, 
    229 F.3d 435
    , 442 (3d
    Cir. 2000) (same). We apply each in turn to analyze FAIR’s
    expressive association claim.
    (a)    The law schools are expressive
    associations.
    A group that engages in some form of public or private
    expression above a de minimis threshold is an “expressive
    association.” Pi Lambda Phi, 
    229 F.3d at 443
    . The group
    23
    need not be an advocacy group or exist primarily for the
    purpose of expression. Dale, 
    530 U.S. at 648
    . The Supreme
    Court held that the Boy Scouts, which “seeks to transmit . . . a
    system of values, engages in expressive activity.” 
    Id. at 650
    .
    “By nature, educational institutions are highly
    expressive organizations, as their philosophy and values are
    directly inculcated in their students.” The Circle School, 
    381 F.3d at 182
    . Because FAIR has shown that the law schools
    “possess[] clear educational philosophies, missions and
    goals,” 
    id.,
     we agree with the District Court’s conclusion that
    they qualify as expressive associations. FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at
    303–04. Therefore, FAIR satisfies the first element of
    the Dale analysis.
    (b)    The Solomon Amendment significantly
    affects the law schools’ ability to express
    their viewpoint.
    FAIR argues that the Solomon Amendment
    significantly affects law schools’ ability to express their
    viewpoint, reflected in their policies, that discrimination on
    the basis of sexual orientation is wrong. The Solomon
    Amendment compels them, they contend, to disseminate the
    opposite message. The schools believe that, by coordinating
    interviews and posting and publishing recruiting notices of an
    employer who discriminates on the basis of sexual orientation,
    they impair their ability to teach an inclusive message by
    24
    example. Put another way, FAIR maintains that the Solomon
    Amendment suppresses the law schools’ chosen speech by
    interfering with their prerogative to shape the way they
    educate (including, of course, the manner in which they
    communicate their message).
    In Dale, the Supreme Court recognized that “[t]he
    forced inclusion of an unwanted person in a group” could
    significantly affect the group’s ability to advocate its public or
    private viewpoint. 
    530 U.S. at 648
    . The viewpoint at issue in
    Dale was the Boy Scouts’ long-held belief that “homosexual
    conduct is inconsistent with . . . the Scout Oath” and that
    “homosexuals [do not] provide a role model consistent with
    the[] expectations [of Scouting families].” 
    Id. at 652
    .
    Because the Boy Scouts’ expressive purpose was to “inculcate
    [youth] with the Boy Scouts’ values—both expressively and
    by example,” 
    id.
     at 649–50, the organization believed that the
    presence of an openly gay assistant scoutmaster could be
    perceived as “promot[ing] homosexual conduct as a
    legitimate form of behavior,” a message inconsistent with the
    expression it wished to convey and the example it wished to
    set. 
    Id. at 651
    .
    The Supreme Court agreed. Because James Dale was
    openly gay, his “presence in the Boy Scouts would, at the very
    least, force the organization to send a message, both to youth
    members and the world, that the Boy Scouts accepts
    homosexual conduct as a legitimate form of behavior.” 
    Id.
     at
    25
    653.
    Just as the Boy Scouts believed that “homosexual
    conduct is inconsistent with the Scout Oath,” 
    id. at 652
    , the
    law schools believe that employment discrimination is
    inconsistent with their commitment to justice and fairness.
    Just as the Boy Scouts maintained that “homosexuals do not
    provide a role model consistent with the expectations of
    Scouting families,” 
    id.,
     the law schools maintain that military
    recruiters engaging in exclusionary hiring “do not provide a
    role model consistent with the expectations of,” 
    id.,
     their
    students and the legal community. Just as the Boy Scouts
    endeavored to “inculcate [youth] with the Boy Scouts’
    values—both expressively and by example,” 
    id.
     at 649–50,
    the law schools endeavor to “inculcate” their students with
    their chosen values by expression and example in the
    promulgation and enforcement of their nondiscrimination
    policies. FAIR Br. at 22–25. And just as “Dale’s presence in
    the Boy Scouts would, at the very least, force the organization
    to send a message, both to youth members and the world, that
    the Boy Scouts accepts homosexual conduct as a legitimate
    form of behavior,” Dale, 
    530 U.S. at 653
    , the presence of
    military recruiters “would, at the very least, force the law
    schools to send a message,” both to students and the legal
    community, that the law schools “accept” employment
    discrimination “as a legitimate form of behavior.” 
    Id.
    Notwithstanding this compelling analogy, the District
    26
    Court distinguished our case from Dale by suggesting there
    was a critical difference between the forced inclusion of a gay
    assistant scoutmaster and the forced presence of an
    “unwanted periodic visitor,” the military recruiter, in the
    context of a larger recruiting effort. FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at 304, 305
    . While there was “no question” that the gay
    scoutmaster would “undermine the Boy Scouts’ ability
    to . . . inculcate its values in younger members,” the District
    Court wrote, the Solomon Amendment does not compel the
    law schools to accept the military recruiters as a “member”
    and does not “bestow upon them any semblance of authority.”
    
    Id. at 305
    .
    But our Court has recently held that compulsory
    accommodation of a government-prescribed message may
    violate schools’ First Amendment expressive association
    rights, even when that message involves our most revered
    affirmations of American patriotism—the Pledge of
    Allegiance and our National Anthem, is only minimally
    intrusive and lacks the schools’ imprimatur. The Circle
    School, 
    381 F.3d at 182
     (holding that a statute requiring
    private schools to lead the Pledge of Allegiance and National
    Anthem violates their rights under the expressive association
    doctrine—“Certainly, the temporal duration of a burden on
    First Amendment rights is not determinative of whether there
    is a constitutional violation . . . . Similarly, the fact that the
    schools can issue a general disclaimer does not erase the First
    Amendment infringement at issue here, for the schools are
    27
    still compelled to speak the [Government’s] message.”). If
    the Pledge and Anthem “only take[] a very short period of
    time each day,” and may be preceded by “a general disclaimer
    regarding the recitation,” yet do not “erase the First
    Amendment infringement at issue here,” 
    id.,
     then focusing on
    the periodic nature of the military recruiter’s visits 11 is
    similarly unavailing.
    Moreover, the District Court’s scrutiny of the law
    schools’ belief that the presence of military recruiters will
    undermine their expressive message about fairness and social
    justice violates the Dale Court’s instruction to “give
    deference to an association’s view of what would impair its
    expression.” 
    530 U.S. at 653
    .12 In Dale, the Court did more
    11
    Furthermore, the Solomon Amendment requires law schools
    to do more than passively accept the presence of an “unwanted
    periodic visitor.” They must actively assist military recruiters in
    a manner equal in quality and scope to the assistance they
    provide other recruiters. 
    10 U.S.C. § 983
    (b)(1).
    12
    Dale may appear to depart from prior Supreme Court
    jurisprudence in this area. In two expressive association cases
    from the 1980s, the Court considered the claims of civic
    associations that state statutes forcing them to accept women as
    members violated their expressive association rights. Bd. of
    Dirs. of Rotary Int’l v. Rotary Club of Duarte, 
    481 U.S. 537
    (1987); Roberts v. United States Jaycees, 
    468 U.S. 609
     (1984).
    Closer review explains the distinction from Dale. In both cases
    28
    than pay lip service to deference notions. Deference
    distinguished the Supreme Court’s conclusion on the
    impairment question from that of the New Jersey Supreme
    Court, which had decided the case previously. The state court
    had ruled in Dale’s favor, holding that because the Boy
    Scouts have a policy of “discourag[ing] its leaders from
    disseminating any views on sexual issues,” Dale’s presence
    the Court examined the organizations’ expressive charitable and
    humanitarian purposes and determined that they would not be
    impaired by the forced inclusion of women members. Duarte,
    
    481 U.S. at
    548–49; Roberts, 
    468 U.S. at
    626–27. The
    difference in outcome between these cases and Dale—the civic
    associations had to admit women, but the Boy Scouts did not
    have to admit Dale—underscores the significance of the Court’s
    decision to extend “deference to an association’s view of what
    would impair its expression.” 
    530 U.S. at 653
    .
    Moreover, we note that the Supreme Court had
    previously extended deference to what an expressive association
    said would impair its expression. E.g., Meyer v. Grant, 
    486 U.S. 414
    , 424 (1988) (“The First Amendment protects appellees’
    right not only to advocate their cause but also to select what they
    believe to be the most effective means for so doing.”);
    Democratic Party v. Wisconsin ex rel. La Follette, 
    450 U.S. 107
    ,
    123–24 (1981) (“[A] court[] may not constitutionally substitute
    its own judgment for that of the Party. A political party’s choice
    among the various ways of determining the makeup of a State’s
    delegation to the party’s national convention is protected by the
    Constitution.”).
    29
    would not significantly affect its ability to disseminate its
    message. 
    530 U.S. at
    654 (citing Dale v. Boy Scouts of
    America, 
    734 A.2d 1196
    , 1223 (N.J. 1999) (emphasis in
    original)). But faced with competing views— the Boy Scouts’
    view that Dale’s presence impaired their message and the
    state court’s view that it could not— the Supreme Court
    deferred to the Boy Scouts’ view. In other words, the reason
    why there was “no question” (in the District Court’s words in
    our case, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at 305
    ) that a gay scoutmaster
    would undermine the Boy Scouts’ message was because the
    Boy Scouts said it would. Dale, 
    530 U.S. at 653
    . In our case,
    FAIR has supplied written evidence of its belief that the
    Solomon Amendment’s forcible inclusion of and assistance to
    military recruiters undermines their efforts to disseminate
    their chosen message of nondiscrimination. Accordingly, we
    must give Dale deference to this belief,13 and conclude that
    13
    Furthermore, the law schools are entitled to at least as much
    deference as the Boy Scouts, as the Supreme Court has
    recognized in other contexts that universities and law schools
    “occupy a special niche in our constitutional tradition,” Grutter
    v. Bollinger, 
    539 U.S. 306
    , 329 (2003), because of their “vital
    role in . . . democracy,” Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 
    354 U.S. 234
    , 250 (1957). The Court has acknowledged the importance
    of “autonomous decisionmaking by the academy.” Regents of
    the Univ. of Mich. v. Ewing, 
    474 U.S. 214
    , 226 n.12 (1985);
    Sweezy, 
    354 U.S. at 263
     (Frankfurter, J., concurring)
    (recognizing “four essential freedoms” of a university “to
    determine for itself on academic grounds who may teach, what
    30
    FAIR likely satisfies the second element of an expressive
    association claim.
    (c)    Balancing of interests
    The third step in evaluating an expressive association
    claim is “balancing the First Amendment interests implicated
    by the Solomon Amendment with competing societal interests
    to determine whether the statute transgresses constitutional
    boundaries.” FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at 310
    .14 We need not
    linger on this analysis. Rarely has government action been
    deemed so integral to the advancement of a compelling
    may be taught, how it shall be taught, and who may be admitted
    to study”).     The Supreme Court’s academic freedom
    jurisprudence thus underscores the importance of Dale
    deference in our case.
    14
    The District Court rejected FAIR’s argument that strict
    scrutiny applies because it did not believe that the Solomon
    Amendment directly burdens expressive association rights.
    FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at
    310–311. But because we concluded
    at step two that the Solomon Amendment impairs law schools’
    expression, strict scrutiny will apply. Dale, 
    530 U.S. at 659
    (rejecting the argument that only intermediate scrutiny should
    apply); The Circle School, 
    381 F.3d at 182
     (applying strict
    scrutiny to statute impairing schools’ expressive association
    rights by requiring them to lead the Pledge of Allegiance and
    National Anthem).
    31
    purpose as to justify the suppression or compulsion of speech.
    We presume that the Government has a compelling interest in
    attracting talented military lawyers.15 But “[i]t is not enough
    15
    Our colleague in dissent states that “[w]e do not write on a
    clean slate regarding the importance Congress places in access
    to college and university facilities by the military” and that
    “[w]e have already decided that issue contrary to the argument
    pressed by Appellants.”          In United States v. City of
    Philadelphia, 
    798 F.2d 81
     (3d Cir. 1986), our Court
    acknowledged that “Congress considers access to college and
    university employment facilities by military recruiters to be a
    matter of paramount importance.” 
    Id. at 86
    . City of
    Philadelphia, however, is distinguishable from this case in two
    important respects. First, in that case the university invited the
    military recruiters on campus; the recruiters’ presence was not
    effectively dictated by a statute, as is the case here. 
    Id. at 83
    .
    Second, City of Philadelphia engaged in a conflict preemption
    analysis and held that, because it was not possible for the
    university to comply with both a Philadelphia anti-
    discrimination ordinance and the clear congressional policy
    concerning military recruitment on campus, the ordinance was
    preempted. 
    Id.
     at 88–89. Our Court did not reach a balancing-
    of-interests inquiry. Therefore, neither this Court’s prior
    acknowledgment of the importance Congress places on military
    recruiting on college and university campuses, nor our
    presumption in this case that there is an important governmental
    interest in attracting talented lawyers to the military, ends our
    analysis. Rather, we must go on to reach an issue that was not
    present in City of Philadelphia—whether the Solomon
    32
    to show that the Government’s ends are compelling; the
    means must be carefully tailored to achieve those ends.”
    Sable Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 
    492 U.S. 115
    ,
    126 (1989).
    As we explain in the final section of our opinion, infra
    Part III.B.3(b), the Solomon Amendment could barely be
    tailored more broadly. Unlike a typical employer, the military
    has ample resources to recruit through alternative means. For
    example, it may generate student interest by means of loan
    repayment programs. And it may use sophisticated
    recruitment devices that are generally too expensive for use
    by civilian recruiters, such as television and radio
    advertisements. These methods do not require the assistance
    of law school space or personnel. And while they may be
    more costly, the Government has given us no reason to
    suspect that they are less effective than on-campus recruiting.
    The availability of alternative, less speech-restrictive
    means of effective recruitment is sufficient to render the
    Solomon Amendment unconstitutional under strict scrutiny
    analysis. Sable, 
    492 U.S. at 126
    ; The Circle School, 
    381 F.3d at 182
    . But our path in this case is even clearer. The
    Government has failed to proffer a shred of evidence that the
    Amendment is narrowly tailored to achieve the Government’s
    ends.
    33
    Solomon Amendment materially enhances its stated goal.
    And not only might other methods of recruitment yield
    acceptable results, they might actually fare better than the
    current system. In fact, it may plausibly be the case that the
    Solomon Amendment, which has generated much ill will
    toward the military on law school campuses,16 actually
    impedes recruitment. 17
    16
    See, e.g., FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at 282
     (describing record
    evidence of student protests over military recruiting).
    17
    The dissent, applying the balancing-of-interests test from
    Roberts, 
    468 U.S. at 620
    , comes to the opposite
    conclusion—“that the law schools’ interests here fall at the
    remote extreme of Justice Brennan’s spectrum–‘where that
    relationship’s objective characteristics locate it . . . [near] the
    most attenuated of personal attachments.’” This balancing test,
    however, comes not from the portion of Roberts dealing with
    freedom of expressive association, but from the portion dealing
    with freedom of intimate association. The law schools are
    clearly not intimate associations, and where they may fall on the
    spectrum articulated by Justice Brennan for determining whether
    particular relationships merit protection under that doctrine is
    irrelevant to our analysis here. In Roberts, the Court went on to
    engage in a strict scrutiny expressive association analysis and
    applied the balancing test we apply here, determining that the
    Government had a compelling interest in eliminating
    discrimination and that the statute at issue was the least
    restrictive means of achieving that end. Roberts, 
    468 U.S. at 620
    .
    34
    *       *       *      *       *
    FAIR likely satisfies the three elements of an
    expressive association claim. The law schools are expressive
    associations, they believe the message they choose to express
    is impaired by the Solomon Amendment, and no compelling
    governmental interest exists in the record to justify this
    impairment. Therefore, FAIR has a reasonable likelihood of
    success on the merits of its expressive association claim
    against the Solomon Amendment.
    2.     Compelled Speech
    The Supreme Court has long recognized that, in
    addition to restricting suppression of speech, “the First
    Amendment may prevent the government from
    . . . compelling individuals to express certain views.” United
    States v. United Foods, Inc., 
    533 U.S. 405
    , 410 (2001) (citing,
    inter alia, W. Va. State Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 
    319 U.S. 624
    (1943)). “At the heart of the First Amendment lies the
    principle that each person should decide for himself or herself
    the ideas and beliefs deserving of expression, consideration,
    and adherence.” Turner Broad. Sys, Inc. v. FCC, 
    512 U.S. 622
    , 641 (1994).
    Consistent with this principle, the Supreme Court has
    found impermissible compelled speech in three categories of
    government action. The first is government action that forces
    35
    a private speaker to propagate a particular message chosen by
    a government. See Barnette, 
    319 U.S. at 642
     (state could not
    enforce compulsory flag salute statute); Wooley v. Maynard,
    
    430 U.S. 705
    , 717 (1977) (state could not require drivers to
    display state motto on their license plates). The second is
    government action that forces a private speaker to
    accommodate or include another private speaker’s message.
    See Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian, & Bisexual
    Group of Boston, 
    515 U.S. 557
    , 581 (1995) (state
    nondiscrimination statute could not be constitutionally applied
    to require parade organizers to include a contingent of gay
    marchers behind their own banner); Pacific Gas & Elec. Co.
    v. Pub. Utils. Comm’n, 
    475 U.S. 1
    , 12–16 (1986) (state
    regulatory commission could not require public utility to
    distribute ratepayer-group’s message in the extra space of the
    utility’s billing statements); Miami Herald Publ’g Co. v.
    Tornillo, 
    418 U.S. 241
    , 258 (1974) (state could not force
    newspaper to provide equal editorial-page space to candidates
    it opposes). The third category is government action that
    forces an individual to subsidize or contribute to an
    organization that engages in speech that the individual
    opposes. See United Foods, 
    533 U.S. at 413
     (Congress could
    not require mushroom growers to pay assessments to fund
    advertisements to promote mushroom sales); Abood v. Detroit
    Bd. of Educ., 
    431 U.S. 209
    , 235 (1977) (state could not
    compel non-union employees to pay union dues to promote
    36
    union causes). 18 FAIR argues that the Solomon Amendment
    forces law schools to propagate, accommodate, and subsidize
    the military’s recruiting, and therefore implicates each of the
    three varieties of compelled speech cases.
    The District Court rejected FAIR’s argument and held
    that the law schools are not compelled to express a particular
    ideological message by admitting and actively assisting the
    military recruiters. We disagree. As we explain in the
    analysis that follows, the military’s recruiting is expressive of
    a message with which the law schools disagree. To comply
    with the Solomon Amendment, the law schools must
    affirmatively assist military recruiters in the same manner
    they assist other recruiters, which means they must propagate,
    accommodate, and subsidize the military’s message. In so
    doing, the Solomon Amendment conditions funding on a
    basis that violates the law schools’ First Amendment rights
    under the compelled speech doctrine.
    (a)    Recruiting is expression.
    The expressive nature of recruiting is evident by the
    oral and written communication that recruiting entails:
    published and posted announcements of the recruiter’s visit,
    18
    We note that the subsidization line of compelled speech case
    law is the only one of these three categories addressed by the
    dissent.
    37
    published and oral descriptions of the employer and the jobs it
    is trying to fill, 19 and the oral communication of an
    employer’s recruiting reception and one-on-one interviews.
    The expressive nature of recruiting is also evident in its
    purpose—to convince prospective employees that an
    employer is worth working for. So understood, recruiting
    necessarily involves “communication of information, the
    dissemination and propagation of views and ideas, and the
    advocacy of causes”—the hallmarks of First Amendment
    expression. Village of Schaumburg v. Citizens for a Better
    Env’t, 
    444 U.S. 620
    , 632 (1980) (soliciting for charitable
    cause is expression entitled to First Amendment protection);
    see also Thomas v. Collins, 
    323 U.S. 516
    , 538 (1945)
    (recognizing First Amendment protection for the solicitation
    of union members).
    The District Court held that recruiting is not expressive
    activity because it “differs dramatically” from other forms of
    expressive activity, such as soliciting contributions and
    19
    For example, most recruiters submit a National Association
    for Law Placement (“NALP”) form that, as NALP puts it,
    “offers employers a thorough yet succinct way to tell their story
    to candidates” and includes a “narrative” section to “discuss the
    special characteristics” of the employer. NALP compiles these
    forms into a directory, which is distributed and/or made
    available by both law schools and employers to prospective
    employees.
    38
    proselytizing. While soliciting and proselytizing cannot be
    separated from the “concomitant advocacy of a particular case
    or viewpoint,” the District Court reasoned, recruiting does not
    advocate any particular cause but only has “an economic or
    functional motive.” FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at
    307–08.
    We agree with the District Court that soliciting and
    proselytizing are obvious forms of expressive activity. We
    part, however, on the notion that efforts to raise a legal staff
    are “economic or functional” while efforts to raise funds and
    membership are not. Recruiting, soliciting and proselytizing
    are similarly economic and functional and, at the same time,
    similarly expressive. Recruiting conveys the message that
    “our organization is worth working for,” while soliciting and
    proselytizing convey the similar functional message that “our
    charity is worth giving to” or “our cause is worth joining.”
    Having determined that recruiting is expressive, we
    now turn to the law schools’ disagreement with that
    expression.
    (b)    The law schools’ disagreement with the
    speech of military recruiters.
    Military recruiters visiting law school campuses
    undoubtedly speak to students about the benefits of a career in
    the military, and the Solomon Amendment requires law
    schools to accept this speech. The law schools do not seem to
    39
    take issue with most of the “expressions of value, opinion, or
    endorsement,” Hurley, 515 U.S. at 573, made by military
    recruiters on campus (to the extent recruiters suggest that
    military careers are honorable and rewarding experiences).
    Nor, for the most part, do military recruiters describing
    careers in the military make “statements of fact the [law
    schools] would rather avoid.” Id.
    The law schools’ lack of objection to most of the
    speech they are forced to accept within their fora raises a key
    question under the compelled speech doctrine: to what extent
    must they disagree with the Government’s message in order
    for strict scrutiny to apply? Justice Souter’s dissent in
    Glickman v. Wileman Bros. & Elliott, Inc., 
    521 U.S. 457
    (1997), summarized the Court’s jurisprudence to that time in
    suggesting that it is not necessary to show disagreement in
    order to sustain a compelled speech challenge.
    [T]he requirement of disagreement finds no
    legal warrant in our compelled-speech cases. In
    Riley [v. Fed’n of the Blind of North Carolina,
    Inc., 
    487 U.S. 781
     (1988)], for example, we
    held that the free-speech rights of charitable
    solicitors were infringed by a law compelling
    statements of fact with which the objectors
    could not, and did not profess to, disagree. See
    
    487 U.S., at 497-98
    , 108 S.Ct., at 2677-2678.
    See also Hurley, 
    515 U.S., at 573
    , 115 S.Ct., at
    40
    2347 (“[The] general rule, that the speaker has
    the right to tailor the speech, applies not only to
    expressions of value, opinion, or endorsement,
    but equally to statements of fact the speaker
    would rather avoid . . . [.]”); Barnette, 
    319 U.S., at 635
    , 
    63 S.Ct., at 1183-1184
     (if the Free
    Speech Clause bars the government from
    making the flag salute a legal duty,
    nonconformist beliefs are not required to
    exempt one from saluting). Indeed, the Abood
    cases themselves protect objecting employees
    from being forced to subsidize ideological
    union activities unrelated to collective
    bargaining, without any requirement that the
    objectors declare that they disagree with the
    positions espoused by the union. See, e.g.,
    [Chicago Teachers Union v. Hudson, 
    475 U.S. 292
    , 301-02 (1986)]; Abood, 
    431 U.S., at 234
    ,
    97 S.Ct., at 1799. Requiring a profession of
    disagreement is likewise at odds with our
    holding two Terms ago that no articulable
    message is necessary for expression to be
    protected, Hurley, 
    supra, at 569
    , 115 S.Ct., at
    2345; protection of speech is not limited to
    clear-cut propositions subject to assent or
    contradiction, but covers a broader sphere of
    expressive preference. . . . One need not
    “disagree” with an abstractionist when buying a
    41
    canvas from a representational painter; one
    merely wishes to support a different act of
    expression.
    Glickman, 
    521 U.S. at
    488–89 (Souter, J., dissenting, joined
    by Rehnquist, C.J., Scalia, J., and Thomas, J.).
    Despite the numerous precedents to the contrary
    discussed by Justice Souter, it is possible to read the Glickman
    majority as implicitly endorsing a disagreement requirement
    in the compelled speech context. Glickman involved a First
    Amendment challenge to regulations requiring fruit growers,
    handlers, and processors to finance generic advertising of
    California nectarines, plums, and peaches. 
    Id. at 460
    . The
    majority “presume[d]” that the fruit growers, handlers, and
    processors “agree[d] with the central message of the speech
    that is generated by the generic [government] program [at
    issue],” and stated that “compelled speech case law” was
    “inapplicable” because the scheme at issue did not, inter alia,
    “require them to use their own property to convey an
    antagonistic ideological message,” or “force them to respond
    to a hostile message when they would prefer to remain silent,”
    
    id.
     at 470–71 (citations and internal quotation marks omitted)
    (emphases added). However, because the degree of
    disagreement that may be required is minimal and in any
    event is present in this case, we need not determine whether
    such a requirement exists nor, if so, decipher its precise
    bounds.
    42
    As our dissenting colleague recently explained, the
    “individual’s disagreement [in a compelled speech case] can
    be minor, as ‘[t]he general rule is that the speaker and the
    audience, not the government, assess the value of the
    information presented.’” Cochran v. Veneman, 
    359 F.3d 263
    ,
    275 (3d Cir. 2004) (quoting United Foods, 
    533 U.S. at 411
    ).
    In Cochran, we held unconstitutional a law requiring dairy
    producers to pay small assessments in support of “generic
    advertising that promotes milk.” 
    Id.
     Although the aggrieved
    dairy producers did not disapprove of the pro-milk message at
    issue, the ads featured milk “produced by methods they
    view[ed] as wasteful and harmful to the environment,” and
    did not promote milk produced by their own favored methods.
    
    Id.
     The ads, in effect, served to promote milk produced by
    efforts with which the plaintiff dairy producers disagreed.
    Here the law schools similarly object to conveying the
    message that all employers are equal, and instead would
    rather only open their fora and use their resources to support
    employers who, in their eyes, do not discriminate against
    gays. This objection constitutes as much of a protected First
    Amendment interest as the objection of the dairy farmers in
    Cochran. Moreover, there is at least one important sense in
    which the law schools strenuously disagree with the very
    words spoken by military recruiters that the Solomon
    Amendment compels them to accept and to which they have
    been forced to respond. 
    10 U.S.C. § 654
    (b) prohibits open,
    practicing gays from serving in the armed forces. Military
    43
    recruiters undisputedly are bound by § 654(b), and do not
    recruit gay persons for service. Unsurprisingly, in light of
    § 654(b), the record demonstrates that openly gay persons
    who meet with military recruiters are told by the recruiters
    that they may not pursue military careers.20 Such speech by
    military recruiters is perhaps the most discordant speech the
    Solomon Amendment compels the law schools to accept.
    Yet, as we have indicated, the act of being forced to accept
    speech promoting an employer whose discriminatory policies
    the law schools disagree with is sufficient “disagreement” to
    bring the Solomon Amendment within the Supreme Court’s
    compelled speech jurisprudence.
    Thus, unlike the regulatory scheme at issue in
    Glickman, the Solomon Amendment, by requiring law schools
    to open their fora to military recruiters when they would
    prefer to do so only for non-discriminating employers,
    “require[s] them to use their own property to convey an
    antagonistic ideological message.” Glickman, 
    521 U.S. at 471
    . Likewise, by directly providing “access” to campuses
    for speech by military recruiters where law students are told
    that openly gay applicants may not serve, the Solomon
    Amendment requires the law schools to allow an
    20
    See JA107 (former ROTC student who had “wanted to be an
    officer in the JAG Corps since high school” interviewed with
    military recruiter, admitted his homosexuality, and was told that
    he was “ineligible due to his sexual orientation”).
    44
    objectionable message counter to their beliefs. In addition,
    both forms of speech with which the law schools disagree
    have resulted in, according to the record, hundreds (if not
    thousands) of instances of responsive speech by members of
    the law school communities (administrators, faculty, and
    students), including various broadcast e-mails by law school
    administrators to their communities, posters in protest of
    military recruiter visits, and open fora held to “ameliorate” the
    effects of forced on-campus speech by military recruiters. All
    of these represent instances in which the schools were
    “force[d] . . . to respond to a hostile message when they
    would prefer to remain silent.” 
    Id.
     (internal quotation marks
    omitted). Therefore, the degree of the law schools’
    disagreement with the military recruiters’ expression is
    sufficient to warrant First Amendment protection. We now
    determine whether the Solomon Amendment compels the law
    schools to engage in that expression.
    (c)    The law schools must propagate,
    accommodate, and subsidize the
    military’s expressive message.
    Reasoning that the Solomon Amendment was not “an
    outright regulation on speech,” the District Court held that the
    Supreme Court’s compelled speech doctrine did not apply.
    FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at 309
    . Put another way, the District
    Court concluded that the statute does not “directly requir[e] a
    private speaker to participate in the dissemination of a
    45
    particular message.” 
    Id.
    We disagree. Having concluded above that recruiting
    is expression, we believe that the Solomon Amendment
    compels the law schools to engage in that expression in all
    three proscribed ways: propagation, accommodation, and
    subsidy. The statute insists not only on access to campus for
    military recruiters, but the active and equal assistance of law
    schools’ career services offices. For example, Harvard Law
    School’s career services staff offers to assist employers to
    “get [their] message out to students in an effective manner.”
    Like many law schools, the assistance Harvard provides
    includes coordinating interviews with students, counseling
    employers on effective recruiting, stuffing students’
    mailboxes with employers’ information, scheduling social
    receptions for students, and printing employers’
    announcements in the School’s newsletter. Under the express
    terms of the Solomon Amendment, law schools like Harvard
    must do the same for the military recruiters.
    By requiring law schools to help military recruiters
    “get [their] message out to students” by distributing
    newsletters and posting notices, the Solomon Amendment
    compels law schools to propagate the military’s message.
    Like the forced display of an unwanted motto on one’s license
    plate, or the compulsory recitation of a pledge, this is
    compelled speech. Wooley, 
    430 U.S. at 717
    ; Barnette, 
    319 U.S. at 642
    . By requiring schools to include military
    46
    recruiters in the interviews and recruiting receptions the
    schools arrange, the Solomon Amendment compels the
    schools to accommodate the military’s message in the
    recruiting-assistance programs they provide for other
    employers. Like the forced inclusion of a parade contingent,
    a statement in the extra space of a utility’s billing statement,
    or a response in a newspaper’s editorial page, this is
    compelled speech. See Hurley, 
    515 U.S. at
    569–81; Pacific
    Gas, 
    475 U.S. at
    12–16; Miami Herald, 
    418 U.S. at
    255–58.
    And by putting demands on the law schools’ employees and
    resources,21 the schools are compelled to subsidize the
    military’s recruiting message. Like mandatory assessments to
    support advertisements or political funds, this is compelled
    speech. See United Foods, 
    533 U.S. at
    411–17; Abood, 
    431 U.S. at 235
    .
    (d)    The Solomon Amendment prohibits
    disclaimers and, even if it did not, risk of
    misattribution is not an element of a
    compelled speech violation.
    21
    While we recognize that the relative cost of providing these
    services to one particular employer is marginal, the Supreme
    Court has never required that compelled subsidies be substantial
    to present a constitutional concern. See, e.g., United Foods, 
    533 U.S. at 408
     (mushroom assessment at issue was one cent per
    pound and only some of it was going toward the objectionable
    advertising).
    47
    The District Court suggested that assisting military
    recruiters is not “obvious endorsement” by the law schools of
    the military’s point of view because “law schools can
    effectively disclaim any recruiting message and can easily
    distance themselves ideologically from the military
    recruiters.” FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at 308, 310
    . But the
    Solomon Amendment, as recently amended, does not appear
    to permit law schools to disclaim the military’s message. Its
    express terms require them to provide treatment to the
    military recruiters “equal in quality and scope” to that
    provided to other employers. As the law schools do not
    disclaim the messages of those employers, similarly they may
    not disclaim the message of the military. Furthermore, it was
    in apparent response to the law schools’ ameliorative
    measures—their efforts to “distance themselves” (in the
    District Court’s words) from the military’s position—that the
    DOD and eventually Congress insisted on equal treatment for
    military recruiters.
    But even if the Solomon Amendment allowed for
    disclaimers, the Supreme Court has never held that compelled
    speech concerns evaporate if a speaker can ameliorate the risk
    of misattribution by disclaiming the message it is being
    compelled to propagate. To the contrary, “the presence of a
    disclaimer . . . does not suffice to eliminate the impermissible
    pressure . . . to respond to [compelled] speech.” Pacific Gas,
    475 U.S. at 15 n.11 (plurality opinion). While a disclaimer
    reduces the risk that readers will misattribute the message, it
    48
    “does nothing to reduce the risk that [the compelled speaker]
    will be forced to respond when there is strong disagreement
    with the substance of [the] message.” Id. Thus, in Pacific
    Gas, the Supreme Court invalidated as compelled speech a
    requirement that a utility share the extra space in its billing
    statements with an organization that opposed its viewpoint.
    The utility’s ability to include a disclaimer did not change the
    analysis. In fact, a “forced reply” may add to the injury of
    compelled speech, not its cure. Id. at 15–16 (noting that the
    “pressure to respond” to compelled speech is “antithetical to
    the free discussion that the First Amendment seeks to foster”).
    In Miami Herald, the Supreme Court also invalidated a
    state law compelling newspapers to provide editorial page
    space to any political candidates that the newspaper assailed
    in an editorial. 
    418 U.S. at
    255–58. It did not suggest that a
    newspaper could alleviate compelled speech by running a
    disclaimer above the candidate’s message.22
    22
    While the newspapers could avoid triggering the penalty of
    having to provide editorial page space to assailed candidates by
    not criticizing any candidates at all, the Court noted that this
    self-censorship was a form of speech suppression, itself a First
    Amendment injury. 
    418 U.S. at 257
    . Our case presents this
    self-censorship concern as well, as the law schools could avoid
    triggering—or at least minimize—the quality and scope of
    active assistance they must provide to military recruiters by
    limiting the quality and scope of their assistance to other
    49
    Similarly, in Wooley the Court held that the state motto
    on the Maynards’ license plate was compelled speech even
    though the state supreme court had expressly found in another
    case that “nothing in the state law . . . precludes appellees
    from displaying their disagreement with the state motto as
    long as the methods used do not obscure the license plates.”
    
    430 U.S. at 722
     (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (citing State v.
    Hoskin, 
    295 A.2d 454
     (1972)). 23 On the facts of Wooley,
    recruiters.
    23
    The Supreme Court has expressed concerns about
    misattribution and ability to disclaim in several of its compelled
    speech cases. See Hurley, 
    515 U.S. at
    556–57 (noting that
    parade organizers do not customarily “disavow ‘any identity of
    viewpoint’ between themselves and the selected participants”
    and that “such disclaimers would be quite curious in a moving
    parade”); Turner Broadcast System v. FCC, 
    512 U.S. 622
     (1994)
    (“TBS”) (noting that regulations requiring cable operators to
    carry broadcast signals posed little risk of misattribution because
    broadcasters are required by federal regulation to identify
    themselves at least once every hour); PruneYard Shopping
    Center v. Robins, 
    447 U.S. 74
    , 87 (1984) (suggesting that there
    was no risk that the message of students distributing political
    pamphlets and conducting a petition drive at a shopping mall
    would be attributed incorrectly to the mall owner and noting that
    the mall owner could disavow any connection with the message
    by posting signs near the petition table).
    But in none of these cases did the Court hold that the risk
    of misattribution and the speaker’s ability to disclaim the
    50
    there was virtually no risk that the compelled speech would be
    attributed to anyone other than the state.
    message were dispositive elements of the compelled speech
    doctrine. In Hurley, the Court noted that it was not “deciding on
    the precise significance of the likelihood of misattribution” and
    did not rest its holding on the parade organizer’s presumed
    difficulty in disclaiming the gay marchers’ message. 515 U.S.
    at 517. And in both PruneYard and TBS the absence of a risk of
    misattribution was only one of a number of factors
    distinguishing them from prior cases in which compelled speech
    had been found. PruneYard, 447 U.S. at 87; TBS, 
    512 U.S. at
    654–55. The Court also considered the content-neutral nature
    of the law causing the challenged “compelled” speech, the
    nonexistent risk of self-censorship, and the unique
    characteristics of the forum (the Court later described the
    shopping mall in PruneYard as a “peculiarly public” forum, see
    Pacific Gas, 
    475 U.S. at
    13 n.8; the TBS Court noted cable’s
    monopoly status and exclusive control over the “essential
    pathway” for disseminating a particular type of communication).
    TBS, 
    512 U.S. at
    654–56; PruneYard, 447 U.S. at 87–88. And
    while PruneYard comes closest to holding that a speaker’s
    ability to disclaim a message may be relevant to the compelled
    speech analysis, it is notable that PruneYard predated Pacific
    Gas, the most express rejection of the ability to disclaim as an
    antidote for compelled speech. Pacific Gas, 475 U.S. at 15 n.11
    (plurality opinion) (“The presence of a disclaimer . . . does not
    suffice to eliminate the impermissible pressure on the appellant
    to respond to [the unwanted] speech . . . .”).
    51
    In sum, law schools are expressly precluded from
    disclaiming or retorting the military’s recruiting message by
    the Solomon Amendment’s new requirement that their
    treatment of military recruiters be “equal in quality and
    scope” to the treatment of other recruiters. And while the
    Court has mentioned the danger of misattribution and the
    speaker’s ability to disclaim in several of its compelled speech
    cases, it has not held to date that the presence of either factor
    eliminated compelled speech concerns. Therefore, the
    District Court was wrong to reject FAIR’s compelled speech
    claims on the basis of its conclusion that the Solomon
    Amendment’s requirements posed little risk of misattribution
    to the law schools who in any event could effectively disclaim
    the military’s message.
    (e)     The Solomon Amendment would not
    likely survive strict scrutiny.
    Although the Solomon Amendment impairs the law
    schools’ First Amendment rights by compelling them to
    propagate, accommodate, and subsidize the military’s
    recruiting message against their will, the statute “could still be
    valid if it were a narrowly tailored means of serving a
    compelling state interest”—i.e., if it passed strict First
    Amendment scrutiny. Pacific Gas, 475 U.S. at 19; see also
    Riley, 
    487 U.S. at 798
     (regulation impairing speakers’ First
    Amendment rights under the compelled speech doctrine was
    subject to “exacting First Amendment scrutiny” that it did not
    52
    survive). We thus inquire (1) whether the Government’s
    interest in recruiting military lawyers is compelling, and (2)
    whether the Solomon Amendment is narrowly tailored to
    advance that goal. But as discussed above in the context of
    FAIR’s expressive association claim, see supra Part
    III.B.1(c), the Solomon Amendment does not survive strict
    scrutiny because the Government has not demonstrated (or
    even argued) that it cannot recruit effectively by less speech-
    restrictive means. Therefore, the balance of interests likely
    tips in the law schools’ favor.
    *      *       *       *       *
    To summarize, the Solomon Amendment conditions
    funding on the law schools’ propagation, accommodation, and
    subsidy of the military’s recruiting, which is expression. The
    Government has not shown that the assistance from law
    schools that the Solomon Amendment requires is narrowly
    tailored to advance its interest in recruiting. FAIR has thus
    established a reasonable likelihood of establishing that the
    Solomon Amendment unconstitutionally conditions funding
    on a basis that infringes law schools’ constitutionally
    protected interests under the First Amendment doctrine of
    compelled speech.
    3.     Consideration of O’Brien
    We turn finally to an argument that is ancillary to our
    53
    holding. Although the Solomon Amendment fits within the
    categories of First Amendment cases described in the
    previous sections, the District Court placed it instead into a
    mold it does not fit: the doctrine of expressive conduct. In so
    doing, it applied the intermediate scrutiny test set out by the
    Supreme Court in United States v. O’Brien, 
    391 U.S. 367
    (1968), discussed at length below, for review of governmental
    regulations with only an incidental effect on expression. For
    the sake of completeness, we close by considering whether
    the law schools’ resistance to the military’s recruitment
    policy, motivated by their ideological opposition to exclusion
    based on sexual orientation, is expressive conduct protected
    by the First Amendment. 24
    (a)    O’Brien is inapplicable when First
    24
    While the expressive content of the law schools’ message is
    relevant also to the law schools’ expressive association claim
    under Dale, the analysis is different in that context. Under the
    rubric of expressive association, we consider whether the
    Solomon Amendment interferes with the law schools’ extant
    message of nondiscrimination, and thus impinges their
    associational freedom, by compelling them to assist in the
    military’s recruitment efforts. But with expressive conduct we
    ask whether resistance to the statute, i.e., exclusion of the
    recruiters in contravention of the statute (or its flip side, “the
    conduct of law schools in permitting or assisting a recruiting
    activity,” FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at 309
    ), is itself expressive
    conduct warranting First Amendment protection.
    54
    Amendment activity is protected on other
    grounds.
    Before exploring the contours of the O’Brien test, we
    explain briefly why expressive conduct fails as a descriptive
    model of the First Amendment issues at stake in this case.
    Activity simultaneously may give rise to an expressive
    conduct claim and to claims based on alternative theories.
    The premise of the category “expressive conduct” is that some
    activity, though it is not speech proper and is not protected
    under other First Amendment grounds, is crucial to public
    debate and warrants protection. See Texas v. Johnson, 
    491 U.S. 397
    , 404 (1989) (explaining that the Court has “long
    recognized that [the First Amendment’s] protection does not
    end at the spoken or written word” and that conduct may be
    “sufficiently imbued with elements of communication” to
    merit First Amendment protection) (citations omitted).
    Expressive conduct is, loosely stated, an overflow category; it
    is broad.25 It is therefore unsurprising that much expression
    25
    As noted in Johnson, 
    id.,
     the Supreme Court has recognized
    the expressive nature of students' wearing of black armbands to
    protest the war in Vietnam, Tinker v. Des Moines Independent
    Community School Dist., 
    393 U.S. 503
    , 505 (1969); of a sit-in
    by black citizens in a segregated area, Brown v. Louisiana, 
    383 U.S. 131
    , 141-142 (1966); of the wearing of American military
    uniforms in a dramatic presentation criticizing American
    involvement in Vietnam, Schacht v. United States, 
    398 U.S. 58
    55
    that falls squarely within the doctrines discussed in the first
    sections may also be cast as expressive conduct. In those
    cases, application of the O’Brien test is inappropriate.
    We need only look at the seminal expressive
    association and compelled speech cases to see that this is so.
    In Dale, for example, the Supreme Court expressly declined
    to rely on O’Brien, explaining: “New Jersey’s public
    accommodations law directly and immediately affects
    associational rights, in this case associational rights that enjoy
    First Amendment protection. Thus, O’Brien is inapplicable.”
    
    530 U.S. at 659
    . Likewise in Wooley v. Maynard, the
    Supreme Court elected not to consider O’Brien because it
    considered compelled speech to be a “more appropriate First
    Amendment ground[].” 
    430 U.S. at 713
    . In short, the Court
    has not applied O’Brien where alternative First Amendment
    grounds were available.
    Taking our cue from the Supreme Court, because the
    Solomon Amendment is subject to strict scrutiny under the
    doctrines of expressive association and compelled speech, we
    need not engage in an O’Brien analysis. Because O’Brien
    scrutiny is intermediate rather than strict, demonstrating a
    constitutional violation under a theory of expressive conduct
    (1970); and of picketing in support of a wide variety of causes,
    see, e.g., Food Employees v. Logan Valley Plaza, Inc., 
    391 U.S. 308
    , 313-314 (1968).
    56
    is significantly more burdensome than under the models we
    have discussed. And the law schools need establish only one
    constitutional infirmity to justify an injunction. See, e.g., Sys.
    Operations, Inc. v. Scientific Games Dev. Corp., 
    555 F.2d 1131
    , 1144 (3d Cir. 1977).
    (b)     Even under O’Brien, the Solomon
    Amendment is likely to impair expressive
    conduct unconstitutionally.
    Even if O’Brien applied, we would reverse the District
    Court’s decision because we disagree with its application of
    intermediate scrutiny. Notwithstanding that the District
    Court’s opinion featured a consistent theme—that the
    Solomon Amendment “targets conduct, not speech”—the
    Court acknowledged a communicative or expressive element
    in the law schools’ policies against offering the schools’
    resources, support, or endorsement to any employer who does
    not conform to their antidiscrimination policies. FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at 311
    . Thus, to the extent we focus on the law
    schools’ conduct, it is nonetheless expressive.
    The First Amendment protects the right to engage in
    expressive conduct. See, e.g., NAACP v. Claiborne Hardware
    Co., 
    458 U.S. 886
    , 907 (1982) (recognizing the right of
    boycotters to “band[] together and collectively express[] their
    dissatisfaction with a social structure that had denied them
    rights to equal treatment and respect”); Spence v. Washington,
    57
    
    418 U.S. 405
    , 411 (1974) (acknowledging First Amendment
    protection for conduct that “convey[s] a particularized
    message” that is understood as expression in the context of
    surrounding circumstances). A government regulation
    impairing expressive conduct is only justified “[1] if it is
    within the constitutional power of the Government; [2] if it
    furthers an important or substantial governmental interest; [3]
    if the governmental interest is unrelated to the suppression of
    free expression; and [4] if the incidental restriction on alleged
    First Amendment freedoms is no greater than is essential to
    the furtherance of that interest.” O’Brien, 391 U.S. at 377.
    We take no issue with the District Court’s conclusion
    that the Solomon Amendment is within the constitutional
    power of the Government, as the Constitution authorizes
    Congress to raise and support a military. FAIR, 
    291 F. Supp. 2d at
    312 (citing U.S. Const. art. 1 § 8). We assume arguendo
    that the District Court was correct in determining that the
    Solomon Amendment is unrelated to the suppression of ideas.
    Id. at 314. And we of course presume that the United States
    has a vital interest in having a system for acquiring talented
    military lawyers. But as we noted above, the Government
    has chosen to submit no evidence that would support the
    necessity of requiring law schools to provide the military with
    a forum for, and assistance in, recruiting. Instead, the
    Government argues that “the impact of the wholesale
    exclusion of military recruiters [from law school campuses] is
    self-evident, and the government is not obligated” during
    58
    preliminary injunction proceedings “to assemble and present a
    factual record that merely confirms the dictates of common
    sense.” The Government fails to offer even an affidavit
    indicating that enforcement of the Solomon Amendment has
    enhanced military recruiting efforts. It suggests simply that
    the scope of the remedy sought by the plaintiffs relieves the
    Government of its obligation, pursuant to the First
    Amendment, to justify its curtailment of expression. How this
    is so we cannot conjure. We are unaware of any case so
    holding.26 And while the Government emphasizes that the
    Nation’s military is at stake, invoking the importance of a
    well-trained military is not a substitute for demonstrating that
    there is an important governmental interest in opening the law
    schools to military recruiting. See Rostker v. Goldberg, 
    453 U.S. 57
    , 89 (1981) (“‘[T]he phrase “war power” cannot be
    invoked as a talismanic incantation to . . . remove
    constitutional limitations safeguarding essential liberties.’”
    (quoting United States v. Robel, 
    389 U.S. 258
    , 263-64
    26
    The Government quotes Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Gov’t
    PAC, 
    528 U.S. 377
    , 378 (2000), for the proposition that “[t]he
    quantum of empirical evidence needed to satisfy heightened
    judicial scrutiny of legislative judgments will vary up or down
    with the novelty and plausibility of the justification raised.” But
    this is not a case where the Government has presented less
    evidence than might otherwise be required; here the
    Government has presented no evidence.
    59
    (1967))). 27
    It may be the case, as the Government argues, that on-
    campus recruitment is an employer’s principal tool for
    attracting talented students. But it does not thereby follow
    that recruiting by means of the Solomon Amendment is
    effective. On the contrary, it seems to us equally plausible
    that the Solomon Amendment has in fact hampered
    recruitment by subjecting the military’s exclusionary policy to
    public scrutiny. The record is replete with references to
    student protests and public condemnation. In this context, it
    is hardly “common sense,” as the military alleges, that its
    presence on campus amidst such commotion and opposition
    has aided its recruitment efforts.
    In closing, we emphasize again that we need not enter
    the thicket of O’Brien analysis in this case. We rely on the
    doctrines of expressive association and compelled speech to
    conclude that FAIR has made the requisite showing of a
    likelihood of success on the merits in support of its motion for
    27
    We note that this is not a case involving military discretion
    to determine whether internal policies are necessary and
    appropriate. Cf. Parker v. Levy, 
    417 U.S. 733
    , 743 (1974)
    (“[T]he military is, by necessity, a specialized society separate
    from civilian society” (citation omitted)). On the contrary, this
    case involves the military’s compelled presence on the campuses
    of civilian institutions.
    60
    a preliminary injunction. And even under the intermediate
    scrutiny test of O’Brien the Solomon Amendment falters thus
    far, for the Government has chosen not to produce any
    evidence that it is no more than necessary to further the
    Government’s interest. Perhaps this explains why the DOD
    initially objected to the Amendment as “unnecessary” and
    “duplicative.” 140 Cong. Rec. H3864 (daily ed. May 23,
    1994).
    C.     Other preliminary injunction factors
    By establishing a likelihood of success on the merits of
    its unconstitutional condition claim based on a First
    Amendment violation, FAIR has necessarily satisfied the
    second element: irreparable harm. Elrod v. Burns, 
    427 U.S. 347
    , 373 (1976) (“The loss of First Amendment freedoms, for
    even minimal periods of time, unquestionably constitutes
    irreparable injury.”); see also Beal v. Stern, 
    184 F.3d 117
    , 123
    (2d Cir. 1999) (“[T]he irreparable injury issue and the
    likelihood of success issue overlap almost entirely” in the
    First Amendment context). On the third element, we
    conclude that the balance of interest tips in FAIR’s favor.
    Without an injunction, the law schools’ First Amendment
    rights under the expressive association doctrine and the
    compelled speech doctrine will be impaired during on-campus
    recruiting seasons. The Government, on the other hand, does
    not lose the opportunity, in a proceeding on the merits, to
    “shoulder its full constitutional burden of proof” of showing
    61
    that a less restrictive alternative would not be as effective.
    Ashcroft v. ACLU, 
    124 S. Ct. 2783
    , 2794 (2004). As for the
    final element, we believe the public is best served by
    enjoining a statute that unconstitutionally impairs First
    Amendment rights.
    IV.   Conclusion
    The Solomon Amendment requires law schools to
    express a message that is incompatible with their educational
    objectives, and no compelling governmental interest has been
    shown to deny this freedom. While no doubt military lawyers
    are critical to the efficient operation of the armed forces, mere
    incantation of the need for legal talent cannot override a clear
    First Amendment impairment. Even were the test less
    rigorous than a compelling governmental riposte to the
    schools’ rights under the First Amendment, failure
    nonetheless is foreordained at this stage, for the military fails
    to provide any evidence that its restrictions on speech are no
    more than required to further its interest in attracting good
    legal counsel.
    In this context, the Solomon Amendment cannot
    condition federal funding on law schools’ compliance with it.
    FAIR has a reasonable likelihood of success on the merits and
    satisfies the other injunctive elements as well. We reverse
    and remand for the District Court to enter a preliminary
    injunction against enforcement of the Solomon Amendment.
    62
    FAIR et al. v. Rumsfeld et al., No. 03-4433
    ALDISERT, Circuit Judge, Dissenting.
    I would affirm the judgment of the district court.
    Although I have myriad problems with the fundamental
    contentions presented by the Appellants and the host of
    supporting amicus curiae briefs, essentially my disagreement
    is with the all-pervasive approach that this is a case of First
    Amendment protection in the nude. It is not.
    Rather, the issues before us are threefold. First, we
    must inquire whether Appellants have met the high burden of
    overcoming the presumption of constitutionality of a
    congressional statute that is not only bottomed on the
    Spending Clause, but on a number of other specific provisions
    in the Constitution that deal with Congress’ obligation to
    support the military. This is especially relevant because, in the
    entire history of the United States, no court heretofore has
    ever declared unconstitutional on First Amendment grounds
    any congressional statute specifically designed to support the
    military.
    Second, we must determine, using canons of logic,
    63
    whether a permissible factual inference—let alone a
    compellable one—may be properly drawn that the law
    schools’ anti-discrimination policies are violated from the
    sole evidentiary datum that a military recruiter appears on
    campus for a short time.
    Third, only if a proper inference may be drawn do we
    meet First Amendment considerations. The First Amendment
    is implicated if and only if, after applying the “balance-of-
    interests” test originally articulated by Justice Brennan in
    Roberts v. United States Jaycees, 
    468 U.S. 609
     (1984), it can
    be concluded that the operation of the First Amendment
    trumps the several clauses of Articles I and II relating to the
    spending power and support of the military.
    Upon analysis, the argument of the Appellants and
    many of the amici curiae, including but not limited to the
    Association of American Law Schools, is rather complex. Its
    point of beginning takes the following tripartite form: (1)
    most, but not all, accredited American law schools have
    adopted policies that indicate they will not discriminate based
    on age, race, color, national origin, disability, religion, gender
    or sexual orientation; (2) the law schools have committed
    themselves to “admit students, grant scholarships, grade
    exams, recruit and promote faculty, and hire staff in light of
    these principles” (J.A. at 509); (3) in conjunction with their
    own commitment not to discriminate, the law schools have
    adopted policies stating that they will not assist employers
    64
    who discriminate.
    Their intermediate statement is that the United States
    military excludes service members based on evidence of
    homosexual conduct or orientation. See 
    10 U.S.C. § 654
    (2004). From this, the law schools conclude that permitting
    the military to recruit on campus for military lawyers and
    military judges creates a compellable inference that the law
    schools are violating their own policies prohibiting
    discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation.
    They then move to the Solomon Amendment which
    provides that certain federal grants will not be made to “an
    institution of higher education ... if the Secretary of Defense
    determines that that institution ... has a policy or practice ..
    that either prohibits, or in effect prevents – (1) the Secretary
    of a military department or [the Department of Homeland
    Security] from gaining entry to campuses, or access to
    students (who are 17 years of age or older) on campuses, for
    purposes of military recruiting . . .” 28 
    10 U.S.C. § 983
    .
    28
    Congress has clarified that the funding restriction does not
    apply to the following: (1) federal grants of funds “to be
    available solely for student financial assistance or related
    administrative costs,” Pub. L. No. 106-79, § 8120, 
    113 Stat. 1260
     (Oct. 25, 1999); (2) an institution that ceased its prior
    policy or practice of prohibiting or effectively preventing entry
    to campus or access to students on campus for military
    65
    This year, Congress amended the Solomon
    Amendment to require military recruiting access “in a manner
    that is at least equal in quality and scope to the [degree of]
    access to campuses and to students that is provided to any
    other employer.” National Defense Authorization Bill for
    Fiscal Year 2005, Pub. L. No. 108-287 (2004).
    From the foregoing premises Appellants’ Second
    Amended Complaint alleges that the Solomon Amendment
    and regulations promulgated thereunder violate the First
    Amendment as applied to law schools by: (1) imposing
    unconstitutional conditions on the receipt of federal funding;
    (2) effecting viewpoint discrimination; (3) forcing the
    plaintiffs to endorse messages repugnant to them and
    suppressing their expression of dissent; and (4) imposing
    vague and overbroad restrictions on speech.
    I would hold that Congress’ use of the spending power
    and fulfillment of the requirements to maintain the military
    under Articles I and II do not unreasonably burden speech
    and, therefore, do not offend the First Amendment. I apply the
    balance-of-interests test and decide that the interest of
    protecting the national security of the United States outweighs
    recruiting, 
    10 U.S.C. § 983
    (c)(1); and (3) an institution that “has
    a longstanding policy of pacifism based on historical religious
    affiliation,” 
    10 U.S.C. § 983
    (c)(2).
    66
    the indirect and attenuated interest in the law schools’ speech,
    expressive association and academic freedom rights. The
    Solomon Amendment survives the constitutional attack
    because its provisions, the 2004 amendments thereto and
    related regulations, govern conduct while only incidentally
    affecting speech. In serving its compelling interest in
    recruiting military lawyers, the statute does not require the
    government to engage in unconstitutional conduct.
    Accordingly, with respect, I dissent. I agree with the
    thoughtful statement of reasons of the district court and would
    affirm its judgment.
    I.
    The starting point for analysis must be fealty to the
    precept that congressional statutes are presumed to be
    constitutional. See, e.g., Edward J. DeBartolo Corp. v. Florida
    Gulf Coast Bldg. & Constr. Trades Council, 
    485 U.S. 568
    ,
    575 (1988) (“‘[t]he elementary rule is that every reasonable
    construction must be resorted to, in order to save a statute
    from unconstitutionality.’”) (quoting Hooper v. California,
    
    155 U.S. 648
    , 657 (1895)); NLRB v. Catholic Bishop of
    Chicago, 
    440 U.S. 490
    , 500 (1979) ( “[A]n act of Congress
    ought not be construed to violate the Constitution if any other
    possible construction remains available.”). Thus in Rust v.
    Sullivan, 
    500 U.S. 173
     (1991), the Court teaches:
    The principle enunciated in Hooper v. California, 
    supra
    67
    and subsequent cases, is a categorical one: As between
    two possible interpretations of a statute, by one of
    which it would be unconstitutional and by the other
    valid, our plain duty is to adopt that which would save
    the Act. Blodgett v. Holden, 
    275 U.S. 142
    , 148 (1927)
    (opinion of Holmes, J.). This principle is based at least
    in part on the fact that a decision to declare an Act of
    Congress unconstitutional “is the gravest and most
    delicate duty that this Court is called on to perform.”
    
    Ibid.
     Following Hooper, 
    supra,
     cases such as United
    States ex rel. Attorney General v. Delaware & Hudson
    Co., 
    213 U.S. 366
    , 408 (1909), and United States v. Jin
    Fuey and Moy, 
    241 U.S. 394
    , 401 (1916), developed
    the corollary doctrine that “[a] statute must be
    construed, if fairly possible, so as to avoid not only the
    conclusion that it is unconstitutional but also grave
    doubts upon that score.” This canon is followed out of
    respect for Congress, which we assume legislates in
    the light of constitutional limitations. FTC v. American
    Tobacco Co., 
    260 U.S. 298
    , 305-307 (1924). It is
    qualified by the proposition that “avoidance of a
    difficulty will not be pressed to the point of
    disingenuous evasion.” George Moore Ice Cream Co.
    v. Rose, 
    298 U.S. 373
    , 379 (1933).
    
    Id. at 190-191
    .
    68
    It is noted that although the Supreme Court considers
    this principle “a categorical one,” it is not included in the
    majority’s analysis.
    II.
    A second disagreement with the approach of my
    distinguished brothers of the majority is that they have not
    identified by name or discussed the several important
    provisions of the Constitution that provide for the support of
    the military and that antedate the promulgation of the
    amendments contained in the Bill of Rights.
    Among the powers granted to Congress is the
    spending power: “The Congress shall have Power To lay and
    collect Taxes, Duties, Imposts and Excises, to pay the Debts
    and provide for the common Defence and general Welfare of
    the United States. . .” U.S. Const. art. I, § 8, cl. 1.
    Furthermore, Congress is specifically given several powers
    related to the military: (1) “[t]o declare War, grant Letters of
    Marque and Reprisal, and make Rules concerning Captures
    on Land and Water,” id. cl. 11; (2) “[t]o raise and support
    Armies, but no appropriation of Money to that Use shall be
    for a longer Term than two Years,” id. cl. 12; (3) “[t]o provide
    and maintain a Navy,” id. cl. 13; and (4) “[t]o make Rules for
    the Government and Regulation of the land and naval
    Forces,” id. cl. 14.
    69
    The Constitution also authorizes Congress “[t]o make
    all Laws which shall be necessary and proper for carrying into
    Execution the foregoing Powers, and all other Powers vested
    by this Constitution in the Government of the United States,
    or in any Department or Officer thereof.” Id. cl. 18.
    The Constitution further states: “[t]he President shall
    be Commander in Chief of the Army and Navy of the United
    States. . . .” Const. art. II, § 2, cl. 1. The President also “shall
    take Care that the Laws be faithfully executed . . .” Id. § 3, cl.
    1.
    Indeed, the only oblique reference to these
    countervailing provisions of the Constitution appears in the
    majority’s discussion of the unconstitutional conditions
    doctrine, citing Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of
    Va., 
    515 U.S. 819
     (1995) (public university could not
    condition funds for student publications on their secular
    perspective); FCC v. League of Women Voters, 
    468 U.S. 364
    (1984) (FCC could not condition federal funds to radio
    stations on editorial content); and Perry v. Sindermann, 
    408 U.S. 593
    , 597 (1972) (relating to non-renewal of a contract
    and citing cases relating to denials of tax exemptions and
    welfare payments, but emphasizing that “most often, we have
    applied the principle to denials of public employment”).
    Significantly, my research has not discovered any
    reported case where an act of Congress exclusively predicated
    70
    on supporting the military has been declared unconstitutional
    by application of the seminal doctrine that “[the government]
    may not deny a benefit to a person on a basis that infringes his
    constitutionally protected interests–especially, his interest in
    freedom of speech.” Speiser v. Randall, 
    357 U.S. 513
    , 526-
    529 (1958); see also Perry, 
    408 U.S. at 597
    . By reversing the
    district court’s judgment, the majority has created new law,
    totally unsupported by binding precedent. In doing so the
    majority selects analogues to cases where state public
    accommodation statutes were involved and not a single case
    where an act of Congress was not only authorized by various
    Clauses in Articles I and II, but commanded by them.
    In the posture of this case, Appellants do not urge that
    the Solomon Amendment is facially unconstitutional, but only
    that it is unconstitutional as applied to the law schools
    because it offends their stated policies of anti-discrimination.
    To succeed in their burden of overcoming the presumption of
    constitutionality of the Solomon Amendment, they must first
    demonstrate that the mere presence of recruiting officers on
    campus constitutes a compellable inference that the law
    schools will be objectively and reasonably viewed as violating
    their anti-discrimination policies. If they succeed at that stage,
    then they must demonstrate that the bite of the First
    Amendment under the facts of this case is so strong as to
    outweigh Congress’ interests to “provide for the common
    Defense . . .,” U.S. Const. art. I, § 8, cl. 1.; “declare War,
    grant Letters of Marque and Reprisal, and make Rules
    71
    concerning Captures on Land and Water,” id. cl. 11; “raise
    and support Armies, id. cl. 12; “provide and maintain a
    Navy,” id. cl. 13; “make Rules for the Government and
    Regulation of the land and naval Forces,” id. cl. 14; and for
    the President to “be Commander in Chief of the Army and
    Navy of the United States. . . .,” U.S. Const. art. II, § 2, cl. 1;
    and to “take Care that the Laws be faithfully executed . . .,”
    id. § 3, cl. 1.
    Before proceeding into this analysis, it bears note that
    the military’s policy against homosexual activity, codified at
    
    10 U.S.C. § 654
    , previously has been adjudged by a number
    of our sister courts of appeals not to violate the Constitution.
    See, e.g., Richenberg v. Perry, 
    97 F.3d 256
    , 261 (8th Cir.
    1996) (“We join six other circuits in concluding that the
    military may exclude those who engage in homosexual acts as
    defined in [10 U.S.C.] § 654(f)(3)(A).”).
    Moreover, in United States v. City of Phil., 
    798 F.2d 81
     (3d Cir. 1986) this court has discussed the very subject of
    this appeal. In that case, the Temple School of Law’s
    placement office invited the Judge Advocate General Corps
    of the Army, Navy and Marine Corps to participate in a job
    recruiting program on its campus. he Philadelphia
    Commission on Human Relations issued an order restraining
    the law school from doing so on the ground that the military
    services did not accept homosexuals. We affirmed a district
    court order prohibiting the Commission from taking any
    72
    adverse action. After reviewing Congressional legislation
    implementing what we described as “the long standing
    Congressional policy of encouraging colleges and universities
    to cooperate with, and open their campuses to, military
    recruiters,” we stated:
    We believe that only one reasonable conclusion can be drawn
    from this legislation: Congress considers access to college and
    university employment facilities by military recruiters to be a
    matter of paramount importance. In other words, we think that
    Congress views such access an integral part of the military’s
    effort to conduct “intensive recruiting campaigns to obtain
    enlistments.” This conclusion is buttressed by the legislative
    history of these provisions. For example, a committee report
    accompanying the DDA Act of 1973 states, in pertinent part,
    that “the Committee believes that [the] national interest is best
    served by colleges and universities which provide for the full
    spectrum of opportunity for various career fields, including
    the military field through the Reserve Officers Training Corps
    program, and by the opportunity for students to talk to all
    recruiting sources, including military recruiters.” H.R.Rep No.
    92-1149, 92d Cong., 2d Sess. 79 (1972). . . .
    We conclude, therefore, that the Order conflicts with a
    clearly discernible Congressional policy concerning military
    recruitment on the campuses of this nation’s colleges and
    universities.
    73
    
    Id. at 86, 88
    . We do not write on a clean slate regarding the
    importance Congress places in access to college and
    university facilities by the military. We already have decided
    that issue contrary to the argument pressed by the Appellants.
    And we made this determination almost twenty years ago.
    III.
    Before we address the application of First Amendment
    precepts, I am unwilling to accept that there is a permissible
    inference, let alone a compellable one, that a military presence
    on campus to recruit, in and of itself, conjures up an
    immediate impression of a discriminatory institution.
    Throughout our history, especially in times of war, like the
    present conflicts in Afghanistan and Iraq, and the military
    campaign against the Al Qaeda, a completely different
    impression is evoked. The men and women in uniform are
    almost universally considered as heroes, sacrificing not only
    their lives and well-being, but living separate from all the
    comforts of stateside living. Again in the current era, almost
    every day, a candidate for President emphasized his four
    months as a swift boat commander in the Vietnam conflict.
    As masters of public opinion, the political apparatus on both
    sides of the aisle certainly would not put a premium on
    military service if the inference of the discrimination
    advanced by Appellants here was attached thereto. Indeed, the
    respect to the man and woman in uniform is so profound that
    in the same Presidential campaign, the other candidate was
    74
    criticized for serving at home in a National Guard unit during
    the Vietnam conflict instead of going overseas.
    This view of service in the armed forces is at the
    farthest polar extreme from the Appellants’ position that the
    mere presence of military recruiters conjures up the image of
    an institution that discriminates. That the military does so in
    fact, does not, in and of itself, generate the direct and
    universal feeling of loathing and abomination to the extent
    that their presence on campus a few days a year deprives law
    school institutions of rights inferred from the First
    Amendment.
    What is involved here in the first instance is not
    operation of legal principles but precepts of logic that
    determine what can be properly inferred from stated
    circumstances. An inference is a process in which one
    proposition (a factual conclusion) is arrived at and affirmed
    on the basis of one or more other propositions, which were
    accepted as the starting point of the process. Professor
    Stebbing observes that an inference “may be defined as a
    mental process in which a thinker passes from the
    apprehension of something given, the datum, to something,
    the conclusion, related in a certain way to the datum, and
    accepted only because the datum has been accepted.” L.S.
    Stebbing, A M odern Introduction to Logic 211-212 (1948).
    Inference is a process where the thinker passes from
    75
    one proposition to another that is connected with the former in
    some way. But for the passage to be valid, it must be made
    according to the laws of logic that permit a reasonable
    movement from one proposition to another. Inference, then is
    “any passing from knowledge to new knowledge.” Joseph
    Gerard Brennan, A Handbook of Logic 1 (1957). The passage
    cannot be mere speculation, intuition or guessing. The key to
    a logical inference is the reasonable probability that the
    conclusion flows from the evidentiary datum because of past
    experiences in human affairs. A moment is necessary to
    discuss the difference between inference and implication.
    These terms are obverse sides of the same coin. We infer a
    conclusion from the data; the data imply a conclusion.
    Professor Cooley explains:
    [w]hen a series of statements is an instance of a valid
    form of inference, the conclusion will be said to follow from
    the premises, and the premises to imply the conclusion. If a
    set of premises implies a conclusion, then, whenever the
    premises are accepted as true, the conclusion must be
    accepted as true also . . . .
    John C. Cooley, A Primer of Formal Logic 13 (1942).
    As Professor Brennan put it: “In ordinary discourse,
    [implication] may mean ‘to give a hint,’ and [inference], ‘to
    take a hint.’” Brennan, A Handbook of Logic at 2-3. Drawing
    a proper inference is critical in this case, and this court has
    76
    heretofore suggested some broad guidelines:
    The line between a reasonable inference that
    may permissibly be drawn by a jury from basic
    facts in evidence and an impermissible
    speculation is not drawn by judicial
    idiosyncracies. The line is drawn by the laws of
    logic. If there is an experience of logical
    probability that an ultimate fact will follow a
    stated narrative or historical fact, then the jury is
    given the opportunity to draw a conclusion
    because there is a reasonable probability that the
    conclusion flows from the proven facts. As the
    Supreme Court has stated, “The essential
    requirement is that mere speculation be not
    allowed to do duty for probative facts after
    making due allowance for all reasonably
    possible inferences favoring the party whose
    case is attacked.”
    Tose v. First. Pa. Bank, N.A., 
    648 F.2d 879
    , 895 (3d Cir.
    1981) (quoting Galloway v. United States, 
    319 U.S. 372
    , 395
    (1943)).
    From these basic precepts of logic we cannot conclude
    that the mere presence of a uniformed military recruiter
    77
    permits or compels the inference that a law school’s anti-
    discrimination policy is violated. It bears repetition that the
    passage from datum to conclusion cannot be mere
    speculation, intuition, or guessing, or by “judicial
    idiosyncracies.” The subjective idiosyncratic impressions of
    some law students, some professors, or some anti-war
    protesters are not the test. What we know as men and women
    we cannot forget as judges. And this we know from
    elementary canons of logical processes—the validity vel non
    of a logical inference is the reasonable probability that the
    conclusion flows from the evidentiary datum because of past
    experiences in human affairs.
    A participant in a military operation cannot be ipso
    facto denigrated as a member of a discriminatory institution.
    And conjuring up such an image is the cornerstone of
    Appellant’s First Amendment argument.
    In my view it is not necessary to meet any First
    Amendment argument because given the evidentiary datum of
    a military recruiter on campus for a few days, a proper
    inference may not be drawn that this, in and of itself, supports
    a factual inference that the law school is violating its anti-
    discrimination policy. I think that this alone is sufficient to
    affirm the judgment of the district court.
    Nevertheless, I go further and assume that Appellants’
    suggested inference may properly be drawn as a fact, and now
    78
    turn to a discussion of whether First Amendment concerns
    trump the demands placed on Congress and the President
    under Articles I and II to support the military.
    IV.
    Our beginning point in approaching a First
    Amendment analysis is the balancing-of-interests test set forth
    in Justice Brennan’s important opinion in Roberts:
    Determining the limits of state authorities over
    an individual’s freedom to enter into a particular
    association therefore unavoidably entails a
    careful assessment of where that relationship’s
    objective characteristics locate it on a spectrum
    from the most intimate to the most attenuated of
    personal attachments. . . . We need not mark the
    potentially significant points on this terrain with
    any precision.
    468 U.S. at 620 (emphasis added). Moreover, important for
    our immediate purposes is the recognition that “[t]he right to
    associate for expressive purposes is not, however, absolute.
    Infringements on that right may be justified by regulations
    adopted to serve compelling state interests, unrelated to the
    suppression of ideas, that cannot be achieved through means
    79
    significantly less restrictive of associational freedoms.” Id. at
    623.
    Although dealing with distinctions between abortions
    and other procedures, Justice Blackmun emphasized that in
    constitutional matters we do not deal with absolutes. “The
    constitutionality of such distinction will depend on its degree
    and the justification for it.” Bellotti v. Baird, 
    428 U.S. 132
    ,
    149-150 (1976). For other cases discussing the necessity to
    weigh or balance conflicting interests, see also New York
    State Club Ass’n. Inc. v. City of New York, 
    487 U.S. 1
    (1988); Bd. of Dirs. of Rotary Int’l v. Rotary Club, 
    481 U.S. 537
     (1987); Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders
    Inc, 
    472 U.S. 749
    , 758 (1985) (“We have long recognized that
    not all speech is of equal First Amendment importance.”);
    Ohralik v. Ohio State Bar Ass’n, 
    436 U.S. 447
     (1978); Maher
    v. Roe, 
    432 U.S. 464
    , 473 (1977); Whalen v. Roe, 
    429 U.S. 589
    , 599, 600 and nn.24 and 26 (1977); Zacchini v. Scripps-
    Howard Broad. Co., 
    433 U.S. 562
     (1977) (emphasizing that a
    line has to be drawn between media reports that are protected
    and those that are not).
    A.
    I now turn to identify and then weigh competing
    interests involved in this case. I have written elsewhere that
    “[a]n interest is a social fact, factor or phenomenon reflected
    by a claim or demand or desire which human beings, either
    80
    individually or as groups or associations or relations, seek to
    satisfy and which has been recognized as socially valid by
    authoritative decision makers in society.” Ruggero J. Aldisert,
    The Judicial Process: Text, Materials and Cases 489 (2d ed.
    1996) (citing authorities). Two important interests conflict
    here. Using the formulation of Dean Roscoe Pound, they are:
    (1) “an interest in general safety, long recognized in the legal
    order in the maxim that the safety of the people is the highest
    law;” and (2) the social interest in political progress and
    individual mental self-assertion, taking form in “the [p]olicy
    in favor of free speech and free belief and opinion[.]” Roscoe
    Pound, “A Survey of Social Interests,” 
    57 Harv. L. Rev. 1
    , 17,
    34 (1943).
    The interest in public safety is expressed in the clauses
    of Articles I and II of the Constitution relating to support of
    the military; the interest in free speech is found in the First
    Amendment.
    I now proceed to weigh these interests.
    B.
    What is perceived to be the flash point of controversy
    here is whether the general interest in public safety has been
    trumped by the interests embodied in the First Amendment.
    Supporting the government’s position are the line of cases
    emphasizing the Supreme Court’s deference to Congress’
    81
    support of the military. Arrayed against this is Appellant’s
    insistence that the national defense interest is trumped by the
    teachings of Boy Scouts of Amer. v. Dale, 
    530 U.S. 640
    (2000), and Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian &
    Bisexual Group of Boston, 
    515 U.S. 557
     (1995).
    The Court has consistently deferred to congressional
    decisions relating to the military. “The case arises in the
    context of Congress’s authority over national defense and
    military affairs, and perhaps in no other area has the
    [Supreme] Court accorded Congress greater deference.”
    Rostker v. Goldberg, 
    453 U.S. 57
    , 64-65 (1981); see also
    Weiss v. United States, 
    510 U.S. 163
    , 177 (1994) (“Judicial
    deference . . . ‘is at its apogee’ when reviewing congressional
    decision making...” in the realm of military affairs). As the
    Supreme Court has explained, “[n]ot only is the scope of
    Congress’ constitutional power in this area broad, but the lack
    of competence on the part of the courts is marked.” Rostker,
    
    453 U.S. at 65
    ; see also Gilligan v. Morgan, 
    413 U.S. 1
    , 10
    (1973) (stating “it is difficult to conceive of an area of
    governmental activity in which the courts have less
    competence...”).
    For example, in Goldman v. Weinberger, 
    475 U.S. 503
    (1986), the Court rejected a Free Exercise challenge to a
    military dress regulation notwithstanding the plaintiff’s claim
    that the military’s assessment of the need for the regulation
    “is mere ipse dixit, with no support from actual experience or
    82
    a scientific study in the record, and is contradicted by expert
    testimony . . .” 
    Id. at 509
    . As the Court explained, “whether or
    not expert witnesses may feel that religious exceptions . . . are
    desirable is quite beside the point[;] [t]he desirability of dress
    regulations in the military is decided by the appropriate
    military officials, and they are under no constitutional
    mandate to abandon their considered professional judgment.”
    
    Id.
    Appellants suggest that even if the military requires
    physical access to campuses, there is no need for military
    recruiters to be given the same degree of access provided to
    other employers. It must be emphasized that even bare
    physical access is more than the Appellants are willing to
    tolerate; they are asserting a constitutional right to exclude the
    military from campuses altogether. Second, it is hardly
    credible for the Appellants to suggest that physical access
    alone is sufficient for effective military recruiting, particularly
    when other employers are being granted far more extensive
    and meaningful access. It is fair to assume that all of the
    facilities and services provided to prospective employers by
    law schools are intended to facilitate the hiring process. If
    military recruiters are denied the ability to reach students on
    the same terms as other employers, damage to military
    recruiting is not simply probable but inevitable. The Solomon
    Amendment reflects Congress’ judgment about the
    requirements of military recruiting, and “[t]he validity of such
    regulations does not turn on a judge’s agreement with the
    83
    responsible decision maker concerning the most appropriate
    method for promoting significant government interests.”
    United States v. Albertini, 
    472 U.S. 675
    , 689 (1985).
    What disturbs me personally and as a judge is that the
    law schools seem to approach this question as an academic
    exercise, a question on a constitutional law examination or a
    moot court topic, with no thought of the effect of their action
    on the supply of military lawyers and military judges in the
    operation of the Uniform Code of Military Justice. They make
    it perfectly clear that they are not opposed to military
    institutions as such; they only want to curtail recruitment of
    military lawyers and judges. It is important for private
    employers to appear on campus to recruit law school
    graduates for positions with law school-sponsored “On
    Campus Recruiting Days” or “On Campus Interviewing”
    replete with interviews, followed by dinners and parties, but
    somehow the military will recruit its lawyers without
    appearing on campus. Somehow, Appellants urge, better law
    graduates will be attracted to the military legal branches with
    its lower pay and fewer benefits by some other recruiting
    method, for example, from the ranks of undergraduate ROTC
    programs. 29 Much of Appellants’ brief takes the form of
    29
    The following colloquy took place at the oral argument:
    THE COURT: What else could the government do as a less
    restrictive alternative?
    84
    conclusory statements that the military is able to attract top of
    the line or high quality students without stepping foot on
    campus. There is no explanation, however, why the law
    schools consider it important to have private national law
    firms come to campus and boast about first year associates’
    salaries and signing bonuses and emphasize that if the
    students want to clerk for a federal judge for a year, the firm
    will add another bonus. This is not only OK for the private
    sector, but also it’s good for the law school. But we don’t
    want military recruiters to pollute our students. No, say the
    law schools, what’s sauce for the private sector goose is not
    sauce for the military gander. No, say the law schools, we
    don’t need a level playing field; let the military shift for
    themselves.
    In its demand for total exclusion of military recruiters
    from their campuses, “fair play” is not a phrase in the law
    schools’ lexicon. They obviously do not desire that our men
    and women in the armed services, all members of a closed
    society, obtain optimum justice in military courts with the
    best-trained lawyers and judges. It scarcely can be an
    exaggeration to suggest that in many respects the need for
    MR. ROSENKRANTZ: [A]ny number of things. Number one,
    ROTC, the single most effective recruiting device the military
    has, by their own admission.
    (Tr. at 25.)
    85
    specially competent lawyers and exceptionally qualified
    judges may be more important in a settled environment
    dominated by the strictures of discipline than in the open
    society of civilian life.
    V.
    I turn now to Appellants’ compelled speech argument.
    They argue that the Solomon Amendment trenches on their
    freedom of speech by compelling them to convey a message
    other than their own. In making this argument, the Appellants
    place principal reliance on the teachings of Hurley v. Irish-
    American Gay, Lesbian & Bisexual Group of Boston. The
    district court recognized, however, that nothing in Hurley
    suggests that the Solomon Amendment crosses the line into
    unconstitutionality. I agree completely and accept the
    government’s analysis of this issue.
    A.
    In Hurley, the Court held that a state public
    accommodation law could not constitutionally be applied to
    compel organizers of a St. Patrick’s Day parade to allow a
    group of gay, lesbian, and bisexual individuals to march in the
    parade for the purpose of conveying a public message about
    homosexual pride and solidarity. 515 U.S. at 572-581. The
    organizers did not object to the participation of the group’s
    members in the parade; the only question was whether the
    86
    group could participate in the parade “as its own parade unit
    carrying its own banner.” Id. at 572. The Court concluded that
    the law’s “apparent object is simply to require speakers to
    modify the content of their expression to whatever extent
    beneficiaries of the law choose to alter it with messages of
    their own,” and that in so doing, the law “violates the
    fundamental rule of protection under the First Amendment[]
    that a speaker has the autonomy to choose the content of his
    own message.” Id. at 573, 578.
    Hurley involved an effort by the government to dictate
    the content of a quintessential form of expressive activity—a
    public parade. The Court emphasized that parades “are . . . a
    form of expression, not just motion,” and “the inherent
    expressiveness of marching to make a point,” id. at 568,
    formed the predicate for its opinion. In contrast, there is
    nothing remotely so expressive about the activity of
    recruiting. The military engages in recruiting on college
    campuses for precisely the same reason as do other
    employers: to hire employees. Recruiting is undertaken solely
    for instrumental reasons, not expressive ones.
    To be sure, recruiting involves speaking, but the
    recruiter speaks purely as part of an economic transaction, and
    the expression is entirely subordinate to the transaction itself.
    It bears no resemblance to the activities of the would-be
    marchers in Hurley, who formed their group “for the very
    purpose of marching” in the parade, and who sought to march
    87
    “as a way to express pride in their Irish heritage as openly
    gay, lesbian, and bisexual individuals, to demonstrate that
    there are such men and women among those so descended,
    and to express their solidarity with like individuals who
    sought to march in New York’s St. Patrick’s Day parade.” Id.
    at 560, 570. In Hurley, unlike here, expression was not a
    subsidiary part of an instrumental activity; expression was the
    activity.
    The role of the parade organizers in Hurley consisted
    of choosing the messages that would comprise the parade, and
    the vice of the challenged statute was that the homosexual
    group’s protest message would be attributed to the organizers
    themselves. The Court reasoned that the group’s participation
    in the parade “would likely be perceived as having resulted
    from the Council’s customary determination about a unit
    admitted to the parade, that its message was worthy of
    presentation and quite possibly of support as well.” Id. at 575.
    Here, in contrast, the likelihood that members of a law
    school community will perceive a military recruiter’s on-
    campus activities as reflecting the school’s “customary
    determination” that the recruiter’s message is “worthy of
    presentation and quite possibly of support” is vanishingly
    small. Unlike bystanders watching a passing parade, law
    school students, and to be sure, their professors, are an
    extraordinarily sophisticated and well-informed group, who
    understand perfectly well that their schools admit military
    88
    recruiters not because they endorse any “message” that may
    be conveyed by the recruiters’ brief and transitory appearance
    on campus, but because the economic consequences of the
    Solomon Amendment have induced them to do so. The
    likelihood that the military’s recruiting will be seen as part of
    a law school’s own message is particularly small when
    schools can take— and have taken— ameliorative steps to
    publicize their continuing disagreement with the military’s
    policies and the reasons for their acquiescence in military
    recruiting.
    There is nothing to prevent the law school
    communities from making speeches discouraging military
    recruiting, posting signs and erecting huge billboards on
    campus or public approaches announcing their opposition and
    stating their reasons. That this is an important consideration
    has been emphasized by the Supreme Court in PruneYard
    Shopping Ctr. v. Robbins, 
    447 U.S. 74
     (1980):
    [f]inally, as far as appears here appellants can
    expressly disavow any connection with the
    message by simply posting signs in the area
    where the speakers or handbillers stand. Such
    signs, for example, could disclaim any
    sponsorship of the message and could explain
    that the persons are communicating their own
    messages by virtue of state law.
    89
    
    Id. at 87
    .
    Clearly, the interests expressed in Hurley lack the
    power to dilute the judiciary’s traditional deference to
    Congress in the interest of national defense.
    In addition to arguing that the Solomon Amendment
    trenches on freedom of speech simpliciter, the Appellants also
    contend that the statute infringes on the law schools’ interests
    in expressive association. Although the First Amendment
    provides a measure of protection to expressive association,
    “the Supreme Court has required a close relationship between
    the [government] action and the affected expressive activity to
    find a constitutional violation.” Pi Lambda Phi Fraternity, Inc.
    v. Univ. of Pittsburgh, 
    229 F.3d 435
    , 438 (3d Cir. 2000). In
    the case at bar, the impact of the Solomon Amendment on the
    law schools’ interests in expressive association is far too
    remote to violate the First Amendment. In applying the
    balancing-of-interests test of Roberts, I am persuaded that the
    law schools’ interests here fall at the remote extreme of
    Justice Brennan’s spectrum – “where that relationship’s
    objective characteristics locate it . . . [near] the most
    attenuated of personal attachments.” 468 U.S. at 620. It is
    important to say again that “[t]he right to associate for
    expressive purposes is not, however, absolute.” Id. at 623.
    First Amendment claims based on expressive
    association are subject to a three-step constitutional inquiry.
    90
    See Pi Lambda Phi, 
    229 F.3d at 442
    . The first question is
    “whether the group making the claim [is] engaged in
    expressive association.” 
    Id.
     If so, the next question is whether
    the government action at issue “significantly affect[s] the
    group’s ability to advocate its viewpoints.” 
    Id.
     If it does, the
    final question is whether the governmental interests served by
    the law outweigh the burden imposed on the group's
    associational interests. Id.; see also The Circle School v.
    Pappert, 
    381 F.3d 172
    , 178 (3d Cir. 2004). In the case at bar
    the district court found as a threshold matter that law schools
    are engaged in expressive association, but went on to
    determine that the Solomon Amendment does not place a
    significant burden on their associational interests and that, in
    any event, the governmental interests served by the Solomon
    Amendment outweigh whatever associational burden the law
    may impose. (J.A. at 54-75.)
    C.
    The majority invokes cases like Glickman v. Wileman
    Bros. & Elliott, Inc., 
    521 U.S. 457
    , 469-470 (1997), United
    States v. United Foods. Inc., 
    533 U.S. 405
     (2001), and
    Cochran v. Veneman, 
    359 F. 3d 263
    , (3d Cir. 2004), for the
    proposition that the Solomon Amendment impermissibly
    obligates them to "subsidize" military recruiting. In all these
    cases the challenged statutes obligated individuals to make
    direct payments of money to finance private speech with
    which they disagreed. Here, in contrast, the recruiting
    91
    activities of military recruiters are paid for exclusively with
    federal tax revenues; the Solomon Amendment does not
    obligate educational institutions to pay one red cent to the
    government or to a private organization. Although Appellants
    complain of having to provide "scarce interview space" and
    "make appointments," (Appellant br. at 31), this kind of
    physical accommodation simply does not present the
    constitutional concern underlying cases like Abood ,
    Glickman, United Foods and Cochran—the concern that
    compelling an individual to pay for someone else's speech
    impinges on his right to "believe as he will" and to have his
    beliefs "shaped by his mind and his conscience rather than
    coerced by the State." Abood, 
    431 U.S. at 235
    .
    Unlike Abood, this case does not involve the right to
    make or not make “contributions for political purposes.” 
    431 U.S. at 234
    . Unlike Glickman, there was no mandatory
    assessments similar to those to be paid by growers of
    nectarines, plums and peaches under regulations 7 C.F.R.
    sections 916.31©), 917.35(f) promulgated under the
    Agricultural Marketing Agreement Act, 
    7 U.S.C. § 601
     et seq.
    Unlike United Foods, there were no mandatory assessments
    similar to those imposed on mushroom producers for the
    purpose of funding generic mushroom advertisements under
    the Mushroom Act, 
    7 U.S.C. § 6101
    . Unlike Cochran, there
    were no mandatory assessments similar to those imposed on
    milk producers under the Dairy Promotion Stabilization Act
    of 1983, 
    7 U.S.C. § 4501
     et seq. The teachings of United
    92
    Foods and Cochran are not applicable because, unlike the
    compelled advertising scheme in those cases, the principal
    object of the Solomon Amendment is not communication of
    expression but rather a furtherance of the government’s
    compelling interest in raising and maintaining a military force
    as mandated by the Constitution. Unlike a regulatory scheme
    requiring subsidization of generic advertising for fruit,
    mushrooms or milk, the Solomon Amendment “impose[s] no
    restraint on the freedom of any [law school] to communicate
    any message to any audience . . . do[es] not compel any
    person to engage in any actual or symbolic speech . . . [and]
    do[es] not compel the [law schools] to endorse or to finance
    any political or ideological views.” Glickman v. Wileman
    Bros. & Elliott, Inc., 
    521 U.S. 457
    , 469-470 (1997).
    Moreover, even if law schools were being required to
    provide direct financial payments to the government to
    support military recruiting, which they manifestly are not, the
    First Amendment provides far more latitude for compelled
    financial support of governmental speech than it does for
    compelled support of private speech. See Abood, 
    431 U.S. at
    259 n. 13 (Powell, J., concurring in the judgment)
    ("Compelled [financial] support of a private association is
    fundamentally different from compelled support of
    government"); United States v. Frame, 
    885 F.2d 1119
    , 1130-
    1133 (3rd Cir. 1989).
    Finally, what we said in Frame is relevant here:
    93
    Both the right to be free from compelled expressive
    association and the right to be free from compelled
    affirmation of belief presuppose a coerced nexus between the
    individual and the specific expressive activity. When the
    government allocates money from the general tax fund to
    controversial protects or expressive activities, the nexus
    between the message and the individual is attenuated.
    
    885 F. 2d at 1132
    .
    It becomes necessary to say again that our task in this
    case is to identify and weigh competing interests and to
    emphasize again that in applying the balancing-of-interests
    test of Roberts v. United States Jaycees, 
    468 U.S. 609
     (1984),
    the law schools’ interests here fall at the remote extreme of
    Justice Brennan’s spectrum— “where that relationship’s
    objective characteristics locate it . . . [near] the most
    attenuated of personal attachments.” 468 U.S. at 620.
    The attempt to analogize the First Amendment
    considerations in compelling an individual to pay for someone
    else's speech with a program of military recruiting fails
    completely because the extreme differences in the compared
    factual scenarios totally dominate over any purported
    94
    resemblances. What we explained in In re Linerboard Anti
    Trust Litig., 
    305 F. 3d 145
     (3d Cir. 2002), is appropriate here:
    To draw an analogy between two entities is to indicate one or
    more respects in which they are similar and thus argue that the
    legal consequence attached to one set of particular facts may
    apply to a different set of particular facts because of the
    similarities in the two sets. Because a successful analogy is
    drawn by demonstrating the resemblances or similarities in
    the facts, the degree of similarity is always the crucial
    element. You cannot conclude that only a partial resemblance
    between two entities is equal to a substantial or exact
    correspondence.
    
    Id. at 147
    .
    VI.
    In challenging the district court’s reasoning,
    Appellants also seek to analogize this case to the teachings of
    Dale. As the district court recognized, (J.A. 68-70), a
    comparison of this case to Dale shows not why the Appellants
    should prevail in this case, as urged by the majority, but why
    they must lose, see id. at 648-650.
    In Dale, the Court was presented with a New Jersey
    95
    public accommodations law that compelled the Boy Scouts of
    America (“BSA”) to admit “an avowed homosexual and gay
    rights activist,” id. at 644, as an adult member and
    scoutmaster. The declared mission of the BSA was to “instill
    values in young people,” id. at 649, and disapproval of
    homosexual conduct was one of BSA’s values. BSA relied on
    its scoutmasters to “inculcate [Boy Scouts] with the Boy
    Scouts’ values—both expressly and by example.” Id. at 650.
    The Court reasoned that “[t]he forced inclusion of an
    unwanted person in a group infringes the group’s freedom of
    expressive association if the presence of that person affects in
    a significant way the group’s ability to advocate public or
    private viewpoints.” Id. at 648. The Court found that “the
    presence of Dale as an assistant scoutmaster would surely
    interfere with the Boy Scouts’ choice not to propound a point
    of view contrary to its beliefs,” because it would “force the
    organization to send a message, both to the youth members
    and the world, that the Boy Scouts accept[] homosexual
    conduct as a legitimate form of behavior.” Id. at 653-654.
    Let me now count the two ways the Solomon
    Amendment differs from the state statute in Dale, both of
    which are critical to the law’s impact vel non on associational
    interests. First, the Solomon Amendment simply does not
    impinge on the right of educational institutions to determine
    their membership. See 
    10 U.S.C. § 983
    . It does not purport to
    tell colleges and universities whom to admit as students or
    whom to hire as professors or administrators. It merely
    96
    requires them to allow the transient presence of recruiters,
    who are not a part of the law school and do not become
    members through their mere presence. In contrast to the
    scoutmaster in Dale, recruiters do not purport to speak
    “for”—and cannot reasonably be understood to be speaking
    “for”—the law schools that they are visiting. This case thus
    does not involve “[t]he forced inclusion of an unwanted
    person in a group.” Dale, 
    530 U.S. at 648
    . It cannot be denied
    that this was the genesis of the constitutional injury in Dale.
    Second, as noted in my discussion of Hurley, recruiting
    is an economic activity whose expressive content is strictly
    secondary to its instrumental goals. In contrast, the
    fundamental goal of the relationship between adult leaders
    and boys in the Boy Scout movement is “[t]o instill values in
    young people,” a goal that is pursued “by example” as well as
    by word. 
    Id. at 649, 650
    . As a result, compelling the BSA to
    appoint an adult leader who was committed to “advocacy of
    homosexual teenagers’ need for gay role models,” 
    id. at 645
    ,
    struck at the heart of the organization’s goals.
    Military recruiting is not intended to “instill values” in
    anyone, nor is it meant to convey any message beyond the
    military’s interest in enlisting qualified men and women to
    serve as military lawyers and judges. As a result, the burden
    on the law schools’ associational interests is vastly less
    significant than the burden imposed on the BSA by the statute
    in Dale.
    97
    These profound distinctions demonstrate that the
    teachings of Dale lack the power to dilute the judiciary’s
    traditional deference to Congress in the interest of national
    defense.
    VII.
    I now turn to the proper measure by which to evaluate
    the weighing of competing interests implicated in this case.
    There should be no question that the teachings of United
    States v. O’Brien, 
    391 U.S. 367
     (1968), control. In that case,
    the Court considered whether a 1965 amendment to the
    Universal Military Training and Service Act, which
    prohibited the knowing destruction or mutilation of a
    Selective Service Registration Certificate, was
    unconstitutional as applied to a man who burned his
    certificate as a symbolic expression of his antiwar beliefs. 
    Id. at 369-370
    . The Court stated:
    We cannot accept the view that an apparently
    limitless variety of conduct can be labeled
    “speech” whenever the person engaging in the
    conduct intends thereby to express an idea.
    However, even on the assumption that the
    alleged communicative element in O’Brien’s
    conduct is sufficient to bring into play the First
    Amendment, it does not necessarily follow that
    the destruction of a registration certificate is
    98
    constitutionally protected activity. This Court
    has held that when “speech” and “nonspeech”
    elements are combined in the same course of
    conduct, a sufficiently important governmental
    interest in regulating the nonspeech element can
    justify incidental limitations on First
    Amendment freedoms.
    
    Id. at 376
    .
    In this case, the law schools portray their efforts to
    keep military recruiters off their campuses as “quintessential
    expression.” (Appellant br. at 20.) But when an institution
    excludes military recruiters from its campuses or otherwise
    restricts their access to students, it is engaging in something
    different from “quintessential expression.” It is engaging in a
    course of conduct which contains both nonspeech and speech
    elements. The acts which the law schools claim they are
    compelled to do by virtue of the military’s post-2001
    “unwritten policy”—disseminating and posting military
    recruitment literature, making appointments for military
    recruiters to meet with students and providing military
    recruiters a place to meet with students—also contain both
    nonspeech and speech elements.
    The constitutional framework for evaluating such laws
    99
    is provided by O’Brien. Regulation of conduct that imposes
    incidental burdens on expression is constitutional if “it
    furthers an important or substantial governmental interest; if
    the governmental interest is unrelated to the suppression of
    free expression; and if the incidental restriction on alleged
    First Amendment freedoms is no greater than is essential to
    the furtherance of that interest.” 391 U.S. at 377. “[A]n
    incidental burden on speech is no greater than is essential, and
    therefore is permissible under O’Brien, so long as the neutral
    regulation promotes a substantial government interest that
    would be achieved less effectively absent the regulation.”
    Albertini, 
    472 U.S. at 689
    . Regulations of conduct that place
    incidental burdens on expression are not subject to a least-
    restrictive-alternative requirement “[s]o long as the means
    chosen are not
    substantially broader than necessary to achieve the government’s
    interest, . . . the regulation will not be invalid simply because a
    court concludes that the government's interest could be
    adequately served by some less-speech-restrictive alternative.”
    Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 
    491 U.S. 781
    , 800 (1989).
    The Solomon Amendment readily passes constitutional
    muster under these constitutional standards. The Appellants
    themselves do not dispute that the government has a substantial
    interest—indeed, a compelling one— in recruiting talented men
    and women for the nation’s armed forces. As the Court
    recognized in O’Brien, “the Nation has a vital interest in having
    a system for raising armies that functions with maximum
    efficiency . . .” 391 U.S. at 381. Effective military recruiting is
    the linchpin of that system. See City of Phil., 
    798 F.2d at 86
    (“Congress considers access to college and university
    employment facilities by military recruiters to be a matter of
    paramount importance.”)
    The government’s interest in military recruiting, as
    embodied in the Solomon Amendment, is manifestly “unrelated
    to the suppression of free expression.” O’Brien, 391 U.S. at 377.
    The Solomon Amendment makes no effort to condition federal
    funding on the absence of campus criticism of military policies;
    a law school and its faculty and students are free to denounce
    military recruiting policies without jeopardizing federal funding
    in the slightest. The only thing that
    matters under the Solomon Amendment is whether the
    institution is denying access to military recruiters. And if the
    institution is denying access, it is irrelevant under the Solomon
    Amendment whether its reasons for doing so are communicative
    (to convey a message about its own principles or those of the
    military) or non-communicative (for example, to avoid
    participation in a recruiting process that it regards as unfair).
    What matters under the Solomon Amendment is “only the
    independent noncommunicative impact of [the] conduct,” id. at
    382,—its impact on the ability of the military to reach students.
    The Appellants argue that because the Solomon
    Amendment is intended to facilitate military recruiting, and
    because recruiters speak to students, the governmental interest
    underlying the Solomon Amendment “is not unrelated to
    expression.” (Appellant br. at 26.) But the question posed by
    O’Brien is not whether the governmental interest is “unrelated
    to expression,” but instead whether the interest “is unrelated to
    the suppression of free expression.” 391 U.S. at 377 (emphasis
    added). The Appellants’ argument deliberately omits the
    touchstone of suppression from the constitutional test. Once it
    is recognized that suppression of expression is the focus of
    O’Brien, the Appellants’ argument falls apart, for the
    governmental interests served by the Solomon Amendment are
    manifestly unrelated to the suppression of anyone’s expression.
    It bears constant emphasis that the First Amendment test
    involves a balancing-of-interests as repeatedly emphasized
    above. The O’Brien measure is quintessentially correct because
    this case involves a weighing of the government’s interest in
    national defense and Appellants’ interest in First Amendment
    protections. In this posture it is difficult to conjure a case that is
    a more perfect fit for the exposition in O’Brien.
    For the foregoing reasons, I respectfully dissent.
    102
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 03-4433P

Citation Numbers: 390 F.3d 219, 2004 WL 2698052

Judges: Ambro, Aldisert, Stapleton

Filed Date: 11/29/2004

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 11/5/2024

Authorities (53)

New York State Club Assn., Inc. v. City of New York , 108 S. Ct. 2225 ( 1988 )

Organization for a Better Austin v. Keefe , 91 S. Ct. 1575 ( 1971 )

Gilligan v. Morgan , 93 S. Ct. 2440 ( 1973 )

PruneYard Shopping Center v. Robins , 100 S. Ct. 2035 ( 1980 )

National Ass'n for the Advancement of Colored People v. ... , 102 S. Ct. 3409 ( 1982 )

Federal Communications Commission v. League of Women Voters ... , 104 S. Ct. 3106 ( 1984 )

joseph-s-cochran-brenda-s-cochran-v-ann-veneman-secretary-us , 359 F.3d 263 ( 2004 )

Hooper v. California , 15 S. Ct. 207 ( 1895 )

Galloway v. United States , 63 S. Ct. 1077 ( 1943 )

Perry v. Sindermann , 92 S. Ct. 2694 ( 1972 )

Village of Schaumburg v. Citizens for a Better Environment , 100 S. Ct. 826 ( 1980 )

Sable Communications of California, Inc. v. Federal ... , 109 S. Ct. 2829 ( 1989 )

Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of University of Virginia , 115 S. Ct. 2510 ( 1995 )

United States v. American Library Assn., Inc. , 123 S. Ct. 2297 ( 2003 )

FORUM FOR ACAD. & INSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS v. Rumsfeld , 291 F. Supp. 2d 269 ( 2003 )

system-operations-inc-a-delaware-corporation-and-mathematica-inc-a , 555 F.2d 1131 ( 1977 )

West Virginia State Board of Education v. Barnette , 63 S. Ct. 1178 ( 1943 )

Riley v. National Federation of Blind of North Carolina, ... , 108 S. Ct. 2667 ( 1988 )

Brown v. Louisiana , 86 S. Ct. 719 ( 1966 )

Northeastern Florida Chapter of the Associated General ... , 113 S. Ct. 2297 ( 1993 )

View All Authorities »