Devin Copeland v. Justin Bieber , 789 F.3d 484 ( 2015 )


Menu:
  •                              PUBLISHED
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT
    No. 14-1427
    DEVIN COPELAND, a/k/a De Rico; MAREIO OVERTON,
    Plaintiffs - Appellants,
    v.
    JUSTIN BIEBER; USHER RAYMOND, IV, a/k/a Usher; HEATHER
    BRIGHT, individually, and d/b/a B−Rhaka Publishing; RAY
    ROMULUS, a/k/a Rayro, individually and d/b/a Please Enjoy
    the Music; JONATHAN YIP, individually and d/b/a Products of
    the Street; JEREMY REEVES, individually and d/b/a Sumphu;
    UNIVERSAL MUSIC CORPORATION; UNIVERSAL MUSIC PUBLISHING
    GROUP;   SONY/ATV   MUSIC   PUBLISHING,   LLC;   WB   MUSIC
    CORPORATION; THE ISLAND DEF JAM MUSIC GROUP; STAGE THREE
    MUSIC (U.S.) INC.; STAGE THREE MUSIC, LLC; JONETTA PATTON,
    d/b/a J Pat Management,
    Defendants - Appellees.
    Appeal from the United States District Court for the Eastern
    District of Virginia, at Norfolk.      Arenda L. Wright Allen,
    District Judge. (2:13-cv-00246-AWA-TEM)
    Argued:   March 24, 2015                   Decided:   June 18, 2015
    Before WYNN, FLOYD, and HARRIS, Circuit Judges.
    Vacated and remanded by published opinion.    Judge Harris wrote
    the opinion, in which Judge Wynn and Judge Floyd joined.
    ARGUED:    Duncan Glover Byers, BYERS LAW GROUP, Norfolk,
    Virginia, for Appellants.     Stephen Edward Noona, KAUFMAN &
    CANOLES, P.C., Norfolk, Virginia; Jonathan David Davis, JONATHAN
    D. DAVIS, P.C., New York, New York, for Appellees.   ON BRIEF:
    Howard Weitzman, Jeremiah T. Reynolds, KINSELLA WEITZMAN ISER
    KUMP & ALDISERT, Santa Monica, California, for Justin Bieber.
    Nathan Muyskens, Washington, D.C., Barry I. Slotnick, Cheng L.
    Chen, LOEB & LOEB LLP, New York, New York, for Heather Bright,
    d/b/a B-Rhaka Publishing, WB Music Corporation, and Sony/ATV
    Music Publishing, LLC.
    2
    PAMELA HARRIS, Circuit Judge:
    Musician      Devin     Copeland    (“Copeland”),         together        with    his
    songwriting      partner,      appeals    the    dismissal      of     his      copyright
    infringement claim against recording artists Justin Bieber and
    Usher Raymond IV.       Copeland alleges that three recorded songs by
    the defendants, each titled “Somebody to Love,” infringe upon
    his copyright over his own, earlier song of the same name.                              The
    district court granted the defendants’ motions to dismiss on the
    ground that no reasonable jury could find Copeland’s song and
    the   defendants’      songs    sufficiently          similar     to   give      rise   to
    liability for infringement.              We disagree, and therefore vacate
    the   district      court’s    order     and    remand    the     case    for     further
    proceedings.
    I.
    A.
    Because Copeland appeals from an order granting a motion to
    dismiss   under      Rule     12(b)(6)    of    the     Federal    Rules        of   Civil
    Procedure,     we    recount      the    facts     as     alleged        by     Copeland,
    accepting them as true for purposes of this appeal.                           See Jackson
    v. Lightsey, 
    775 F.3d 170
    , 173 (4th Cir. 2014).
    Copeland is a Virginia-based R&B singer and songwriter who
    performs under the name “De Rico.”                 In 2008, together with his
    songwriting partner Mareio Overton, Copeland began writing and
    3
    recording songs to perform on his upcoming album, My Story II.
    Among them was “Somebody to Love,” the song that is the subject
    matter of this case (the “Copeland song”).                  Copeland registered
    a copyright for the My Story II songs, including “Somebody to
    Love,” later that year.
    In     late    2009,   Copeland     entered     into       discussions       with
    Sangreel Media (“Sangreel”), a company that recruits artists for
    record    labels    including   Island      Records,     Sony    Music,    and     RCA
    Records.     Sangreel was interested in promoting Copeland’s music,
    and Copeland turned over copies of My Story II so that Sangreel
    could provide       promotional   copies      to   its   clients.         Among    the
    figures to whom Sangreel presented Copeland’s music was Usher
    Raymond IV, a world-famous recording artist who performs under
    the name “Usher.”
    According       to   Copeland’s   complaint,        Usher    liked    what    he
    heard.     Usher’s mother and manager, Jonetta Patton (“Patton”),
    scheduled    a     conference   call   with    Copeland,     during    which       she
    informed Copeland that both she and Usher had listened to My
    Story II, and that they were interested in having Copeland re-
    record the album and join Usher on tour.                  Yet the plans never
    materialized, and that was the last Copeland heard from anyone
    in Usher’s camp.
    Within a few months of Copeland’s phone conversation with
    Patton, however, Usher had recorded and posted on his YouTube
    4
    channel a demo song also titled “Somebody to Love” (the “Usher
    demo song”).       Usher did not commercially release this song, but
    instead allegedly brought it to his protégé and fellow recording
    artist,    Justin      Bieber       (“Bieber”).           Bieber   recorded       his    own
    “Somebody to Love” (the “Bieber album song”) and released it on
    his debut album, My World 2.0, in the spring of 2010.                            Bieber’s
    “Somebody to Love” was a hit, peaking at number 15 on the U.S.
    Billboard Hot 100 chart.              Finally, Bieber released a fourth and
    final    “Somebody     to     Love,”    a    remix       with   lead    vocals    by    both
    himself and Usher (the “Bieber-Usher remix song”) in June 2010.
    Bieber has continued to perform live versions of those songs
    while on tour.
    B.
    Alleging that Bieber and Usher had access to the Copeland
    song     via    Sangreel      and     that       their     songs   bear     a    striking
    resemblance to his own work, Copeland filed suit for copyright
    infringement       against      Bieber,          Usher,     and    other        associated
    defendants (collectively, “Bieber and Usher”).                          Bieber and Usher
    moved to dismiss the action under Rule 12(b)(6), contending, as
    relevant       here,   that    no    reasonable      jury       could    find    that    the
    Copeland song and the Bieber and Usher songs were “substantially
    similar,” as required to make out an infringement claim.
    After a hearing, the district court agreed with Bieber and
    Usher, and entered an order granting their motions to dismiss.
    5
    The court applied our precedent requiring copyright plaintiffs
    to     prove     two   distinct       forms     of     similarity:       “extrinsic”
    similarity, an objective match between the copyright-protectable
    elements of an original work and a purported copy, often based
    on     expert     testimony;    and       “intrinsic”         similarity,   a   more
    subjective and “essentially aesthetic judgment” as to whether
    the    intended    audience    of   two    works      would    experience   them   as
    similar in overall effect.            While acknowledging that substantial
    similarity is “largely a matter of fact,” J.A. 249, the district
    court understood our precedent to allow for dismissal on the
    pleadings under either prong where no reasonable jury could find
    substantial similarity of the requisite kind.
    The court began its analysis with intrinsic similarity, and
    the overall appeal of the two works to their intended audience.
    Relying again on Fourth Circuit precedent, the court held that
    the relevant “intended audience” in this case is the general
    public, as the expected ultimate market for Copeland’s song.
    And the general public, the court concluded, would not “construe
    the aesthetic appeal of the songs as being similar,” for despite
    some shared elements, the “mood, tone, and subject matter” of
    the songs differ “significantly.”               J.A. 253-54.          Having decided
    that    no     reasonable   jury    could      find    the    songs    substantially
    similar under the intrinsic prong, the district court granted
    6
    defendants’          motions    to     dismiss     without   reaching      extrinsic
    similarity.       This appeal followed.
    II.
    To establish a claim for copyright infringement under the
    Copyright Act of 1976, 17 U.S.C. § 101 et seq., a plaintiff must
    prove that it possesses a valid copyright and that the defendant
    copied        elements     of        its    work    that     are    original      and
    protectable.          See Feist Publ’ns, Inc. v. Rural Tel. Serv. Co.,
    
    499 U.S. 340
    , 361 (1991); Universal Furniture Int’l, Inc., v.
    Collezione Europa USA, Inc., 
    618 F.3d 417
    , 435 (4th Cir. 2010).
    Absent direct proof of copying, which is hard to come by, a
    plaintiff may prove copying indirectly, with evidence showing
    that the defendant had access to the copyrighted work and that
    the     purported        copy     is       “substantially     similar”      to    the
    original.       See Universal 
    Furniture, 618 F.3d at 435
    .                 It is that
    final step in the analysis that is at issue here.                         Bieber and
    Usher    do    not    challenge      Copeland’s    copyright   in   his    song   nor
    their access to that song.                 Instead, this case turns on whether
    Copeland can show the “substantial similarity” that would give
    rise, together with undisputed access, to a presumption that
    Bieber and Usher copied his song.
    We begin by laying out the standard under which we consider
    that question, and addressing Copeland’s arguments for changes
    7
    or     refinements        to    that       standard.             As    the   district       court
    correctly explained, in this circuit, a plaintiff’s substantial
    similarity showing has two components: extrinsic and intrinsic
    similarity.             And while both bear, obviously, on the likeness
    between       a    copyrighted       work     and      a     supposed        copy,   they    are
    different in important ways.
    The “extrinsic inquiry is an objective one,” looking to
    specific          and    “external      criteria”           of    substantial        similarity
    between the original elements (and only the original elements)
    of     a    protected       work     and    an       alleged      copy.        
    Id. at 435-
    36; see also Dawson v. Hinshaw Music, Inc., 
    905 F.2d 731
    , 732-33
    (4th       Cir.    1990).      Because       the      inquiry         is   objective,      expert
    testimony often will be relevant.                      Universal 
    Furniture, 618 F.3d at 435
    .       And because it is focused only on the original elements
    of the copyrighted work, a court examining extrinsic similarity
    must       first    engage     in   a   process        we    sometimes        call   “analytic
    dissection,” separating out those parts of the work that are
    original and protected from those that are not.                                  See 
    id. at 436-37.
    Intrinsic similarity, by contrast, is a subjective inquiry
    that centers on the impressions of a work’s “intended audience,”
    usually the general public.                   See Lyons P’ship, L.P. v. Morris
    Costumes, 
    243 F.3d 789
    , 801 (4th Cir. 2001).                                   So under the
    intrinsic prong, we analyze works as cohesive wholes, without
    8
    distinguishing between protected and unprotected elements, just
    as the works’ intended audiences likely would encounter them in
    the marketplace.        See Universal 
    Furniture, 618 F.3d at 437
    .                 We
    often   have    described     intrinsic        similarity    as    measuring    the
    “total concept and feel” of the works in question.                          
    Id. at 436;
    Lyons, 243 F.3d at 801
    .
    Copeland asks us to modify this approach in two respects.
    First, pointing to Ninth Circuit case law, see Apple Computer,
    Inc. v. Microsoft Corp., 
    35 F.3d 1435
    , 1442-43 (9th Cir. 1994),
    Copeland suggests that we revisit our precedent and insist that
    comparison under the intrinsic prong, as well as the extrinsic,
    be   confined    to    original    elements       and    preceded    by   analytic
    dissection.     We can put to one side whether the Ninth Circuit
    actually has adopted the rule that Copeland endorses, because
    our court has held just the opposite:                   In Universal Furniture,
    we joined the Second and Eighth Circuits in finding expressly
    that    analytic      dissection      is   inapplicable      to    the    intrinsic
    analysis,   because      a   work’s    intended    audience       “does   not   make
    th[e]    distinction”        between       protectable      and     unprotectable
    elements and instead encounters a work “as one 
    object.” 618 F.3d at 437
    .
    Even if we were free to reconsider that holding, Copeland
    has offered no compelling reason to do so.                   Indeed, as Bieber
    and Usher point out, our rule, allowing for comparison of entire
    9
    works      under    the    intrinsic       prong,    generally    advantages      rather
    than       disadvantages       copyright       plaintiffs       like     Copeland,    by
    broadening the grounds upon which a court may find intrinsic
    similarity.         The district court committed no error by declining
    to engage in analytic dissection before conducting its inquiry
    into intrinsic similarity.
    Second, Copeland urges us to adopt the rule from Shaw v.
    Lindheim, 
    919 F.2d 1353
    (9th Cir. 1990), under which intrinsic
    similarity is a question reserved for the trier of fact, and
    only the extrinsic similarity prong can be grounds for dismissal
    at   the     summary       judgment    and    pleading      stages.       Because    the
    intrinsic similarity inquiry turns on an inherently subjective
    appreciation of a work’s tone and feel, Copeland argues, it is
    unfair      to    resolve    it   as   a    matter    of   law,   with    one    judge’s
    personal         opinion    trumping    what      could    be   overwhelming      expert
    evidence showing the substantial similarity of two songs under
    the extrinsic prong.
    We have not squarely addressed whether a district court may
    grant an infringement defendant’s motion to dismiss, or motion
    for summary judgment, under the intrinsic prong alone. 1                        Nor have
    1
    By contrast, we have indicated that a district court may
    grant a motion to dismiss or summary judgment under the
    extrinsic prong alone. See Universal 
    Furniture, 618 F.3d at 436
    (“A court may grant summary judgment for defendant as a matter
    of law if the similarity between the two works concerns only
    10
    we analyzed the precise scope of the Shaw rule in the Ninth
    Circuit, or decided whether to adopt it in our own.                We need not
    resolve those issues today, however, because in our view, even
    assuming that a motion to dismiss may be granted on the ground
    that no reasonable jury could find intrinsic similarity, the
    district court erred in doing so here.                It is to that question
    that we now turn.
    III.
    This court reviews de novo a district court’s decision to
    grant a motion to dismiss under Rule 12(b)(6), see 
    Jackson, 775 F.3d at 177
    –78,    and   also   conducts     de   novo   the   analysis   of
    whether works are substantially similar, see Peters v. West, 
    692 F.3d 629
    , 632 (7th Cir. 2012).           Like the district court, we may
    examine all four of the songs at issue at the pleading stage,
    because all were “integral to and explicitly relied on in the
    complaint”    and     because   Bieber     and   Usher   “do   not   challenge
    [their] authenticity.”          Phillips v. LCI Int’l, Inc., 
    190 F.3d 609
    , 618 (4th Cir. 1999).
    A.
    noncopyrightable elements of the plaintiff’s work.” (quoting
    Herzog v. Castle Rock Entm’t, 
    193 F.3d 1241
    , 1257 (11th Cir.
    1999))); see also 
    Lyons, 243 F.3d at 803
    (court decides as a
    “matter of law” whether extrinsic similarity exists).
    11
    As noted above, intrinsic similarity is assessed from the
    perspective        of    a    work’s       intended           audience.        See       Universal
    
    Furniture, 618 F.3d at 435
    .                      That means that the first step in
    undertaking an analysis of intrinsic similarity is identifying
    the   right    audience.             The    district          court    concluded         that    the
    general public was the intended audience for the Copeland song,
    and we agree.
    In Dawson, we clarified our intrinsic similarity analysis
    by introducing the “intended audience” formulation.                                   Because a
    primary purpose of copyright law is to “protect[] a creator’s
    market,” we reasoned, the intrinsic similarity inquiry should be
    keyed     to   the      impressions          of        the    intended       audience      for     a
    creator’s      work     —    the    impressions          that       count   for     purposes      of
    
    marketability. 905 F.2d at 734
    .                     So where the market for a
    given work consists of a discrete and specialized class, the
    reactions      of       a    generic         ordinary           observer       will       not    be
    particularly        relevant.              See    
    id. But in
        most     cases,      we
    cautioned, the general public is in fact the intended audience,
    and “a court should be hesitant” to find otherwise.                                        
    Id. at 737;
    see 
    Lyons, 243 F.3d at 801
    .
    Copeland      argues       that    this        case    is    the    exception      to    the
    ordinary rule.          According to Copeland, the intended audience for
    his song was not the general public but instead the “industry
    professionals”          to    whom    he     distributed             his    song    by    way    of
    12
    Sangreel.     The “market” Copeland was trying to reach, in other
    words, was the Ushers of the world, and Copeland would be harmed
    if industry professionals believed his song was substantially
    similar to those of the defendants even if the general public
    saw no resemblance.
    Like the district court, we are unpersuaded.                     It may be
    that Copeland intended to promote his music directly to industry
    professionals.         But “[i]f . . .        industry professionals reject
    [Copeland’s] song because it is too similar to the [d]efendants’
    songs, it would be because those companies fear that the public
    will find the songs to be overly similar.”                 J.A. 252 (emphasis
    in original).          There is a reason that the Dawson formulation
    uses the word “audience,” rather than “buyer” or “recipient”:
    Ultimate     marketability        is    not    always     determined     by    the
    impressions       of   a   first-hand   purchaser    or   recipient,     but   may
    sometimes rest on the impressions of third parties — the work’s
    actual “audience” — whose preferences the buyer or recipient has
    in mind when acquiring the work.
    Our decision in Lyons illustrates the point.                     There, we
    considered whether the intended audience for a purple dinosaur
    costume resembling the character “Barney” from the television
    series Barney & Friends was the adult performers who would buy
    the costumes or the young children they sought to 
    entertain. 243 F.3d at 802
    .      We   concluded   that   it   was   the    children’s
    13
    reactions     that    mattered        to    the       intrinsic       similarity      inquiry,
    because   even       though     they       were       not     themselves       the    intended
    purchasers     of     the     costumes,          it     was     their       impressions        (or
    misimpressions) that could lead adults to buy the infringing
    costumes.      
    Id. at 802–03.
            Adults         might     discern     differences
    between the two costumes, but if children could not, then there
    would be no reason for adults to insist on the original — with
    the result that the “knock-off” costumes would cut into Barney’s
    market and the profits of Barney’s owner.                         
    Id. at 803.
           The same
    reasoning applies here.               Though industry professionals may have
    been the intended direct recipients of Copeland’s music, the
    impressions that matter are those of the general public that
    constitutes the market for popular music — because, as Copeland
    admits,   J.A.       252,     those    are        the       impressions       that    industry
    professionals        would    have     in    mind       in     choosing       whether     to    do
    business with Copeland.
    Again, this should come as no surprise.                          When we left open
    in   Dawson   the     possibility          that       the     intended      audience      for    a
    choral arrangement of a spiritual song was more specialized than
    the general public and might be limited to choral directors, we
    also   made    clear     that     we       were       crafting      a    narrow      rule      for
    exceptional    circumstances.               We    specifically          distinguished          the
    subject matter        there    from        popular      music,        for   which    we     noted
    approvingly      that       courts    “routinely”             apply     the    lay    observer
    14
    test.     
    Dawson, 905 F.2d at 737
    .                 That is because the intended
    audience for popular music is usually an ordinary listener or,
    put differently, the general public.                          And indeed, the entire
    premise of Copeland’s case is that his song is substantially
    similar to one that appears on a multi-platinum album by one of
    the world’s most recognizable popular music stars.                          This is not
    a case about niche audience appeal, and there is no reason to
    think    of   the   “intended       audience”          as   anything    other    than   the
    general public.
    B.
    Finally, we come to the question at the heart of this case:
    Whether the songs at issue, assessed from the perspective of the
    intended audience — here, the general public — and taking into
    account their “total concept and feel,” 
    Lyons, 243 F.3d at 801
    ,
    are sufficiently intrinsically similar to give rise to a valid
    infringement        claim.          The    district         court     answered    in    the
    negative,       holding      that    no     reasonable         jury    could     find   the
    requisite intrinsic similarity.                    But under the applicable de
    novo standard of review, see 
    Peters, 692 F.3d at 632
    , we must
    listen    for    ourselves      and       come    to    our    own    conclusion.       And
    because the general public typically encounters popular music
    songs by hearing them from start to finish, we undertake that
    analysis by listening to the songs in their entirety and side by
    15
    side, to determine whether a reasonable jury could find that
    they are subjectively similar.
    1.
    As a preliminary matter, we should clarify that the “songs”
    to which we refer include all three of the defendants’ versions
    of “Somebody to Love”: the Usher demo version, the Bieber album
    version, and the Bieber-Usher remix version.                           At oral argument,
    Copeland suggested that each of those songs must be considered
    individually, and separately compared to the Copeland song.                                  We
    disagree.        In     our    view,        the       defendants’      three       songs     are
    sufficiently     similar       to     each       other    that      they    may    be   grouped
    together, and the same intrinsic analysis applied to all.                                     If
    any   one   of   them    fails        to    meet       the    threshold      for     intrinsic
    similarity, then all of them do.
    The Bieber album song and the Bieber-Usher remix are to our
    ears identical; the only difference we can hear is that Bieber
    is the only singer featured on the album song, whereas Usher
    provides    lead      vocals    in    the    second          verse   and     backing     vocals
    elsewhere on the remix.               On the Usher demo song, Usher is the
    only singer featured, and that song is in a different key than
    the others, presumably to accommodate his different vocal range.
    But   the   Usher     demo     song    is    otherwise         in    lock-step       with    the
    others down to minor details — everything from the lead singer’s
    exclamation      of     “oh”     in        the        introductory         section      to   the
    16
    distinctive synthesizer chords in the verses and the bass line
    in the pre-chorus. 2      By the unscientific intrinsic standard, the
    three Bieber and Usher songs are not just substantially similar
    to one another; they are the same.
    2.
    We turn now to a comparison of the Copeland song with,
    collectively, the three Bieber and Usher songs.                  The district
    court acknowledged that the Usher and Bieber songs “have some
    elements in common” with the Copeland song.            J.A. 253.      But for
    the   district   court,    what   was    dispositive   was   a    significant
    difference in the overall “aesthetic appeal” of the respective
    songs.    J.A. 254.    We cannot agree.      In our view, that analysis
    attaches too much weight to what the district court termed a
    difference in “mood” and “tone,” and too little to similarities
    between the “element” of the songs — their choruses — that is
    most important.
    First, if by “mood” and “tone” the district court meant
    genre, then we agree with this much:           The Copeland song belongs
    to a different genre than the three Bieber and Usher songs.
    2
    More specifically, the synthesizer chords in the three
    songs share    a   distinctive  “gated”  effect:     Instead  of
    maintaining a steady tone, the chords sharply fade in and out in
    a stabbing, off-beat fashion. And in all three songs, the pre-
    chorus and chorus bass line follows an “octave” pattern,
    repeating the same note (e.g., a C or a B-flat) but jumping up
    and down a full scale, which lends a forward-moving, propulsive
    effect to the music.
    17
    Though all fall under the same broad umbrella of popular music,
    the Copeland song is squarely within the R&B subgenre, while the
    Bieber and Usher songs would be labeled dance pop, perhaps with
    hints of electronica.        Indeed, that difference is striking upon
    first listen, and at least as a linguistic matter, the very fact
    of these different genres might be thought to make the songs
    different in “concept and feel,” 
    Lyons, 243 F.3d at 801
    , or, in
    the words of the district court, in “aesthetic appeal,” J.A.
    254.
    But as Bieber’s counsel conceded at oral argument, while
    genre may be relevant to intrinsic analysis of musical works, it
    cannot be dispositive under copyright law.             For if a difference
    in genre were enough by itself to preclude intrinsic similarity,
    then nothing would prevent someone from translating, say, the
    Beatles’ songbook into a different genre, and then profiting
    from an unlicensed reggae or heavy metal version of “Hey Jude”
    on the ground that it is different in “concept and feel” than
    the original.    From Copeland’s perspective, it may be true that
    the “aesthetic appeal” of an R&B song is different, in some
    sense, than that of a dance pop song — but if there is going to
    be a dance pop version of his R&B “Somebody to Love,” then it is
    his to record or to license, so that he can reap the full return
    on his creative efforts.       Cf. Castle Rock Entm’t, Inc. v. Carol
    Pub.   Grp.,   Inc.,   
    150 F.3d 132
    ,   140   (2d   Cir.   1998)   (“total
    18
    concept and feel” analysis must take account of fact that works
    from different genres “must necessarily have a different concept
    and feel”).        And by the same token, of course, were we to put
    too much stock in identity of genre at the intrinsic stage, we
    would risk deeming each successive work in a genre — whether it
    be R&B, ragtime, or bossa nova — an appropriation of the same-
    genre works that came before it.
    Second, we do not doubt that the songs at issue here are in
    many respects dissimilar.          And if substantial similarity were a
    purely quantitative inquiry, asking only whether the majority of
    the   works   in    question     overlapped,    we     would   agree   with    the
    district court that no reasonable jury could find the requisite
    intrinsic similarity.            For instance, while the Copeland song
    concludes with a repeated instrumental figure, the Bieber and
    Usher songs end more abruptly, after ad-libbed vocal lines.                    The
    Bieber and Usher songs include a post-chorus interval, with the
    lyric “I-I need somebody” sung in a syncopated manner, that has
    no    equivalent     in    the    Copeland     song.       And    perhaps     most
    significantly,       the    songs’    verses     feature       different    vocal
    melodies and beats 3 as well as different lyrical content, with
    3
    The Copeland verses feature a hectic R&B beat, with a
    shaker and a busy eighth-note pattern on the bass drum.     The
    musical accompaniment in those verses is two chords played in a
    backbeat, with a whimsical sound reminiscent of a circus organ.
    Both differ significantly from the sparser beats and regimented
    19
    the Copeland verses lamenting the end of a relationship gone
    sour and the Bieber and Usher verses conveying the hope and
    optimism of the start of a relationship with an unidentified
    love interest.        The district court may have had some or all of
    these in mind when it referred to differences in “mood, tone,
    and    subject    matter,”     J.A.     253,      and     we        agree    that   taken
    numerically, the points of dissimilarity may well exceed the
    points of similarity.
    But what that analysis fails to account for, we think, is
    the relative importance of these differences as compared to what
    the songs reasonably could be heard to have in common: their
    choruses.     Even when quantitative majorities of two works bear
    little    resemblance,       courts     routinely         permit       a     finding   of
    substantial      similarity    where    the      works    share       some    especially
    significant sequence of notes or lyrics.                   See Swirsky v. Carey,
    
    376 F.3d 841
    , 851 (9th Cir. 2004) (overlap in first measure of
    chorus    —   seven    total    notes       —    enough        to     make    pop    songs
    substantially similar); Fisher v. Dees, 
    794 F.2d 432
    , 434 & n.2
    (9th   Cir.   1986)    (similarity     in       first    six    measures      of    songs,
    amounting to twenty-nine seconds on a forty-minute album, enough
    to constitute appropriation of album); Elsmere Music, Inc. v.
    three-chord progression of the verses in the Bieber and Usher
    songs.
    20
    Nat’l Broad. Co., 
    482 F. Supp. 741
    , 744 (S.D.N.Y.), aff’d, 
    623 F.2d 252
    (2d Cir. 1980) (four-note phrase accompanying lyrics “I
    love   New   York”    protectable      because        it   is   “the   heart    of   the
    composition”); Santrayll v. Burrell, No. 91 Civ. 3166, 
    1996 WL 134803
    ,   at   *1–2    (S.D.N.Y.      Mar.      25,   1996)     (repetition     of   the
    phrase    “uh-oh”     four    times    in    a   distinctive       rhythm      for   one
    measure is protectable).            And we think it is clear that when it
    comes to popular music, a song’s chorus may be the kind of key
    sequence that can give rise to intrinsic similarity, even when
    works differ in other respects.
    It is the chorus — often termed the “hook,” in recognition
    of its power to keep a listener coming back for more — that many
    listeners will recognize immediately or hear in their minds when
    a song title is mentioned.             As the part of a song that is most
    often repeated and remembered, a chorus hook is important not
    only   aesthetically         but    also    commercially,        where   it    may   be
    central to a song’s economic success.                  See, e.g., Gary Burns, A
    Typology of ‘Hooks’ in Popular Records, 6 Popular Music 1 (1987)
    (cataloging characteristics and definitions of term “hook,” and
    noting that “the hook is ‘what you’re selling’” and that hooks
    are “the foundation of commercial songwriting, particularly hit-
    single writing”).        From “Respect” by Aretha Franklin to “Seven
    Nation Army” by the White Stripes, the choruses or hooks of
    popular   music     songs     are   often    disproportionately          significant,
    21
    relative    to     the    amount        of   time     or    number     of    measures      they
    occupy.     See 
    id. at 1
    (“[V]irtually no hit record is without a
    bit of music or words so compelling that it worms its way into
    one’s memory and won’t go away.”).
    After listening to the Copeland song and the Bieber and
    Usher    songs     as    wholes,        we   conclude        that    their     choruses     are
    similar enough and also significant enough that a reasonable
    jury    could     find    the        songs   intrinsically          similar.        The    most
    obvious    similarity,          of     course,       is    the     shared    chorus      lyric,
    mirrored in the songs’ titles:                       “I [] need somebody to love.”
    As Bieber and Usher point out, this phrase is common in popular
    music, appearing most famously in songs also titled “Somebody to
    Love” by psychedelic-rock band Jefferson Airplane and arena-rock
    band     Queen,    and        common     lyrical          phrases    generally      are     not
    copyrightable, see 
    Peters, 692 F.3d at 635
    –36 (discussing rap
    songs’    use     of    the     maxim     “what      does     not    kill    me,    makes   me
    stronger”).             That     might         preclude       consideration         of     this
    similarity under the extrinsic prong, where analysis is preceded
    by analytic dissection to determine which portions of a work are
    protectable.            But     as     Bieber    and       Usher     concede,      under    the
    intrinsic       prong,     we     do     not    engage       in     analytic    dissection.
    Instead,    we     examine        the     chorus’s         lyrics     together      with    the
    accompanying music, taking the works in their entirety, as an
    ordinary musical listener would.
    22
    And when we listen to the choruses that way, and in the
    context of the entire songs, we hear the kind of meaningful
    overlap   on    which   a   reasonable   jury    could    rest     a   finding   of
    substantial similarity.           It is not simply that both choruses
    contain the lyric “somebody to love”; it is that the lyric is
    delivered in what seems to be an almost identical rhythm and a
    strikingly similar melody.         To us, it sounds as though there are
    a couple of points in the respective chorus melodies where the
    Bieber and Usher songs go up a note and the Copeland song goes
    down a note, or vice versa.          In our view, however, a reasonable
    jury could find that these small variations would not prevent a
    member    of     the    general     public      from     hearing       substantial
    similarity. 4
    We also conclude that the choruses of the Copeland song and
    the Bieber and Usher songs are sufficiently important to the
    songs’ overall effect that they may be the basis for a finding
    4
    In this respect, comparison with the Jefferson Airplane
    and Queen songs cited by Bieber and Usher undermines rather than
    supports their position.   To the lay listeners of this panel,
    the Copeland and Bieber and Usher choruses are much more similar
    to each other in “total concept and feel” than they are to the
    refrains of those classic rock‘nʹroll songs.      Because courts
    have often taken judicial notice of such well-known songs, see,
    e.g., ZZ Top v. Chrysler Corp., 
    54 F. Supp. 2d 983
    , 986 n.6
    (W.D. Wash. 1999); Testa v. Janssen, 
    482 F. Supp. 1195
    , 1199 n.3
    (W.D. Pa. 1980), we may consider them for purposes of this
    comparison, though we emphasize that our holding today rests on
    our analysis of the Copeland song and the Bieber and Usher songs
    alone.
    23
    of intrinsic similarity.               In both the Copeland song and the
    Bieber and Usher songs, the singing of the titular lyric is an
    anthemic,    sing-along       moment,        delivered      at     a    high    volume   and
    pitch.         Quite         simply,         it     is      “the        heart     of     the
    composition[s],” Elsmere 
    Music, 482 F. Supp. at 744
    , the most
    prominent and memorable part of the songs, and just the sort of
    significant sequence that courts have found sufficient to render
    musical works substantially similar.                       Whether a member of the
    general public could experience these songs primarily through
    their    choruses      and     thus     find        them    substantially         similar,
    notwithstanding the differences catalogued above, is in our view
    a close enough question that it cannot be disposed of as a
    matter of law and should instead be decided by a jury.
    IV.
    In summary, we hold that a reasonable jury could find that
    the     Copeland    song      and      the        Bieber    and        Usher    songs    are
    intrinsically similar.              Because our holding is sufficient to
    dispose of this appeal, we decline to reach Copeland’s other
    arguments.     For     the     reasons       set    forth    above,       we    vacate   the
    judgment of the district court and remand the case for further
    proceedings.
    VACATED AND REMANDED
    24