Bryan Range v. Attorney General United States ( 2023 )


Menu:
  •                                        PRECEDENTIAL
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE THIRD CIRCUIT
    ______________
    No. 21-2835
    ______________
    BRYAN DAVID RANGE,
    Appellant
    v.
    ATTORNEY GENERAL UNITED STATES OF AMERICA;
    REGINA LOMBARDO, Acting Director, Bureau of Alcohol,
    Tobacco, Firearms and Explosives
    ______________
    On Appeal from the United States District Court
    for the Eastern District of Pennsylvania
    (D.C. No. 5:20-CV-03488)
    District Judge: Honorable Gene E.K. Pratter
    ______________
    Argued before Merits Panel on September 19, 2022
    Argued En Banc on February 15, 2023
    ______________
    Before: CHAGARES, Chief Judge, JORDAN, HARDIMAN,
    GREENAWAY, JR., SHWARTZ, KRAUSE, RESTREPO,
    BIBAS, PORTER, MATEY, PHIPPS, FREEMAN,
    MONTGOMERY-REEVES, ROTH,* and AMBRO,**
    Circuit Judges.
    (Filed: June 6, 2023)
    William V. Bergstrom
    Peter A. Patterson [Argued]
    David H. Thompson
    Cooper & Kirk
    1523 New Hampshire Avenue, N.W.
    Washington, DC 20036
    Michael P. Gottlieb
    Vangrossi & Recchuiti
    319 Swede Street
    Norristown, PA 19401
    Counsel for the Appellant
    Joseph G. S. Greenlee
    Firearms Policy Coalition Action
    5550 Painted Mirage Road
    Suite 320
    Las Vegas, NV 89149
    *
    Judge Roth is participating as a member of the en banc court
    pursuant to 3d Cir. I.O.P. 9.6.4.
    **
    Judge Ambro assumed senior status on February 6, 2023 and
    elected to continue participating as a member of the en banc
    court pursuant to 3d Cir. I.O.P. 9.6.4.
    2
    Counsel for Amici Curiae FPC Action Foundation and
    Firearms Policy Coalition, Inc. in Support of Appellant
    Lisa B. Freeland
    Renee Pietropaolo
    Eleni Kousoulis
    K. Anthony Thomas
    Helen A. Marino
    Heidi R. Freese
    Matthew Campbell
    Office of Federal Public Defender
    1001 Liberty Avenue
    1500 Liberty Center
    Pittsburgh, PA 15222
    Counsel for Amicus Curiae Federal Public &
    Community Defender Organization of the Third
    Circuit in Support of Appellant
    Brian M. Boynton
    Jacqueline C. Romero
    Mark B. Stern
    Michael S. Raab
    Abby C. Wright
    Kevin B. Soter [Argued]
    United States Department of Justice
    Civil Division
    950 Pennsylvania Avenue, N.W.
    Washington, DC 20530
    Counsel for the Appellees
    3
    Janet Carter
    Everytown Law
    450 Lexington Avenue
    P.O. Box 4148
    New York, NY 10017
    Counsel for Amicus Curiae Everytown for Gun Safety
    in Support of Appellees
    ______________
    OPINION OF THE COURT
    ______________
    HARDIMAN, Circuit Judge, with whom CHAGARES, Chief
    Judge, and JORDAN, GREENAWAY, JR., BIBAS,
    PORTER, MATEY, PHIPPS, and FREEMAN, Circuit
    Judges, join.
    Bryan Range appeals the District Court’s summary
    judgment rejecting his claim that the federal “felon-in-
    possession” law—
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1)—violates his Second
    Amendment right to keep and bear arms. We agree with Range
    that, despite his false statement conviction, he remains among
    “the people” protected by the Second Amendment. And
    because the Government did not carry its burden of showing
    that our Nation’s history and tradition of firearm regulation
    support disarming Range, we will reverse and remand.
    4
    I
    A
    The material facts are undisputed. In 1995, Range
    pleaded guilty in the Court of Common Pleas of Lancaster
    County to one count of making a false statement to obtain food
    stamps in violation of Pennsylvania law. See 62 Pa. Stat. Ann.
    § 481(a). In those days, Range was earning between $9.00 and
    $9.50 an hour as he and his wife struggled to raise three young
    children on $300 per week. Range’s wife prepared an
    application for food stamps that understated Range’s income,
    which she and Range signed. Though he did not recall
    reviewing the application, Range accepted full responsibility
    for the misrepresentation.
    Range was sentenced to three years’ probation, which
    he completed without incident. He also paid $2,458 in
    restitution, $288.29 in costs, and a $100 fine. Other than his
    1995 conviction, Range’s criminal history is limited to minor
    traffic and parking infractions and a summary offense for
    fishing without a license.
    When Range pleaded guilty in 1995, his conviction was
    classified as a Pennsylvania misdemeanor punishable by up to
    five years’ imprisonment. That conviction precludes Range
    from possessing a firearm because federal law generally makes
    it “unlawful for any person . . . who has been convicted in any
    court, of a crime punishable by imprisonment for a term
    exceeding one year” to “possess in or affecting commerce, any
    firearm or ammunition.” 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1). Although state
    misdemeanors are excluded from that prohibition if they are
    “punishable by a term of imprisonment of two years or less,”
    5
    
    18 U.S.C. § 921
    (a)(20)(B), that safe harbor provided no refuge
    for Range because he faced up to five years’ imprisonment.
    In 1998, Range tried to buy a firearm but was rejected
    by Pennsylvania’s instant background check system. Range’s
    wife, thinking the rejection a mistake, gifted him a deer-
    hunting rifle. Years later, Range tried to buy a firearm and was
    rejected again. After researching the reason for the denial,
    Range learned he was barred from buying a firearm because of
    his 1995 conviction. Range then sold his deer-hunting rifle to
    a firearms dealer.
    B
    Range sued in the United States District Court for the
    Eastern District of Pennsylvania, seeking a declaration that
    § 922(g)(1) violates the Second Amendment as applied to him.
    He also requested an injunction prohibiting the law’s
    enforcement against him. Range asserts that but for
    § 922(g)(1), he would “for sure” purchase another deer-
    hunting rifle and “maybe a shotgun” for self-defense at home.
    App. 197–98. Range and the Government cross-moved for
    summary judgment.
    The District Court granted the Government’s motion.
    Range v. Lombardo, 
    557 F. Supp. 3d 609
    , 611 (E.D. Pa. 2021).
    Faithfully applying our then-controlling precedents, the Court
    held that Range’s crime was “serious” enough to deprive him
    of his Second Amendment rights. 
    Id.
     In doing so, the Court
    noted the two-step framework we established in United States
    v. Marzzarella, 
    614 F.3d 85
     (3d Cir. 2010). Range, 557 F.
    Supp. 3d at 613. The Court began—and ended—its analysis at
    the first step. It considered five factors to determine whether
    Range’s conviction made him an “unvirtuous citizen” of the
    6
    kind historically barred from possessing a firearm: (1) whether
    the conviction was classified as a misdemeanor or a felony; (2)
    whether the elements of the offense involve violence; (3) the
    sentence imposed; (4) whether there was a cross-jurisdictional
    consensus as to the seriousness of the crime, Binderup v. Att’y
    Gen., 
    836 F.3d 336
    , 351–52 (3d Cir. 2016) (en banc)
    (plurality); and (5) the potential for physical harm to others
    created by the offense, Holloway v. Att’y Gen., 
    948 F.3d 164
    ,
    173 (3d Cir. 2020). Range, 557 F. Supp. 3d at 613–14.
    The Government conceded that four of the five factors
    favored Range because he was convicted of a nonviolent, non-
    dangerous misdemeanor and had not been incarcerated. Id. at
    614. But the District Court held the “cross-jurisdictional
    consensus” factor favored the Government because about 40
    jurisdictions would have classified his crime as a felony. Id. at
    614–15. Noting that our decisions in Holloway, 948 F.3d at
    177, and Folajtar v. Att’y Gen., 
    980 F.3d 897
    , 900 (3d Cir.
    2020), had rejected as-applied challenges to § 922(g)(1)
    despite only one of the relevant factors weighing in the
    Government’s favor, the District Court held that the cross-
    jurisdictional consensus alone sufficed to disarm Range.
    Range, 557 F. Supp. 3d at 615–16. Range timely appealed.
    While Range’s appeal was pending, the Supreme Court
    decided New York State Rifle & Pistol Ass’n, Inc. v. Bruen, 
    142 S. Ct. 2111 (2022)
    . The parties then submitted supplemental
    briefing on Bruen’s impact. A panel of this Court affirmed the
    District Court’s summary judgment, holding that the
    Government had met its burden to show that § 922(g)(1)
    reflects the Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation
    such that Range’s conviction “places him outside the class of
    people traditionally entitled to Second Amendment rights.”
    7
    Range v. Att’y Gen., 
    53 F.4th 262
    , 266 (3d Cir. 2022) (per
    curiam).
    Range petitioned for rehearing en banc. We granted the
    petition and vacated the panel opinion. Range v. Att’y Gen., 
    56 F.4th 992
     (3d Cir. 2022).
    II
    The District Court had jurisdiction under 
    28 U.S.C. § 1331
     because Range’s complaint raised a federal question:
    whether the federal felon-in-possession law, 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1), violates the Second Amendment as applied to
    Range. We have jurisdiction under 
    28 U.S.C. § 1291
    .
    III
    In District of Columbia v. Heller, the Supreme Court
    held that the Second Amendment guarantees an individual
    right to keep and bear arms unconnected with militia service.
    
    554 U.S. 570
    , 583–84 (2008). In view of that right, the Court
    held unconstitutional a District of Columbia law that banned
    handguns and required other “firearms in the home be rendered
    and kept inoperable at all times.” 
    Id. at 630
    . It reached that
    conclusion after scrutinizing the text of the Second
    Amendment and deducing that it “codified a pre-existing
    right.” 
    Id. at 592
    . The Heller opinion did not apply
    intermediate or strict scrutiny. In fact, it did not apply means-
    end scrutiny at all. But in response to Justice Breyer’s dissent,
    the Court noted in passing that the challenged law would be
    unconstitutional “[u]nder any of the standards of scrutiny that
    we have applied to enumerated constitutional rights.” 
    Id.
     at
    628–29.
    8
    Many courts around the country, including this one,
    overread that passing comment to require a two-step approach
    in Second Amendment cases, utilizing means-end scrutiny at
    the second step. We did so for the first time in Marzzarella,
    
    614 F.3d at 97
    , and we continued down that road for over a
    decade. See, e.g., Drake v. Filko, 
    724 F.3d 426
    , 429, 434–40
    (3d Cir. 2013); Binderup, 
    836 F.3d at
    344–47, 353–56; Ass’n
    of N.J. Rifle & Pistol Clubs, Inc. v. Att’y Gen. N.J., 
    910 F.3d 106
    , 117 (3d Cir. 2018); Beers v. Att’y Gen., 
    927 F.3d 150
    ,
    154–55 (3d Cir. 2019), vacated sub nom. as moot, Beers v.
    Barr, 
    140 S. Ct. 2758 (2020)
    ; Holloway, 948 F.3d at 169–172;
    Folajtar, 980 F.3d at 901.
    Bruen rejected the two-step approach as “one step too
    many.” 142 S. Ct. at 2127. The Supreme Court declared:
    “Heller and McDonald do not support applying means-end
    scrutiny in the Second Amendment context.” Id. Instead, those
    cases teach “that when the Second Amendment’s plain text
    covers an individual’s conduct, the Constitution presumptively
    protects that conduct.” Id. at 2126. And “[o]nly if a firearm
    regulation is consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition
    may a court conclude that the individual’s conduct falls outside
    the Second Amendment’s ‘unqualified command.’” Id.
    (quoting Konigsberg v. State Bar of Cal., 
    366 U.S. 36
    , 50 n.10
    (1961)).
    Applying that standard, Bruen held “that the Second and
    Fourteenth Amendments protect an individual’s right to carry
    a handgun for self-defense outside the home.” Id. at 2122. But
    the “where” question decided in Bruen is not at issue here.
    Range’s appeal instead requires us to examine who is among
    “the people” protected by the Second Amendment. U.S. Const.
    amend. II; see Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2157 (Alito, J., concurring)
    (“Our holding decides nothing about who may lawfully
    9
    possess a firearm . . . .”); see also Eugene Volokh,
    Implementing the Right to Keep and Bear Arms for Self-
    Defense: An Analytical Framework and a Research Agenda,
    
    56 UCLA L. Rev. 1443
     (2009) (distinguishing among “who,”
    “what,” “where,” “when,” and “how” restrictions). Range
    claims he is one of “the people” entitled to keep and bear arms
    and that our Nation has no historical tradition of disarming
    people like him. The Government responds that Range has not
    been one of “the people” since 1995, when he pleaded guilty
    in Pennsylvania state court to making a false statement on his
    food stamp application, and that his disarmament is historically
    supported.
    IV
    Having explained how Bruen abrogated our Second
    Amendment jurisprudence, we now apply the Supreme Court’s
    established method to the facts of Range’s case. Both sides
    agree that we no longer conduct means-end scrutiny. And as
    the panel wrote: “Bruen’s focus on history and tradition,”
    means that “Binderup’s multifactored seriousness inquiry no
    longer applies.” Range, 53 F.4th at 270 n.9.
    After Bruen, we must first decide whether the text of the
    Second Amendment applies to a person and his proposed
    conduct. 142 S. Ct. at 2134–35. If it does, the government now
    bears the burden of proof: it “must affirmatively prove that its
    firearms regulation is part of the historical tradition that
    delimits the outer bounds of the right to keep and bear arms.”
    Id. at 2127.
    10
    A
    We begin with the threshold question: whether Range is
    one of “the people” who have Second Amendment rights. The
    Government contends that the Second Amendment does not
    apply to Range at all because “[t]he right to bear arms has
    historically extended to the political community of law-
    abiding, responsible citizens.” Gov’t En Banc Br. at 2. So
    Range’s 1995 conviction, the Government insists, removed
    him from “the people” protected by the Second Amendment.
    The Supreme Court referred to “law-abiding citizens”
    in Heller. In response to Justice Stevens’s dissent, which relied
    on United States v. Miller, 
    307 U.S. 174
     (1939), the Court
    reasoned that “the Second Amendment does not protect those
    weapons not typically possessed by law-abiding citizens for
    lawful purposes.” Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 625
    . In isolation, this
    language seems to support the Government’s argument. But
    Heller said more; it explained that “the people” as used
    throughout the Constitution “unambiguously refers to all
    members of the political community, not an unspecified
    subset.” 
    Id. at 580
    . So the Second Amendment right, Heller
    said, presumptively “belongs to all Americans.” 
    Id. at 581
    .
    Range cites these statements to argue that “law-abiding
    citizens” should not be read “as rejecting Heller’s
    interpretation of ‘the people.’” Range Pet. for Reh’g at 8. We
    agree with Range for four reasons.
    First, the criminal histories of the plaintiffs in Heller,
    McDonald, and Bruen were not at issue in those cases. So their
    references to “law-abiding, responsible citizens” were dicta.
    And while we heed that phrase, we are careful not to overread
    it as we and other circuits did with Heller’s statement that the
    District of Columbia firearm law would fail under any form of
    11
    heightened scrutiny. Second, other Constitutional provisions
    reference “the people.”1 It mentions “the people” twice with
    respect to voting for Congress,2 and “the people” are
    recognized as having rights to assemble peaceably, to petition
    the government for redress,3 and to be protected against
    unreasonable searches and seizures.4 Unless the meaning of the
    phrase “the people” varies from provision to provision—and
    the Supreme Court in Heller suggested it does not—to
    conclude that Range is not among “the people” for Second
    Amendment purposes would exclude him from those rights as
    1
    See, e.g., U.S. Const. pmbl. (“We the People of the United
    States . . . .” (emphasis added)); 
    id.
     amend. IX (recognizing
    rights “retained by the people”); 
    id.
     amend. X (acknowledging
    the powers reserved “to the people”).
    2
    U.S. Const. art. I, § 2 (“The House of Representatives shall
    be composed of Members chosen every second Year by the
    People of the several States . . . .” (emphasis added)); id.
    amend. XVII (“The Senate of the United States shall be
    composed of two Senators from each State, elected by the
    people thereof . . . .” (emphasis added)).
    3
    U.S. Const. amend. I (“Congress shall make no law
    respecting . . . the right of the people peaceably to assemble,
    and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances.”
    (emphasis added)).
    4
    U.S. Const. amend. IV (“The right of the people to be secure
    in their persons, houses, papers, and effects, against
    unreasonable searches and seizures, shall not be violated . . . .”
    (emphasis added)).
    12
    well. See 
    554 U.S. at 580
    . And we see no reason to adopt an
    inconsistent reading of “the people.”
    Third, as the plurality stated in Binderup: “That
    individuals with Second Amendment rights may nonetheless
    be denied possession of a firearm is hardly illogical.” 
    836 F.3d at 344
     (Ambro, J.). That statement tracks then-Judge Barrett’s
    dissenting opinion in Kanter v. Barr, in which she persuasively
    explained that “all people have the right to keep and bear
    arms,” though the legislature may constitutionally “strip
    certain groups of that right.” 
    919 F.3d 437
    , 452 (7th Cir. 2019).
    We agree with that statement in Binderup and then-Judge
    Barrett’s reasoning.
    Fourth, the phrase “law-abiding, responsible citizens” is
    as expansive as it is vague. Who are “law-abiding” citizens in
    this context? Does it exclude those who have committed
    summary offenses or petty misdemeanors, which typically
    result in a ticket and a small fine? No. We are confident that
    the Supreme Court’s references to “law-abiding, responsible
    citizens” do not mean that every American who gets a traffic
    ticket is no longer among “the people” protected by the Second
    Amendment. Perhaps, then, the category refers only to those
    who commit “real crimes” like felonies or felony-equivalents?
    At English common law, felonies were so serious they were
    punishable by estate forfeiture and even death. 4 William
    Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 54 (1769).
    But today, felonies include a wide swath of crimes, some of
    13
    which seem minor.5 And some misdemeanors seem serious.6
    As the Supreme Court noted recently: “a felon is not always
    more dangerous than a misdemeanant.” Lange v. California,
    
    141 S. Ct. 2011
    , 2020 (2021) (cleaned up). As for the modifier
    “responsible,” it serves only to undermine the Government’s
    argument because it renders the category hopelessly vague. In
    our Republic of over 330 million people, Americans have
    widely divergent ideas about what is required for one to be
    considered a “responsible” citizen.
    At root, the Government’s claim that only “law-abiding,
    responsible citizens” are protected by the Second Amendment
    devolves authority to legislators to decide whom to exclude
    from “the people.” We reject that approach because such
    “extreme deference gives legislatures unreviewable power to
    manipulate the Second Amendment by choosing a label.”
    Folajtar, 980 F.3d at 912 (Bibas, J., dissenting). And that
    deference would contravene Heller’s reasoning that “the
    enshrinement of constitutional rights necessarily takes certain
    policy choices off the table.” 
    554 U.S. at 636
    ; see also Bruen,
    5
    See, e.g., 
    18 U.S.C. § 1464
     (uttering “any obscene, indecent,
    or profane language by means of radio communication”);
    
    Mich. Comp. Laws Ann. § 445
    .574a(2)(d) (returning out-of-
    state bottles or cans); 18 Pa. Cons. Stat. Ann. § 3929.1 (third
    offense of library theft of more than $150); id. § 7613 (reading
    another’s email without permission).
    6
    See, e.g., 18 Pa. Cons. Stat. Ann. § 2504 (involuntary
    manslaughter); id. § 2707 (propulsion of missiles into an
    occupied vehicle or onto a roadway); 11 Del. Code § 881
    (bribery).
    14
    142 S. Ct. at 2131 (warning against “judicial deference to
    legislative interest balancing”).
    In sum, we reject the Government’s contention that only
    “law-abiding, responsible citizens” are counted among “the
    people” protected by the Second Amendment. Heller and its
    progeny lead us to conclude that Bryan Range remains among
    “the people” despite his 1995 false statement conviction.
    Having determined that Range is one of “the people,”
    we turn to the easy question: whether § 922(g)(1) regulates
    Second Amendment conduct. It does. Range’s request—to
    possess a rifle to hunt and a shotgun to defend himself at
    home—tracks the constitutional right as defined by Heller. 
    554 U.S. at 582
     (“[T]he Second Amendment extends, prima facie,
    to all instruments that constitute bearable arms, even those that
    were not in existence at the time of the founding.”). So “the
    Second Amendment’s plain text covers [Range’s] conduct,”
    and “the Constitution presumptively protects that conduct.”
    Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2126.
    B
    Because Range and his proposed conduct are protected
    by the Second Amendment, we now ask whether the
    Government can strip him of his right to keep and bear arms.
    To answer that question, we must determine whether the
    Government has justified applying § 922(g)(1) to Range “by
    demonstrating that it is consistent with the Nation’s historical
    tradition of firearm regulation.” Id. at 2130. We hold that the
    Government has not carried its burden.
    To preclude Range from possessing firearms, the
    Government must show that § 922(g)(1), as applied to him, “is
    15
    part of the historical tradition that delimits the outer bounds of
    the right to keep and bear arms.” Id. at 2127. Historical
    tradition can be established by analogical reasoning, which
    “requires only that the government identify a well-established
    and representative historical analogue, not a historical twin.”
    Id. at 2133. To be compatible with the Second Amendment,
    regulations targeting longstanding problems must be
    “distinctly similar” to a historical analogue. Id. at 2131. But
    “modern regulations that were unimaginable at the founding”
    need only be “relevantly similar” to one. Id. at 2132. Bruen
    offers two metrics that make historical and modern firearms
    regulations similar enough: “how and why the regulations
    burden a law-abiding citizen’s right to armed self-defense.” Id.
    at 2133.
    In attempting to carry its burden, the Government relies
    on the Supreme Court’s statement in Heller that “nothing in
    our opinion should be taken to cast doubt on longstanding
    prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons.” 
    554 U.S. at 626
    . A plurality of the Court reiterated that point in
    McDonald v. City of Chicago, 
    561 U.S. 742
    , 786 (2010). And
    in his concurring opinion in Bruen, Justice Kavanaugh, joined
    by the Chief Justice, wrote that felon-possession prohibitions
    are “presumptively lawful” under Heller and McDonald. 142
    S. Ct. at 2162 (quoting Heller, 
    554 U.S. at
    626–27 & n.26).7
    Section 922(g)(1) is a straightforward “prohibition[] on the
    possession of firearms by felons.” Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 626
    . And
    since 1961 “federal law has generally prohibited individuals
    convicted of crimes punishable by more than one year of
    7
    The Heller, McDonald, and Bruen Courts cited no such
    “longstanding prohibitions,” presumably because they did “not
    undertake an exhaustive historical analysis . . . of the full scope
    of the Second Amendment.” Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 626
    .
    16
    imprisonment from possessing firearms.” Gov’t En Banc Br. at
    1; see An Act To Strengthen The Federal Firearms Act, 
    Pub. L. No. 87-342, 75
     Stat. 757 (1961). But the earliest version of
    that statute, the Federal Firearms Act of 1938, applied only to
    violent criminals. 
    Pub. L. No. 75-785, §§ 1
    (6), 2(f), 
    52 Stat. 1250
    , 1250–51 (1938). As the First Circuit explained: “the
    current federal felony firearm ban differs considerably from
    the [original] version . . . . [T]he law initially covered those
    convicted of a limited set of violent crimes such as murder,
    rape, kidnapping, and burglary, but extended to both felons and
    misdemeanants convicted of qualifying offenses.” United
    States v. Booker, 
    644 F.3d 12
    , 24 (1st Cir. 2011); see also
    United States v. Skoien, 
    614 F.3d 638
    , 640 (7th Cir. 2010) (en
    banc).
    Even if the 1938 Act were “longstanding” enough to
    warrant Heller’s assurance—a dubious proposition given the
    Bruen Court’s emphasis on Founding- and Reconstruction-era
    sources, 142 S. Ct. at 2136, 2150—Range would not have been
    a prohibited person under that law. Whatever timeframe the
    Supreme Court might establish in a future case, we are
    confident that a law passed in 1961—some 170 years after the
    Second Amendment’s ratification and nearly a century after
    the Fourteenth Amendment’s ratification—falls well short of
    “longstanding” for purposes of demarcating the scope of a
    constitutional right. So the 1961 iteration of § 922(g)(1) does
    not satisfy the Government’s burden.8
    8
    Nor are we convinced by the slightly older state and local
    felon-in-possession laws cited by the amicus brief in support
    of the Government filed by Everytown for Gun Safety. Amicus
    cites a series of state statutes banning firearm possession by
    17
    The Government’s attempt to identify older historical
    analogues also fails.9 The Government argues that “legislatures
    traditionally used status-based restrictions” to disarm certain
    groups of people. Gov’t En Banc Br. at 4 (quoting Range, 53
    F.4th at 282). Apart from the fact that those restrictions based
    felons passed in the 1920s. But this is still too late: “20th-
    century evidence . . . does not provide insight into the meaning
    of the Second Amendment when it contradicts earlier
    evidence.” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2154 n.28. And the 19th-
    century local laws cited by Amicus are inapposite because they
    involved prohibitions on concealed carry, a lesser restriction
    than the total ban on firearm possession that § 922(g)(1)
    imposes.
    9
    Range argues that because “there is no historical tradition of
    disarming nonviolent felons,” dangerousness is the
    “touchstone.” Range Pet. for Reh’g at 10. In support of that
    view, Range quotes a concurring opinion of five judges in
    Binderup that focused on dangerousness. 
    836 F.3d at 369
    (Hardiman, J., concurring in part). He also cites Judge Bibas’s
    dissent in Folajtar, 980 F.3d at 913–20, and then-Judge
    Barrett’s dissent in Kanter: “The historical evidence . . .
    [shows] that the legislature may disarm those who have
    demonstrated a proclivity for violence or whose possession of
    guns would otherwise threaten the public safety.” 
    919 F.3d at 454
    . The Government replies that 10 of the 15 judges in
    Binderup and the Court in Holloway and Folajtar rejected
    dangerousness or violence as the touchstone. We need not
    decide this dispute today because the Government did not carry
    its burden to provide a historical analogue to permanently
    disarm someone like Range, whether grounded in
    dangerousness or not.
    18
    on race and religion now would be unconstitutional under the
    First and Fourteenth Amendments, the Government does not
    successfully analogize those groups to Range and his
    individual circumstances. That Founding-era governments
    disarmed groups they distrusted like Loyalists, Native
    Americans, Quakers, Catholics, and Blacks does nothing to
    prove that Range is part of a similar group today. And any such
    analogy would be “far too broad[ ].” See Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at
    2134 (noting that historical restrictions on firearms in
    “sensitive places” do not empower legislatures to designate
    any place “sensitive” and then ban firearms there).
    The Government also points out that “founding-era
    felons were exposed to far more severe consequences than
    disarmament.” Gov’t En Banc Br. at 4. It is true that “founding-
    era practice” was to punish some “felony offenses with death.”
    Id. at 9. For example, the First Congress made forging or
    counterfeiting a public security punishable by death. See An
    Act for the Punishment of Certain Crimes Against the United
    States, 
    1 Stat. 112
    , 115 (1790). States in the early Republic
    likewise treated nonviolent crimes “such as forgery and horse
    theft” as capital offenses. See Folajtar, 980 F.3d at
    904 (citations omitted). Such severe treatment reflects the
    founding generation’s judgment about the gravity of those
    offenses and the need to expose offenders to the harshest of
    punishments.
    Yet the Government’s attempts to analogize those early
    laws to Range’s situation fall short. That Founding-era
    governments punished some nonviolent crimes with death does
    not suggest that the particular (and distinct) punishment at
    issue—lifetime disarmament—is rooted in our Nation’s
    history and tradition. The greater does not necessarily include
    the lesser: founding-era governments’ execution of some
    19
    individuals convicted of certain offenses does not mean the
    State, then or now, could constitutionally strip a felon of his
    right to possess arms if he was not executed. As one of our
    dissenting colleagues notes, a felon could “repurchase arms”
    after successfully completing his sentence and reintegrating
    into society. Krause Dissent at 28–29. That aptly describes
    Range’s situation. So the Government’s attempt to disarm
    Range is not “relevantly similar” to earlier statutes allowing for
    execution and forfeiture. See Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2132.
    Founding-era laws often prescribed the forfeiture of the
    weapon used to commit a firearms-related offense without
    affecting the perpetrator’s right to keep and bear arms
    generally. See, e.g., Act of Dec. 21, 1771, ch. 540, N.J. Laws
    343–344 (“An Act for the Preservation of Deer, and other
    Game, and to prevent trespassing with Guns”); Act of Apr. 20,
    1745, ch. 3, N.C. Laws 69–70 (“An Act to prevent killing deer
    at unseasonable times, and for putting a stop to many abuses
    committed by white persons, under pretence of
    hunting”). Range’s crime, however—making a false statement
    on an application for food stamps—did not involve a firearm,
    so there was no criminal instrument to forfeit. And even if there
    were, government confiscation of the instruments of crime (or
    a convicted criminal’s entire estate) differs from a status-based
    lifetime ban on firearm possession. The Government has not
    cited a single statute or case that precludes a convict who has
    served his sentence from purchasing the same type of object
    that he used to commit a crime. Nor has the Government cited
    forfeiture cases in which the convict was prevented from
    regaining his possessions, including firearms (except where
    forfeiture preceded execution). That’s true whether the object
    forfeited to the government was a firearm used to hunt out of
    season, a car used to transport cocaine, or a mobile home used
    20
    as a methamphetamine lab. And of those three, only firearms
    are mentioned in the Bill of Rights.10
    Finally, the Government makes an argument from
    authority. It points to a decision from a sister circuit court that
    “look[ed] to tradition and history” in deciding that “those
    convicted of felonies are not among those entitled to possess
    arms.” Gov’t En Banc Br. at 4 (quoting Medina v. Whitaker,
    
    913 F.3d 152
    , 157–61 (D.C. Cir. 2019)). The Government also
    cites appellate decisions that “have categorically upheld felon-
    possession prohibitions without relying on means-end
    scrutiny.” 
    Id.
     (citing United States v. Scroggins, 
    599 F.3d 433
    ,
    451 (5th Cir. 2010); United States v. Rozier, 
    598 F.3d 768
    , 771
    (11th Cir. 2010) (per curiam); United States v. McCane, 
    573 F.3d 1037
    , 1047 (10th Cir. 2009)). And it cites the more than
    80 district court decisions that have addressed § 922(g)(1) and
    have ruled in favor of the Government. Id. at 5 (citing Brief for
    Fed. Gov’t at 17 n.5, Vincent v. Garland, No. 21-4121 (10th
    Cir. Jan. 17, 2023)).
    As impressive as these authorities may seem at first blush,
    they fail to persuade. First, the circuit court opinions were all
    decided before Bruen. Second, the district courts are bound to
    follow their circuits’ precedent. Third, the Government’s
    10
    Even arms used to commit crimes bordering on treason were
    sometimes returned to the perpetrators during the Founding
    era. After the Massachusetts militia quelled Shays’s Rebellion
    in 1787, the state required the rebels and those who supported
    them to “deliver up their arms.” 1 Private and Special Statutes
    of the Commonwealth of Massachusetts from 1780–1805,
    145–47 (1805). But those arms were to be returned after three
    years upon satisfaction of certain conditions. Id. at 146–47.
    21
    contention that “Bruen does not meaningfully affect this
    Court’s precedent,” Gov’t Supp. Br. at 9, is mistaken for the
    reasons we explained in Section III, supra.
    For the reasons stated, we hold that the Government has
    not shown that the Nation’s historical tradition of firearms
    regulation supports depriving Range of his Second
    Amendment right to possess a firearm. See Bruen, 142 S. Ct.
    at 2126.
    *      *      *
    Our decision today is a narrow one. Bryan Range
    challenged the constitutionality of 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1) only
    as applied to him given his violation of 62 Pa. Stat. Ann.
    § 481(a). Range remains one of “the people” protected by the
    Second Amendment, and his eligibility to lawfully purchase a
    rifle and a shotgun is protected by his right to keep and bear
    arms. Because the Government has not shown that our
    Republic has a longstanding history and tradition of depriving
    people like Range of their firearms, § 922(g)(1) cannot
    constitutionally strip him of his Second Amendment rights. We
    will reverse the judgment of the District Court and remand so
    the Court can enter a declaratory judgment in favor of Range,
    enjoin enforcement of § 922(g)(1) against him, and conduct
    any further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
    22
    PORTER, Circuit Judge, concurring.
    I join the majority opinion in full. I write separately to
    highlight one reason why there are no examples of founding,
    antebellum, or Reconstruction-era federal laws like 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1) permanently disarming non-capital criminals.
    Until well into the twentieth century, it was settled that
    Congress lacked the power to abridge anyone’s right to keep
    and bear arms. The right declared in the Second Amendment
    was important, but cumulative. The people’s first line of
    defense was the reservation of a power from the national
    government.1 As James Wilson explained, “A bill of rights
    annexed to a constitution is an enumeration of the powers
    reserved.” James Wilson, Remarks in the Pennsylvania
    Convention to Ratify the Constitution of the United States
    (Nov. 28, 1787), reprinted in 1 Collected Works of James
    Wilson 195 (Liberty Fund ed., 2007).
    Even without the Second Amendment, the combination
    of enumerated powers and the Ninth and Tenth Amendments
    ensured that Congress could not permanently disarm anyone.
    1
    “The powers delegated by the proposed constitution to the
    federal government, are few and defined. Those which are to
    remain in the state governments, are numerous and indefinite.
    The former will be exercised principally on external objects, as
    war, peace, negotiation, and foreign commerce; with which last
    the power of taxation will, for the most part, be connected. The
    powers reserved to the several states will extend to all the
    objects, which, in the ordinary course of affairs, concern the
    lives, liberties, and properties of the people; and the internal
    order, improvement, and prosperity of the state.” The
    Federalist No. 45, at 241 (Madison) (Liberty Fund ed. 2001).
    1
    See Kurt T. Lash, The Lost History of the Ninth Amendment
    72–93 (2009) (discussing how the Ninth and Tenth
    Amendments work in tandem to serve federalist purposes). The
    adoption of substantive protections in the Bill of Rights, such
    as the right to keep and bear arms, was another layer of
    protection reinforcing dual sovereignty.
    A founding-era source is illustrative. In his influential
    constitutional law treatise, William Rawle, a Federalist,
    grounded the people’s right to keep and bear arms in
    Congress’s lack of delegated power. He described the Second
    Amendment as a backstop to prevent the pursuit of “inordinate
    power.”
    The prohibition is general. No clause in the
    Constitution could by any rule of construction be
    conceived to give congress a power to disarm the
    people. Such a flagitious attempt could only be
    made under some general pretence by a state
    legislature. But if in any blind pursuit of
    inordinate power, either should attempt it, this
    amendment may be appealed to as a restraint on
    both.
    William Rawle, A View of the Constitution of the United States
    of America 125–26 (2d ed. 1829).
    At oral argument, counsel for the government
    hypothesized that the paucity of early American criminal laws
    resulting in disarmament may be explained by a lack of
    political demand. That’s implausible. As Judge Krause’s
    dissenting opinion shows, states were free to, and did, regulate
    2
    gun ownership and use, indicating political demand. The most
    obvious explanation for a century and a half of congressional
    inaction is not lack of political will but dual sovereignty and
    respect for state police power.
    A New Deal Era attempt at federal gun control is
    revealing. In 1934, the Roosevelt Administration proposed the
    National Firearms Act to address the gangster-style violence of
    the Prohibition Era by reducing the sale of automatic weapons
    and machine guns. Stymied by the federal government’s lack
    of police power, Attorney General Homer Cummings urged
    Congress to regulate guns indirectly through its enumerated
    taxing power. Nicholas J. Johnson, The Power Side of the
    Second Amendment Question: Limited, Enumerated Powers
    and the Continuing Battle Over the Legitimacy of the
    Individual Right to Arms, 70 Hastings L. J. 717, 750–58
    (2019). Congress accepted that suggestion, avoiding the
    acknowledged constitutional problem by imposing a tax—
    rather than a direct prohibition—on the making and transfer of
    particular firearms. See National Firearms Act, ch. 757, Pub.
    L. No. 73–474, 
    48 Stat. 1236
     (1934) (current version at 
    26 U.S.C. § 5801
     et seq.).
    The landscape changed in 1937, when the Supreme
    Court adopted an expansive conception of the Commerce
    Clause. See NLRB v. Jones & Laughlin Steel Corp., 
    301 U.S. 1
     (1937). Newly empowered, Congress promptly enacted the
    Federal Firearms Act of 1938. For the first time, that law
    disarmed felons convicted of a “crime of violence,” which the
    Act defined as “murder, manslaughter, rape, mayhem,
    kidnapping, burglary, housebreaking; assault with intent to
    kill, commit rape, or rob; assault with a dangerous weapon, or
    assault with intent to commit any offense punishable by more
    than one year.” Federal Firearms Act, Pub. L. No. 75–785, 52
    
    3 Stat. 1250
     (1938). In 1961, Congress extended the firearms
    disqualification to all felons, violent or otherwise. See An Act
    to Strengthen the Federal Firearms Act, 
    Pub. L. No. 87-342, 75
    Stat. 757 (1961); see also 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1).
    As the majority opinion makes plain, these modern laws
    have no longstanding analogue in our national history and
    tradition of firearm regulation.2 Maj. Op. 15–22. That’s
    unsurprising because before the New Deal Revolution,
    Congress was powerless to regulate gun possession and use.
    See United States v. Cruikshank, 
    92 U.S. 542
    , 553 (1875)
    (Congress lacks power to infringe the right declared by the
    Second Amendment); Presser v. People of State of Ill. 
    116 U.S. 252
    , 265 (1886) (same).
    Lacking any relevant historical federal data, we may
    look to state statutes and cases for contemporaneous clues
    about the people’s right to keep and bear arms.3 By 1803, seven
    of the seventeen states protected gun possession and use in
    their own declarations of rights. Eugene Volokh, State
    Constitutional Rights to Keep and Bear Arms, 
    11 Tex. Rev. L. & Pol. 191
    , 208–11 (2006). And by 1868, twenty-two of thirty-
    seven states protected the right in their state constitutions. 
    Id.
    The history and tradition of firearm regulation in those states
    2
    Bruen defines relevant history for these purposes as the period
    between approximately 1791 and 1868. New York State Rifle
    & Pistol Ass’n., Inc. v. Bruen, 597 U.S. ----, 
    142 S. Ct. 2111
    ,
    2137–50 (2022) (summarizing “antebellum” historical
    evidence).
    3
    Pace Judge Shwartz, I do not understand the Supreme Court
    to require that firearm regulations can be supported only “by a
    federally enacted analog in existence at the founding[.]”
    Shwartz Dissent at n.5.
    4
    may shed light on the scope of the federal constitutional right,
    depending on how similar each state’s constitutional protection
    was to the Second Amendment. See District of Columbia v.
    Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 600–03 (2008) (founding-era state
    constitutions corroborate individual-right interpretation of
    Second Amendment). After all, state constitutions and their
    respective bills of rights were “the immediate source from
    which Madison derived what became the U.S. Bill of Rights.”
    Donald S. Lutz, The State Constitutional Pedigree of the U.S.
    Bill of Rights, 22 Publius 19, 29 (1992).
    But precisely because the states—unlike the national
    government—retained sweeping police powers and weren’t
    originally constrained by the Bill of Rights, they were free to
    regulate the possession and use of weapons in whatever ways
    they thought appropriate (subject to state constitutional
    restrictions that were not uniform). See Barron ex rel. Tiernan
    v. Mayor of Baltimore, 
    32 U.S. (7 Pet.) 243
     (1833). Because of
    that important difference, it’s unclear what many early state
    laws prove about the contours of the Second Amendment right.
    For example, Judge Krause’s dissent cites founding or
    antebellum-era disarmament laws from Delaware, Maryland,
    New Jersey, New York, and Virginia. Krause Dissent at 15-21,
    26-28 & nn. 94-96, 98. But Maryland, New Jersey, and New
    York have never enumerated a Second Amendment analogue.
    Volokh, supra, at 205. Delaware and Virginia did not do so
    until 1987 and 1971, respectively. Id. at 194, 204. So those
    states’ laws provide little insight about the scope of the Second
    Amendment right.
    After McDonald v. City of Chicago, 
    561 U.S. 742
    (2010), state gun laws are subject to the Second Amendment
    because it is incorporated through the Fourteenth Amendment.
    5
    The Supreme Court has said that “if a Bill of Rights protection
    is incorporated, there is no daylight between the federal and
    state conduct it prohibits or requires.” Timbs v. Indiana, 586
    U.S. ----, 
    139 S. Ct. 682
    , 687 (2019); see also Bruen, 142 S.
    Ct. at 2137. But unlike McDonald, Timbs, and Bruen, this case
    doesn’t involve application of an incorporated right against a
    state law; it’s a challenge to the constitutionality of a relatively
    recent federal statute that has no historical analogue in
    antebellum federal law.
    Using state laws indiscriminately to determine the scope
    of the constitutional right seems incongruous in this context. It
    seeks effectively to reverse incorporate state law into federal
    constitutional law. In Bolling v. Sharpe, 
    347 U.S. 497
     (1954),
    the Supreme Court held that Fourteenth Amendment equal-
    protection principles applicable to the states also bind the
    federal government through the Fifth Amendment’s Due
    Process Clause because the alternative would be
    “unthinkable.” 
    Id. at 500
    ; but see United States v. Vaello
    Madero, 
    142 S. Ct. 1539
    , 1544–47 (2022) (Thomas, J.,
    concurring) (criticizing Bolling’s rationale). Here, there is no
    textual basis plausibly supporting reverse incorporation. And
    Bolling’s rule appears to be cabined to equal-protection claims;
    the Court has only invoked reverse incorporation to redress
    invidious discrimination. Without an equal-protection or due-
    process hook, using state law to define a federal constitutional
    amendment that was fashioned to protect individual rights and
    a reserved power poses a doctrinal conundrum.
    A conception of the Second Amendment right that
    retcons modern commerce power into early American state law
    is anachronistic and flunks Bruen’s history-and-tradition test.
    Setting the federal floor through a combination of antebellum
    state police power and Congress’s post-New Deal commerce
    6
    authority, as the dissents propose, would underprotect the
    constitutional right to keep and bear arms.
    7
    AMBRO, Circuit Judge, concurring, joined by
    GREENAWAY, JR. and MONTGOMERY-REEVES, Circuit
    Judges.
    Bryan Range decades ago made a false statement to
    obtain food stamps to feed his family. That untrue statement,
    however, was a misdemeanor in violation of Pennsylvania law.
    See 62 Pa. Stat. Ann. § 481(a). And his conviction barred him
    from possessing a firearm per 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1).
    I agree with the well-crafted majority opinion of Judge
    Hardiman that Range is among “the people” protected by the
    Second Amendment and that the law is unconstitutional as
    applied to him. I write separately, however, to explain why the
    Government’s failure to carry its burden in this case does not
    spell doom for § 922(g)(1). It remains “presumptively lawful.”
    New York State Rifle & Pistol Ass’n, Inc. v. Bruen, 
    142 S. Ct. 2111
    , 2162 (2022) (Kavanaugh, J., concurring) (quoting
    District of Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 626–27 (2008)).
    This is so because it fits within our Nation’s history and
    tradition of disarming those persons who legislatures believed
    would, if armed, pose a threat to the orderly functioning of
    society. That Range does not conceivably pose such a threat
    says nothing about those who do. And I join the majority
    opinion with the understanding that it speaks only to his
    situation, and not to those of murderers, thieves, sex offenders,
    domestic abusers, and the like.
    Section 922(g)(1) is the federal “felon-in-possession”
    law. It makes it “unlawful for any person . . . who has been
    convicted in any court . . . of a crime punishable by
    imprisonment for a term exceeding one year” to possess
    firearms or ammunition. 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1). Although
    1
    those convicted of state misdemeanors “punishable by a term
    of imprisonment of two years or less” are excluded from the
    prohibition, Range is subject to it because his crime carried a
    maximum penalty of five years’ imprisonment even though he
    received no prison sentence. 
    18 U.S.C. § 921
    (a)(20)(B).
    Congress may disarm felons because, as Justice Scalia
    explained in Heller, “[l]ike most rights, the right secured by the
    Second Amendment is not unlimited.” 
    554 U.S. at 626
    . He
    demonstrated this is so by listing “presumptively lawful”
    regulations that the ruling should not “be taken to cast doubt
    on.” 
    Id.
     at 626–27 & n.26. That list included “longstanding
    prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons.” 
    Id.
     at
    626–27. Just two years later, in McDonald v. City of Chicago,
    the Supreme Court incorporated the Second Amendment
    against the states. 
    561 U.S. 742
    , 767–68 (2010). In doing so,
    it assured the public that “incorporation does not imperil every
    law regulating firearms.” 
    Id. at 786
    . Thus, it stood by its
    statement “in Heller that our holding did not cast doubt on such
    longstanding regulatory measures as ‘prohibitions on the
    possession of firearms by felons.’” 
    Id.
     (quoting Heller, 
    554 U.S. at
    626–27). See also United States v. Jackson, No. 22-
    2870, --- F.4th ----, 
    2023 WL 3769242
    , at *4 (8th Cir. June 2,
    2023) (observing the Supreme Court has provided assurances
    that felon-in-possession laws are constitutional).
    In United States v. Barton, we held that “Heller’s list of
    ‘presumptively lawful’ regulations is not dicta.” 
    633 F.3d 168
    ,
    171 (3d Cir. 2011). That aligned us with the Ninth and
    Eleventh Circuits. 
    Id.
     (citing United States v. Vogxay, 
    594 F.3d 1111
    , 1115 (9th Cir. 2010), and United States v. Rozier, 
    598 F.3d 768
    , 771 n.6 (11th Cir. 2010)). And every other circuit
    2
    court has looked to the Supreme Court’s treatment of
    “presumptively lawful” prohibitions for guidance.1
    New York State Rifle & Pistol Ass’n v. Bruen reaffirms
    that felon-in-possession laws are presumed to be lawful. 
    142 S. Ct. 2111 (2022)
    . Although that case had nothing to do with
    those laws, three of the six Justices in the majority went out of
    their way to signal that view.             Justice Kavanaugh’s
    concurrence, joined by Chief Justice Roberts, explained that,
    “[p]roperly interpreted, the Second Amendment allows a
    ‘variety’ of gun regulations” before quoting the Heller excerpt
    that casts prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons
    as presumptively lawful. 
    Id. at 2162
     (quoting Heller, 
    554 U.S. at
    626–27 & n.26). Justice Alito’s concurrence also explained
    that the Court’s opinion has not “disturbed anything that we
    said in Heller or McDonald about restrictions that may be
    imposed on the possession or carrying of guns.” Id. at 2157
    (citation omitted).
    Of course, we are here for a reason. Bruen abrogated
    the circuit courts’ use of means-end analysis and replaced it
    with a history-driven test:
    1
    See United States v. Booker, 
    644 F.3d 12
    , 23–24 (1st
    Cir. 2011); United States v. Jimenez, 
    895 F.3d 228
    , 233 (2d
    Cir. 2018); United States v. Chester, 
    628 F.3d 673
    , 679–80 (4th
    Cir. 2010); Hollis v. Lynch, 
    827 F.3d 436
    , 446–47 (5th Cir.
    2016); Tyler v. Hillsdale Cnty. Sheriff’s Dep’t, 
    837 F.3d 678
    ,
    686–87 (6th Cir. 2016) (en banc); United States v. Skoien, 
    614 F.3d 638
    , 639–40 (7th Cir. 2010); United States v. Bena, 
    664 F.3d 1180
    , 1182–83 (8th Cir. 2011); Bonidy v. United States
    Postal Serv., 
    790 F.3d 1121
    , 1124 (10th Cir. 2015); Heller v.
    District of Columbia, 
    670 F.3d 1244
    , 1253 (D.C. Cir. 2011).
    3
    [W]hen the Second Amendment’s plain text
    covers an individual’s conduct, the Constitution
    presumptively protects that conduct. To justify
    its regulation, the government may not simply
    posit that the regulation promotes an important
    interest.     Rather, the government must
    demonstrate that the regulation is consistent with
    this Nation’s historical tradition of firearm
    regulation. Only if a firearm regulation is
    consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition
    may a court conclude that the individual’s
    conduct falls outside the Second Amendment’s
    “unqualified command.”
    Id. at 2126. In the wake of Bruen, assessing a gun restriction
    by balancing a government’s interest (safety of citizens) with
    the burden imposed on an individual’s right to bear arms is out.
    Instead, laws that burden Second Amendment rights must have
    “a well-established and representative historical analogue, not
    a historical twin.” Id. at 2133 (emphases in original). So we
    must use “analogical reasoning” to determine whether
    § 922(g)(1) is “relevantly similar” to a law from a period of
    history that sheds light on the Second Amendment’s meaning.
    Id. at 2132.
    Given that three Justices in Bruen’s majority opinion
    reminded us that felon-in-possession laws remain
    presumptively lawful, and the three dissenting Justices echoed
    that view, id. at 2189 (Breyer, J., dissenting) (“Like Justice
    Kavanaugh, I understand the Court’s opinion today to cast no
    doubt on that aspect of Heller’s holding.”), a sound basis exists
    for § 922(g)(1)’s constitutional application in a substantial
    amount of cases. Any historical inquiry that reaches a contrary
    4
    result must be wrong in view of the answer the Supreme Court
    has already supplied. See Jackson, 
    2023 WL 3769242
    , at *4.
    We begin with a look to firearm regulation in the era of
    the Second Amendment’s ratification. In England, non-
    Anglican Protestants and Catholics were disarmed during
    times of tumult. See Range v. Att’y Gen., 
    53 F.4th 262
    , 274–
    76 (3d Cir. 2022), reh’g en banc granted, opinion vacated, 
    56 F.4th 992
     (3d Cir. 2023). The American colonies also
    disarmed religious dissenters. See 
    id.
     at 276–77. And in the
    Revolutionary War period, British loyalists and those who
    refused to take loyalty oaths were disarmed by several
    colonies. See 
    id.
     at 277–79. See also Jackson, 
    2023 WL 3769242
    , at *5.
    True, those laws are, by today’s standards,
    unconstitutional on non-Second Amendment grounds. But at
    our Founding they were measures driven by the fear of those
    who, the political majority believed, would threaten the orderly
    functioning of society if they were armed. From this
    perspective, it makes sense that § 922(g)(1) is presumptively
    lawful. Society is protecting itself by disarming, inter alia,
    those who murder, rob, possess child porn, and leak classified
    national security information. See id. at *7. Most felons have
    broken laws deemed to underpin society’s orderly functioning,
    be their crimes violent or not. Section 922(g)(1) thus disarms
    them for the same reason we prohibited British loyalists from
    being armed.
    Of course, the relevant period may extend beyond the
    Founding era. Indeed, the Supreme Court has not yet decided
    whether individual rights are defined by their public
    understanding at the time of the ratification of the Bill of Rights
    5
    in 1791 or the Fourteenth Amendment in 1868. See Bruen, 142
    S. Ct. at 2162–63 (Barrett., J., concurring). If the latter, as the
    Eleventh Circuit held in National Rifle Ass’n v. Bondi, 
    61 F.4th 1317
    , 1322–24 (11th Cir. 2023), then Founding-era regulations
    remain instructive unless contradicted by something specific in
    the Reconstruction-era. In any event, the more longstanding a
    prohibition, the more likely it is to be constitutional.2
    Certain regulations contemporaneous with the
    Fourteenth Amendment’s ratification reaffirm the familiar
    desire to keep arms from those perceived to threaten the orderly
    functioning of society. A slew of states prohibited “tramps”
    from carrying firearms or dangerous weapons.3 Kansas barred
    those “not engaged in any legitimate business, any person
    under the influence of intoxicating drink, and any person who
    has ever borne arms against the government of the United
    2
    The Supreme Court did not specify how long it takes for
    a law to become “longstanding.”
    3
    See, e.g., 
    1878 N.H. Laws 612
    , ch. 270 § 2; 1878 Vt.
    Laws 30, ch. 14 § 3; 1879 R.I. Laws 110, ch. 806 § 3; 1880
    Ohio Rev. St. 1654, ch. 8 § 6995; 1880 Mass. Laws 232,
    ch. 257, § 4; 1987 Iowa Laws 1981, ch. 5 § 5135.
    Tramps were typically defined along the lines of the
    following Pennsylvania statute: “Any person going about from
    place to place begging, asking or subsisting upon charity, and
    for the purpose of acquiring money or living, and who shall
    have no fixed place of residence, or lawful occupation in the
    county or city in which he shall be arrested, shall be taken and
    deemed to be a tramp.” 1 A DIGEST OF THE STATUTE LAW OF
    THE STATE OF PENNSYLVANIA FROM THE YEAR 1700 TO 1894,
    541 (Frank F. Brightly, 12th ed. 1894).
    6
    States” from carrying “a pistol, bowie-knife, dirk or other
    deadly weapon.” 2 General Statutes of the State of Kansas 353
    (1897) (passed in 1868). And Wisconsin prohibited “any
    person in a state of intoxication to go armed with any pistol or
    revolver.” 
    1883 Wis. Sess. Laws 290
    , ch. 329, § 3. Although
    these regulations are not felon-in-possession laws, they echo
    the impetus of the Founding-era laws—a desire to stop
    firearms from being possessed or carried by those who cannot
    be trusted with them.
    But presumptions aren’t rules—they can be rebutted.
    And so it may be that an individual subject to § 922(g)(1)
    would not, if armed, plausibly pose a threat to the orderly
    functioning of society. Here, the Government has not carried
    its burden of proving that Range poses such a threat. Hence,
    he may not be constitutionally disarmed on the record
    presented.
    Range committed a small-time offense. He did so with
    a pen to receive food stamps for his family. There is nothing
    that suggests he is a threat to society. He therefore stands apart
    from most other individuals subject to § 922(g)(1) whom we
    fear much like early Americans feared loyalists or
    Reconstruction-era citizens feared armed tramps. I therefore
    concur because there is no historical basis for disarming him.
    I close with the observation that the Supreme Court will
    have to square its history-driven test with its concurrent view
    that felon gun restrictions are presumptively lawful. Scholars
    have scrambled to find historical roots for that presumption.
    See, e.g., Carlton F.W. Larson, Four Exceptions in Search of a
    Theory: District of Columbia v. Heller and Judicial Ipse Dixit,
    60 HASTINGS L.J. 1371, 1386 (2008) (originalist analysis
    7
    “yield[s] partial and incomplete answers” for why the
    measures Heller cited as presumptively lawful enjoy that
    status). Others conclude that a historical basis only exists for
    disarming violent felons, see, e.g., Joseph G.S. Greenlee, The
    Historical Justification for Prohibiting Dangerous Persons
    from Possessing Arms, 20 WYO. L. REV. 249 (2020), who
    represent but a small fraction of the felon population, thus
    leaving out, for example, those who leak national security
    information, disrupt markets with their fraud, and possess child
    porn. See Brian A. Reaves, U.S. Dep’t of Justice, Bureau of
    Justice Statistics, State Violent Felons in Large Urban
    Counties, at 1 (2006) (“From 1990 to 2002, 18% of felony
    convictions in the 75 largest counties were for violent
    offenses.”).
    This opinion is one attempt to offer a historical
    justification for § 922(g)(1), recognizing that history offers no
    precise analogue. And if that proves unsatisfying to the Court,
    it may do away with the presumption that disarming felons is
    lawful. I hope it does not do so. Not just because arming those
    who pose a threat to the orderly functioning of society will lead
    to more deaths, but because it would be a dangerous precedent.
    It is incongruous to believe history displaces means-ends
    balancing for the Second Amendment only. The Court’s
    approach here will affect our ability to pass any rights-
    burdening law—whether the right be protected by the First,
    Second, Fourth, or Sixth Amendment—that lacks a neat
    historical basis. I trust it will fulfill its promise that Bruen
    imposes no “regulatory straightjacket,” 142 S. Ct. at 2133, and
    permit § 922(g)(1) to apply to those who threaten the orderly
    functioning of civil society.
    8
    SHWARTZ, Circuit Judge, dissenting, joined by RESTREPO,
    Circuit Judge.
    Today, the Majority of our Court has decided that an
    individual convicted of fraud cannot be barred from possessing
    a firearm. While my colleagues state that their opinion is
    narrow, the analytical framework they have applied to reach
    their conclusion renders most, if not all, felon bans
    unconstitutional. Because the Supreme Court has made clear
    that such bans are presumptively lawful, and there is a
    historical basis for such bans, I respectfully dissent.1
    In New York State Rifle & Pistol Ass’n, Inc. v. Bruen,
    
    142 S. Ct. 2111 (2022)
    , the Supreme Court set forth a history-
    based framework for deciding whether a firearm regulation is
    constitutional under the Second Amendment. Courts must now
    examine whether the “regulation [being reviewed] is part of the
    historical tradition that delimits the outer boundaries of the
    right to keep and bear arms.” 
    Id. at 2127
    . To make this
    determination, a court must decide whether the challenger or
    conduct at issue is protected by the Second Amendment and, if
    so, whether the Government has presented sufficient historical
    analogues to justify the restriction. See 
    id. at 2129-30
    .
    1
    While I agree with Judge Krause’s excellent and
    comprehensive review of the history as well as her incisive
    critique of the Majority opinion, I write separately to
    emphasize both that the history supports banning felons from
    possessing firearms and that the Majority opinion is far from
    narrow.
    1
    The Majority’s analysis is inconsistent with the
    Supreme Court’s jurisprudence and has far-reaching
    consequences. First, the Majority downplays the Supreme
    Court’s consistent admonishment that felon bans are
    “longstanding” and “presumptively lawful.” District of
    Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 626-27 & n.26 (2008);
    McDonald v. City of Chicago, 
    561 U.S. 742
    , 786 (2010). In
    Heller and McDonald, the Supreme Court stated that felon
    bans are consistent with our historical tradition. Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 626-27
    ; McDonald, 
    561 U.S. at 786
    . More recently, a
    majority of the Bruen Court reiterated that felon bans are
    presumptively lawful, and notably did so in the very case that
    explicitly requires courts to find historical support for every
    firearm regulation. Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2157 (Alito, J.,
    concurring) (explaining that Bruen did not “disturb” anything
    the Court said in Heller or McDonald); id. at 2162 (Kavanaugh,
    J., concurring, joined by Roberts, J.) (“Nothing in our opinion
    should be taken to cast doubt on the longstanding prohibitions
    on the possession of firearms by felons.” (quoting Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 626
    )); id. at 2189 (Breyer, J., dissenting, joined by
    Sotomayor, J., & Kagan, J.) (“I understand the Court’s opinion
    today to cast no doubt on . . . Heller’s holding [regarding
    longstanding prohibitions.]”). These statements show that
    felon bans have historical roots.2 See United States v. Jackson,
    No. 22-2870, 
    2023 WL 3769242
    , --- F. 4th ----, at *4, *7 n.3
    (8th Cir. June 2, 2023) (upholding the constitutionality of the
    2
    The Supreme Court also recognized that other firearm
    regulations are “longstanding” and “presumptively lawful.”
    Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 626-27
    . Thus, the Majority’s willingness
    to devalue the Supreme Court’s observations may have
    consequences on regulations beyond the status-based ban at
    issue here.
    2
    federal felon ban as applied to a non-violent drug offender
    based, in part, on the Supreme Court’s statements).
    Second, the Majority incorrectly discounts the
    importance of the Supreme Court’s emphasis on law-
    abidingness as a limitation on the Second Amendment right.
    While the Majority dismisses this language as “dicta,” Maj.
    Op. at 11, the Bruen Court’s use of the phrase fourteen times
    highlights the significance that this criterion played in its
    decision, Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2122, 2125, 2131, 2133-34, 2135
    n.8, 2138 n.9, 2150, 2156; see also Jackson, 
    2023 WL 3769242
    , at *6 (noting Bruen’s repeated statements about a
    law-abider’s right to possess arms). Indeed, the Bruen court
    approved of certain gun regulations that included criminal
    background checks. Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2138 n. 9. While the
    Majority says that the phrase “law abiding” is “expansive” and
    “vague,” Maj. Op. at 13, there is no question that one who has
    a felony or felony-equivalent conviction is not law abiding.
    Thus, the Supreme Court’s jurisprudence tells us that the right
    to bear arms is limited to law abiders, and that felon bans are
    presumptively lawful.
    Third, the Majority acknowledges but then disregards
    important aspects of Bruen. The Bruen Court emphasized that
    its test should not be a “regulatory straightjacket [sic]” and that
    courts should look for a “historical analogue” to the challenged
    regulation, not a “historical twin.” 142 S. Ct. at 2133. Despite
    these instructions, the Majority demands a historical twin by
    requiring the Government to identify a historical crime,
    including its punishment, that mirrors Bryan Range’s
    conviction. At the founding, the fraud-based crime of the type
    Range committed was considered a capital offense, which
    3
    obviously carries with it the loss of all possessory rights.3
    Folajtar v. Att’y Gen., 
    980 F.3d 897
    , 904-05 (3d Cir. 2020)
    (collecting authorities). The Majority recognizes that this
    severe punishment “reflects the founding generation’s
    judgment about the gravity of those offenses” and the need for
    harsh punishment. Maj. Op. at 19. It then, however, rejects
    this historical data by stressing that today, a far less severe
    punishment results, thereby rendering Range’s offense not
    “relevantly similar” to founding-era fraud offenses. 
    Id.
     at 19-
    20 (quoting Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2132). The problem with this
    analysis is that it focuses on present-day punishments to
    determine whether a founding-era crime is a historical
    analogue. Like it or not, Bruen mandates that we look at the
    law as it existed at the founding, and so the fact that the law
    has changed, or in this case, the punishment has changed, is
    irrelevant. Put differently, Bruen requires us to don blinders
    and look at only whether there is a historical analogue for the
    firearm regulation at issue. When we do so, history
    demonstrates that fraudsters could lose their life, and hence
    their firearms rights.
    The Majority also rejects the Government’s analogy to
    now unconstitutional status-based bans on Native Americans,
    Blacks, Catholics, Quakers, loyalists, and others because
    Range is not “part of a similar group today.” Maj. Op. at 19.
    Whether Range is a member of one of these groups is
    3
    Even some noncapital offenses resulted in life
    imprisonment and the forfeiture of the offender’s entire estate,
    which contemplates the loss of all property, including
    firearms. Act of Apr. 18, 1786, 2 Laws of the State of New
    York 253, 260–61 (1886); Act of Nov. 27, 1700, 2 Statutes at
    Large of Pennsylvania 12 (Wm. Stanley Ray ed., 1904).
    4
    irrelevant. Rather, under Bruen, the relevant inquiry is why a
    given regulation, such as a ban based on one’s status, was
    enacted and how that regulation was implemented. Bruen, 142
    S. Ct. at 2133. No matter how repugnant and unlawful these
    bans are under contemporary standards, the founders
    categorically disarmed the members of these groups because
    the founders viewed them as disloyal to the sovereign. Range
    v. Att’y Gen., 
    53 F.4th 262
    , 273-82 (3d Cir. 2022) (per curiam)
    (collecting authorities), vacated by 
    56 F.4th 992
     (3d Cir. 2023);
    see also Jackson, 
    2023 WL 3769242
    , at *5 (observing that the
    founding-era categorical prohibitions are relevant “in
    determining the historical understanding of the right to keep
    and bear arms”). The felon designation similarly serves as a
    proxy for disloyalty and disrespect for the sovereign and its
    laws. Such categorization is especially applicable here, where
    Range’s felony involved stealing from the government, a crime
    that directly undermines the sovereign. Therefore, the trust and
    loyalty reasons underlying the status-based bans imposed at the
    founding show that the bans are an appropriate historical
    analogue for the present-day prohibition on felon possession.4
    4
    The Majority also gives no weight to various
    founding-era statutory violations that led to disarmament, see,
    e.g., Act of Dec. 21, 1771, ch. 540, N.J. Laws 343–344; Act of
    Apr. 20, 1745, ch. 3, N.C. Laws 69–70; see also Range, 53
    F.4th at 281 (collecting additional authorities), because it
    contends that offenders were only disarmed of the firearm they
    possessed at the time of the violation and not barred from
    possessing firearms in the future, Maj. Op. at 19-20. From this,
    the Majority asserts crime-based bans were not permanent. Id.
    Whether true or not, the federal felon ban under 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g) is not permanent. Congress specifically identified
    5
    Finally, the Majority’s approach will have far-reaching
    consequences. Although the Majority states that its holding is
    “narrow” because it is limited to Range’s individual
    circumstances, Maj. Op. at 22, the only individual
    circumstance the Majority identifies is that the penalty Range
    faced differs from the penalty imposed at the founding. As
    discussed above, that fact is irrelevant under Bruen. Thus, the
    ruling is not cabined in any way and, in fact, rejects all
    historical support for disarming any felon.5 As a result, the
    Majority’s analytical framework leads to only one conclusion:
    ways to avoid the ban, such as by securing an expungement,
    pardon, or having one’s civil rights restored. 
    18 U.S.C. § 921
    (a)(20). Additionally, although it is currently unfunded,
    Congress enacted 
    18 U.S.C. § 925
    (c), which allows the Bureau
    of Alcohol, Tobacco, and Firearms to restore an individual’s
    right to possess a firearm upon consideration of the
    individual’s personal circumstances. See Logan v. United
    States, 
    552 U.S. 23
    , 28 n.1 (2007).
    5
    The Majority also says that it need not decide whether
    disarmament of violent criminals is supported by the historical
    evidence, Maj. Op. at 18 n.9, but its view of the history, its
    requirement of a historical twin, and its explanation that federal
    felon prohibitions enacted in 1938 and 1961 are too recent to
    be longstanding, necessarily mean that the Majority would
    conclude that bans on violent felons cannot be justified.
    Moreover, the framework outlined in Judge Porter’s
    concurrence would mean that the federal government would be
    prohibited from enacting any gun regulation. In fact, Judge
    Porter’s requirement that a current federal regulation be
    supported by a federally enacted analog in existence at the
    founding would call into question the federal government’s
    ability to regulate activities that did not then exist.
    6
    there will be no, or virtually no, felony or felony-equivalent
    crime that will bar an individual from possessing a firearm.6
    This is a broad ruling and, to me, is contrary to both the
    sentiments of the Supreme Court and our history.
    I therefore respectfully dissent.
    6
    Moreover, and significantly, the Majority provides no
    way for a felon to know whether his crime of conviction
    prevents him from possessing a firearm. This, however, is not
    entirely the Majority’s fault. Bruen requires a review of our
    nation’s history during a finite time period to determine
    whether a felon’s particular crime of conviction
    constitutionally permits disarmament—an inquiry that, under
    the Majority’s test, will vary from crime to crime. Thus, the
    concerns about due process and notice discussed in Judge
    Fuentes’s dissent in Binderup v. Attorney General, 
    836 F.3d 336
    , 409-11 (3d Cir. 2016) (Fuentes, J., dissenting in part and
    concurring in part), are even more pronounced after Bruen.
    7
    KRAUSE, Circuit Judge, dissenting.
    As Americans, we hold dear the values of individual
    liberty and freedom from tyranny that galvanized our Founders
    and are enshrined in the Constitution. So it is not surprising
    that we often look to history and tradition to inform our
    constitutional interpretation.1 But as Alexis de Tocqueville
    rightly observed of “the philosophical method of the
    Americans,” we “accept tradition only as a means of
    information, and existing facts only as a lesson to be used in .
    . . doing better.”2 Thus, when we draw on parallels with the
    past to assess what is permissible in the present, we typically
    look to match history in principle, not with precision.
    When it comes to permissible regulation of the right to
    bear arms, it might make good sense to hew precisely to history
    and tradition in a world where “arms” still meant muskets and
    1
    In the past few years, the Supreme Court has adopted a “his-
    tory and tradition” test in a variety of constitutional contexts,
    breaking from its own history where its precedent diverged
    from that interpretive method. See, e.g., Dobbs v. Jackson
    Women’s Health Org., 
    142 S. Ct. 2228 (2022)
     (interpreting the
    Due Process Clause and overruling Roe v. Wade, 
    410 U.S. 113
    (1973)); Kennedy v. Bremerton Sch. Dist., 
    142 S. Ct. 2407 (2022)
     (interpreting the Free Exercise Clause and overruling
    Lemon v. Kurtzman, 
    403 U.S. 602
     (1971)); TransUnion LLC v.
    Ramirez, 
    141 S. Ct. 2190 (2021)
     (explaining Article III stand-
    ing); Am. Legion v. Am. Humanist Ass’n, 
    139 S. Ct. 2067 (2019)
     (interpreting the Establishment Clause).
    2
    2 Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America 1 (Francis
    Bowen ed., Henry Reeve trans., 3d ed. 1863).
    1
    flintlock pistols,3 and where communities were still so small
    and “close-knit” that “[e]veryone knew everyone else,” “word-
    of-mouth spread quickly,” and the population “knew and
    agreed on what acts were right and wrong, which ones were
    permitted and forbidden.”4 But that is not the America of
    today. In modern times, arms include assault rifles,5 high-
    capacity magazines, and semi-automatic handguns; our
    population of more than 330 million is mobile, diverse, and, as
    to social mores, deeply divided; and, tragically, brutal gun
    deaths and horrific mass shootings—exceeding 260 in just the
    past five months—are a daily occurrence in our schools, our
    3
    See Joseph Blocher & Eric Ruben, Originalism-by-Analogy
    and Second Amendment Adjudication, 133 Yale L.J. (forth-
    coming 2023) (manuscript at 47), https://ssrn.com/ab-
    stract=4408228 (“Americans in 1791 generally owned muzzle-
    loading flintlocks, liable to misfire and incapable of firing mul-
    tiple shots. Guns, thus, generally were not kept or carried
    loaded in 1791[.]” (quotation omitted)); Akhil Reed Amar,
    Second Thoughts, 
    65 Law & Contemp. Probs. 103
    , 107 (2002)
    (“At the Founding . . . [a] person often had to get close to you
    to kill you, and, in getting close, he typically rendered himself
    vulnerable to counterattack. Reloading took time, and thus one
    person could not ordinarily kill dozens in seconds.”).
    4
    Stephanos Bibas, The Machinery of Criminal Justice 2
    (2012).
    5
    See Robert J. Spitzer, Gun Accessories and the Second
    Amendment: Assault Weapons, Magazines, and Silencers, 
    83 Law & Contemp. Probs. 231
    , 240 (2020) (“[A]ssault weapons
    play a disproportionately large role in three types of criminal
    activity: mass shootings, police killings, and gang activity.”).
    2
    streets, and our places of worship.6 In today’s world, the
    responsibilities that should accompany gun ownership are
    flouted by those who lack respect for the law.
    As debates rage on about the causes of this crisis and
    the solutions, the people’s elected representatives bear the
    heavy responsibility of enacting legislation that preserves the
    right to armed self-defense while ensuring public safety.
    Although they face evolving challenges in pursuing those twin
    aims, striking that delicate balance has long been a core
    function of the legislature in our system of separated powers,7
    6
    See Statement from President Joe Biden on the Shooting in
    Allen,    Texas,    White      House      (May       7,   2023),
    https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefing-room/statements-re-
    leases/2023/05/07/statement-from-president-joe-biden-on-
    the-shooting-in-allen-texas/; A Partial List of U.S. Mass Shoot-
    ings in 2023, N.Y. Times (May 30, 2023), https://www.ny-
    times.com/article/mass-shootings-2023.html; Gun Violence in
    America, Everytown for Gun Safety (Feb. 13, 2023),
    https://everytownresearch.org/report/gun-violence-in-amer-
    ica/.
    7
    See Adam Winkler, Scrutinizing the Second Amendment, 
    105 Mich. L. Rev. 683
    , 715 (2007) (“Achievement of that balance
    requires highly complex socio-economic calculations regard-
    ing what kinds of weapons ought to be possessed by individu-
    als and how to limit access to them by those deemed untrust-
    worthy or dangerous. Such complicated multi-factor judg-
    ments require trade-offs that courts are not institutionally
    equipped to make. Legislatures, by contrast, are structured to
    make precisely those kinds of determinations.”); see also Lon
    L. Fuller, The Forms and Limits of Adjudication, 92 Harv. L.
    3
    and legislatures’ authority to disarm those who cannot be
    trusted to follow the laws has long been crucial to that
    endeavor.
    Section 922(g)(1) of the U.S. Code, Title 18, embodies
    this delicate equilibrium and comports with traditional
    principles that have guided centuries of legislative judgments
    as to who can possess firearms. As Justice Alito has observed,
    § 922(g) “is no minor provision. It probably does more to
    combat gun violence than any other federal law.”8 And as a
    “longstanding”9 and widely accepted aspect of our national
    gun culture,10 the federal felon-possession ban—carefully
    crafted to respect the laws of the states—is the keystone of our
    national background check system,11 and has repeatedly been
    characterized by the Supreme Court as “presumptively
    Rev. 353, 371 (1978) (noting the “relative incapacity of adju-
    dication to solve ‘polycentric’ problems”).
    8
    Rehaif v. United States, 
    139 S. Ct. 2191
    , 2201 (2019) (Alito,
    J., dissenting).
    9
    District of Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 626 (2008).
    10
    See Dru Stevenson, In Defense of Felon-in-Possession Laws,
    
    43 Cardozo L. Rev. 1573
    , 1574 (2022) (explaining § 922(g)(1)
    is “the centerpiece of gun laws in the United States” and “the
    center of the gun-regulation universe”).
    11
    See id. at 1575 (“The felon prohibitor functions as the cor-
    nerstone of the federal background check system for firearm
    purchases[.]”).
    4
    lawful.”12 Where, as here, the legislature has made a
    reasonable and considered judgment to disarm those who show
    disrespect for the law, it is not the place of unelected judges to
    substitute that judgment with their own.
    Yet today’s majority brushes aside these realities and
    the seismic effect of its ruling. It is telling that, although it
    describes itself as limited “to Range’s situation,”13 today’s
    opinion is not designated non-precedential as appropriate for a
    unique individual case, but has precedential status, necessarily
    reaching beyond the particular facts presented. It is also telling
    that it tracks precisely the Fifth Circuit’s deeply disturbing
    opinion in United States v. Rahimi, which, finding no precise
    historical analogue, struck down as unconstitutional the ban on
    gun possession by domestic abusers.14 And in the process, the
    majority creates a circuit split with the Eighth Circuit’s recent
    opinion in United States v. Jackson, which rejected the notion
    of “felony-by-felony litigation” and recognized that “Congress
    acted within the historical tradition when it enacted § 922(g)(1)
    and the prohibition on possession of firearms by felons.”15
    In short, for all its assurances to the contrary and its
    lulling simplicity, the majority opinion commits our Court to a
    12
    E.g., Heller, 
    554 U.S. at
    627 n.26.
    13
    Maj. Op. at 19.
    14
    
    61 F.4th 443
     (5th Cir. 2023), petition for cert. filed (U.S.
    Mar. 21, 2023) (No. 22-915).
    15
    No. 22-2870, 
    2023 WL 3769242
    , at *4, *7 (8th Cir. June 2,
    2023).
    5
    framework so indefinite as to be void for vagueness and with
    dire consequences for our case law and citizenry. I therefore
    respectfully dissent.
    I write here to clarify three points16: First, the historical
    record demonstrates that, contrary to the majority opinion,
    legislatures have historically possessed the authority to disarm
    entire groups, like felons, whose conduct evinces disrespect for
    the rule of law. Second, the doctrinal and practical
    ramifications of the majority’s approach, which my colleagues
    do not even acknowledge, let alone address, are profound and
    pernicious. Third, in order to hold § 922(g)(1) inapplicable to
    Range in a truly narrow opinion, my colleagues did not need to
    throw out the baby with the bath water; instead, they could
    have issued a declaratory judgment holding § 922(g)(1)
    unconstitutional as applied to the petitioner currently before
    the Court—in effect, prospectively restoring his firearm rights.
    At least that approach would have been more faithful to history
    and consistent with the rule of law than the majority’s
    sweeping, retroactive pronouncement and the calamity it
    portends.
    I.     The Historical Validity of § 922(g)(1)
    We begin our historical inquiry with the benefit of more
    than a decade of Supreme Court precedent that illuminates the
    Court’s understanding of traditional firearm regulations. In
    Bruen, the majority characterized the holders of Second
    16
    I also share the doctrinal and historical concerns raised in
    Judge Shwartz’s cogent dissent, with which I agree in full.
    6
    Amendment rights as “law-abiding” citizens fourteen times.17
    Delimiting the “unqualified command” of the Second Amend-
    ment to “law-abiding” individuals was not novel.18 In holding
    “the right of the people”19 protected by the Second Amendment
    was an “individual right,”20 Justice Scalia’s seminal opinion in
    Heller specified this meant “the right of law-abiding,
    17
    N.Y. State Rifle & Pistol Ass’n, Inc. v. Bruen, 
    142 S. Ct. 2111
    , 2122, 2125, 2131, 2133–34, 2135 n.8, 2138 & n.9, 2150,
    2156 (2022).
    18
    
    Id.
     at 2130–31 (quotation omitted).
    19
    Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 579
    . In the first part of its analysis, the
    majority defends its belief that convicted felons remain part of
    “the people,” so their firearm possession is presumptively pro-
    tected and the Government must prove its disarmament regu-
    lation comports with historical tradition. Maj. Op. at 11–15.
    Other jurists believe that historical tradition permits the dis-
    armament of felons precisely because “the people” historically
    meant “law-abiding, responsible citizens.” Bruen, 142 S. Ct.
    at 2131 (quotation omitted). But that debate—unlike the test
    for what constitutes an adequate “historical analogue,” id. at
    2133 (quoting Drummond v. Robinson, 
    9 F.4th 217
    , 226 (3d
    Cir. 2021))—is largely academic. As then-Judge Barrett rec-
    ognized, the “same body of evidence” can be used to illuminate
    who is part of the people or “the scope of the legislature’s
    power,” and either approach “yield[s] the same result.” Kanter
    v. Barr, 
    919 F.3d 437
    , 452 (7th Cir. 2019) (Barrett, J., dissent-
    ing).
    20
    Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 592
    .
    7
    responsible citizens” to keep and bear arms,21 and therefore
    characterized “prohibitions on the possession of firearms by
    felons” as both “longstanding” and “presumptively lawful.”22
    In Bruen, the Supreme Court clarified who qualifies as
    a “law-abiding” citizen when it explained that, despite the in-
    firmity of New York’s may-issue open-carry licensing regime,
    “nothing in our analysis should be interpreted to suggest the
    unconstitutionality of the 43 States’ ‘shall-issue’ licensing re-
    gimes . . . [,] which often require applicants to undergo a [crim-
    inal] background check” and “are designed to ensure only that
    those bearing arms in the jurisdiction are, in fact, ‘law-abiding,
    responsible citizens.’”23
    Thus, time and again, the Supreme Court has acknowl-
    edged that the deep roots of felon-possession bans in American
    history impart a presumption of lawfulness to 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1). Yet my colleagues persist in disputing it. They
    21
    
    Id. at 635
    .
    22
    
    Id.
     at 626–27 & n.26; see also McDonald v. City of Chicago,
    
    561 U.S. 742
    , 786 (2010) (plurality) (“repeat[ing] those assur-
    ances”); Bruen 142 S. Ct. at 2157 (Alito, J., concurring)
    (same), 2162 (Kavanaugh, J., concurring) (same).
    23
    142 S. Ct. at 2138 n.9 (quoting Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 635
    ).
    Those background checks screen for both violent and non-vio-
    lent offenses.      See, e.g., 
    Wash. Rev. Code Ann. § 9.41.070
    (1)(a); 
    Colo. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 18-12-203
    (1)(c);
    
    Kan. Stat. Ann. § 75
    -7c04(a)(2); Miss. Code. Ann. § 45-9-
    101(2)(d); 
    N.H. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 159:6
    (I)(a); 
    N.C. Gen. Stat. Ann. § 14-415.12
    (b)(1).
    8
    contend that, as a twentieth-century enactment, § 922(g)(1)
    “falls well short of ‘longstanding’ for purposes of demarcating
    the scope of a constitutional right.”24 But “longstanding” can
    mean decades, not centuries,25 when a practice has become an
    accepted part of “our Nation’s public traditions,”26 as the felon-
    possession ban has,27 and, by virtue of that acceptance, it is en-
    titled to a “strong presumption of constitutionality.”28 Moreo-
    ver, Bruen observed that historical analogies must be more
    flexible when a contemporary regulation implicates “unprece-
    dented societal concerns or dramatic technological
    changes[.]”29 Section 922(g)(1) is such a regulation, as the le-
    thality of today’s weaponry, the ubiquity of gun violence, the
    24
    Maj. Op. at 17.
    25
    Am. Legion, 139 S. Ct. at 2082.
    26
    Freedom from Religion Found., Inc. v. County of Lehigh,
    
    933 F.3d 275
    , 283 (3d Cir. 2019).
    27
    See Stevenson, supra note 10, at 1574.
    28
    Am. Legion, 139 S. Ct. at 2085.
    29
    142 S. Ct. at 2132 (quotation omitted). The Eighth Circuit
    likewise observed that common sense and flexibility are indis-
    pensable in assessing historical analogues because “the Con-
    stitution can, and must, apply to circumstances beyond those
    the Founders specifically anticipated.” Jackson, No. 22-2870,
    
    2023 WL 3769242
    , at *6 (quoting Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2132).
    9
    size and anonymity of the population, and the extent of inter-
    state travel were unknown at the Founding.30
    As the Supreme Court has not performed an “exhaustive
    historical analysis” of the felon-possession ban, much less “the
    full scope of the Second Amendment,”31 we must conduct that
    review to determine whether § 922(g)(1)’s application to fel-
    ons, including Range, finds support in our national tradition.
    That analysis confirms it does.
    For purposes of this inquiry, “not all history is created
    equal.”32 As the right to keep and bear arms was a “pre-exist-
    ing right,” we must consider “English history dating from the
    late 1600s, along with American colonial views leading up to
    the founding.”33 Post-ratification practices from the late eight-
    eenth and early nineteenth centuries are also highly relevant,
    while later nineteenth century history is less informative.34 If
    we heed the Supreme Court’s admonition to analogize to his-
    torical regulations, but not to require a “historical twin,”35 these
    30
    Even aside from these modern-day developments, however,
    the tradition of categorically disarming entire groups whom
    legislatures did not trust to obey the law dates back to at least
    the seventeenth century. See infra Section I.A.
    31
    Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2128 (quotation omitted).
    32
    Id. at 2136.
    33
    Id. at 2127 (citing Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 595
    ).
    34
    See 
    id.
     at 2136–37.
    35
    Id. at 2133.
    10
    sources demonstrate the validity of § 922(g)(1) as applied in
    this case.
    A.     England’s Restoration and Glorious Revolution
    During the late seventeenth century, the English
    government repeatedly disarmed individuals whose conduct
    indicated that they could not be trusted to abide by the
    sovereign and its dictates.
    Following the tumult of the English Civil War, the
    restored Stuart monarchs disarmed nonconformist (i.e., non-
    Anglican) Protestants.36 Of course, not all nonconformists
    were dangerous; to the contrary, many belonged to pacificist
    denominations like the Quakers.37 However, they refused to
    participate in the Church of England, an institution headed by
    the King as a matter of English law.38 And nonconformists
    36
    See Joyce Lee Malcolm, To Keep and Bear Arms: The Ori-
    gins of an Anglo-American Right 45 (1994) (describing how
    Charles II “totally disarmed . . . religious dissenters”).
    37
    See Joyce Lee Malcolm, The Right of the People to Keep and
    Bear Arms: The Common Law Tradition, 
    10 Hastings Const. L.Q. 285
    , 304 n.117 (1983) (“Persons judged to be suspicious
    by the royal administration were those . . . who belonged to the
    Protestant sects that refused to remain within the Church of
    England. The Quakers were prominent sufferers.”).
    38
    See Church of England, BBC (June 30, 2011),
    https://www.bbc.co.uk/religion/religions/christian-
    ity/cofe/cofe_1.shtml (describing “the Act of Supremacy” en-
    acted during the reign of Henry VIII).
    11
    often refused to take mandatory oaths acknowledging the
    King’s sovereign authority over matters of religion.39 As a
    result, Anglicans accused nonconformists of believing their
    faith exempted them from obedience to the law.40
    Protestants had their rights restored after the Glorious
    Revolution of 1688 replaced the Catholic King James II with
    William of Orange and Mary, James’s Protestant daughter.41
    But even then, Parliament enacted the English Bill of Rights,
    which declared: “Subjects which are Protestants, may have
    Arms for their Defence suitable to their Conditions, and as
    allowed by Law.”42 This “predecessor to our Second
    Amendment”43 reveals that the legislature—Parliament—was
    39
    See Frederick B. Jonassen, “So Help Me?”: Religious Ex-
    pression and Artifacts in the Oath of Office and the Courtroom
    Oath, 12 Cardozo Pub. L., Pol’y & Ethics J. 303, 322 (2014)
    (describing Charles II’s reinstation of the Oath of Supremacy);
    Caroline Robbins, Selden’s Pills: State Oaths in England,
    1558–1714, 35 Huntington Lib. Q. 303, 314–15 (1972) (dis-
    cussing nonconformists’ refusal to take such oaths).
    40
    See Christopher Haigh, ‘Theological Wars’: ‘Socinians’ v.
    ‘Antinomians’ in Restoration England, 67 J. Ecclesiastical
    Hist. 325, 326, 334 (2016).
    41
    See Alice Ristroph, The Second Amendment in a Carceral
    State, 
    116 Nw. U. L. Rev. 203
    , 228 (2021).
    42
    1 W. & M., Sess. 2, ch. 2, § 7 (Eng. 1689) (emphasis added).
    43
    Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2141 (quoting Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 593
    ).
    12
    understood to have the authority and discretion to decide who
    was sufficiently law-abiding to keep and bear arms.44
    In 1689, the pendulum of distrust swung the other way.
    Parliament enacted a statute prohibiting Catholics who refused
    to take an oath renouncing the tenets of their faith from owning
    firearms, except as necessary for self-defense.45 As with
    nonconformists, this prohibition was not based on the notion
    that every single Catholic was dangerous. Rather, the
    categorical argument English Protestants made against
    Catholicism at the time was that Catholics’ faith put the
    dictates of a “foreign power,” namely the Vatican, before
    English law.46 Official Anglican doctrine—regularly preached
    throughout England—warned that the Pope taught “that they
    that are under him are free from all burdens and charges of the
    commonwealth, and obedience toward their prince[.]”47
    44
    Cf. Lois G. Schwoerer, To Hold and Bear Arms: The English
    Perspective, 
    76 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 27
    , 47–48 (2000) (explain-
    ing how the English Bill of Rights preserved Parliament’s au-
    thority to limit who could bear arms).
    45
    An Act for the Better Securing the Government by Disarm-
    ing Papists and Reputed Papists, 1 W. & M., Sess. 1, ch. 15
    (Eng. 1688); see Malcolm, supra note 36, at 123.
    46
    See Diego Lucci, John Locke on Atheism, Catholicism, An-
    tinomianism, and Deism, 20 Etica & Politica/Ethics & Pol.
    201, 228–29 (2018).
    47
    An Exhortation Concerning Good Order, and Obedience to
    Rulers and Magistrates, in Sermons or Homilies Appointed to
    13
    Accordingly, the disarmament of Catholics in 1689 reflects
    Protestant fears that Catholics could not be trusted to obey the
    law.
    That restriction could be lifted only prospectively and
    on an individual basis. That is, Parliament permitted Catholics
    who “repeated and subscribed” to the necessary oath before
    “any two or more Justices of the Peace” to resume keeping
    arms.48 Disavowal of religious tenets hardly demonstrated that
    the swearing individual no longer had the capacity to commit
    violence; rather, the oath was a gesture of allegiance to the
    English government and an assurance of conformity to its laws.
    The status-based disarmament of Catholics thus again evinces
    the “historical understanding”49 that legislatures could
    categorically disarm a group they viewed as unwilling to obey
    the law.
    B.     Colonial America
    The English notion that the government could disarm
    those not considered law-abiding traveled to the American
    colonies. Although some of the earliest firearm laws in
    colonial America forbid Native Americans and Black persons
    Be Read in Churches in the Time of Queen Elizabeth of Fa-
    mous Memory 114, 125 (new ed., Gilbert & Rivington 1839).
    48
    1 W. & M., Sess. 1, ch. 15 (Eng. 1688).
    49
    Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2131.
    14
    from owning guns,50 the colonies also repeatedly disarmed
    full-fledged members of the political community as it then
    existed—i.e., free, Christian, white men—whom the
    authorities believed could not be trusted to obey the law. Those
    restrictions are telling because they were imposed at a time
    when, before the advent of the English Bill of Rights, the
    charters of Virginia and Massachusetts provided
    unprecedented protections for colonists’ firearm rights.51
    The Virginia Company carried out one of the earliest
    recorded disarmaments in the American colonies in 1624. For
    his “opprobrious” and “base and detracting speeches
    concerning the Governor,” the Virginia Council ordered
    Richard Barnes “disarmed” and “banished” from Jamestown.52
    50
    See Clayton E. Cramer, Armed America: The Remarkable
    Story of How and Why Guns Became as American as Apple Pie
    31, 43 (2006). Today, we emphatically reject these bigoted and
    unconstitutional laws, as well as their premise that one’s race
    or religion correlates with disrespect for the law. I cite them
    here only to demonstrate the tradition of categorical, status-
    based disarmaments. See Blocher & Ruben, supra note 3, at
    63 (urging courts examining historical disarmament laws that
    would violate the Constitution today to “ask[] why earlier gen-
    erations regulated gun possession more generally, rather than
    just who they disarmed”).
    51
    See Nicholas J. Johnson et al., Firearms Law and the Second
    Amendment: Regulation, Rights, and Policy 174 (3d ed. 2022).
    52
    David Thomas Konig, “Dale’s Laws” and the Non-Common
    Law Origins of Criminal Justice in Virginia, 
    26 Am. J. Legal Hist. 354
    , 371 (1982).
    15
    By disrespecting the colonial authorities, Barnes demonstrated
    that he could no longer be trusted as a law-abiding member of
    the community and thus forfeited his ability to keep arms.
    During the late 1630s, a Boston preacher named Anne
    Hutchinson challenged the Massachusetts Bay government’s
    authority over spiritual matters by advocating for direct,
    personal relationships with the divine.53 Governor John
    Winthrop accused Hutchinson and her followers of being
    Antinomians—those who viewed their salvation as exempting
    them from the law—and banished her.54 The colonial
    government also disarmed at least fifty-eight of Hutchinson’s
    supporters, not because those supporters had demonstrated a
    propensity for violence, but rather “to embarrass the offenders”
    who were forced to personally deliver their arms to the
    authorities in an act of public submission.55 The Massachusetts
    authorities therefore disarmed Hutchinson’s supporters to
    shame those colonists because the authorities concluded their
    conduct evinced a willingness to disobey the law.56 Again,
    53
    See Edmund S. Morgan, The Case Against Anne Hutchinson,
    10 New Eng. Q. 635, 637–38, 644 (1937).
    54
    
    Id. at 648
    ; Ann Fairfax Withington & Jack Schwartz, The
    Political Trial of Anne Hutchinson, 51 New Eng. Q. 226, 226
    (1978).
    55
    James F. Cooper, Jr., Anne Hutchinson and the “Lay Rebel-
    lion” Against the Clergy, 61 New Eng. Q. 381, 391 (1988).
    56
    Cf. John Felipe Acevedo, Dignity Takings in the Criminal
    Law of Seventeenth-Century England and the Massachusetts
    Bay Colony, 
    92 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 743
    , 761 (2017) (describing
    16
    restoration of that right was available, but only prospectively,
    for individuals who affirmatively sought relief: Hutchinson’s
    followers who renounced her teachings and confessed their
    sins to the authorities “were welcomed back into the
    community and able to retain their arms,” as they had shown
    that they could once again be trusted to abide by the law.57
    Like the Stuart monarchs in England, the Anglican
    colony of Virginia disarmed nonconformist Protestants in the
    1640s due to their rejection of the King’s sovereign power over
    religion. When a group of nonconformist Puritans from
    Massachusetts resettled in southeastern Virginia,58 Virginia
    Governor William Berkeley “acted quickly to silence the
    Puritan[s].”59 His concern with any “[o]pposition to the
    other shaming punishments used at the time, including scarlet
    letters).
    57
    Joseph G.S. Greenlee, The Historical Justification for Pro-
    hibiting Dangerous Persons from Possessing Arms, 
    20 Wyo. L. Rev. 249
    , 263 (2020).
    58
    Charles Campbell, History of the Colony and Ancient Do-
    minion of Virginia 211 (1860).
    59
    Kevin Butterfield, The Puritan Experiment in Virginia,
    1607–1650, at 21 (June 1999) (M.A. thesis, College of William
    and Mary) (on file with William and Mary Libraries).
    17
    king”60 led Governor Berkeley to disarm the Puritans before
    banishing them from the colony.61
    After the Glorious Revolution, the American colonies
    also followed England in disarming their Catholic residents.
    Just three years after designating Anglicanism as the colony’s
    official religion,62 Governor Benjamin Fletcher of New York
    disarmed Catholic colonists in 1696.63 The colonies redoubled
    their disarmament of Catholics during the Seven Years’ War
    of 1756–1763.64 Maryland, for example, though founded as a
    haven for persecuted English Catholics,65 confiscated firearms
    from its Catholic residents during the war.66 Notably, that
    decision was not in response to violence; indeed, the colony’s
    60
    
    Id.
    61
    Campbell, supra note 58, at 212.
    62
    See George J. Lankevich, New York City: A Short History 30
    (2002).
    63
    See Shona Helen Johnston, Papists in a Protestant World:
    The Catholic Anglo-Atlantic in the Seventeenth Century 219–
    20 (May 11, 2011) (Ph.D. dissertation, Georgetown Univer-
    sity) (on file with the Georgetown University Library).
    64
    See Greenlee, supra note 57, at 263.
    65
    See Michael W. McConnell, The Origins and Historical Un-
    derstanding of Free Exercise of Religion, 
    103 Harv. L. Rev. 1409
    , 1424 (1990).
    66
    See Greenlee, supra note 57, at 263; Johnson et al., supra
    note 51, at 197.
    18
    governor at the time, Horatio Sharpe, observed that “the
    Papists behave themselves peaceably and as good subjects.”67
    Neighboring Virginia likewise disarmed Catholics, but
    allowed those who demonstrated their willingness to obey the
    law by swearing an oath of loyalty to the King to retain their
    weapons.68 The colonies therefore continued the English
    practice of disarming Catholics based on their perceived
    unwillingness to adhere to the King’s sovereign dictates.
    Catholics were not the only group of colonists disarmed
    during the Seven Years’ War. New Jersey confiscated firearms
    from Moravians, a group of nonconformist Protestants from
    modern-day Germany.69 Like the Quakers, Moravians were—
    as they are today—committed pacifists who owned weapons
    for hunting instead of fighting.70 Regardless, New Jersey
    Governor Jonathan Belcher deemed their nonconformist views
    sufficient evidence that they could not be trusted to obey royal
    authority, so he ordered their disarmament.71
    67
    Elihu S. Riley, A History of the General Assembly of Mary-
    land 224 (1912) (quoting a July 9, 1755 letter from Governor
    Sharpe).
    68
    See Johnson et al., supra note 51, at 198.
    69
    See id.
    70
    See id.
    71
    See id. (discussing Governor Belcher’s view that the Mora-
    vians were “Snakes in the Grass and Enemies of King
    George”).
    19
    C.     Revolutionary War
    As the colonies became independent states, legislatures
    continued to disarm individuals whose status indicated that
    they could not be trusted to obey the law. John Locke—a
    philosopher who profoundly influenced the American
    revolutionaries72—argued that the replacement of individual
    judgments of what behavior is acceptable with communal
    norms is an essential characteristic of the social contract.73
    Members of a social compact, he explained, therefore have a
    civic obligation to comply with communal judgments
    regarding proper behavior.74
    Drawing on Locke, state legislatures conditioned their
    citizens’ ability to keep arms on compliance with that civic
    72
    See Thad W. Tate, The Social Contract in America, 1774–
    1787: Revolutionary Theory as a Conservative Instrument, 22
    Wm. & Mary Q. 375, 376 (1965); see also Gundy v. United
    States, 
    139 S. Ct. 2116
    , 2133 (2019) (Gorsuch, J., dissenting)
    (observing “John Locke [was] one of the thinkers who most
    influenced the framers”).
    73
    See John Locke, Two Treatises of Government § 163
    (Thomas I. Cook ed., Hafner Press 1947) (reasoning “there
    only is political society where every one of the members hath
    quitted his natural power [to judge transgressions and] resigned
    it up into the hands of the community”).
    74
    Locke grounded that duty in the consent of those within a
    political society; however, he argued that mere presence in a
    territory constitutes tacit consent to the laws of the reigning
    sovereign. See id. § 119.
    20
    obligation, and several states enacted statutes disarming all
    those who refused to recognize the sovereignty of the new
    nation.75 In Connecticut, for instance, as tensions with England
    rose, colonists denounced loyalists’ dereliction of their duty to
    the civic community. The inhabitants of Coventry passed a
    resolution in 1774 stating loyalists were “unworthy of that
    friendship and esteem which constitutes the bond of social
    happiness, and ought to be treated with contempt and total
    neglect.”76    “Committees of Inspection” formed across
    Connecticut and published the names and addresses of
    suspected loyalists in local newspapers as “persons held up to
    the public view as enemies to their country.”77 Concerns that
    loyalists could not be trusted to uphold their civic duties as
    members of a new state culminated in a 1775 statute that forbid
    anyone who defamed resolutions of the Continental Congress
    from keeping arms, voting, or serving as a public official.78
    75
    See Robert H. Churchill, Gun Regulation, the Police Power,
    and the Right to Keep Arms in Early America: The Legal Con-
    text of the Second Amendment, 
    25 Law & Hist. Rev. 139
    , 158
    (2007).
    76
    G.A. Gilbert, The Connecticut Loyalists, 4 Am. Hist. Rev.
    273, 280 (1899) (describing this resolution as “a fair sample of
    most of the others passed at this time”).
    77
    
    Id.
     at 280–81.
    78
    See 
    id. at 282
    .
    21
    Virginia disarmed those viewed as unwilling to abide by
    the newly sovereign state’s legal norms.79 Virginia’s loyalty
    oath statute disarmed “all free born male inhabitants of this
    state, above the age of sixteen years, except imported servants
    during the time of their service” who refused to swear their
    “allegiance and fidelity” to the state.80 And conversely, it
    allowed for prospective restoration of rights upon the taking of
    that oath.81
    Pennsylvania also disarmed entire groups whose status
    suggested they could not be trusted to abide by the law. In
    1777, the legislature enacted a statute requiring all white male
    inhabitants above the age of eighteen to swear to “be faithful
    and bear true allegiance to the commonwealth of Pennsylvania
    as a free and independent state,”82 and providing that those who
    failed to take the oath “shall be disarmed” by the local
    79
    An Act to Oblige the Free Male Inhabitants of this State
    Above a Certain Age to Give Assurance of Allegiances to the
    Same, and for Other Purposes ch. III (1777), 9 Statutes at
    Large; Being a Collection of All the Laws of Virginia, from the
    First Session of the Legislature in the Year 1619 281, 281 (Wil-
    liam W. Hening ed., 1821).
    80
    
    Id.
    81
    
    Id.
    82
    Act of June 13, 1777, § 1 (1777), 9 The Statutes at Large of
    Pennsylvania from 1652–1801 110, 111 (William Stanley Ray
    ed., 1903).
    22
    authorities.83 That statute is especially illuminating because
    Pennsylvania’s 1776 constitution protected the people’s right
    to bear arms.84 Yet the disarmament law deprived sizable
    numbers of pacifists of that right because oath-taking violated
    the religious convictions of Quakers, Moravians, Mennonites,
    and other groups.85 Those groups were not disarmed because
    they were dangerous,86 but rather because their refusal to swear
    allegiance demonstrated that they would not submit to
    communal judgments embodied in law when it conflicted with
    83
    Id. § 3, at 112–13.
    84
    See Saul Cornell, “Don’t Know Much About History”: The
    Current Crisis in Second Amendment Scholarship, 
    29 N. Ky. L. Rev. 657
    , 670–71 (2002).
    85
    See Jim Wedeking, Quaker State: Pennsylvania’s Guide to
    Reducing the Friction for Religious Outsiders Under the Es-
    tablishment Clause, 2 N.Y.U. J.L. & Liberty 28, 51 (2006); see
    also Thomas C. McHugh, Moravian Opposition to the Penn-
    sylvania Test Acts, 1777 to 1789, at 49–50 (Sept. 7, 1965)
    (M.A. thesis, Lehigh University) (on file with the Lehigh Pre-
    serve Institutional Repository).
    86
    See Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 590
     (“Quakers opposed the use of
    arms not just for militia service, but for any violent purpose
    whatsoever . . . .”); Johnson et al., supra note 51, at 301 (noting
    that states disarmed “Quakers and other pacifists; although
    they were not fighters, they did own guns for hunting”).
    23
    personal conviction.87           Only those presumptively
    untrustworthy individuals who came forward and established
    that they were indeed law-abiding by swearing the loyalty oath
    before state authorities had their firearm rights restored.88
    D.     Ratification Debates
    The Founding generation reiterated the longstanding
    principle that legislatures could disarm non-law-abiding
    citizens during the deliberations over whether to ratify the
    Constitution.
    Debates between the Federalists and Anti-Federalists in
    Pennsylvania “were among the most influential and widely
    distributed of any essays published during ratification.”89
    Those essays included “The Dissent of the Minority,” a
    statement of the Anti-Federalist delegates’ views90 that proved
    87
    See Wedeking, supra note 85, at 51–52 (describing how
    Quakers were “penal[ized] for allegiance to their religious
    scruples over the new government”).
    88
    Act of June 13, 1777, § 3 (1777), 9 The Statutes at Large of
    Pennsylvania from 1652–1801 110, 112 (William Stanley Ray
    ed., 1903).
    89
    Saul Cornell, Commonplace or Anachronism: The Standard
    Model, the Second Amendment, and the Problem of History in
    Contemporary Constitutional Theory, 
    16 Const. Comment. 221
    , 227 (1999).
    90
    See 
    id.
     at 232–33.
    24
    “highly influential” for the Second Amendment.91 The Dissent
    of the Minority proposed an amendment stating:
    [T]he people have a right to bear
    arms for the defence of themselves
    and their own State or the United
    States, or for the purpose of killing
    game; and no law shall be passed
    for disarming the people or any of
    them unless for crimes committed,
    or real danger of public injury from
    individuals.92
    While this amendment was not adopted, it is important
    because, read in the context of traditional Anglo-American
    firearm laws, it reflects the understanding of the Founding
    generation—particularly among those who favored enshrining
    91
    Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 604
    ; see also Amul R. Thapar & Joe Mas-
    terman, Fidelity and Construction, 
    129 Yale L.J. 774
    , 797
    (2020) (“Although one might question why we should listen to
    the debate’s ‘losers,’ the Anti-Federalist Papers are relevant for
    the same reason that the Federalist Papers are: to quote Justice
    Scalia, ‘their writings, like those of other intelligent and in-
    formed people of the time, display how the text of the Consti-
    tution was originally understood.’ Plus, the Anti-Federalists
    did not exactly ‘lose,’ in the same way in which a party who
    settles a case but gets important concessions does not ‘lose’ the
    case.” (quoting Antonin Scalia, A Matter of Interpretation:
    Federal Courts and the Law 38 (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997))).
    92
    2 Bernard Schwartz, The Bill of Rights: A Documentary His-
    tory 665 (1971) (emphasis added).
    25
    the right to armed self-defense in the Constitution—that
    “crimes committed,” whether dangerous or not, justified
    disarmament.
    E.    Criminal Punishment
    The penalties meted out for a variety of offenses
    between the seventeenth and nineteenth centuries also
    demonstrate the widespread acceptance of legislatures’
    authority to disarm felons.
    At the Founding, a conviction for a serious crime
    resulted in the permanent loss of the offender’s ability to keep
    and bear arms. Those who committed grave felonies—both
    violent and non-violent—were executed.93 A fortiori, the
    ubiquity of the death penalty94 suggests that the Founding
    generation would have had no objection to imposing on felons
    the comparatively lenient penalty of disarmament. Indeed,
    under English law, executed felons traditionally forfeited all
    their firearms, as well as the rest of their estate, to the
    government.95 That practice persisted in the American
    colonies and the Early Republic.96 Even some non-capital
    93
    See Folajtar v. Att’y Gen., 
    980 F.3d 897
    , 904–05 (3d Cir.
    2020).
    94
    See Baze v. Rees, 
    553 U.S. 35
    , 94 (2008) (Thomas, J., con-
    curring).
    95
    See 4 William Blackstone, Commentaries *97–98.
    96
    See Respublica v. Doan, 
    1 U.S. 86
    , 91 (Pa. 1784) (“Doan,
    besides the forfeiture of his estate, has forfeited his life.”). At
    26
    offenses triggered the permanent loss of an offender’s estate,
    including any firearms. For example, a 1786 New York statute
    punished those who counterfeited state bills of credit with life
    imprisonment and the forfeiture of their entire estate.97 Again,
    this drastic punishment indicates that the Founding generation
    would not have considered the lesser punishment of
    disarmament beyond a legislature’s authority.
    Individuals who committed less serious crimes also lost
    their firearms on a temporary, if not permanent, basis. Where
    state legislatures stipulated that certain offenses were not
    common law, forfeiture also resulted in “corruption of the
    blood,” which prevented the felon’s heirs from inheriting or
    transmitting the offender’s property. Richard E. Finneran &
    Steven K. Luther, Criminal Forfeiture and the Sixth Amend-
    ment: The Role of the Jury at Common Law, 
    35 Cardozo L. Rev. 1
    , 27 (2013). In the Early Republic, several states limited
    the loss of one’s property to the lifetime of the offender. See 2
    James Kent, Commentaries on American Law *387 (1826); cf.
    U.S. Const. art. III, § 3, cl. 2 (“The Congress shall have Power
    to declare the Punishment of Treason, but no Attainder of Trea-
    son shall work Corruption of Blood, or Forfeiture except dur-
    ing the Life of the Person attainted.” (emphasis added)). Estate
    forfeiture ultimately fell into disuse in the 1820s. See Com. v.
    Pennock, 
    1817 WL 1789
    , at *1–2 (Pa. 1817); Will Tress, Un-
    intended Collateral Consequences: Defining Felony in the
    Early American Republic, 
    57 Clev. St. L. Rev. 461
    , 473 (2009).
    97
    Act of Apr. 18, 1786, 2 Laws of the State of New York 253,
    260–61 (1886); see also Act of Nov. 27, 1700, 2 Statutes at
    Large of Pennsylvania 12 (Wm. Stanley Ray ed., 1904) (pun-
    ishing arson with life imprisonment and estate forfeiture).
    27
    punishable by death or life imprisonment, but rather resulted in
    forfeiture,98 the offender was stripped of his then-existing
    estate, including any firearms,99 and only upon successfully
    98
    See, e.g., Act of Apr. 5, 1790, § 2 (1790), 13 Statutes at Large
    of Pennsylvania 511, 511–12 (Wm. Stanley Ray ed., 1908)
    (robbery, burglary, sodomy, buggery); Act of Jan. 4, 1787, § 9
    (1787), 24 Colonial Records of North Carolina 787, 788 (Wal-
    ter Clark ed., 1905) (filing a false inventory of property in con-
    nection with a procurement fraud investigation); An Act to Pre-
    vent Routs, Riots, and Tumultuous Assemblies, § 4 (1786), 3
    Compendium and Digest of the Laws of Massachusetts 1132,
    1134 (Thomas B. Wait ed., 1810) (rioting); Act of Nov. 26,
    1779, § 2 (1779), 10 Statutes at Large of Pennsylvania 12, 15–
    16 (Wm. Stanley Ray ed., 1904) (counterfeiting); An Act for
    the Regulation of the Markets in the City of Philadelphia, and
    for Other Purposes Therein Mentioned, § 1 (1779), 9 Statutes
    at Large of Pennsylvania 387, 388–89 (Wm. Stanley Ray ed.,
    1904) (diverting food en route to Philadelphia or attempting to
    raise the price of food at the city’s market three times); An Act
    for Establishing an Office for the Purpose of Borrowing Money
    for the Use of the Commonwealth, § 4 (1777), 9 Statutes at
    Large; Being a Collection of All the Laws of Virginia, from the
    First Session of the Legislature in the Year 1619, at 286, 287
    (William W. Hening ed., 1821) (counterfeiting).
    99
    See, e.g., Act of Apr. 5, 1790, § 2 (1790), 13 Statutes at Large
    of Pennsylvania 511, 511–12 (Wm. Stanley Ray ed., 1908)
    (providing that the offender “shall forfeit to the commonwealth
    all . . . goods and chattels whereof he or she was seized or pos-
    sessed at the time the crime was committed and at any time
    afterwards until conviction”).
    28
    serving of his sentence and reintegrating into society could he
    presumably repurchase arms.
    Finally, colonial and state legislatures punished minor
    infractions with partial disarmaments by seizing firearms
    involved in those offenses. For example, individuals who
    hunted in certain prohibited areas had to forfeit any weapons
    used in the course of that violation.100
    *    *      *
    As this survey reflects, and as the Supreme Court
    observed in Heller, restrictions on the ability of felons to
    possess firearms are indeed “longstanding[.]”101        Four
    centuries of Anglo-American history demonstrate that
    legislatures repeatedly exercised their discretion to impose
    “status-based restrictions” disarming entire “categories of
    persons,” who were presumed, based on past conduct,
    100
    See 
    1652 N.Y. Laws 138
    ; Act of Apr. 20, ch. III (1745), 23
    Acts of the North Carolina General Assembly 218, 219 (1805);
    
    1771 N.J. Laws 19
    –20; An Act for the Protection and Security
    of the Sheep and Other Stock on Tarpaulin Cove Island, Oth-
    erwise Called Naushon Island, and on Nennemessett Island,
    and Several Small Islands Contiguous, Situated in the County
    of Dukes County § 2 (1790), 1 Private and Special Statutes of
    the Commonwealth of Massachusetts 258, 259 (Manning &
    Loring ed., 1805); 
    1832 Va. Acts 70
    ; 
    1838 Md. Laws 291
    –92;
    
    12 Del. Laws 365
     (1863).
    101
    
    554 U.S. at 626
    .
    29
    unwilling to obey the law.102 Legislatures did so not because
    the individuals in these groups were considered dangerous, but
    because, based on their status, they were deemed non-law-
    abiding subjects.103 The particular groups varied dramatically
    over time, but the Founding generation understood that felons
    were one such group.
    The length of disarmaments varied too, but the
    Founding generation recognized that legislatures—in their
    discretion—could impose permanent, temporary, or indefinite
    bans that lasted until the individual affirmatively sought relief
    and made a showing of commitment to abide by the law. In
    that case, the showing was not viewed as voiding the ban
    retroactively, from its inception; rather, it operated
    prospectively. Only after the individual had made the requisite
    showing to a government official—and thus rebutted the
    presumption that those with his status were not law-abiding—
    was the individual’s right to possess firearms restored.
    That is precisely how § 922(g)(1) functions, disarming
    a group that has demonstrated disregard for the law104 and
    allowing for restoration of the right to keep arms upon the
    102
    Jackson, No. 22-2870, 
    2023 WL 3769242
    , at *7.
    103
    Even if dangerousness were “the traditional sine qua non
    for dispossession, then history demonstrates that there is no re-
    quirement for an individualized determination of dangerous-
    ness as to each person in a class of prohibited persons.” 
    Id. at *6
    .
    104
    See 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1).
    30
    requisite showing.105 Because that statutory scheme is
    “consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition of firearm
    regulation,”106 it comports with the Second Amendment.
    II.      Consequences of the Majority Opinion
    Instead of respecting legislatures’ longstanding
    authority to disarm groups who pose a threat to the rule of law,
    the majority usurps that function and enacts its own policy.
    And instead of heeding the Supreme Court’s instruction to take
    § 922(g)(1) as “longstanding” and “lawful,”107 the majority
    nullifies it with an insurmountably rigid view of historical
    analogues and an approach so standardless as to render it void
    for vagueness in any application.
    My colleagues have adopted and prescribed a
    methodology by which courts must examine each historical
    practice in isolation and reject it if it deviates in any respect
    from the contemporary regulation:              Confronted with
    legislatures’ regular practice at the Founding of imposing the
    far more severe penalty of death for even non-violent felonies,
    the majority responds that the permanent loss of all rights is
    not analogous to “the particular . . . punishment at issue—
    lifetime disarmament[.]”108 To the longstanding practice of
    forfeiture, which resulted in a permanent loss of firearms for
    those felons convicted of capital offenses or sentenced to life
    105
    See 
    18 U.S.C. § 921
    (a)(20).
    106
    Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2126.
    107
    Heller, 
    554 U.S. at
    626–27 & n.26.
    108
    Maj. Op. at 19.
    31
    imprisonment, the majority avers that forfeiture is entirely
    distinguishable because other felons—those who committed
    lesser offenses and thus served temporary rather than life
    sentences—could repurchase arms upon their release.109 To
    evidence that legislatures repeatedly disarmed entire groups of
    people based on their distrusted status, the majority dismisses
    those laws as inconsistent with contemporary understandings
    of the First and Fourteenth Amendments.110 To the historical
    reality that disarmament was not limited to those considered
    violent and indeed extended to well-known pacifists like the
    Quakers, the majority decrees without elaboration that any
    analogy between § 922(g)(1) and those laws would be “far too
    broad.”111      Finally, to the notion that Congress can
    categorically disarm felons today, just as legislatures once
    disarmed loyalists, Catholics, and other groups, the majority
    falls back on its bottom line: any analogy will be unlike “Range
    and his individual circumstances.”112
    The Supreme Court in Bruen specifically admonished
    the judiciary not to place “a regulatory straightjacket” on our
    109
    Id. at 19–20.
    110
    Id. at 18–19. Strikingly, several of my colleagues once as-
    serted that these same laws justified disarming dangerous fel-
    ons. See Binderup v. Att’y Gen., 
    836 F.3d 336
    , 368–69 (3d Cir.
    2016) (en banc) (Hardiman, J., concurring in part); Folajtar,
    980 F.3d at 914–15 (Bibas, J., dissenting). Today’s majority
    provides no such assurance. Maj. Op. at 18 n.9.
    111
    Id. at 19 (quoting Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2134).
    112
    Id.
    32
    Government by requiring a “historical twin,” and explained
    that “even if a modern-day regulation is not a dead ringer for
    historical precursors, it still may be analogous enough to pass
    constitutional muster.”113 Yet, how else would one describe
    the kind of analogue the majority demands—a Founding-era
    statute that imposed the “particular”114 restriction for the same
    length of time on the same group of people as a modern
    law115—if not as a contemporary regulation’s “dead ringer”
    and “historical twin”?116
    While the majority opinion spurns this instruction from
    Bruen and the Eighth Circuit’s conclusion that § 922(g)(1) is
    constitutional as applied to any felon,117 it fully embraces the
    Fifth Circuit’s reasoning in United States v. Rahimi.118 In that
    case, the Fifth Circuit held that 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(8), which
    prohibits individuals subject to domestic abuse civil protective
    orders from possessing firearms, violates the Second
    Amendment.119 After rejecting the Supreme Court’s repeated
    references to “law-abiding citizens” as devolving too much
    113
    Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2133.
    114
    Maj. Op. at 19.
    115
    See id.
    116
    Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2133.
    117
    Jackson, No. 22-2870, 
    2023 WL 3769242
    , at *4.
    118
    61 F.4th at 443.
    119
    Id. at 461.
    33
    discretion to the Government,120 the Fifth Circuit addressed
    each of the Government’s historical analogues in isolation and,
    paving the way for today’s majority, concluded every one was
    distinguishable from § 922(g)(8):          Statutes disarming
    distrusted groups were inapt because legislatures believed
    those groups threatened social and political order generally,
    whereas domestic abusers threaten identifiable individuals;121
    criminal forfeiture laws seizing arms from those who terrorized
    the public were insufficient because domestic abuse protective
    orders derive from civil proceedings.122 Like my colleagues,
    the Rahimi Court concluded that any difference between a
    historical law and contemporary regulation defeats an
    otherwise-compelling analogy.
    For all their quibbling, though, neither today’s majority
    nor the Fifth Circuit explain why those differences suggest the
    Founding generation would have considered § 922(g) beyond
    the authority of a legislature. Furthermore, the methodology
    the majority adopts from Rahimi creates a one-way ratchet:
    My colleagues offer a detailed roadmap for rejecting historical
    analogues yet refuse to state when, if ever, a historical practice
    will justify a contemporary regulation.
    By confining permissible firearm regulations to the pre-
    cise measures employed at the Founding, the majority dis-
    places a complex array of interlocking statutes that embody the
    considered judgments of elected representatives at the federal
    120
    Id. at 453.
    121
    Id. at 457.
    122
    Id. at 458–59.
    34
    and state level. For example, in § 922(g)(1), Congress dis-
    armed those who commit felonies or felony-equivalent misde-
    meanors, but specifically excluded particular offenses it
    deemed not sufficiently serious: “antitrust violations, unfair
    trade practices, restraints of trade, or other similar offenses re-
    lating to the regulation of business practices[.]”123 The major-
    ity ignores that judgment and rewrites the statute with its own
    expansive view of excludable offenses.
    Section 922(g)(1) also disarms those who commit state
    felonies out of respect for the historic power of state legisla-
    tures to designate which offenses were considered sufficiently
    serious by the people of that state to be punished as felonies.
    Underlying the majority’s decision to exempt a felon-equiva-
    lent “like Range” from § 922(g)(1), however, is an unspoken
    premise antithetical to federalism and the separation of powers:
    that federal judges know better than the people’s elected rep-
    resentatives what offenses should qualify as serious to the peo-
    ple of that state.
    In addition to eviscerating the federal disarmament stat-
    ute, the vague test adopted by the majority impugns the consti-
    tutional application of every state statute that prohibits felons
    from possessing guns. Those laws differ significantly across
    the forty-eight states that restrict offenders’ firearm rights—
    including which offenses trigger restrictions as well as their
    duration—in keeping with each state’s local circumstances and
    values.124 But, under the Supremacy Clause, the majority’s
    123
    
    18 U.S.C. § 921
    (a)(20)(A).
    124
    See generally Fifty-State Comparison: Loss and Restora-
    tion of Civil/Firearms Rights, Restoration Rts. Project (Nov.
    35
    test, indeterminant as it is, necessarily supplants those laws no
    less than it does § 922(g)(1).
    Similarly, out of respect for federalism, Congress ex-
    empted from the federal felon-possession ban any offender
    whose conviction “has been expunged,” who “has been par-
    doned,” or who has had his “civil rights restored.”125 In every
    single state, the governor or pardon board is authorized to issue
    a pardon, automatically restoring an offender’s firearm
    rights.126 Thirty-six states also offer additional gun rights res-
    toration mechanisms127—from automatic restoration after a set
    term of years,128 to individualized judicial expungement pro-
    ceedings.129 The divergent “state policy judgments” codified
    2022),        https://ccresourcecenter.org/state-restoration-pro-
    files/chart-1-loss-and-restoration-of-civil-rights-and-firearms-
    privileges-2/. None of these statutes appears to disarm individ-
    uals who commit pretextual offenses. I note, however, that his-
    tory suggests any pretextual disarmament law would violate
    the Second Amendment. See 1 William Blackstone, Commen-
    taries app. *300 (St. George Tucker ed., Birch & Small 1803)
    (decrying how “[i]n England, the people have been disarmed,
    generally, under the specious pretext of preserving the game”).
    125
    
    18 U.S.C. § 921
    (a)(20).
    126
    See Fifty-State Comparison: Loss and Restoration of
    Civil/Firearms Rights, supra note 124.
    127
    See id.
    128
    See, e.g., 
    Mich. Comp. Laws § 750
    .224f.
    129
    See, e.g., 
    Tenn. Code Ann. § 39-17-1307
    (c)(1)(C).
    36
    in these statutes promote “the benefits of federalism: experi-
    mentation, localism, and to some extent, decentralization”130—
    so much so that the Supreme Court itself has acknowledged the
    significance of Congress’s decision “to defer to a State’s dis-
    pensation relieving an offender from disabling effects of a con-
    viction.”131 Yet the majority annuls these mechanisms for the
    restoration of gun rights by declaring that offenders like Range
    can never be disarmed in the first place.
    In place of legislatures’ measured judgments, the ma-
    jority imposes a constitutional framework so standardless as to
    thwart the lawful application of 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1) to any
    offender. Congress enacted a bright-line rule distinguishing
    offenders who can possess firearms from those who cannot.
    By looking to the maximum punishment available for his of-
    fense, a felon or state misdemeanant can easily determine if he
    can possess a gun.132 The majority, however, replaces that
    straightforward test with an opaque inquiry—whether the of-
    fender is “like Range.”133
    So what exactly is this new test? What specifically is it
    about Range that exempts him—and going forward, those “like
    [him]”—from § 922(g)(1)’s enforcement? Regrettably, that is
    130
    D. Bowie Duncan, Note, Dynamic Incorporation, Rights
    Restoration, and 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1), 15 N.Y.U. J.L. & Lib-
    erty 233, 274 (2021).
    131
    Logan v. United States, 
    552 U.S. 23
    , 37 (2007).
    132
    See 
    18 U.S.C. § 921
    (a)(20).
    133
    Maj. Op. at 22.
    37
    left to conjecture. My colleagues describe Range’s individual
    circumstances in minute detail, appearing to attach signifi-
    cance to such specifics as his hourly wage, his marital status,
    the number of children he raised, his purported justification for
    his fraud, the amount he stole, his culpability relative to his
    wife who was not charged, his employment history, his largely
    law-abiding life post-conviction, his explanations for his post-
    conviction attempts to purchase a gun, the circumstances in
    which his wife then purchased it for him, his intended use of
    firearms to hunt deer in his spare time, and the timing of his
    discovery that he was subject to § 922(g)(1).134 The particulars
    are plentiful, but the majority never specifies, among these and
    other descriptors of Range’s life pre- and post-conviction, the
    respects in which an offender must be “like Range” to preclude
    the application of § 922(g)(1).
    If it is that Range’s offense was not “violent,” that
    standard is unworkable and leads to perverse results. Federal
    courts’ prior attempts to define “violent felony,” e.g., for pur-
    poses of the Armed Career Criminal Act, yielded “repeated at-
    tempts and repeated failures to craft a principled and objective
    standard [for that term,] confirm[ing] its hopeless indetermi-
    nacy.”135 Accordingly, the Supreme Court in Johnson v.
    United States held that the “violent felony” provision “denie[d]
    fair notice to defendants and invite[d] arbitrary enforcement by
    judges,” thus violating due process.136 So does the “like
    Range” test relegate us to the widely disparaged “categorical
    134
    Id. at 5–6.
    135
    Johnson v. United States, 
    576 U.S. 591
    , 598 (2015).
    136
    
    Id. at 597
    .
    38
    approach,” excluding all offenses that lack an element of the
    “use of force”?137 Of what relevance is the conduct underlying
    a given crime? Will courts be limited to considering Shepard
    documents?138 What about crimes that lack an element of force
    but are undeniably associated with violence, like drug traffick-
    ing, human trafficking, drunk driving, and treason?139
    If it is Range’s largely law-abiding life in the nearly 30
    years since his conviction, that standard is even more con-
    founding. My colleagues hold that Range’s disarmament was
    invalid ab initio, meaning he could have prevailed on a Second
    Amendment challenge to § 922(g)(1) had he raised one at the
    time of his conviction (as will myriad felons after today’s de-
    cision).140 Yet judges are not soothsayers. Post-conviction
    conduct would be relevant if my colleagues were holding
    137
    United States v. Scott, 
    14 F.4th 190
    , 195 (3d Cir. 2021).
    138
    Those documents include the “charging document, written
    plea agreement, transcript of plea colloquy, and any explicit
    factual finding by the trial judge to which the defendant as-
    sented.” Shepard v. United States, 
    544 U.S. 13
    , 16 (2005).
    139
    As Range’s counsel candidly conceded at argument, under
    a “violence” test, offenses like possession of child pornogra-
    phy, money laundering, and drunk driving would not support
    disarmament. Oral Arg. at 19:51–20:20, 24:00–24:26.
    140
    See Maj. Op. at 4 (“[Range] remains among ‘the people’
    protected by the Second Amendment. And . . . the Government
    did not carry its burden of showing that our Nation’s history
    and tradition of firearm regulation support disarming
    Range[.]”).
    39
    narrowly that Range’s firearm rights should be restored going
    forward. But how can they possibly hold that he should not
    have lost them upon conviction, based on post-conviction con-
    duct?
    This retrospective mode of analysis defies not just logic,
    but also the Due Process Clause. Due process guarantees that
    a “person of ordinary intelligence [must have] a reasonable op-
    portunity to know what is prohibited, so he may act accord-
    ingly.”141 Under the majority’s “like Range” test, however, of-
    fenders cannot possibly know in advance of a court’s retroac-
    tive declaration whether possessing a firearm post-conviction
    is a constitutional entitlement or a federal felony. As inter-
    preted today by the majority, § 922(g)(1) is rendered so vague
    as to be facially unconstitutional.
    On the enforcement side, the majority opinion makes
    the statute’s mens rea impossible to establish. In Rehaif, the
    Supreme Court held that to convict a defendant under § 922(g)
    the Government must prove the defendant not only knew that
    he possessed a firearm, but also knew that “he had the relevant
    status when he possessed [the firearm.]”142 The Court then
    clarified in Greer that a Rehaif error is not a basis for relief
    under the plain-error standard unless the defendant can make a
    sufficient argument on appeal that, but for the error, he could
    have established he did not know he was a felon.143 That would
    be a difficult argument to make, the Court observed, because
    141
    Grayned v. City of Rockford, 
    408 U.S. 104
    , 108 (1972).
    142
    Rehaif, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2194
    .
    143
    Greer v. United States, 
    141 S. Ct. 2090
    , 2097 (2021).
    40
    “as common sense suggests, individuals who are convicted fel-
    ons ordinarily know that they are convicted felons [for pur-
    poses of § 922(g)(1).]”144
    But, today, the majority displaces Rehaif’s clear and as-
    certainable standard with an incoherent one: the Government
    must prove the defendant knew he was not “like Range” when
    he possessed firearms. And in lieu of Greer’s high threshold
    for plain-error relief, the majority hands defendants a ready-
    made argument for appeal: that they could not know at the time
    they possessed a firearm—indeed, at any time before a court
    made a “like Range” determination—whether their status was
    subject to or exempt from § 922(g)(1). In short, the floodgates
    the Supreme Court attempted to close on Rehaif errors in
    Greer, my colleagues throw wide open: Today’s opinion will
    strain the federal courts with a deluge of Rehaif challenges,145
    compelling us to vacate countless § 922(g)(1) convictions on
    144
    Id. at 2095.
    145
    As explained above, courts will struggle to apply the major-
    ity’s “like Range” test, which apparently extends to offenders’
    post-conviction conduct. For example, how should a court rule
    when a felon committed a murder thirty years ago, but has
    since become deeply religious and a model prisoner? What
    about someone with Range’s employment history and family
    ties who has amassed a lengthy rap sheet of nonviolent misde-
    meanors in the decades since his welfare fraud conviction? Or
    someone otherwise like Range who knew he was subject to
    § 922(g)(1) as understood before today, yet deliberately en-
    gaged his spouse as a straw purchaser to circumvent that stat-
    ute? There is no reason for the federal judiciary to hurl itself
    into this morass.
    41
    direct appeal and compelling our district court colleagues to
    dismiss countless indictments.
    Today’s decision will also undermine law enforcement
    in three critical respects. First, it will cripple the FBI’s Na-
    tional Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS).
    Currently, NICS includes over five million felony conviction
    records,146 and that number continues to grow as additional
    agencies contribute records to the NICS database.147 Prior fel-
    ony convictions are by far the most common reason individuals
    fail NICS background checks148—the very background checks
    the Supreme Court endorsed in Bruen as ensuring individuals
    bearing firearms are “law-abiding” citizens.149 Yet the major-
    ity’s indeterminant and post-hoc test for which felons fall out-
    side § 922(g)(1) and under what circumstances renders NICS
    a dead letter.
    If the police receive a tip that an ex-offender is toting an
    assault rifle, it is no longer sufficient for probable cause to
    simply confirm a prior felony conviction in NICS. How will
    officers—or prosecutors for that matter—know whether that
    felon is sufficiently “like Range” to justify his arrest as a felon-
    146
    Active Records in the NICS Indices, FBI (Jan. 31, 2023),
    https://www.fbi.gov/file-repository/active_rec-
    ords_in_the_nics-indices.pdf/view.
    147
    See Stevenson, supra note 10, at 1597.
    148
    Federal   Denials,     FBI     (Jan.    31,     2023),
    https://www.fbi.gov/file-repository/federal_denials.pdf/view.
    149
    See 142 S. Ct. at 2138 n.9.
    42
    in-possession, or whether they are instead bringing liability on
    themselves for violating the felon’s civil rights? Must they re-
    search the suspect’s post-conviction conduct? Should they
    consider relevant conduct underlying the original violation?
    How could they possibly determine that conduct in the case of
    guilty pleas entered decades earlier?
    Second, without a functional background check system,
    how will federal firearms licensees (FFLs) comply with federal
    law? FFLs who discover that a potential customer was con-
    victed of a felony will have no way of knowing whether the
    individual’s crime and post-conviction conduct are sufficiently
    similar to Range’s to preclude the application of § 922(g)(1).150
    Of particular concern, any assessments based on the majority
    opinion’s “vague criteria are vulnerable to biases” along race,
    class, gender, and other lines, resulting in disparities between
    which groups retain gun rights and which do not.151
    Third, until today, the prohibition on possessing a fire-
    arm was a well-accepted “standard condition” of bail,
    150
    The penalty for incorrectly concluding a felon can purchase
    a weapon without an exhaustive inspection of the felon’s
    crime, conduct, and personal circumstances will be stiff: a sin-
    gle error will result in the loss of the FFL’s license, barring the
    FFL from the industry. See Simpson v. Att’y Gen., 
    913 F.3d 110
    , 114 (3d Cir. 2019) (holding a single violation in which
    “the licensee knew of his legal obligation and purposefully dis-
    regarded or was plainly indifferent to the requirements” is
    grounds for revocation).
    151
    Ryan T. Sakoda, The Architecture of Discretion: Implica-
    tions of the Structure of Sanctions for Racial Disparities,
    43
    supervised release, probation, and parole.152 But under my col-
    leagues’ reasoning, the inclusion of that condition among state
    or federal conditions of release now appears to be unconstitu-
    tional as to any number of defendants, depending on whether
    the judge at the bail or sentencing hearing views them as “like
    Range.” That means disarmament on release will be anything
    but “standard,” leaving scores of non-incarcerated criminal de-
    fendants armed and subjecting not just the public, but also pro-
    bation and parole officers to significant risk of harm.
    In sum, the majority opinion casts aside the admonitions
    that § 922(g)(1) is “longstanding,”153 “presumptively
    lawful,”154 and “does more to combat gun violence than any
    other federal law.”155 Instead, it abandons judicial restraint,
    jettisons principles of federalism, unsettles countless
    indictments and convictions, debilitates law enforcement, and
    vitiates our background check system—all in the name of re-
    Severity, and Net Widening, 
    117 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1213
    , 1227
    (2023); cf. Joseph Blocher & Reva B. Siegel, Race and Guns,
    Courts and Democracy, 135 Harv. L. Rev. F. 449, 449 (2022)
    (arguing “racial justice concerns [with firearm laws] should be
    addressed in democratic politics rather than in the federal
    courts”).
    152
    U.S.S.G. § 5D1.3(c)(10).
    153
    Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 626
    .
    154
    
    Id.
     at 627 n.26.
    155
    Rehaif, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2201
     (Alito, J., dissenting).
    44
    arming convicted felons. There is a narrower and less
    hazardous path they could have chosen.
    III.      The Narrow Road Not Taken
    My colleagues object that § 922(g)(1) can impose a
    “permanent[],”156 “lifetime ban on firearm possession,”157 but
    their retroactive holding—that the Government could not
    constitutionally disarm Range when he was convicted—is far
    broader than necessary to address their concern. Had they
    heeded judicial restraint when granting Range relief, the
    majority would have issued a purely prospective declaratory
    judgment, restoring Range’s gun rights going forward. That
    approach would have prevented the most grievous
    consequences of the majority’s decision today. And should the
    Supreme Court agree with my colleagues that the statutory
    exclusions to § 922(g)(1) are constitutionally inadequate, that
    approach also offers an administrable alternative worthy of
    consideration. How could the majority have resolved this case
    narrowly?
    First, the only question the Court had to answer is
    whether § 922(g)(1) is unconstitutional as applied to the
    individual petitioning the Court today, accounting for his
    present circumstances and potentially entitling him to bear
    arms on a forward-looking basis. After all, Range did not
    challenge the loss of his firearm rights at the time of his
    conviction or at any time until he initiated the underlying suit
    here, and all he now seeks is declaratory relief enabling him to
    156
    Maj. Op. at 18 n.9.
    157
    Id. at 20.
    45
    purchase and possess firearms in the future. The majority,
    however, reaches out to answer a different question: whether
    Range’s disarmament was ever consistent with the Second
    Amendment.158       Needlessly invalidating Range’s initial
    disarmament violates “the fundamental principle of judicial
    restraint that courts should neither anticipate a question of
    constitutional law in advance of the necessity of deciding it nor
    formulate a rule of constitutional law broader than is required
    by the precise facts to which it is to be applied.”159
    Second, providing prospective declaratory relief in this
    case and similar as-applied challenges would resolve my
    colleagues’ permanency concern. I appreciate that their
    opposition to imposing a permanent ban or putting the onus on
    the offender to seek relief finds some historical support for
    certain lesser offenses. That is, the subset of felons who were
    not sentenced to death or lifetime imprisonment only forfeited
    their firearms temporarily and did not need to petition to regain
    their firearm rights; they could simply repurchase arms after
    completing their sentences. But times have changed. Gone are
    the days of “close-knit” communities in which “everyone knew
    everyone else,”160 and with the extreme mobility and relative
    158
    See Maj. Op. at 19 (asserting that the “punishment at is-
    sue—lifetime disarmament—is [not] rooted in our Nation’s
    history and tradition”); id. at 22 (framing the issue presented as
    “the constitutionality of 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1) [] as applied to
    [Range] given his violation of 62 Pa. Stat. Ann. § 481(a)”).
    159
    Wash. St. Grange v. Wash. St. Republican Party, 
    552 U.S. 442
    , 450 (2008) (quotations omitted).
    160
    Bibas, supra note 4, at 1.
    46
    anonymity of today’s society and the magnitude of harm that
    can be inflicted by a single assault rifle,161 automatic
    restoration of the right to bear arms upon completion of a
    sentence would jeopardize public safety and the utility of
    background checks. In any event, it is not the case that
    legislatures historically imposed only bans that expired of their
    own accord: They sometimes exercised their authority—just
    as Congress did in § 922(g)(1)—to categorically disarm a
    group presumed, based on status, to be non-law-abiding and to
    place the burden on individuals in that group to petition for
    relief and prove, through oaths or similar gestures of
    allegiance, that they could be trusted to obey the law.162
    Section 922(g)(1) is sufficiently analogous to that
    model to meet the history-and-tradition test, as it already
    allows felons to petition for relief by seeking an expungement,
    pardon, or restoration of rights under state law. True, Congress
    provided another avenue for relief in § 925(c) that it has not
    161
    See Terry Spencer, Florida School Shooter’s AR-15 Shown
    to His Jurors, AP (July 25, 2022), https://apnews.com/arti-
    cle/education-florida-fort-lauderdale-parkland-school-shoot-
    ing-60791bdf38785f494400c43b90a97c39 (describing the
    AR-15 rifle “used to murder 17 students and staff members . .
    . at Parkland’s Marjory Stoneman Douglas High School”).
    162
    Historical examples include Parliament’s disarmament of
    Catholics in 1689, Massachusetts’s disarmament of Anne
    Hutchinson’s followers, Virginia’s disarmament of Catholics
    during the Seven Years’ War, and the loyalty oath laws of
    Pennsylvania and Virginia during the Revolution. See supra
    notes 45–49, 53–57, 68, 82–88 and accompanying text.
    47
    funded in recent years,163 but § 921(a)(20) ensures the felon-
    possession ban fits comfortably in the history of our nation’s
    traditional firearm regulations. And if those avenues are
    deemed inadequate, that purported infirmity would be cured by
    a prospective declaratory judgment finding that a convicted
    felon no longer poses a threat to the rule of law and therefore
    can once again possess firearms.
    Third, such declaratory judgment proceedings would
    give effect to the purportedly rebuttable presumption to which
    the Supreme Court referred in describing felon-possession
    bans as “presumptively lawful,”164 as well as its admonition
    that the Government bears the burden at the outset to
    “demonstrate that the regulation is consistent with this
    163
    Section 925(c) permitted the Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco,
    Firearms and Explosives to conduct individualized reviews and
    make an administrative determination that the applicant could
    keep arms prospectively, but that mechanism proved so costly
    for the country that it was disbanded and has not been funded
    since 1992. See Logan, 
    552 U.S. at
    28 n.1; S. Rep. No. 102-
    353 (1992).
    164
    Heller, 
    554 U.S. at
    626–27 & n.26; see McDonald, 
    561 U.S. at 786
    ; see also Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2162 (Kavanaugh, J., con-
    curring); id. at 2157 (Alito, J., concurring). Like the Eighth
    Circuit, I believe the premise that the Supreme Court used the
    phrase “presumptively lawful” to establish “a presumption of
    constitutionality that could be rebutted on a case-by-case ba-
    sis” is dubious. Jackson, No. 22-2870, 
    2023 WL 3769242
    , at
    *7 n.2. Rather, the Court most likely “termed the conclusion
    presumptive because the specific regulations were not at issue
    in Heller.” 
    Id.
    48
    Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation[.]”165 That is
    because once the Government establishes that an offender
    committed a felony, it has necessarily satisfied its burden
    consistent with the historical practice of disarming felons upon
    conviction. The burden at that point, like the taking of oaths
    or swearing of allegiance, would fall on the felon to rebut the
    ban’s presumptive lawfulness by establishing he is presently a
    “law-abiding, responsible” citizen.166
    Fourth, limiting relief in as-applied § 922(g)(1) chal-
    lenges to prospective declaratory judgments would eliminate
    the intractable due process problems with the majority’s ap-
    proach. Any felon who possessed a firearm without first se-
    curing a favorable declaratory judgment would remain subject
    to prosecution pursuant to § 922(g)(1), and those granted relief
    would have their rights restored prospectively. In contrast to
    the “like Range” test, that clear rule would provide felons with
    constitutionally adequate notice as to whether and when they
    regained their right to bear arms and thus would allow
    § 922(g)(1) to withstand void-for-vagueness challenges. Pro-
    spective declaratory judgments likewise would avoid opening
    the floodgates to mens rea challenges to § 922(g)(1)
    165
    Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2126.
    166
    Id. at 2131. This approach would not result in repetitive
    actions because a felon who brings an unsuccessful declaratory
    judgment suit must provide “newly discovered evidence that,
    with reasonable diligence, could not have been discovered” to
    prevail in a subsequent as-applied challenge to § 922(g)(1).
    Fed. R. Civ. P. 60(b)(2).
    49
    prosecutions, and the high threshold Greer set for defendants
    to overturn § 922(g)(1) convictions would endure.167
    Fifth, this use of declaratory judgments would respect
    both the separation of powers and federalism. Other than for
    felons who received favorable declaratory judgments, Con-
    gress’s decision to disarm those who commit felonies or com-
    parable state misdemeanors would remain intact. Likewise,
    state statutes restricting the ability of felons to possess firearms
    would be generally enforceable, ensuring local communities’
    priorities continue to shape when felons are permitted to pos-
    sess firearms under state law. The states’ rights-restoration re-
    gimes would also continue to perform an important function,
    serving as alternatives to federal declaratory judgments.
    Finally, prospective relief would avoid the debilitating
    effect of today’s decision on law enforcement, U.S. Attorney’s
    Offices, and our background check system. Currently, those
    previously convicted of a felony can submit documentation to
    the FBI through a voluntary appeal file application, including
    “information regarding an expungement, restoration of firearm
    rights, pardon, etc.”168 Successful applicants receive a unique
    personal identification number to prevent future background
    check denials.169      A felon who secures a prospective
    167
    See 141 S. Ct. at 2097.
    168
    Types of Documents Requested Based on Prohibitor, FBI
    (Sept. 14, 2018), https://www.fbi.gov/file-repository/nics-ap-
    peal-documents-requested.pdf/view.
    169
    Firearm-Related Challenge (Appeal) and Voluntary Appeal
    File (VAF), FBI (last accessed Mar. 3, 2023),
    50
    declaratory judgment could simply submit that judgment to the
    FBI to prevent false positives on his background check when
    next purchasing firearms. Thus, just as they do today, law en-
    forcement and prosecutors could depend on NICS for data
    when deciding whom to charge with violating § 922(g)(1);
    courts could rely on existing jury instructions, the standard
    conditions of supervised release or parole, and the plain-error
    test set out in Greer; and firearm dealers could ascertain from
    a background check whether a convicted felon is entitled to
    purchase weapons.
    The majority has taken a far more radical approach,
    creating a stark circuit split and holding § 922(g)(1) is
    unconstitutional ab initio based on a seemingly random
    sampling of observations about the pre- and post-conviction
    conduct of this Appellant. Our district courts are left without
    any intelligible standard, and our citizenry will be left reeling
    from the consequences: a flood of motions to dismiss
    indictments, appeals, and reversals of § 922(g)(1) convictions;
    more armed felons and gun violence on our streets; less faith
    in elected representatives stymied in their efforts to protect the
    public; and less trust in a judiciary mired in formalism and the
    usurpation of legislative function. The sooner the Supreme
    Court takes up this issue, the safer our republic will be.
    IV.    Conclusion
    For the foregoing reasons, I respectfully dissent.
    https://www.fbi.gov/how-we-can-help-you/more-fbi-services-
    and-information/nics/national-instant-criminal-background-
    check-system-nics-appeals-vaf.
    51
    ROTH, Circuit Judge, dissenting
    I agree with the Majority’s well-reasoned conclusions
    that (1) New York State Rifle & Pistol Association, Inc. v.
    Bruen1 abrogated the use of means-end scrutiny to assess
    Second Amendment challenges and (2) Bryan Range is among
    “the people” protected by the Second Amendment. I part with
    my colleagues, however, over their determination that the
    government failed to show that 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1), as
    applied to Range, is consistent with our nation’s historical
    tradition of firearms regulation.
    In Bruen, the Supreme Court considered whether a
    regulation issued by a state government was a facially
    constitutional exercise of its traditional police power. Range
    presents a distinguishable question: Whether a federal statute,
    which the Supreme Court has upheld as a valid exercise of
    Congress’s authority under the Commerce Clause,2 is
    constitutional as applied to him. The parties and the Majority
    conflate these spheres of authority and fail to address binding
    precedents affirming Congress’s power to regulate the
    possession of firearms in interstate commerce. Because Range
    lacks standing under the applicable Commerce Clause
    jurisprudence, I respectfully dissent.
    I.
    As the Majority explains, the Supreme Court in Bruen
    invalidated the means-end component test that we have, in
    1
    
    142 S. Ct. 2111 (2022)
    .
    2
    U.S. Const. art. 1, § 8, cl. 3 (authorizing Congress “to regulate
    commerce with foreign nations, and among the several states,
    and with the Indian tribes”).
    1
    recent years, applied to Second Amendment challenges.3 The
    Supreme Court held: “[W]hen the Second Amendment’s plain
    text covers an individual’s conduct, the Constitution
    presumptively protects that conduct. To justify its regulation .
    . . the government must demonstrate that the regulation is
    consistent with this Nation’s historical tradition of firearm
    regulation.”4
    While I agree with the Majority’s assessment of the
    government’s burden, I read Bruen to articulate a structured
    framework for the government’s comparative analysis. This
    framework is useful because it clarifies both what the
    government must compare and how close the match must be.
    As I read Bruen, the government must begin by
    identifying the societal problem addressed by the challenged
    regulation.5 The government must demonstrate whether the
    problem is (1) persistent (“has persisted since the 18th
    century”) or (2) modern (involves “unprecedented societal
    concerns or dramatic technological changes”).6
    If the problem is persistent, the government must
    demonstrate that its modern regulation is “distinctly similar” to
    a historical forebear, showing that early and recent legislatures
    approached the problem in basically the same way.7 Here,
    “lack of a distinctly similar historical regulation addressing
    that problem” or evidence that “earlier generations addressed
    3
    Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2127.
    4
    Id. at 2126.
    5
    Id. at 2131–32.
    6
    Id. at 2131.
    7
    Id. at 2132.
    2
    the societal problem . . . through materially different means”
    are “relevant evidence that the challenged regulation is
    inconsistent with the Second Amendment.”8
    In contrast, for modern problems that early legislatures
    did not confront, Bruen allows for a more extended
    comparison. Here, the government must show by analogical
    reasoning that its regulation is “relevantly similar” to a
    historical firearm regulation.9         Under this prong, the
    government must show that the “modern and historical
    regulations impose a comparable burden on the right of armed
    self-defense and . . . that the burden is comparably justified.”10
    In other words, the government need not identify a “historical
    twin,” but only show that the regulations are aligned as to “how
    and why [they] burden a law-abiding citizen’s right to armed
    self-defense.”11
    II.
    This framework helps to illuminate my substantive
    disagreement with the Majority opinion, which begins with its
    characterization of the societal problem addressed by §
    922(g)(1). The Majority asserts that Ҥ 922(g)(1) is a
    straightforward ‘prohibition[] on the possession of firearms by
    felons.’”12 This is overbroad.
    8
    Id.
    9
    Id.
    10
    Id. at 2133.
    11
    Id. (emphasis added).
    12
    Op. 16 (quoting Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 626
    ).
    3
    To identify the problem Congress intended to address,
    “we look to the text, structure, and purpose of the statute and
    the surrounding statutory framework.”13 Section 922(g)(1)
    makes it unlawful for a person “convicted in any court, of a
    crime punishable by imprisonment for a term exceeding one
    year” to “possess in or affecting commerce, any firearm or
    ammunition.”14 This jurisdictional language is essential. In
    other contexts, such as for the purposes of categorical analysis
    or meeting the requirement of scienter, the Supreme Court has
    distinguished “substantive” from “jurisdictional” elements.15
    In § 922(g)(1), however, “far from being token, [the]
    ‘conventional jurisdictional element[]’ serve[s] to narrow the
    kinds of crimes that can be prosecuted.”16           Here, the
    jurisdictional element constrains Congress’s reach “to a
    discrete set of firearm possessions that additionally have an
    explicit connection with or effect on interstate commerce.”17
    The Supreme Court reached this exact conclusion in
    analyzing § 922(g)(1)’s predecessor, “conclud[ing] that the
    commerce requirement . . . must be read as part of the
    ‘possesses’ and ‘receives’ offenses.”18 Otherwise, the Court
    concluded, the statute would “dramatically intrude[] upon
    13
    Rosenberg v. DVI Receivables XVII, LLC, 
    835 F.3d 414
    , 419
    (3d Cir. 2016) (citing Medtronic, Inc. v. Lohr, 
    518 U.S. 470
    ,
    486 (1996)).
    14
    
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(1) (emphasis added).
    15
    See Rehaif v. United States, 
    139 S. Ct. 2191
    , 2196 (2019);
    Torres v. Lynch, 
    578 U.S. 452
    , 457 (2016).
    16
    Torres, 578 U.S. at 486 (dissent, J. Sotomayor, with Thomas,
    J. and Breyer, J.).
    17
    United States v. Lopez, 
    514 U.S. 549
    , 562 (1995).
    18
    United States v. Bass, 
    404 U.S. 336
    , 350 (1971).
    4
    traditional state criminal jurisdiction.”19 The line of Supreme
    Court decisions concerning § 922(g)(1) and its predecessor
    statute20 deal squarely with the Commerce Clause,21
    considering Congress’s authority to regulate firearms in
    interstate commerce in light of those “modern-era precedents”
    that, within strict limits, expanded Congress’s authority to
    address “great changes that had occurred in the way business
    was carried on in this country.”22 Our Court, with our sisters,
    expressly upheld the constitutionality of § 922(g)(1) because
    “by its very terms, [it] only regulates those weapons affecting
    interstate commerce by being the subject of interstate trade. It
    addresses items sent in interstate commerce and the channels
    of commerce themselves, delineating that the latter be kept
    clear of firearms.”23 Accordingly, the societal problem
    19
    Id.
    20
    Title VII of the Omnibus Crime Control and Safe Streets Act
    of 1968, 18 U.S.C.App. § 1202(a).
    21
    Lopez, 
    514 U.S. at 556
     (favorably contrasting § 922(g)(1)
    with § 922(q), which the Court deemed unconstitutional for
    lack of a nexus to interstate commerce); Scarborough v. United
    States, 
    431 U.S. 563
     (1977) (holding § 922(g)(1)’s predecessor
    statute constitutional); Bass, 
    404 U.S. 336
     (same).
    22
    Lopez, 514 at 556.
    23
    United States v. Singletary, 
    268 F.3d 196
    , 204 (2001); United
    States v. Gateward, 
    84 F.3d 670
    , 672 (3d Cir. 1996)
    (“Congress drafted § 922(g) to include a jurisdictional element,
    one which requires a defendant felon to have possessed a
    firearm ‘in or affecting commerce.’”); accord U.S. v. Wallace,
    
    889 F.2d 580
     (5th Cir. 1989) (“[S]ection 922(g) reaches only
    those firearms that traveled in interstate or foreign commerce
    and is thus constitutional); United States v. Dupree, 
    258 F.3d 1258
    , 1259 (2001); United States v. Stuckey, 
    255 F.3d 528
    ,
    5
    addressed by § 922(g)(1) is the possession of firearms in
    interstate commerce by particular “channels of commerce”—
    those channels under the language of § 922(g)(1) being
    individuals with certain criminal convictions.24
    The Majority concludes, and I agree, that Bruen
    “abrogated our Second Amendment jurisprudence,”25 meaning
    the line of cases from Marzzarella,26 through Binderup,27 to
    Holloway and Folajtar.28 Yet the Majority does not assert that
    Bruen abrogated our Commerce Clause jurisprudence or that
    of the Supreme Court.29 Rightly so. We must “leave to the
    529-30 (8th Cir. 2001); United States v. Gallimore, 
    247 F.3d 134
    , 137–38 (4th Cir. 2001); United States v. Davis, 
    242 F.3d 1162
    , 1162–63 (9th Cir. 2001); United States v. Santiago, 
    238 F.3d 213
    , 216-17 (2d Cir. 2001); United States v. Dorris, 
    236 F.3d 582
    , 584–86 (10th Cir. 2000); United States v. Napier,
    
    233 F.3d 394
    , 399–402 (6th Cir. 2000); United States v.
    Wesela, 
    223 F.3d 656
    , 659–60 (7th Cir. 2000).
    24
    Notably, § 921(a)(20)(A) makes clear that § 922(g)(1) does
    not apply uniformly to individuals convicted of any felony
    offense, expressly excluding individuals convicted of serious
    “Federal and State offenses pertaining to antitrust violations,
    unfair trade practices, restraints of trade, or other similar
    offenses.” Accordingly, to describe the statute as a ban on
    possession by “felons” overstates its reach.
    25
    Op. 10.
    26
    United States v. Marzzarella, 
    614 F.3d 85
     (3d Cir. 2010).
    27
    Binderup v. Att’y Gen., 
    836 F.3d 336
     (3d Cir. 2016) (en
    banc) (plurality).
    28
    Holloway v. Att’y Gen., 
    948 F.3d 164
     (3d Cir. 2020);
    Folajtar v. Att’y Gen., 980 F.3d (1)
    29
    Lopez, 
    514 U.S. at 556
    ; Scarborough, 
    431 U.S. at
    566–67
    (holding proof the firearm petitioner possessed had previously
    6
    [Supreme] Court itself ‘the prerogative of overruling its own
    decision[s].’”30 The Court did not, in Bruen, overrule its
    decisions upholding Congress’s power to regulate the
    possession of firearms in interstate commerce.31 These
    decisions remain good law.
    Under the constitutionally mandated Commerce Clause
    jurisprudence that continues to bind us, Range lacks standing.
    “It is well established that plaintiffs bear the burden of
    demonstrating that they have standing in the action that they
    traveled in interstate commerce sufficient to meet the nexus
    requirement); Bass, 
    404 U.S. at 350
     (holding § 922(g)(1)’s
    predecessor constitutional in light of the jurisdictional
    element); accord Greer v. United States, 
    141 S. Ct. 2090
    , 2095
    (2021) (citing Rehaif, 
    139 S. Ct. at 2194
     (clarifying the mens
    rea requirement under § 922(g)(1)); Logan v. United States,
    
    552 U.S. 23
    , 37 (2007) (clarifying the scope of § 921(a)(20)).
    See also Small v. United States, 
    544 U.S. 385
    , 394 (2005)
    (Thomas, J., dissenting) (calling for § 922(g)(1) to apply to a
    wider category of individuals, specifically those convicted in
    foreign courts).
    30
    Singletary, 
    268 F.3d at 205
    .
    31
    As the Majority acknowledges, Op. 16, Justice Kavanaugh’s
    concurrence in Bruen, joined by the Chief Justice, asserted that
    felon-possession prohibitions remain “presumptively lawful”
    under Heller and McDonald. 142 S. Ct. at 2162 (quoting
    District of Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 626–27 & n.26
    (2008)) (citing McDonald v. City of Chicago, 
    561 U.S. 742
    ,
    786 (2010)).
    7
    have brought.”32 To meet this burden, they must demonstrate
    “(1) the invasion of a concrete and particularized legally
    protected interest and resulting [actual or imminent] injury. . .
    . (2) a causal connection between the injury and the conduct
    complained of . . . and [3] that the injury will be redressed by
    a favorable decision.”33
    Before the District Court, Range alleged that “he suffers
    the on-going harm of being unable to obtain firearms from
    licensed federal firearms dealers.”34 While the District of
    Columbia Court of Appeals has recognized a cognizable injury
    where “the federal regulatory scheme thwarts [a challenger’s]
    continuing desire to purchase a firearm,” it did so in cases
    where the regulation’s facial constitutionality was at issue.35
    32
    Blunt v. Lower Merion Sch. Dist., 
    767 F.3d 247
    , 278 (3d Cir.
    2014) (citing Danvers Motor Co. v. Ford Motor Co., 
    432 F.3d 286
    , 291 (3d Cir. 2005)).
    33
    
    Id.
     at 278 (citing Lujan v. Defenders of Wildlife, 
    504 U.S. 555
    , 560 (1992)).
    34
    Appx026.
    35
    Dearth v. Holder, 
    641 F.3d 499
    , 503 (D.C. Cir. 2011)
    (affirming that the petitioner suffered a cognizable injury
    where “the federal regulatory scheme thwarts his continuing
    desire to purchase a firearm”); see Parker v. District of
    Columbia, 
    478 F.3d 370
    , 376 (D.C. Cir. 2007) (“The formal
    process of application and denial, however routine, makes the
    injury to [the petitioner’s] alleged constitutional interest
    concrete and particular.”), aff’d sub nom. District of Columbia
    v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
     (2008); see United States v. Salerno,
    
    481 U.S. 739
    , 745 (1987) (“A party asserting a facial challenge
    ‘must establish that no set of circumstances exists under which
    the Act would be valid.”).
    8
    Here, Range brought only an as-applied challenge.36
    Moreover, he has identified no specific firearm that he has been
    prohibited from possessing. To sustain a conviction under §
    922(g)(1), the government must prove beyond a reasonable
    doubt that the specific firearm possessed by the individual
    moved through interstate commerce.37 The reason is that while
    the nexus need only be minimal,38 § 922(g)(1) simply does not
    36
    See United States v. Marcavage, 
    609 F.3d 264
    , 273 (3d Cir.
    2010) (“An as-applied attack . . . does not contend that a law is
    unconstitutional as written but that its application to a
    particular person under particular circumstances deprived that
    person of a constitutional right.”).
    37
    See Singletary, 
    268 F.3d at 200
    ; accord United States v.
    Shambry, 
    392 F.3d 631
    , 632 (3d Cir. 2004); United States v.
    Leuschen, 
    395 F.3d 155
    , 160 (3d Cir. 2005).
    38
    See Shambry, 
    392 F. 3d at
    635 (citing United States v.
    Corey, 
    207 F.3d 84
    , 88 (1st Cir.2000) (“[T]he ‘interstate
    nexus’ element was met provided the government
    demonstrated that [the defendant] possessed the shotgun in a
    state other than the one in which it was manufactured.”);
    United States v. Lawson,
    173 F.3d 666
    , 670 (8th Cir. 1999)
    (finding that the stipulation that the guns were manufactured
    outside of the state where the defendant possessed them
    satisfied “‘the minimal nexus that the firearms have been, at
    some time, in interstate commerce,’ that is, that the firearms at
    some point prior to [the defendant’s] possession . . . crossed a
    state line” (quoting United States v. Shelton, 
    66 F.3d 991
    , 992
    (8th Cir. 1995) (per curiam))); United States v. Pierson, 
    139 F.3d 501
    , 504 (5th Cir. 1998) (“[E]vidence that a gun was
    manufactured in one state and possessed in another state is
    sufficient to establish a past connection between the firearm
    and interstate commerce.”); United States v. Crump, 
    120 F.3d
                            9
    criminalize possession of firearms out of interstate commerce.
    Here, Range has not asserted that this constitutionally reviewed
    regulation of commerce intrudes on any Second Amendment
    rights by establishing in § 922(g)(1) a prohibition on certain
    channels of commerce, i.e., felons, possessing firearms that
    have circulated in interstate commerce.39
    462, 466 & n. 2 (4th Cir. 1997) (“[It] is our view that the
    movement of a firearm beyond the boundaries of its state of
    manufacture ‘substantially affects’ interstate commerce. . . .”);
    United States v. Lewis, 
    100 F.3d 49
    , 50 (7th Cir. 1996)
    (“[P]roof of a gun’s manufacture outside of the state in which
    it was allegedly possessed is sufficient to support the factual
    finding that the firearm was ‘in or affecting commerce.’”
    (quoting United States v. Lowe, 
    860 F.2d 1370
    , 1374 (7th Cir.
    1988))); United States v. Farnsworth, 
    92 F.3d 1001
    , 1006 (10th
    Cir. 1996) (finding expert testimony that the defendant’s gun
    had been manufactured in a different state from that in which
    it was found was sufficient nexus to interstate commerce);
    United States v. Sanders, 
    35 F.3d 61
    , 62 (2d Cir. 1994) (finding
    fact that gun was manufactured in a state different from that in
    which it was possessed was sufficient nexus to interstate
    commerce); United States v. Morris, 
    904 F.2d 518
    , 519 (9th
    Cir. 1990) (same); United States v. Singleton, 
    902 F.2d 471
    ,
    473 (6th Cir. 1990) (“[T]he mere fact that the firearm was
    manufactured in a different state established a sufficient nexus
    with interstate commerce.”)).
    39
    The Eighth Circuit recently rejected a similar as-applied
    challenge to § 922(g)(1). The decision underscored Congress’
    recognition that “only through adequate Federal control over
    interstate and foreign commerce in these weapons” could the
    “grave problem” of lawlessness and violent crime in the
    United States be dealt with, as it arose from the “widespread
    10
    In short, the harm that Range has asserted is not
    constitutional. He has failed to set forth the necessary
    interstate commerce connections to allow federal jurisdiction
    of his complaint. He has merely established that a thoroughly
    reviewed statute has had its intended effect by preventing him
    from possessing a firearm in interstate commerce because of
    his particular criminal conviction, which falls within the
    statute’s clearly defined ambit.
    This jurisdictional deficiency has put Range’s claims
    beyond our reach. It is not unlikely, however, that a future
    challenge to the prohibition of § 922(g)(1) will come before us
    in which federal jurisdiction has been properly established. In
    such a case, I would share the concern expressed today by my
    dissenting colleagues40 about the extent to which this
    precedential opinion may reverberate beyond the
    circumstances presented in this as-applied challenge.
    Certainly, such an analysis would be crucial for us should a
    future, similar challenge arise within our jurisdiction,
    particularly on a facial basis.
    traffic in firearms moving in or otherwise affecting interstate
    or foreign commerce” and “the ease with which any person can
    acquire firearms other than a rifle or shotgun.” United States
    v. Jackson, No. 22-2870, 
    2023 WL 3769242
    , *8 (8th Cir. June
    2, 2023). Although the court thus tacitly and, in my view,
    appropriately acknowledged that Congress’ authority to
    regulate here was under the Commerce Clause, it unfortunately
    did not address whether Jackson had established standing
    accordingly for his as-applied challenge.
    40
    See generally Shwartz Dissent; Krause Dissent 4–5.
    11
    For the above reasons, I respectfully dissent.
    12