Timothy Bostic v. George Schaefer ( 2014 )


Menu:
  •                                  PUBLISHED
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT
    No. 14-1167
    TIMOTHY B.     BOSTIC;   TONY   C.   LONDON;   CAROL   SCHALL;   MARY
    TOWNLEY,
    Plaintiffs − Appellees,
    JOANNE HARRIS; JESSICA DUFF; CHRISTY BERGHOFF; VICTORIA
    KIDD, on behalf of themselves and all others similarly
    situated,
    Intervenors,
    v.
    GEORGE E. SCHAEFER, III, in his official capacity as the
    Clerk of Court for Norfolk Circuit Court,
    Defendant – Appellant,
    and
    JANET M. RAINEY, in her official capacity as State Registrar
    of Vital Records; ROBERT F. MCDONNELL, in his official
    capacity as Governor of Virginia; KENNETH T. CUCCINELLI, II,
    in his official capacity as Attorney General of Virginia,
    Defendants,
    MICHÈLE MCQUIGG,
    Intervenor/Defendant.
    ------------------------------------
    DAVID A. ROBINSON; ALAN J. HAWKINS; JASON S. CARROLL; NORTH
    CAROLINA   VALUES   COALITION;  LIBERTY,   LIFE,  AND   LAW
    FOUNDATION; SOCIAL SCIENCE PROFESSORS; FAMILY RESEARCH
    COUNCIL; VIRGINIA CATHOLIC CONFERENCE, LLC; CENTER FOR
    CONSTITUTIONAL   JURISPRUDENCE; STATE   OF  WEST  VIRGINIA;
    INSTITUTE FOR MARRIAGE AND PUBLIC POLICY; HELEN M. ALVARE;
    STATE OF INDIANA; STATE OF ALABAMA; STATE OF ALASKA; STATE
    OF ARIZONA; STATE OF COLORADO; STATE OF IDAHO; STATE OF
    LOUISIANA; STATE OF MONTANA; STATE OF NEBRASKA; STATE OF
    OKLAHOMA; STATE OF SOUTH CAROLINA; STATE OF SOUTH DAKOTA;
    STATE OF UTAH; STATE OF WYOMING; WALLBUILDERS, LLC; LIBERTY
    COUNSEL; AMERICAN COLLEGE OF PEDIATRICIANS; SCHOLARS OF
    HISTORY AND RELATED DISCIPLINES; AMERICAN LEADERSHIP FUND;
    ROBERT P. GEORGE; SHERIF GIRGIS; RYAN T. ANDERSON; PAUL
    MCHUGH; UNITED STATES CONFERENCE OF CATHOLIC BISHOPS;
    NATIONAL ASSOCIATION OF EVANGELICALS; CHURCH OF JESUS CHRIST
    OF LATTER−DAY SAINTS; THE ETHICS & RELIGIOUS LIBERTY
    COMMISSION OF THE SOUTHERN BAPTIST CONVENTION; LUTHERAN
    CHURCH−MISSOURI SYNOD; THE BECKET FUND FOR RELIGIOUS
    LIBERTY; EAGLE FORUM EDUCATION AND LEGAL DEFENSE FUND; DAVID
    BOYLE; ROBERT OSCAR LOPEZ; CONCERNED WOMEN FOR AMERICA; THE
    FAMILY FOUNDATION OF VIRGINIA,
    Amici Supporting Appellant,
    CONSTITUTIONAL    LAW   SCHOLARS;    ASHUTOSH    BHAGWAT;    LEE
    BOLLINGER; ERWIN CHEMERINSKY; WALTER DELLINGER; MICHAEL C.
    DORF; LEE EPSTEIN; DANIEL FARBER; BARRY FRIEDMAN; MICHAEL
    JAY GERHARDT, Professor; DEBORAH HELLMAN; JOHN CALVIN
    JEFFRIES, JR.; LAWRENCE LESSIG; WILLIAM MARSHALL; FRANK
    MICHELMAN; JANE S. SCHACTER; CHRISTOPHER H. SCHROEDER;
    SUZANNA SHERRY; GEOFFREY R. STONE; DAVID STRAUSS; LAURENCE
    H. TRIBE, Professor; WILLIAM VAN ALSTYNE; OUTSERVE−SLDN; THE
    AMERICAN   MILITARY   PARTNER    ASSOCIATION;    THE   AMERICAN
    SOCIOLOGICAL   ASSOCIATION;    VIRGINIA    CONSTITUTIONAL    LAW
    PROFESSORS; AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGICAL ASSOCIATION; THE AMERICAN
    ACADEMY OF PEDIATRICS; AMERICAN PSYCHIATRIC ASSOCIATION;
    NATIONAL    ASSOCIATION    OF    SOCIAL    WORKERS;    VIRGINIA
    PSYCHOLOGICAL ASSOCIATION; EQUALITY NC; SOUTH CAROLINA
    QUALITY    COALITION;     CHANTELLE     FISHER−BORNE;     MARCIE
    FISHER−BORNE; CRYSTAL HENDRIX; LEIGH SMITH; SHANA CARIGNAN;
    MEGAN PARKER; TERRI BECK; LESLIE ZANAGLIO; LEE KNIGHT
    CAFFERY; DANA DRAA; SHAWN LONG; CRAIG JOHNSON; ESMERALDA
    MEJIA;     CHRISTINA     GINTER−MEJIA;      CATO     INSTITUTE;
    CONSTITUTIONAL    ACCOUNTABILITY    CENTER;     HISTORIANS    OF
    MARRIAGE; PETER W. BARDAGLIO; NORMA BASCH; STEPHANIE COONTZ;
    NANCY F. COTT; TOBY L. DITZ; ARIELA R. DUBLER; LAURA F.
    EDWARDS; SARAH BARRINGER GORDON; MICHAEL GROSSBERG; HENDRIK
    HARTOG; ELLEN HERMAN; MARTHA HODES; LINDA K. KERBER; ALICE
    KESSLER−HARRIS; ELAINE TYLER MAY; SERENA MAYERI; STEVEN
    MINTZ; ELIZABETH PLECK; CAROLE SHAMMAS; MARY L. SHANLEY; AMY
    DRU STANLEY; BARBARA WELKE; PARENTS, FAMILIES AND FRIENDS OF
    2
    LESBIANS AND GAYS, INC.; KERRY ABRAMS, Albert Clark Tate,
    Jr. Professor of Law, University of Virginia School of Law;
    VIVIAN HAMILTON, Professor of Law, William and Mary;
    MEREDITH HARBACH, Professor of Law, University of Richmond;
    JOAN HEIFETZ HOLLINGER, John and Elizabeth Boalt Lecturer in
    Residence, University of California, Berkeley School of Law;
    COURTNEY G. JOSLIN, Professor of Law, University of
    California, Davis School of Law; NAACP LEGAL DEFENSE AND
    EDUCATION    FUND,  INC.;    NATIONAL   ASSOCIATION   FOR    THE
    ADVANCEMENT OF COLORED PEOPLE; HOWARD UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF
    LAW CIVIL RIGHTS CLINIC; FAMILY EQUALITY COUNCIL; COLAGE;
    GLMA: HEALTH PROFESSIONALS ADVANCING LGBT EQUALITY; WILLIAM
    N. ESKRIDGE, JR.; REBECCA L. BROWN; DANIEL A. FARBER;
    MICHAEL GERHARDT; JACK KNIGHT; ANDREW KOPPELMAN; MELISSA
    LAMB SAUNDERS; NEIL S. SIEGEL; JANA B. SINGER; HISTORIANS OF
    ANTI−GAY DISCRIMINATION; ANTI−DEFAMATION LEAGUE; AMERICANS
    UNITED FOR SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE; BEND THE ARC: A
    JEWISH PARTNERSHIP FOR JUSTICE; HADASSAH, THE WOMEN'S
    ZIONIST ORGANIZATION OF AMERICA; HINDU AMERICAN FOUNDATION;
    THE   INTERFAITH   ALLIANCE   FOUNDATION;   JAPANESE   AMERICAN
    CITIZENS LEAGUE; JEWISH SOCIAL POLICY ACTION NETWORK;
    KESHET;   METROPOLITAN    COMMUNITY   CHURCHES;    MORE    LIGHT
    PRESBYTERIANS; THE NATIONAL COUNCIL OF JEWISH WOMEN;
    NEHIRIM;    PEOPLE   FOR    THE   AMERICAN   WAY    FOUNDATION;
    PRESBYTERIAN WELCOME; RECONCILINGWORKS: LUTHERANS FOR FULL
    PARTICIPATION; RELIGIOUS INSTITUTE, INC.; SIKH AMERICAN
    LEGAL DEFENSE AND EDUCATION FUND; SOCIETY FOR HUMANISTIC
    JUDAISM; T'RUAH: THE RABBINIC CALL FOR HUMAN RIGHTS; WOMEN'S
    LEAGUE FOR CONSERVATIVE JUDAISM; COLUMBIA LAW SCHOOL
    SEXUALITY AND GENDER LAW CLINIC; BISHOPS OF THE EPISCOPAL
    CHURCH IN VIRGINIA; CENTRAL ATLANTIC CONFERENCE OF THE
    UNITED CHURCH OF CHRIST; CENTRAL CONFERENCE OF AMERICAN
    RABBIS; MORMONS FOR EQUALITY; RECONSTRUCTIONIST RABBINICAL
    ASSOCIATION; RECONSTRUCTIONIST RABBINICAL COLLEGE AND JEWISH
    RECONSTRUCTIONIST COMMUNITIES; UNION FOR REFORM JUDAISM; THE
    UNITARIAN UNIVERSALIST ASSOCIATION; AFFIRMATION; COVENANT
    NETWORK OF PRESBYTERIANS; METHODIST FEDERATION FOR SOCIAL
    ACTION; MORE LIGHT PRESBYTERIANS; PRESBYTERIAN WELCOME;
    RECONCILING MINISTRIES NETWORK; RECONCILINGWORKS: LUTHERANS
    FOR FULL PARTICIPATION; RELIGIOUS INSTITUTE, INC.; WOMEN OF
    REFORM JUDAISM; 28 EMPLOYERS AND ORGANIZATIONS REPRESENTING
    EMPLOYERS;    COMMONWEALTH    OF   MASSACHUSETTS;    STATE    OF
    CALIFORNIA; STATE OF CONNECTICUT; DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA;
    STATE OF ILLINOIS; STATE OF IOWA; STATE OF MAINE; STATE OF
    MARYLAND; STATE OF NEW HAMPSHIRE; STATE OF NEW MEXICO; STATE
    OF NEW YORK; STATE OF OREGON; STATE OF VERMONT; STATE OF
    WASHINGTON; GARY J. GATES; NATIONAL AND WESTERN STATES
    3
    WOMEN'S RIGHTS ORGANIZATIONS; VIRGINIA CHAPTER OF THE
    AMERICAN ACADEMY OF MATRIMONIAL LAWYERS; THE NATIONAL
    WOMEN'S LAW CENTER; EQUAL RIGHTS ADVOCATES; LEGAL MOMENTUM;
    NATIONAL ASSOCIATION OF WOMEN LAWYERS; NATIONAL PARTNERSHIP
    FOR WOMEN & FAMILIES; SOUTHWEST WOMEN'S LAW CENTER; WOMEN'S
    LAW PROJECT; PROFESSORS OF LAW ASSOCIATED WITH THE WILLIAMS
    INSTITUTE;    BAY   AREA    LAWYERS   FOR   INDIVIDUAL    FREEDOM;
    LEADERSHIP CONFERENCE ON CIVIL AND HUMAN RIGHTS; PUBLIC
    INTEREST ORGANIZATIONS; BAR ASSOCIATIONS; FAMILY LAW AND
    CONFLICT OF LAWS PROFESSORS; GAY AND LESBIAN ADVOCATES AND
    DEFENDERS; PEOPLE OF FAITH FOR EQUALITY IN VIRGINIA;
    CELEBRATION     CENTER    FOR    SPIRITUAL    LIVING;    CLARENDON
    PRESBYTERIAN      CHURCH;     COMMONWEALTH      BAPTIST    CHURCH;
    CONGREGATION OR AMI; HOPE UNITED CHURCH OF CHRIST; LITTLE
    RIVER UCC; METROPOLITAN COMMUNITY CHURCH OF NORTHERN
    VIRGINIA; MT. VERNON UNITARIAN CHURCH; ST. JAMES UCC,; ST.
    JOHN'S   UCC;    NEW   LIFE    METROPOLITAN    COMMUNITY   CHURCH;
    UNITARIAN    UNIVERSALIST     FELLOWSHIP    OF    THE   PENINSULA;
    UNITARIAN UNIVERSALIST CONGREGATION OF STERLING; UNITED
    CHURCH OF CHRIST OF FREDERICKSBURG; UNITARIAN UNIVERSALIST
    CHURCH OF LOUDOUN; ANDREW MERTZ; REV. MARIE HULM ADAM; REV.
    MARTY ANDERSON; REV ROBIN ANDERSON; REV. VERNE ARENS; RABBI
    LIA BASS; REV. JOSEPH G. BEATTIE; REV. SUE BROWNING; REV.
    JIM BUNDY; REV. MARK BYRD; REV. STEVEN C. CLUNN; REV. DR.
    JOHN COPERHAVER; RABBI GARY CREDITOR; REV. DAVID ENSIGN;
    REV.   HENRY    FAIRMAN;     RABBI   JESSE   GALLOP;    REV.   TOM
    GERSTENLAUER; REV. ROBIN H. GORSLINE; REV. TRISH HALL; REV.
    WARREN HAMMONDS; REV. JON HEASLET; REV. DOUGLAS HODGES; REV.
    PHYLLIS HUBBELL; REV. STEPHEN G. HYDE; REV. JANET JAMES;
    REV. JOHN MANWELL; REV. JAMES W. MCNEAL; REV. MARC BOSWELL;
    REV. ANDREW CLIVE MILLARD; REV. DR. MELANIE MILLER; REV.
    AMBER NEUROTH; REV. JAMES PAPILE; REV. LINDA OLSON PEEBLES;
    REV. DON PRANGE; RABBI MICHAEL RAGOZIN; RABBI BEN ROMER;
    REV. JENNIFER RYU; REV. ANYA SAMMLER−MICHAEL; REV. AMY
    SCHWARTZMAN; REV. DANNY SPEARS; REV. MARK SURIANO; REV. ROB
    VAUGHN; REV. DANIEL VELEZ−RIVERA; REV. KATE R. WALKER; REV.
    TERRYE WILLIAMS; REV. DR. KAREN−MARIE YUST,
    Amici Supporting Appellees.
    4
    No. 14-1169
    TIMOTHY B.     BOSTIC;   TONY   C.   LONDON;   CAROL   SCHALL;   MARY
    TOWNLEY,
    Plaintiffs − Appellees,
    JOANNE HARRIS; JESSICA DUFF; CHRISTY BERGHOFF; VICTORIA
    KIDD, on behalf of themselves and all others similarly
    situated,
    Intervenors,
    v.
    JANET M. RAINEY, in her official capacity as State Registrar
    of Vital Records,
    Defendant – Appellant,
    and
    GEORGE E. SCHAEFER, III, in his official capacity as the
    Clerk of Court for Norfolk Circuit Court; ROBERT F.
    MCDONNELL, in his official capacity as Governor of Virginia;
    KENNETH T. CUCCINELLI, II, in his official capacity as
    Attorney General of Virginia,
    Defendants,
    MICHÈLE MCQUIGG,
    Intervenor/Defendant.
    ------------------------------------
    DAVID A. ROBINSON; ALAN J. HAWKINS; JASON         S. CARROLL; NORTH
    CAROLINA   VALUES   COALITION;  LIBERTY,          LIFE,   AND   LAW
    FOUNDATION; SOCIAL SCIENCE PROFESSORS;             FAMILY RESEARCH
    COUNCIL; VIRGINIA CATHOLIC CONFERENCE,            LLC; CENTER FOR
    CONSTITUTIONAL   JURISPRUDENCE; STATE   OF          WEST  VIRGINIA;
    INSTITUTE FOR MARRIAGE AND PUBLIC POLICY;          HELEN M. ALVARE;
    STATE OF INDIANA; STATE OF ALABAMA; STATE          OF ALASKA; STATE
    OF ARIZONA; STATE OF COLORADO; STATE OF            IDAHO; STATE OF
    5
    LOUISIANA; STATE OF MONTANA; STATE OF NEBRASKA; STATE OF
    OKLAHOMA; STATE OF SOUTH CAROLINA; STATE OF SOUTH DAKOTA;
    STATE OF UTAH; STATE OF WYOMING; WALLBUILDERS, LLC; LIBERTY
    COUNSEL; AMERICAN COLLEGE OF PEDIATRICIANS; SCHOLARS OF
    HISTORY AND RELATED DISCIPLINES; AMERICAN LEADERSHIP FUND;
    ROBERT P. GEORGE; SHERIF GIRGIS; RYAN T. ANDERSON; PAUL
    MCHUGH; UNITED STATES CONFERENCE OF CATHOLIC BISHOPS;
    NATIONAL ASSOCIATION OF EVANGELICALS; CHURCH OF JESUS CHRIST
    OF LATTER−DAY SAINTS; THE ETHICS & RELIGIOUS LIBERTY
    COMMISSION OF THE SOUTHERN BAPTIST CONVENTION; LUTHERAN
    CHURCH−MISSOURI SYNOD; THE BECKET FUND FOR RELIGIOUS
    LIBERTY; EAGLE FORUM EDUCATION AND LEGAL DEFENSE FUND; DAVID
    BOYLE; ROBERT OSCAR LOPEZ; CONCERNED WOMEN FOR AMERICA; THE
    FAMILY FOUNDATION OF VIRGINIA,
    Amici Supporting Appellant,
    CONSTITUTIONAL    LAW   SCHOLARS;    ASHUTOSH    BHAGWAT;    LEE
    BOLLINGER; ERWIN CHEMERINSKY; WALTER DELLINGER; MICHAEL C.
    DORF; LEE EPSTEIN; DANIEL FARBER; BARRY FRIEDMAN; MICHAEL
    JAY GERHARDT, Professor; DEBORAH HELLMAN; JOHN CALVIN
    JEFFRIES, JR.; LAWRENCE LESSIG; WILLIAM MARSHALL; FRANK
    MICHELMAN; JANE S. SCHACTER; CHRISTOPHER H. SCHROEDER;
    SUZANNA SHERRY; GEOFFREY R. STONE; DAVID STRAUSS; LAURENCE
    H. TRIBE, Professor; WILLIAM VAN ALSTYNE; OUTSERVE−SLDN; THE
    AMERICAN   MILITARY   PARTNER    ASSOCIATION;    THE   AMERICAN
    SOCIOLOGICAL   ASSOCIATION;    VIRGINIA    CONSTITUTIONAL    LAW
    PROFESSORS; AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGICAL ASSOCIATION; THE AMERICAN
    ACADEMY OF PEDIATRICS; AMERICAN PSYCHIATRIC ASSOCIATION;
    NATIONAL    ASSOCIATION    OF    SOCIAL    WORKERS;    VIRGINIA
    PSYCHOLOGICAL ASSOCIATION; EQUALITY NC; SOUTH CAROLINA
    QUALITY    COALITION;     CHANTELLE     FISHER−BORNE;     MARCIE
    FISHER−BORNE; CRYSTAL HENDRIX; LEIGH SMITH; SHANA CARIGNAN;
    MEGAN PARKER; TERRI BECK; LESLIE ZANAGLIO; LEE KNIGHT
    CAFFERY; DANA DRAA; SHAWN LONG; CRAIG JOHNSON; ESMERALDA
    MEJIA;     CHRISTINA     GINTER−MEJIA;      CATO     INSTITUTE;
    CONSTITUTIONAL    ACCOUNTABILITY    CENTER;     HISTORIANS    OF
    MARRIAGE; PETER W. BARDAGLIO; NORMA BASCH; STEPHANIE COONTZ;
    NANCY F. COTT; TOBY L. DITZ; ARIELA R. DUBLER; LAURA F.
    EDWARDS; SARAH BARRINGER GORDON; MICHAEL GROSSBERG; HENDRIK
    HARTOG; ELLEN HERMAN; MARTHA HODES; LINDA K. KERBER; ALICE
    KESSLER−HARRIS; ELAINE TYLER MAY; SERENA MAYERI; STEVEN
    MINTZ; ELIZABETH PLECK; CAROLE SHAMMAS; MARY L. SHANLEY; AMY
    DRU STANLEY; BARBARA WELKE; PARENTS, FAMILIES AND FRIENDS OF
    LESBIANS AND GAYS, INC.; KERRY ABRAMS, Albert Clark Tate,
    Jr. Professor of Law, University of Virginia School of Law;
    VIVIAN HAMILTON, Professor of Law, William and Mary;
    6
    MEREDITH HARBACH, Professor of Law, University of Richmond;
    JOAN HEIFETZ HOLLINGER, John and Elizabeth Boalt Lecturer in
    Residence, University of California, Berkeley School of Law;
    COURTNEY G. JOSLIN, Professor of Law, University of
    California, Davis School of Law; NAACP LEGAL DEFENSE AND
    EDUCATION    FUND,  INC.;    NATIONAL   ASSOCIATION   FOR    THE
    ADVANCEMENT OF COLORED PEOPLE; HOWARD UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF
    LAW CIVIL RIGHTS CLINIC; FAMILY EQUALITY COUNCIL; COLAGE;
    GLMA: HEALTH PROFESSIONALS ADVANCING LGBT EQUALITY; WILLIAM
    N. ESKRIDGE, JR.; REBECCA L. BROWN; DANIEL A. FARBER;
    MICHAEL GERHARDT; JACK KNIGHT; ANDREW KOPPELMAN; MELISSA
    LAMB SAUNDERS; NEIL S. SIEGEL; JANA B. SINGER; HISTORIANS OF
    ANTI−GAY DISCRIMINATION; ANTI−DEFAMATION LEAGUE; AMERICANS
    UNITED FOR SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE; BEND THE ARC: A
    JEWISH PARTNERSHIP FOR JUSTICE; HADASSAH, THE WOMEN'S
    ZIONIST ORGANIZATION OF AMERICA; HINDU AMERICAN FOUNDATION;
    THE   INTERFAITH   ALLIANCE   FOUNDATION;   JAPANESE   AMERICAN
    CITIZENS LEAGUE; JEWISH SOCIAL POLICY ACTION NETWORK;
    KESHET;   METROPOLITAN    COMMUNITY   CHURCHES;    MORE    LIGHT
    PRESBYTERIANS; THE NATIONAL COUNCIL OF JEWISH WOMEN;
    NEHIRIM;    PEOPLE   FOR    THE   AMERICAN   WAY    FOUNDATION;
    PRESBYTERIAN WELCOME; RECONCILINGWORKS: LUTHERANS FOR FULL
    PARTICIPATION; RELIGIOUS INSTITUTE, INC.; SIKH AMERICAN
    LEGAL DEFENSE AND EDUCATION FUND; SOCIETY FOR HUMANISTIC
    JUDAISM; T'RUAH: THE RABBINIC CALL FOR HUMAN RIGHTS; WOMEN'S
    LEAGUE FOR CONSERVATIVE JUDAISM; COLUMBIA LAW SCHOOL
    SEXUALITY AND GENDER LAW CLINIC; BISHOPS OF THE EPISCOPAL
    CHURCH IN VIRGINIA; CENTRAL ATLANTIC CONFERENCE OF THE
    UNITED CHURCH OF CHRIST; CENTRAL CONFERENCE OF AMERICAN
    RABBIS; MORMONS FOR EQUALITY; RECONSTRUCTIONIST RABBINICAL
    ASSOCIATION; RECONSTRUCTIONIST RABBINICAL COLLEGE AND JEWISH
    RECONSTRUCTIONIST COMMUNITIES; UNION FOR REFORM JUDAISM; THE
    UNITARIAN UNIVERSALIST ASSOCIATION; AFFIRMATION; COVENANT
    NETWORK OF PRESBYTERIANS; METHODIST FEDERATION FOR SOCIAL
    ACTION; MORE LIGHT PRESBYTERIANS; PRESBYTERIAN WELCOME;
    RECONCILING MINISTRIES NETWORK; RECONCILINGWORKS: LUTHERANS
    FOR FULL PARTICIPATION; RELIGIOUS INSTITUTE, INC.; WOMEN OF
    REFORM JUDAISM; 28 EMPLOYERS AND ORGANIZATIONS REPRESENTING
    EMPLOYERS;    COMMONWEALTH    OF   MASSACHUSETTS;    STATE    OF
    CALIFORNIA; STATE OF CONNECTICUT; DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA;
    STATE OF ILLINOIS; STATE OF IOWA; STATE OF MAINE; STATE OF
    MARYLAND; STATE OF NEW HAMPSHIRE; STATE OF NEW MEXICO; STATE
    OF NEW YORK; STATE OF OREGON; STATE OF VERMONT; STATE OF
    WASHINGTON; GARY J. GATES; NATIONAL AND WESTERN STATES
    WOMEN'S RIGHTS ORGANIZATIONS; VIRGINIA CHAPTER OF THE
    AMERICAN ACADEMY OF MATRIMONIAL LAWYERS; THE NATIONAL
    WOMEN'S LAW CENTER; EQUAL RIGHTS ADVOCATES; LEGAL MOMENTUM;
    7
    NATIONAL ASSOCIATION OF WOMEN LAWYERS; NATIONAL PARTNERSHIP
    FOR WOMEN & FAMILIES; SOUTHWEST WOMEN'S LAW CENTER; WOMEN'S
    LAW PROJECT; PROFESSORS OF LAW ASSOCIATED WITH THE WILLIAMS
    INSTITUTE;    BAY   AREA    LAWYERS   FOR   INDIVIDUAL    FREEDOM;
    LEADERSHIP CONFERENCE ON CIVIL AND HUMAN RIGHTS; PUBLIC
    INTEREST ORGANIZATIONS; BAR ASSOCIATIONS; FAMILY LAW AND
    CONFLICT OF LAWS PROFESSORS; GAY AND LESBIAN ADVOCATES AND
    DEFENDERS; PEOPLE OF FAITH FOR EQUALITY IN VIRGINIA;
    CELEBRATION     CENTER    FOR    SPIRITUAL    LIVING;    CLARENDON
    PRESBYTERIAN      CHURCH;     COMMONWEALTH      BAPTIST    CHURCH;
    CONGREGATION OR AMI; HOPE UNITED CHURCH OF CHRIST; LITTLE
    RIVER UCC; METROPOLITAN COMMUNITY CHURCH OF NORTHERN
    VIRGINIA; MT. VERNON UNITARIAN CHURCH; ST. JAMES UCC,; ST.
    JOHN'S   UCC;    NEW   LIFE    METROPOLITAN    COMMUNITY   CHURCH;
    UNITARIAN    UNIVERSALIST     FELLOWSHIP    OF    THE   PENINSULA;
    UNITARIAN UNIVERSALIST CONGREGATION OF STERLING; UNITED
    CHURCH OF CHRIST OF FREDERICKSBURG; UNITARIAN UNIVERSALIST
    CHURCH OF LOUDOUN; ANDREW MERTZ; REV. MARIE HULM ADAM; REV.
    MARTY ANDERSON; REV ROBIN ANDERSON; REV. VERNE ARENS; RABBI
    LIA BASS; REV. JOSEPH G. BEATTIE; REV. SUE BROWNING; REV.
    JIM BUNDY; REV. MARK BYRD; REV. STEVEN C. CLUNN; REV. DR.
    JOHN COPERHAVER; RABBI GARY CREDITOR; REV. DAVID ENSIGN;
    REV.   HENRY    FAIRMAN;     RABBI   JESSE   GALLOP;    REV.   TOM
    GERSTENLAUER; REV. ROBIN H. GORSLINE; REV. TRISH HALL; REV.
    WARREN HAMMONDS; REV. JON HEASLET; REV. DOUGLAS HODGES; REV.
    PHYLLIS HUBBELL; REV. STEPHEN G. HYDE; REV. JANET JAMES;
    REV. JOHN MANWELL; REV. JAMES W. MCNEAL; REV. MARC BOSWELL;
    REV. ANDREW CLIVE MILLARD; REV. DR. MELANIE MILLER; REV.
    AMBER NEUROTH; REV. JAMES PAPILE; REV. LINDA OLSON PEEBLES;
    REV. DON PRANGE; RABBI MICHAEL RAGOZIN; RABBI BEN ROMER;
    REV. JENNIFER RYU; REV. ANYA SAMMLER−MICHAEL; REV. AMY
    SCHWARTZMAN; REV. DANNY SPEARS; REV. MARK SURIANO; REV. ROB
    VAUGHN; REV. DANIEL VELEZ−RIVERA; REV. KATE R. WALKER; REV.
    TERRYE WILLIAMS; REV. DR. KAREN−MARIE YUST,
    Amici Supporting Appellees.
    8
    No. 14-1173
    TIMOTHY B.     BOSTIC;   TONY   C.   LONDON;   CAROL   SCHALL;   MARY
    TOWNLEY,
    Plaintiffs − Appellees,
    JOANNE HARRIS; JESSICA DUFF; CHRISTY BERGHOFF; VICTORIA
    KIDD, on behalf of themselves and all others similarly
    situated,
    Intervenors,
    v.
    MICHÈLE MCQUIGG,
    Intervenor/Defendant – Appellant,
    and
    GEORGE E. SCHAEFER, III, in his official capacity as the
    Clerk of Court for Norfolk Circuit Court; JANET M. RAINEY,
    in her official capacity as State Registrar of Vital
    Records; ROBERT F. MCDONNELL, in his official capacity as
    Governor of Virginia; KENNETH T. CUCCINELLI, II, in his
    official capacity as Attorney General of Virginia,
    Defendants.
    ------------------------------------
    DAVID A. ROBINSON; ALAN J. HAWKINS; JASON S. CARROLL; NORTH
    CAROLINA   VALUES   COALITION;  LIBERTY,   LIFE,  AND   LAW
    FOUNDATION; SOCIAL SCIENCE PROFESSORS; FAMILY RESEARCH
    COUNCIL; VIRGINIA CATHOLIC CONFERENCE, LLC; CENTER FOR
    CONSTITUTIONAL   JURISPRUDENCE; STATE   OF  WEST  VIRGINIA;
    INSTITUTE FOR MARRIAGE AND PUBLIC POLICY; HELEN M. ALVARE;
    STATE OF INDIANA; STATE OF ALABAMA; STATE OF ALASKA; STATE
    OF ARIZONA; STATE OF COLORADO; STATE OF IDAHO; STATE OF
    LOUISIANA; STATE OF MONTANA; STATE OF NEBRASKA; STATE OF
    OKLAHOMA; STATE OF SOUTH CAROLINA; STATE OF SOUTH DAKOTA;
    STATE OF UTAH; STATE OF WYOMING; WALLBUILDERS, LLC; LIBERTY
    COUNSEL; AMERICAN COLLEGE OF PEDIATRICIANS; SCHOLARS OF
    9
    HISTORY AND RELATED DISCIPLINES; AMERICAN LEADERSHIP FUND;
    ROBERT P. GEORGE; SHERIF GIRGIS; RYAN T. ANDERSON; PAUL
    MCHUGH; UNITED STATES CONFERENCE OF CATHOLIC BISHOPS;
    NATIONAL ASSOCIATION OF EVANGELICALS; CHURCH OF JESUS CHRIST
    OF LATTER−DAY SAINTS; THE ETHICS & RELIGIOUS LIBERTY
    COMMISSION OF THE SOUTHERN BAPTIST CONVENTION; LUTHERAN
    CHURCH−MISSOURI SYNOD; THE BECKET FUND FOR RELIGIOUS
    LIBERTY; EAGLE FORUM EDUCATION AND LEGAL DEFENSE FUND; DAVID
    BOYLE; ROBERT OSCAR LOPEZ; CONCERNED WOMEN FOR AMERICA; THE
    FAMILY FOUNDATION OF VIRGINIA,
    Amici Supporting Appellant,
    CONSTITUTIONAL    LAW   SCHOLARS;    ASHUTOSH    BHAGWAT;    LEE
    BOLLINGER; ERWIN CHEMERINSKY; WALTER DELLINGER; MICHAEL C.
    DORF; LEE EPSTEIN; DANIEL FARBER; BARRY FRIEDMAN; MICHAEL
    JAY GERHARDT, Professor; DEBORAH HELLMAN; JOHN CALVIN
    JEFFRIES, JR.; LAWRENCE LESSIG; WILLIAM MARSHALL; FRANK
    MICHELMAN; JANE S. SCHACTER; CHRISTOPHER H. SCHROEDER;
    SUZANNA SHERRY; GEOFFREY R. STONE; DAVID STRAUSS; LAURENCE
    H. TRIBE, Professor; WILLIAM VAN ALSTYNE; OUTSERVE−SLDN; THE
    AMERICAN   MILITARY   PARTNER    ASSOCIATION;    THE   AMERICAN
    SOCIOLOGICAL   ASSOCIATION;    VIRGINIA    CONSTITUTIONAL    LAW
    PROFESSORS; AMERICAN PSYCHOLOGICAL ASSOCIATION; THE AMERICAN
    ACADEMY OF PEDIATRICS; AMERICAN PSYCHIATRIC ASSOCIATION;
    NATIONAL    ASSOCIATION    OF    SOCIAL    WORKERS;    VIRGINIA
    PSYCHOLOGICAL ASSOCIATION; EQUALITY NC; SOUTH CAROLINA
    QUALITY    COALITION;     CHANTELLE     FISHER−BORNE;     MARCIE
    FISHER−BORNE; CRYSTAL HENDRIX; LEIGH SMITH; SHANA CARIGNAN;
    MEGAN PARKER; TERRI BECK; LESLIE ZANAGLIO; LEE KNIGHT
    CAFFERY; DANA DRAA; SHAWN LONG; CRAIG JOHNSON; ESMERALDA
    MEJIA;     CHRISTINA     GINTER−MEJIA;      CATO     INSTITUTE;
    CONSTITUTIONAL    ACCOUNTABILITY    CENTER;     HISTORIANS    OF
    MARRIAGE; PETER W. BARDAGLIO; NORMA BASCH; STEPHANIE COONTZ;
    NANCY F. COTT; TOBY L. DITZ; ARIELA R. DUBLER; LAURA F.
    EDWARDS; SARAH BARRINGER GORDON; MICHAEL GROSSBERG; HENDRIK
    HARTOG; ELLEN HERMAN; MARTHA HODES; LINDA K. KERBER; ALICE
    KESSLER−HARRIS; ELAINE TYLER MAY; SERENA MAYERI; STEVEN
    MINTZ; ELIZABETH PLECK; CAROLE SHAMMAS; MARY L. SHANLEY; AMY
    DRU STANLEY; BARBARA WELKE; PARENTS, FAMILIES AND FRIENDS OF
    LESBIANS AND GAYS, INC.; KERRY ABRAMS, Albert Clark Tate,
    Jr. Professor of Law, University of Virginia School of Law;
    VIVIAN HAMILTON, Professor of Law, William and Mary;
    MEREDITH HARBACH, Professor of Law, University of Richmond;
    JOAN HEIFETZ HOLLINGER, John and Elizabeth Boalt Lecturer in
    Residence, University of California, Berkeley School of Law;
    COURTNEY G. JOSLIN, Professor of Law, University of
    10
    California, Davis School of Law; NAACP LEGAL DEFENSE AND
    EDUCATION    FUND,   INC.;    NATIONAL   ASSOCIATION   FOR    THE
    ADVANCEMENT OF COLORED PEOPLE; HOWARD UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF
    LAW CIVIL RIGHTS CLINIC; FAMILY EQUALITY COUNCIL; COLAGE;
    GLMA: HEALTH PROFESSIONALS ADVANCING LGBT EQUALITY; WILLIAM
    N. ESKRIDGE, JR.; REBECCA L. BROWN; DANIEL A. FARBER;
    MICHAEL GERHARDT; JACK KNIGHT; ANDREW KOPPELMAN; MELISSA
    LAMB SAUNDERS; NEIL S. SIEGEL; JANA B. SINGER; HISTORIANS OF
    ANTI−GAY DISCRIMINATION; ANTI−DEFAMATION LEAGUE; AMERICANS
    UNITED FOR SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE; BEND THE ARC: A
    JEWISH PARTNERSHIP FOR JUSTICE; HADASSAH, THE WOMEN'S
    ZIONIST ORGANIZATION OF AMERICA; HINDU AMERICAN FOUNDATION;
    THE   INTERFAITH    ALLIANCE   FOUNDATION;   JAPANESE   AMERICAN
    CITIZENS LEAGUE; JEWISH SOCIAL POLICY ACTION NETWORK;
    KESHET;   METROPOLITAN     COMMUNITY   CHURCHES;    MORE    LIGHT
    PRESBYTERIANS; THE NATIONAL COUNCIL OF JEWISH WOMEN;
    NEHIRIM;    PEOPLE    FOR    THE   AMERICAN    WAY   FOUNDATION;
    PRESBYTERIAN WELCOME; RECONCILINGWORKS: LUTHERANS FOR FULL
    PARTICIPATION; RELIGIOUS INSTITUTE, INC.; SIKH AMERICAN
    LEGAL DEFENSE AND EDUCATION FUND; SOCIETY FOR HUMANISTIC
    JUDAISM; T'RUAH: THE RABBINIC CALL FOR HUMAN RIGHTS; WOMEN'S
    LEAGUE FOR CONSERVATIVE JUDAISM; COLUMBIA LAW SCHOOL
    SEXUALITY AND GENDER LAW CLINIC; BISHOPS OF THE EPISCOPAL
    CHURCH IN VIRGINIA; CENTRAL ATLANTIC CONFERENCE OF THE
    UNITED CHURCH OF CHRIST; CENTRAL CONFERENCE OF AMERICAN
    RABBIS; MORMONS FOR EQUALITY; RECONSTRUCTIONIST RABBINICAL
    ASSOCIATION; RECONSTRUCTIONIST RABBINICAL COLLEGE AND JEWISH
    RECONSTRUCTIONIST COMMUNITIES; UNION FOR REFORM JUDAISM; THE
    UNITARIAN UNIVERSALIST ASSOCIATION; AFFIRMATION; COVENANT
    NETWORK OF PRESBYTERIANS; METHODIST FEDERATION FOR SOCIAL
    ACTION; MORE LIGHT PRESBYTERIANS; PRESBYTERIAN WELCOME;
    RECONCILING MINISTRIES NETWORK; RECONCILINGWORKS: LUTHERANS
    FOR FULL PARTICIPATION; RELIGIOUS INSTITUTE, INC.; WOMEN OF
    REFORM JUDAISM; 28 EMPLOYERS AND ORGANIZATIONS REPRESENTING
    EMPLOYERS;     COMMONWEALTH    OF   MASSACHUSETTS;    STATE    OF
    CALIFORNIA; STATE OF CONNECTICUT; DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA;
    STATE OF ILLINOIS; STATE OF IOWA; STATE OF MAINE; STATE OF
    MARYLAND; STATE OF NEW HAMPSHIRE; STATE OF NEW MEXICO; STATE
    OF NEW YORK; STATE OF OREGON; STATE OF VERMONT; STATE OF
    WASHINGTON; GARY J. GATES; NATIONAL AND WESTERN STATES
    WOMEN'S RIGHTS ORGANIZATIONS; VIRGINIA CHAPTER OF THE
    AMERICAN ACADEMY OF MATRIMONIAL LAWYERS; THE NATIONAL
    WOMEN'S LAW CENTER; EQUAL RIGHTS ADVOCATES; LEGAL MOMENTUM;
    NATIONAL ASSOCIATION OF WOMEN LAWYERS; NATIONAL PARTNERSHIP
    FOR WOMEN & FAMILIES; SOUTHWEST WOMEN'S LAW CENTER; WOMEN'S
    LAW PROJECT; PROFESSORS OF LAW ASSOCIATED WITH THE WILLIAMS
    INSTITUTE;    BAY   AREA   LAWYERS   FOR   INDIVIDUAL   FREEDOM;
    11
    LEADERSHIP CONFERENCE ON CIVIL AND HUMAN RIGHTS; PUBLIC
    INTEREST ORGANIZATIONS; BAR ASSOCIATIONS; FAMILY LAW AND
    CONFLICT OF LAWS PROFESSORS; GAY AND LESBIAN ADVOCATES AND
    DEFENDERS; PEOPLE OF FAITH FOR EQUALITY IN VIRGINIA;
    CELEBRATION    CENTER     FOR    SPIRITUAL    LIVING;    CLARENDON
    PRESBYTERIAN      CHURCH;     COMMONWEALTH      BAPTIST    CHURCH;
    CONGREGATION OR AMI; HOPE UNITED CHURCH OF CHRIST; LITTLE
    RIVER UCC; METROPOLITAN COMMUNITY CHURCH OF NORTHERN
    VIRGINIA; MT. VERNON UNITARIAN CHURCH; ST. JAMES UCC,; ST.
    JOHN'S   UCC;    NEW   LIFE    METROPOLITAN    COMMUNITY   CHURCH;
    UNITARIAN    UNIVERSALIST     FELLOWSHIP    OF    THE   PENINSULA;
    UNITARIAN UNIVERSALIST CONGREGATION OF STERLING; UNITED
    CHURCH OF CHRIST OF FREDERICKSBURG; UNITARIAN UNIVERSALIST
    CHURCH OF LOUDOUN; ANDREW MERTZ; REV. MARIE HULM ADAM; REV.
    MARTY ANDERSON; REV ROBIN ANDERSON; REV. VERNE ARENS; RABBI
    LIA BASS; REV. JOSEPH G. BEATTIE; REV. SUE BROWNING; REV.
    JIM BUNDY; REV. MARK BYRD; REV. STEVEN C. CLUNN; REV. DR.
    JOHN COPERHAVER; RABBI GARY CREDITOR; REV. DAVID ENSIGN;
    REV.   HENRY    FAIRMAN;    RABBI    JESSE   GALLOP;    REV.   TOM
    GERSTENLAUER; REV. ROBIN H. GORSLINE; REV. TRISH HALL; REV.
    WARREN HAMMONDS; REV. JON HEASLET; REV. DOUGLAS HODGES; REV.
    PHYLLIS HUBBELL; REV. STEPHEN G. HYDE; REV. JANET JAMES;
    REV. JOHN MANWELL; REV. JAMES W. MCNEAL; REV. MARC BOSWELL;
    REV. ANDREW CLIVE MILLARD; REV. DR. MELANIE MILLER; REV.
    AMBER NEUROTH; REV. JAMES PAPILE; REV. LINDA OLSON PEEBLES;
    REV. DON PRANGE; RABBI MICHAEL RAGOZIN; RABBI BEN ROMER;
    REV. JENNIFER RYU; REV. ANYA SAMMLER−MICHAEL; REV. AMY
    SCHWARTZMAN; REV. DANNY SPEARS; REV. MARK SURIANO; REV. ROB
    VAUGHN; REV. DANIEL VELEZ−RIVERA; REV. KATE R. WALKER; REV.
    TERRYE WILLIAMS; REV. DR. KAREN−MARIE YUST,
    Amici Supporting Appellees.
    Appeals from the United States District Court for the Eastern
    District of Virginia, at Norfolk.      Arenda L. Wright Allen,
    District Judge. (2:13-cv-00395-AWA-LRL)
    Argued:   May 13, 2014                      Decided:   July 28, 2014
    Before NIEMEYER, GREGORY, and FLOYD, Circuit Judges.
    12
    Affirmed by published opinion.   Judge Floyd wrote the majority
    opinion, in which Judge Gregory joined. Judge Niemeyer wrote a
    separate dissenting opinion.
    ARGUED: David Brandt Oakley, POOLE MAHONEY PC, Chesapeake,
    Virginia; David Austin Robert Nimocks, ALLIANCE DEFENDING
    FREEDOM, Washington, D.C., for Appellants George E. Schaefer,
    III and Michèle McQuigg. Stuart Alan Raphael, OFFICE OF THE
    ATTORNEY GENERAL OF VIRGINIA, Richmond, Virginia, for Appellant
    Janet M. Rainey.    Theodore B. Olson, GIBSON, DUNN & CRUTCHER,
    LLP, Washington, D.C., for Appellees. James D. Esseks, AMERICAN
    CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION, New York, New York, for Intervenors. ON
    BRIEF: Jeffrey F. Brooke, POOLE MAHONEY PC, Chesapeake,
    Virginia, for Appellant George E. Schaefer, III.         Byron J.
    Babione, Kenneth J. Connelly, J. Caleb Dalton, ALLIANCE
    DEFENDING FREEDOM, Scottsdale, Arizona, for Appellant Michèle B.
    McQuigg. Mark R. Herring, Attorney General, Cynthia E. Hudson,
    Chief Deputy Attorney General, Rhodes B. Ritenour, Deputy
    Attorney General, Allyson K. Tysinger, Senior Assistant Attorney
    General, Catherine Crooks Hill, Senior Assistant Attorney
    General, Trevor S. Cox, Deputy Solicitor General, OFFICE OF THE
    ATTORNEY GENERAL OF VIRGINIA, Richmond, Virginia, for Appellant
    Janet M. Rainey.     David Boies, Armonk, New York, William A.
    Isaacson,   Washington,   D.C.,   Jeremy   M.   Goldman,  Oakland,
    California, Robert Silver, Joshua I. Schiller, BOIES, SCHILLER &
    FLEXNER LLP, New York, New York; Theodore J. Boutrous, Jr.,
    Joshua S. Lipshutz, GIBSON, DUNN & CRUTCHER LLP, Los Angeles,
    California; Thomas B. Shuttleworth, Robert E. Ruloff, Charles B.
    Lustig, Andrew M. Hendrick, Erik C. Porcaro, SHUTTLEWORTH,
    RULOFF, SWAIN, HADDAD & MORECOCK, P.C., Virginia Beach,
    Virginia, for Appellees.     Rebecca K. Glenberg, AMERICAN CIVIL
    LIBERTIES   UNION   OF   VIRGINIA   FOUNDATION,   INC.,  Richmond,
    Virginia; Joshua A. Block, AMERICAN CIVIL LIBERTIES UNION
    FOUNDATION, New York, New York; Gregory R. Nevins, Tara L.
    Borelli, LAMBDA LEGAL DEFENSE AND EDUCATION FUND, INC., Atlanta,
    Georgia; Paul M. Smith, Luke C. Platzer, Mark P. Gaber, JENNER &
    BLOCK LLP, Washington, D.C., for Intervenors.            David A.
    Robinson, North Haven, Connecticut, as Amicus. Lynn D. Wardle,
    BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW SCHOOL, Provo, Utah; William C.
    Duncan, MARRIAGE LAW FOUNDATION, Lehi, Utah, for Amici Alan J.
    Hawkins and Jason S. Carroll.      Deborah J. Dewart, DEBORAH J.
    DEWART, ATTORNEY AT LAW, Swansboro, North Carolina, for Amici
    North Carolina Values Coalition and Liberty, Life, and Law
    Foundation.   Steve C. Taylor, ALLIANCE LEGAL GROUP, Chesapeake,
    Virginia, for Amicus Social Science Professors.      Paul Benjamin
    13
    Linton, Northbrook,    Illinois,   for  Amicus  Family  Research
    Council.     John C. Eastman, Anthony T. Caso, Center for
    Constitutional Jurisprudence, CHAPMAN UNIVERSITY DALE E. FOWLER
    SCHOOL OF LAW, Orange, California, for Amici Virginia Catholic
    Conference, LLC and Center for Constitutional Jurisprudence.
    Patrick Morrisey, Attorney General, Julie Marie Blake, Assistant
    Attorney General, Elbert Lin, Solicitor General, OFFICE OF THE
    WEST VIRGINIA ATTORNEY GENERAL, Charleston, West Virginia, for
    Amicus State of West Virginia.       D. John Sauer, St. Louis,
    Missouri, for Amicus Institute for Marriage and Public Policy.
    Henry P. Wall, Columbia, South Carolina, for Amicus Helen M.
    Alvare. Gregory F. Zoeller, Attorney General, Thomas M. Fisher,
    Solicitor General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL, Indianapolis,
    Indiana; Luther Strange, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE
    ATTORNEY GENERAL OF ALABAMA, Montgomery, Alabama; Michael C.
    Geraghty, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
    ALASKA, Juneau, Alaska; Thomas C. Horne, Attorney General,
    OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF ARIZONA, Phoenix, Arizona;
    John Suthers, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL
    OF COLORADO, Denver, Colorado; Lawrence G. Wasden, Attorney
    General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF IDAHO, Boise, Idaho;
    James D. "Buddy" Caldwell, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE
    ATTORNEY GENERAL OF LOUISIANA, Baton Rouge, Louisiana; Timothy
    C. Fox, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
    MONTANA, Helena, Montana; Jon Bruning, Attorney General, OFFICE
    OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF NEBRASKA, Lincoln, Nebraska; E. Scott
    Pruitt, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
    OKLAHOMA,   Oklahoma  City,   Oklahoma;  Alan  Wilson,  Attorney
    General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF SOUTH CAROLINA,
    Columbia, South Carolina; Marty J. Jackley, Attorney General,
    OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF SOUTH DAKOTA, Pierre, South
    Dakota; Sean Reyes, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY
    GENERAL OF THE STATE OF UTAH, Salt Lake City, Utah; Peter K.
    Michael, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
    WYOMING, Cheyenne, Wyoming, for Amici States of Indiana,
    Alabama, Alaska, Arizona, Colorado, Idaho, Louisiana, Montana,
    Nebraska, Oklahoma, South Carolina, South Dakota, Utah, and
    Wyoming.     Stephen M. Crampton, Mary E. McAlister, LIBERTY
    COUNSEL, Lynchburg, Virginia, for Amicus WallBuilders, LLC.
    Mathew D. Staver, Anita L. Staver, LIBERTY COUNSEL, Orlando,
    Florida, for Amici Liberty Counsel and American College of
    Pediatricians. Frank D. Mylar, MYLAR LAW, P.C., Salt Lake City,
    Utah, for Amici Scholars of History and Related Disciplines and
    American Leadership Fund. Michael F. Smith, THE SMITH APPELLATE
    LAW FIRM, Washington, D.C., for Amici Robert P. George, Sherif
    Girgis, and Ryan T. Anderson. Gerard V. Bradley, NOTRE DAME LAW
    SCHOOL, Notre Dame, Indiana; Kevin T. Snider, PACIFIC JUSTICE
    14
    INSTITUTE, Oakland, California, for Amicus Paul McHugh. Anthony
    R. Picarello, Jr., U.S. CONFERENCE OF CATHOLIC BISHOPS,
    Washington, D.C.; R. Shawn Gunnarson, KIRTON MCCONKIE, Salt Lake
    City, Utah, for Amici United States Conference of Catholic
    Bishops, National Association of Evangelicals, Church of Jesus
    Christ of Latter-Day Saints, The Ethics & Religious Liberty
    Commission of the Southern Baptist Convention, and Lutheran
    Church-Missouri Synod.      Eric Rassbach, Asma Uddin, THE BECKET
    FUND FOR RELIGIOUS LIBERTY, Washington, D.C., for Amicus The
    Becket Fund for Religious Liberty.              Lawrence J. Joseph,
    Washington, D.C. for Amicus Eagle Forum Education and Legal
    Defense Fund.     David Boyle, Long Beach, California, as Amicus.
    David Boyle, Long Beach, California, for Amicus Robert Oscar
    Lopez.    Abbe David Lowell, Christopher D. Man, CHADBOURNE &
    PARKE LLP, Washington, D.C., for Amici Outserve-SLDN and The
    American Military Partner Association.        Geoffrey R. Stone, THE
    UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO LAW SCHOOL, Chicago, Illinois; Lori Alvino
    McGill, LATHAM & WATKINS LLP, Washington, D.C., for Amici
    Constitutional Law Scholars Ashutosh Bhagwat, Lee Bollinger,
    Erwin Chemerinsky, Walter Dellinger, Michael C. Dorf, Lee
    Epstein, Daniel Farber, Barry Friedman, Michael J. Gerhardt,
    Deborah Hellman, John C. Jeffries, Jr., Lawrence Lessig, William
    Marshall, Frank Michelman, Jane S. Schacter, Christopher H.
    Schroeder, Suzanna Sherry, Geoffrey R. Stone, David Strauss,
    Laurence H. Tribe, and William Van Alstyne. Steven W. Fitschen,
    THE NATIONAL LEGAL FOUNDATION, Virginia Beach, Virginia; Holly
    L. Carmichael, San Jose, California, for Amicus Concerned Women
    for America. Carmine D. Boccuzzi, Jr., Mark A. Lightner, Andra
    Troy, Andrew P. Meiser, CLEARY GOTTLIEB STEEN & HAMILTON LLP,
    New York, New York, for Amicus The American Sociological
    Association.    L. Steven Emmert, SYKES, BOURDON, AHERN & LEVY,
    P.C.,    Virginia     Beach,   Virginia,     for    Amicus    Virginia
    Constitutional Law Professors. Nathalie F.P. Gilfoyle, AMERICAN
    PSYCHOLOGICAL ASSOCIATION, Washington, D.C.; Bruce V. Spiva, THE
    SPIVA LAW FIRM PLLC, Washington, D.C., for Amici American
    Psychological Association, American Academy of Pediatrics,
    American Psychiatric Association, National Association of Social
    Workers,    and    Virginia   Psychological    Association.        Mark
    Kleinschmidt, TIN FULTON WALKER & OWEN, Chapel Hill, North
    Carolina; Ryan T. Butler, Greensboro, North Carolina, for Amici
    Equality NC and South Carolina Equality Coalition.             Rose A.
    Saxe,   James    D.   Esseks,   AMERICAN    CIVIL    LIBERTIES    UNION
    FOUNDATION, New York, New York; Garrard R. Beeney, David A.
    Castleman,    Catherine   M.   Bradley,   W.    Rudolph   Kleysteuber,
    SULLIVAN & CROMWELL LLP, New York, New York, for Amici Marcie
    and Chantelle Fisher-Borne, Crystal Hendrix and Leigh Smith,
    Shana Carignan and Megan Parker, Terri Beck and Leslie Zanaglio,
    15
    Lee Knight Caffery and Dana Draa, Shawn Long and Craig Johnson,
    and Esmeralda Mejia and Christina Ginter-Mejia.      Elizabeth B.
    Wydra, Douglas T. Kendall, Judith E. Schaeffer, David H. Gans,
    CONSTITUTIONAL ACCOUNTABILITY CENTER, Washington, D.C.; Ilya
    Shapiro, CATO INSTITUTE, Washington, D.C., for Amici Cato
    Institute and Constitutional Accountability Center.         Daniel
    McNeel Lane, Jr., Matthew E. Pepping, San Antonio, Texas,
    Jessica M. Weisel, AKIN GUMP STRAUSS HAUER & FELD LLP, Los
    Angeles, California, for Amici Historians of Marriage Peter W.
    Bardaglio, Norma Basch, Stephanie Coontz, Nancy F. Cott, Toby L.
    Ditz, Ariela R. Dubler, Laura F. Edwards, Sarah Barringer
    Gordon, Michael Grossberg, Hendrik Hartog, Ellen Herman, Martha
    Hodes, Linda K. Kerber, Alice Kessler-Harris, Elaine Tyler May,
    Serena Mayeri, Steve Mintz, Elizabeth Pleck, Carole Shammas,
    Mary L. Shanley, Amy Dru Stanley, and Barbara Welke.         Jiyun
    Cameron Lee, Andrew J. Davis, FOLGER LEVIN LLP, San Francisco,
    California, for Amicus Parents, Families and Friends of Lesbians
    and Gays, Inc.    Rita F. Lin, Laura W. Weissbein, Sara Bartel,
    MORRISON & FOERSTER LLP, San Francisco, California, for Amici
    Kerry Abrams, Albert Clark Tate, Jr. Professor of Law University
    of Virginia School of Law, Vivian Hamilton, Professor of Law
    William and Mary, Meredith Harbach, Professor of Law University
    of Richmond, Joan Heifetz Hollinger, John and Elizabeth Boalt
    Lecturer in Residence University of California, Berkeley School
    of Law, Courtney G. Joslin, Professor of Law University of
    California, Davis School of Law, and Forty-Four Other Family Law
    Professors.   Sherrilyn Ifill, Christina A. Swarns, Ria Tabacco
    Mar, NAACP LEGAL DEFENSE & EDUCATIONAL FUND, INC., New York, New
    York; Kim M. Keenan, NAACP, Baltimore, Maryland, for Amici NAACP
    Legal Defense & Educational Fund, Inc. and National Association
    for the Advancement of Colored People.         Aderson Bellegarde
    Francois, HOWARD UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF LAW CIVIL RIGHTS CLINIC,
    Washington, D.C.; Brad W. Seiling, Benjamin G. Shatz, MANATT,
    PHELPS & PHILLIPS, LLP, Los Angeles, California, for Amicus
    Howard University School of Law Civil Rights Clinic.      Alec W.
    Farr, Washington, D.C., Tracy M. Talbot, Katherine Keating,
    BRYAN CAVE LLP, San Francisco, California, for Amici Family
    Equality Council and COLAGE. Nicholas M. O'Donnell, SULLIVAN &
    WORCESTER LLP, Boston, Massachusetts, for Amicus GLMA: Health
    Professionals Advancing LGBT Equality.    Kathleen M. O'Sullivan,
    Mica D. Simpson, PERKINS COIE LLP, Seattle, Washington, for
    Amici William N. Eskridge, Jr., Rebecca L. Brown, Daniel A.
    Farber, Michael Gerhardt, Jack Knight, Andrew Koppelman, Melissa
    Lamb Saunders, Neil S. Siegel, and Jana B. Singer. Catherine E.
    Stetson, Erica Knievel Songer, Mary Helen Wimberly, Katie D.
    Fairchild,   Madeline   H.  Gitomer,   HOGAN   LOVELLS   US   LLP,
    Washington,    D.C.,   for   Amicus    Historians    of    Antigay
    16
    Discrimination.     Rocky C. Tsai, Samuel P. Bickett, Rebecca
    Harlow, ROPES & GRAY LLP, San Francisco, California; Steven M.
    Freeman, Seth M. Marnin, Melissa Garlick, ANTI-DEFAMATION
    LEAGUE, New York, New York, for Amici Anti-Defamation League,
    Americans United for Separation of Church and State, Bend the
    Arc: A Jewish Partnership for Justice, Hadassah, The Women's
    Zionist Organization of America, Hindu American Foundation, The
    Interfaith Alliance Foundation, Japanese American Citizens
    League,   Jewish     Social     Policy   Action    Network,    Keshet,
    Metropolitan Community Churches, More Light Presbyterians, The
    National Council of Jewish Women, Nehirim, People For the
    American Way Foundation, Presbyterian Welcome, Reconcilingworks:
    Lutherans for Full Participation, Religious Institute, Inc.,
    Sikh American Legal Defense and Education Fund, Society for
    Humanistic Judaism, T'Ruah: The Rabbinic Call for Human Rights,
    and Women's League For Conservative Judaism.               Matthew P.
    McGuire, Beverlee E. Silva, Diane S. Wizig, ALSTON & BIRD LLP,
    Durham, North Carolina; Suzanne B. Goldberg, Sexuality and
    Gender Law Clinic, COLUMBIA LAW SCHOOL, New York, New York, for
    Amicus Columbia Law School Sexuality and Gender Law Clinic.
    Jeffrey S. Trachtman, Norman C. Simon, Jason M. Moff, Kurt M.
    Denk, Jessica N. Witte, KRAMER LEVIN NAFTALIS & FRANKEL LLP, New
    York, New York, for Amici Bishops of the Episcopal Church in
    Virginia, The Central Atlantic Conference of the United Church
    of Christ, Central Conference of American Rabbis, Mormons for
    Equality,       Reconstructionist       Rabbinical        Association,
    Reconstructionist        Rabbinical       College      and      Jewish
    Reconstructionist Communities, Union for Reform Judaism, The
    Unitarian    Universalist     Association,    Affirmation,    Covenant
    Network of Presbyterians, Methodist Federation for Social
    Action,   More    Light     Presbyterians,    Presbyterian    Welcome,
    Reconciling Ministries Network, Reconsilingworks: Lutherans For
    Full Participation, Religious Institute, Inc., and Women of
    Reform Judaism.      Susan Baker Manning, Michael L. Whitlock,
    Margaret E. Sheer, Jared A. Craft, Sara M. Carian, Jessica C.
    Brooks, Katherine R. Moskop, John A. Polito, Stephanie Schuster,
    BINGHAM MCCUTCHEN LLP, Washington, D.C., for Amicus 28 Employers
    and Organizations Representing Employers.            Martha Coakley,
    Attorney   General,    Jonathan    B.  Miller,    Assistant   Attorney
    General, Genevieve C. Nadeau, Assistant Attorney General,
    Michelle L. Leung, Assistant Attorney General, Frederick D.
    Augenstern, Assistant Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY
    GENERAL   OF    THE    COMMONWEALTH    OF    MASSACHUSETTS,    Boston,
    Massachusetts; Kamala D. Harris, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE
    ATTORNEY GENERAL OF CALIFORNIA, Sacramento, California; George
    Jepsen, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
    CONNECTICUT, Hartford, Connecticut; Irvin B. Nathan, Attorney
    17
    General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL FOR THE DISTRICT OF
    COLUMBIA, Washington, D.C.; Lisa Madigan, Attorney General,
    OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF ILLINOIS, Chicago, Illinois;
    Tom Miller, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
    IOWA, Des Moines, Iowa; Janet T. Mills, Attorney General, OFFICE
    OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MAINE, Augusta, Maine; Douglas F.
    Gansler, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
    MARYLAND, Baltimore, Maryland; Joseph A. Foster, Attorney
    General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF NEW HAMPSHIRE,
    Concord, New Hampshire; Gary K. King, Attorney General, OFFICE
    OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF NEW MEXICO, Santa Fe, New Mexico;
    Eric T. Schneiderman, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY
    GENERAL OF NEW YORK, New York, New York; Ellen F. Rosenblum,
    Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF OREGON,
    Salem, Oregon; William H. Sorrell, Attorney General, OFFICE OF
    THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF VERMONT, Montpelier, Vermont; Robert W.
    Ferguson, Attorney General, OFFICE OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL OF
    WASHINGTON,   Olympia,    Washington,    for   Amici  Massachusetts,
    California, Connecticut, District of Columbia, Illinois, Iowa,
    Maine, Maryland, New Hampshire, New Mexico, New York, Oregon,
    Vermont, and Washington.      Brad W. Seiling, Benjamin G. Shatz,
    MANATT, PHELPS & PHILLIPS, LLP, Los Angeles, California, for
    Amicus Gary J. Gates.        Bruce A. Wessel, Moez M. Kaba, C.
    Mitchell Hendy, Brian Eggleston, IRELL & MANELLA LLP, Los
    Angeles, California, for Amicus National and Western States
    Women's Rights Organizations.      Donald K. Butler, BATZLI STILES
    BUTLER, P.C., Richmond, Virginia; Susan M. Butler, SHOUNBACH,
    P.C., Fairfax, Virginia; Daniel L. Gray, Stephanie J. Smith,
    Kristen L. Kugel, Anne B. Robinson, COOPER GINSBERG GRAY, PLLC,
    Fairfax, Virginia, for Amicus Virginia Chapter of The American
    Academy of Matrimonial Lawyers. Marcia D. Greenberger, Emily J.
    Martin, Cortelyou C. Kenney, NATIONAL WOMEN'S LAW CENTER,
    Washington, D.C., for Amici The National Women's Law Center,
    Equal Rights Advocates, Legal Momentum, National Association of
    Women Lawyers, National Partnership for Women & Families,
    Southwest   Women's   Law    Center,   Women's   Law   Project,   and
    Professors of Law Associated with The Williams Institute.
    Jerome C. Roth, Nicole S. Phillis, MUNGER, TOLLES & OLSON LLP,
    San Francisco, California, for Amicus Bay Area Lawyers for
    Individual Freedom.    Shannon P. Minter, Christopher F. Stoll,
    Jaime Huling Delaye, NATIONAL CENTER FOR LESBIAN RIGHTS,
    Washington, D.C., for Amici Leadership Conference on Civil and
    Human   Rights,    Public     Interest    Organizations,    and   Bar
    Associations.      Joanna    L.   Grossman,   HOFSTRA   LAW   SCHOOL,
    Hempstead, New York; Marjory A. Gentry, ARNOLD & PORTER LLP, San
    Francisco, California, for Amicus Family Law and Conflict of
    Laws Professors. Mark C. Fleming, Felicia H. Ellsworth, Boston,
    18
    Massachusetts, Paul R.Q. Wolfson, Dina B. Mishra, Leah M.
    Litman, Washington,    D.C.,   Alan    Schoenfeld,  WILMER   CUTLER
    PICKERING HALE AND DORR LLP, New York, New York, for Amicus Gay
    & Lesbian Advocates & Defenders.      John Humphrey, THE HUMPHREY
    LAW FIRM, Alexandria, Virginia, for Amici People of Faith For
    Equality in Virginia (POFEV), Celebration Center for Spiritual
    Living, Clarendon Presbyterian Church, Commonwealth Baptist
    Church, Congregation or AMI, Hope United Church of Christ,
    Little River UCC, Metropolitan Community Church of Northern
    Virginia, Mt. Vernon Unitarian Church, St. James UCC, St. John's
    UCC,   New   Life   Metropolitan    Community   Church,   Unitarian
    Universalist Fellowship of the Peninsula, Unitarian Universalist
    Congregation   of   Sterling,    United   Church   of   Christ   of
    Fredericksburg, Unitarian Universalist Church of Loudoun, Rev.
    Marie Hulm Adam, Rev. Marty Anderson, Rev. Robin Anderson, Rev.
    Verne Arens, Rabbi Lia Bass, Rev. Joseph G. Beattie, Rev. Marc
    Boswell, Rev. Sue Browning, Rev. Jim Bundy, Rev. Mark Byrd, Rev.
    Steven C. Clunn, Rev. Dr. John Coperhaver, Rabbi Gary Creditor,
    Rev. David Ensign, Rev. Henry Fairman, Rabbi Jesse Gallop, Rev.
    Tom Gerstenlauer, Rev. Dr. Robin H. Gorsline, Rev. Trish Hall,
    Rev. Warren Hammonds, Rev. Jon Heaslet, Rev. Douglas Hodges,
    Rev. Phyllis Hubbell, Rev. Stephen G. Hyde, Rev. Janet James,
    Rev. John Manwell, Rev. James W. McNeal, Andrew Mertz, Rev.
    Andrew Clive Millard, Rev. Dr. Melanie Miller, Rev. Amber
    Neuroth, Rev. James Papile, Rev. Linda Olson Peebles, Rev. Don
    Prange, Rabbi Michael Ragozin, Rabbi Ben Romer, Rev. Jennifer
    Ryu, Rev. Anya Sammler-Michael, Rabbi Amy Schwartzman, Rev.
    Danny Spears, Rev. Mark Suriano, Rev. Rob Vaughn, Rev. Daniel
    Velez-Rivera, Rev. Kate R. Walker, Rev. Terrye Williams, and
    Rev. Dr. Karen-Marie Yust.
    19
    FLOYD, Circuit Judge:
    Via    various     state    statutes     and    a   state      constitutional
    amendment, Virginia prevents same-sex couples from marrying and
    refuses     to   recognize    same-sex      marriages     performed        elsewhere.
    Two       same-sex      couples     filed      suit       to        challenge     the
    constitutionality of these laws, alleging that they violate the
    Due   Process     and   Equal     Protection    Clauses        of   the    Fourteenth
    Amendment.       The district court granted the couples’ motion for
    summary judgment and enjoined Virginia from enforcing the laws.
    This appeal followed.         Because we conclude that Virginia’s same-
    sex   marriage       bans   impermissibly      infringe        on    its    citizens’
    fundamental right to marry, we affirm.
    I.
    A.
    This case concerns a series of statutory and constitutional
    mechanisms that Virginia employed to prohibit legal recognition
    for same-sex relationships in that state. 1               Virginia enacted the
    1
    Three other states in this Circuit have similar bans:
    North Carolina, N.C. Const. art. XIV, § 6; 
    N.C. Gen. Stat. §§ 51-1
    , 51-1.2; South Carolina, S.C. Const. art. XVII, § 15;
    
    S.C. Code Ann. §§ 20-1-10
    , 20-1-15; and West Virginia, 
    W. Va. Code § 48-2-603
    .    The Southern District of West Virginia has
    stayed a challenge to West Virginia’s statute pending our
    resolution of this appeal.     McGee v. Cole, No. 3:13-cv-24068
    (S.D. W. Va. June 10, 2014) (order directing stay).
    20
    first of these laws in 1975:                 Virginia Code section 20-45.2,
    which provides that “marriage between persons of the same sex is
    prohibited.”         After the Supreme Court of Hawaii took steps to
    legalize same-sex marriage in the mid-1990s, Virginia amended
    section 20-45.2 to specify that “[a]ny marriage entered into by
    persons of the same sex in another state or jurisdiction shall
    be void in all respects in Virginia and any contractual rights
    created by such marriage shall be void and unenforceable.”                        In
    2004, Virginia added civil unions and similar arrangements to
    the    list     of     prohibited      same-sex    relationships        via      the
    Affirmation of Marriage Act.           See 
    Va. Code Ann. § 20-45.3
    .
    Virginia’s      efforts   to    ban    same-sex    marriage    and     other
    legally      recognized    same-sex     relationships      culminated       in   the
    Marshall/Newman Amendment to the Virginia Constitution:
    That only a union between one man and one woman may be
    a marriage valid in or recognized by this Commonwealth
    and its political subdivisions.
    This Commonwealth and its political subdivisions shall
    not   create   or   recognize  a   legal  status   for
    relationships of unmarried individuals that intends to
    approximate the design, qualities, significance, or
    effects of marriage. Nor shall this Commonwealth or
    its political subdivisions create or recognize another
    union, partnership, or other legal status to which is
    assigned the rights, benefits, obligations, qualities,
    or effects of marriage.
    Va. Const. art. I, § 15-A.              The Virginia Constitution imposes
    two hurdles that a potential amendment must jump before becoming
    law:   the    General     Assembly    must   approve     the   amendment    in   two
    21
    separate legislative sessions, and the people must ratify it.
    Va. Const. art. XII, § 1.                    The General Assembly approved the
    Marshall/Newman Amendment in 2005 and 2006.                                In November 2006,
    Virginia’s voters ratified it by a vote of fifty-seven percent
    to    forty-three       percent.            In        the    aggregate,       Virginia    Code
    sections 20-45.2 and 20-45.3 and the Marshall/Newman Amendment
    prohibit same-sex marriage, ban other legally recognized same-
    sex     relationships,         and       render        same-sex      marriages       performed
    elsewhere legally meaningless under Virginia state law.
    B.
    Same-sex couples Timothy B. Bostic and Tony C. London and
    Carol    Schall    and       Mary    Townley          (collectively,        the    Plaintiffs)
    brought    this    lawsuit          to     challenge         the    constitutionality       of
    Virginia Code sections 20-45.2 and 20-45.3, the Marshall/Newman
    Amendment,       and    “any    other        Virginia         law    that     bars    same-sex
    marriage    or    prohibits          the    State’s         recognition       of   otherwise-
    lawful      same-sex           marriages              from         other      jurisdictions”
    (collectively,         the    Virginia       Marriage         Laws).         The     Plaintiffs
    claim that the “inability to marry or have their relationship
    recognized by the Commonwealth of Virginia with the dignity and
    respect accorded to married opposite-sex couples has caused them
    significant hardship . . . and severe humiliation, emotional
    distress, pain, suffering, psychological harm, and stigma.”
    22
    Bostic    and    London      have    been         in    a    long-term,       committed
    relationship with each other since 1989 and have lived together
    for more than twenty years.                 They “desire to marry each other
    under the laws of the Commonwealth in order to publicly announce
    their    commitment      to     one    another        and      to     enjoy    the     rights,
    privileges, and protections that the State confers on married
    couples.”        On July 1, 2013, Bostic and London applied for a
    marriage license from the Clerk for the Circuit Court for the
    City of Norfolk.             The Clerk denied their application because
    they are both men.
    Schall and Townley are women who have been a couple since
    1985    and    have    lived   together         as   a    family      for     nearly      thirty
    years.        They were lawfully married in California in 2008.                               In
    1998,    Townley      gave    birth    to   the      couple’s         daughter,      E.   S.-T.
    Schall    and    Townley      identify      a   host      of       consequences      of    their
    inability       to    marry    in     Virginia       and       Virginia’s       refusal      to
    recognize their California marriage, including the following:
    •    Schall could not visit Townley in the hospital for several
    hours when Townley was admitted due to pregnancy-related
    complications.
    •    Schall cannot legally adopt E. S.-T., which forced her to
    retain an attorney to petition for full joint legal and
    physical custody.
    23
    •   Virginia will not list both Schall and Townley as E. S.-
    T.’s parents on her birth certificate.
    •   Until February 2013, Schall and Townley could not cover one
    another    on    their     employer-provided            health       insurance.
    Townley   has   been   able     to   cover     Schall    on    her   insurance
    since then, but, unlike an opposite-sex spouse, Schall must
    pay state income taxes on the benefits she receives.
    •   Schall and Townley must pay state taxes on benefits paid
    pursuant to employee benefits plans in the event of one of
    their deaths.
    •   Schall    and   Townley    cannot       file   joint     state   income    tax
    returns, which has cost them thousands of dollars.
    On July 18, 2013, Bostic and London sued former Governor
    Robert     F.   McDonnell,      former        Attorney     General     Kenneth    T.
    Cuccinelli,     and   George     E.   Schaefer,       III,     in    his    official
    capacity as the Clerk for the Circuit Court for the City of
    Norfolk.     The Plaintiffs filed their First Amended Complaint on
    September 3, 2013.      The First Amended Complaint added Schall and
    Townley    as   plaintiffs,     removed        McDonnell      and   Cuccinelli    as
    defendants, and added Janet M. Rainey as a defendant in her
    official capacity as the State Registrar of Vital Records.                       The
    Plaintiffs allege that the Virginia Marriage Laws are facially
    invalid under the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses of
    24
    the Fourteenth Amendment and that Schaefer and Rainey violated
    
    42 U.S.C. § 1983
     by enforcing those laws.
    The parties filed cross-motions for summary judgment. The
    Plaintiffs also requested a permanent injunction in connection
    with   their     motion     for    summary    judgment         and   moved,    in     the
    alternative, for a preliminary injunction in the event that the
    district court denied their motion for summary judgment.                              The
    district court granted a motion by Michèle McQuigg—the Prince
    William County Clerk of Court—to intervene as a defendant on
    January 21, 2014.           Two days later, new Attorney General Mark
    Herring—as       Rainey’s     counsel—submitted           a     formal     change     in
    position   and     refused    to     defend   the    Virginia        Marriage       Laws,
    although Virginia continues to enforce them.                         McQuigg adopted
    Rainey’s prior motion for summary judgment and the briefs in
    support of that motion.
    The district court held that the Virginia Marriage Laws
    were unconstitutional on February 14, 2014.                      Bostic v. Rainey,
    
    970 F. Supp. 2d 456
    , 483 (E.D. Va. 2014).                      It therefore denied
    Schaefer’s       and   McQuigg’s      motions   for       summary        judgment     and
    granted    the     Plaintiffs’      motion.         The       district    court     also
    enjoined       Virginia’s         employees—including           Rainey      and      her
    employees—and Schaefer, McQuigg, and their officers, agents, and
    employees from enforcing the Virginia Marriage Laws.                            
    Id.
     at
    25
    484.    The court stayed the injunction pending our resolution of
    this appeal.      
    Id.
    Rainey, Schaefer, and McQuigg timely appealed the district
    court’s decision.         We have jurisdiction pursuant to 
    28 U.S.C. § 1291
    .      On   March   10,    2014,    we     allowed     the    plaintiffs    from
    Harris v. Rainey—a similar case pending before Judge Michael
    Urbanski     in   the   Western    District          of   Virginia—to     intervene.
    Judge Urbanski had previously certified that case as a class
    action on behalf of “all same-sex couples in Virginia who have
    not married in another jurisdiction” and “all same-sex couples
    in Virginia who have married in another jurisdiction,” excluding
    the    Plaintiffs.      Harris    v.   Rainey,        No.   5:13-cv-077,      
    2014 WL 352188
    , at *1, 12 (W.D. Va. Jan. 31, 2014).
    Our analysis proceeds in three steps.                    First, we consider
    whether the Plaintiffs possess standing to bring their claims.
    Second,      we   evaluate      whether        the    Supreme      Court’s    summary
    dismissal of a similar lawsuit in Baker v. Nelson, 
    409 U.S. 810
    (1972) (mem.), remains binding.                Third, we determine which level
    of constitutional scrutiny applies here and test the Virginia
    Marriage Laws using the appropriate standard.                       For purposes of
    this opinion, we adopt the terminology the district court used
    to describe the parties in this case.                     The Plaintiffs, Rainey,
    and    the   Harris     class    are   the      “Opponents”        of   the   Virginia
    Marriage Laws.       Schaefer and McQuigg are the “Proponents.”
    26
    II.
    Before we turn to the merits of the parties’ arguments in
    this case, we consider Schaefer’s contention that “[t]he trial
    court erred as a matter of law when it found all Plaintiffs had
    standing and asserted claims against all Defendants.”                            We review
    the district court’s disposition of cross-motions for summary
    judgment—including        its        determinations         regarding       standing—de
    novo, viewing the facts in the light most favorable to the non-
    moving party.         Libertarian Party of Va. v. Judd, 
    718 F.3d 308
    ,
    313 (4th Cir. 2013); Covenant Media of S.C., LLC v. City of N.
    Charleston,     
    493 F.3d 421
    ,    427-28      (4th    Cir.     2007).           Summary
    judgment is appropriate when “there is no genuine dispute as to
    any material fact and the movant is entitled to judgment as a
    matter of law.”         Libertarian Party of Va., 718 F.3d at 313-14
    (quoting Fed. R. Civ. P. 56(a)).
    To     establish          standing       under        Article        III        of   the
    Constitution, a plaintiff must “allege (1) an injury that is
    (2) fairly      traceable       to     the    defendant’s         allegedly          unlawful
    conduct and that is (3) likely to be redressed by the requested
    relief.”      Lujan v. Defenders of Wildlife, 
    504 U.S. 555
    , 590
    (1992)    (quoting      Allen    v.    Wright,      
    468 U.S. 737
    ,     751       (1984))
    (internal quotation marks omitted).                      The standing requirement
    applies    to    each     claim       that     a   plaintiff       seeks        to    press.
    DaimlerChrysler        Corp.     v.    Cuno,       
    547 U.S. 332
    ,    352       (2006).
    27
    Schaefer premises his argument that the Plaintiffs lack standing
    to bring their claims on the idea that every plaintiff must have
    standing as to every defendant.                 However, the Supreme Court has
    made it clear that “the presence of one party with standing is
    sufficient      to     satisfy        Article       III’s    case-or-controversy
    requirement.”         Rumsfeld v. Forum for Academic & Institutional
    Rights, Inc., 
    547 U.S. 47
    , 52 n.2 (2006); see also Dep’t of
    Commerce v. U.S. House of Representatives, 
    525 U.S. 316
    , 330
    (1999) (holding that a case is justiciable if some, but not
    necessarily     all,    of     the    plaintiffs      have   standing       as    to   a
    particular    defendant);         Vill.    of    Arlington    Heights       v.   Metro.
    Housing Dev. Corp., 
    429 U.S. 252
    , 263-64 (1977) (same).                            The
    Plaintiffs’    claims       can   therefore       survive    Schaefer’s      standing
    challenge     as     long    as      one   couple     satisfies    the       standing
    requirements with respect to each defendant.
    Schaefer serves as the Clerk for the Circuit Court for the
    City    of   Norfolk.        In      Virginia,     circuit    court     clerks     are
    responsible for issuing marriage licenses and filing records of
    marriage.      
    Va. Code Ann. §§ 20-14
    , 32.1-267.                  Although Schall
    and Townley did not seek a marriage license from Schaefer, the
    district court found that Bostic and London did so and that
    Schaefer     denied    their      request       because   they   are    a    same-sex
    28
    couple. 2   Bostic, 970 F. Supp. 2d at 462, 467.                   This license
    denial   constitutes   an   injury   for   standing       purposes.      See   S.
    Blasting Servs., Inc. v. Wilkes Cnty., 
    288 F.3d 584
    , 595 (4th
    Cir. 2002) (explaining that the plaintiffs had not suffered an
    injury because they had not applied for, or been denied, the
    permit in question); Scott v. Greenville Cnty., 
    716 F.2d 1409
    ,
    1414-15 & n.6 (4th Cir. 1983) (holding that denial of building
    permit constituted an injury).       Bostic and London can trace this
    denial      to   Schaefer’s      enforcement         of      the      allegedly
    unconstitutional   Virginia    Marriage    Laws, 3    and    declaring    those
    2
    Schaefer contends that Schall and Townley cannot bring a
    § 1983 claim against him for the same reason: he did not commit
    any act or omission that harmed them.      To bring a successful
    § 1983   claim,   a  plaintiff  must  show   that  “the  alleged
    infringement of federal rights [is] ‘fairly attributable to the
    state[.]’”    Rendell-Baker v. Kohn, 
    457 U.S. 830
    , 838 (1982)
    (quoting Lugar v. Edmondson Oil Co., 
    457 U.S. 922
    , 937 (1982)).
    Schaefer’s action in denying Bostic and London’s application for
    a marriage license is clearly attributable to the state.     The
    district court could therefore entertain a § 1983 claim against
    Schaefer without ascertaining whether he committed any action
    with respect to Schall and Townley.
    3
    For this reason, and contrary to Schaefer’s assertions,
    Schaefer is also a proper defendant under Ex parte Young, 
    209 U.S. 123
     (1908).     Pursuant to Ex parte Young, the Eleventh
    Amendment does not bar a citizen from suing a state officer to
    enjoin the enforcement of an unconstitutional law when the
    officer has “some connection with the enforcement of the act.”
    Lytle v. Griffith, 
    240 F.3d 404
    , 412 (4th Cir. 2001) (emphasis
    omitted) (quoting Ex parte Young, 
    209 U.S. at 157
    ).   Schaefer
    bears the requisite connection to the enforcement of the
    Virginia Marriage Laws due to his role in granting and denying
    applications for marriage licenses.
    29
    laws    unconstitutional            and    enjoining          their    enforcement       would
    redress    Bostic       and        London’s     injuries.             Bostic    and   London
    therefore possess Article III standing with respect to Schaefer.
    We consequently need not consider whether Schall and Townley
    have standing to sue Schaefer.                     See Horne v. Flores, 
    557 U.S. 433
    ,    446-47    (2009)          (declining       to   analyze       whether    additional
    plaintiffs had standing when one plaintiff did).
    Rainey—as    the       Registrar       of    Vital      Records—is       tasked    with
    developing       Virginia’s         marriage       license      application       form    and
    distributing it to the circuit court clerks throughout Virginia.
    
    Va. Code Ann. §§ 32.1-252
    (A)(9),            32.1-267(E).            Neither
    Schaefer’s nor Rainey’s response to the First Amended Complaint
    disputes its description of Rainey’s duties:
    Defendant    Rainey   is   responsible   for    ensuring
    compliance with the Commonwealth’s laws relating to
    marriage   in   general  and,  more   specifically,   is
    responsible for enforcement of the specific provisions
    at issue in this Amended Complaint, namely those laws
    that limit marriage to opposite-sex couples and that
    refuse to honor the benefits of same-sex marriages
    lawfully entered into in other states.
    In    addition     to    performing         these       marriage-related         functions,
    Rainey    develops           and     distributes          birth       certificate     forms,
    oversees the rules relating to birth certificates, and furnishes
    forms    relating       to    adoption     so      that    Virginia      can    collect    the
    information       necessary         to    prepare       the    adopted     child’s       birth
    30
    certificate.        
    Id.
     §§ 32.1-252(A)(2)-(3), (9), 32.1-257, 32.1-
    261(A)(1), 32.1-262, 32.1-269.
    Rainey’s      promulgation     of    a     marriage   license   application
    form that does not allow same-sex couples to obtain marriage
    licenses resulted in Schaefer’s denial of Bostic and London’s
    marriage license request.           For the reasons we describe above,
    this license denial constitutes an injury.                   Bostic and London
    can trace this injury to Rainey due to her role in developing
    the marriage license application form in compliance with the
    Virginia Marriage Laws, and the relief they seek would redress
    their injuries.       Bostic and London consequently have standing to
    sue Rainey.
    Schall and Townley also possess standing to bring their
    claims against Rainey.           They satisfy the injury requirement in
    two ways.        First, in equal protection cases—such as this case—
    “[w]hen    the    government     erects    a    barrier    that   makes    it    more
    difficult for members of one group to obtain a benefit than it
    is for members of another group, . . . . [t]he ‘injury in fact’
    . . . is    the    denial   of    equal        treatment   resulting      from    the
    imposition of the barrier[.]”              Ne. Fla. Chapter of Associated
    Gen. Contractors of Am. v. City of Jacksonville, 
    508 U.S. 656
    ,
    666 (1993).        The Virginia Marriage Laws erect such a barrier,
    which prevents same-sex couples from obtaining the emotional,
    social, and financial benefits that opposite-sex couples realize
    31
    upon marriage.       Second, Schall and Townley allege that they have
    suffered     stigmatic    injuries      due    to    their     inability       to   get
    married in Virginia and Virginia’s refusal to recognize their
    California        marriage.         Stigmatic         injury        stemming        from
    discriminatory      treatment      is   sufficient        to   satisfy     standing’s
    injury requirement if the plaintiff identifies “some concrete
    interest   with     respect   to    which     [he    or    she]    [is]    personally
    subject to discriminatory treatment” and “[t]hat interest . . .
    independently satisf[ies] the causation requirement of standing
    doctrine.”        Allen, 
    468 U.S. at
    757 n.22, abrogated on other
    grounds by Lexmark Int’l, Inc. v. Static Control Components, 
    134 S. Ct. 1377
        (2014).      Schall      and     Townley     point     to   several
    concrete ways in which the Virginia Marriage Laws have resulted
    in   discriminatory      treatment.       For     example,        they    allege    that
    their marital status has hindered Schall from visiting Townley
    in the hospital, prevented Schall from adopting E. S.-T., 4 and
    subjected Schall and Townley to tax burdens from which married
    opposite-sex couples are exempt.                  Because Schall and Townley
    highlight specific, concrete instances of discrimination rather
    4
    Virginia does not explicitly prohibit same-sex couples
    from adopting children.     The Virginia Marriage Laws impose a
    functional ban on adoption by same-sex couples because the
    Virginia   Code  allows   only   married  couples  or  unmarried
    individuals to adopt children. 
    Va. Code Ann. § 63.2-1232
    (A)(6).
    32
    than making abstract allegations, their stigmatic injuries are
    legally cognizable.
    Schall    and    Townley’s       injuries      are   traceable     to   Rainey’s
    enforcement of the Virginia Marriage Laws.                      Because declaring
    the Virginia Marriage Laws unconstitutional and enjoining their
    enforcement would redress Schall and Townley’s injuries, they
    satisfy standing doctrine’s three requirements with respect to
    Rainey.     In sum, each of the Plaintiffs has standing as to at
    least one defendant.
    III.
    Having     resolved       the     threshold      issue     of     whether     the
    Plaintiffs have standing to sue Schaefer and Rainey, we now turn
    to the merits of the Opponents’ Fourteenth Amendment arguments.
    We begin with the issue of whether the Supreme Court’s summary
    dismissal in Baker v. Nelson settles this case.                       Baker came to
    the Supreme Court as an appeal from a Minnesota Supreme Court
    decision,     which    held    that    a    state     statute    that    the     court
    interpreted     to    bar     same-sex     marriages      did   not    violate    the
    Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process or Equal Protection Clauses.
    Baker v. Nelson, 
    191 N.W.2d 185
    , 187 (Minn. 1971).                     At the time,
    
    28 U.S.C. § 1257
     required the Supreme Court to accept appeals of
    state supreme court cases involving constitutional challenges to
    state statutes, such as Baker.                  See Hicks v. Miranda, 
    422 U.S. 33
    332, 344 (1975).         The Court dismissed the appeal in a one-
    sentence opinion “for want of a substantial federal question.”
    Baker, 
    409 U.S. 810
    .
    Summary dismissals qualify as “votes on the merits of a
    case.”      Hicks, 422 U.S. at 344 (quoting Ohio ex rel. Eaton v.
    Price,   
    360 U.S. 246
    ,    247     (1959))      (internal       quotation     marks
    omitted).      They therefore “prevent lower courts from coming to
    opposite     conclusions      on      the    precise       issues     presented      and
    necessarily    decided.”        Mandel       v.   Bradley,    
    432 U.S. 173
    ,    176
    (1977) (per curiam).          However, the fact that Baker and the case
    at   hand    address   the    same     precise       issues    does    not   end     our
    inquiry.       Summary   dismissals         lose     their    binding    force      when
    “doctrinal developments” illustrate that the Supreme Court no
    longer views a question as unsubstantial, regardless of whether
    the Court explicitly overrules the case.                   Hicks, 422 U.S. at 344
    (quoting Port Auth. Bondholders Protective Comm. v. Port of N.Y.
    Auth., 
    387 F.2d 259
    , 263 n.3 (2d Cir. 1967)) (internal quotation
    marks omitted).        The district court determined that doctrinal
    developments stripped Baker of its status as binding precedent.
    Bostic, 970 F. Supp. 2d at 469-70.                     Every federal court to
    consider     this   issue     since    the       Supreme   Court    decided     United
    States v. Windsor, 
    133 S. Ct. 2675
     (2013), has reached the same
    conclusion.     See Bishop v. Smith, Nos. 14-5003, 14-5006, 
    2014 WL 3537847
    , at *6-7 (10th Cir. July 18, 2014); Kitchen v. Herbert,
    34
    No.   13-4178,     
    2014 WL 2868044
    ,    at    *7-10    (10th    Cir.       June   25,
    2014); Love v. Beshear, No. 3:13-cv-750-H, 
    2014 WL 2957671
    , *2-3
    (W.D. Ky. July 1, 2014); Baskin v. Bogan, Nos. 1:14-cv-00355-
    RLY-TAB, 1:14-cv-00404-RLY-TAB, 
    2014 WL 2884868
    , at *4-6 (S.D.
    Ind. June 25, 2014); Wolf v. Walker, No. 14-cv-64-bbc, 
    2014 WL 2558444
    , at *4-6 (W.D. Wis. June 6, 2014); Whitewood v. Wolf,
    No. 1:13-cv-1861, 
    2014 WL 2058105
    , at *5-6 (M.D. Pa. May 20,
    2014);    Geiger    v.    Kitzhaber,      Nos.   6:13-cv-01834-MC,            6:13-cv-
    02256-MC, 
    2014 WL 2054264
    , at *1 n.1 (D. Or. May 19, 2014);
    Latta v. Otter, No. 1:13-cv-00482-CWD, 
    2014 WL 1909999
    , at *8-9
    (D. Idaho May 13, 2014); DeBoer v. Snyder, 
    973 F. Supp. 2d 757
    ,
    773 n.6 (E.D. Mich. 2014); De Leon v. Perry, 
    975 F. Supp. 2d 632
    , 647-49 (W.D. Tex. 2014); McGee v. Cole, No. 3:13-24068,
    
    2014 WL 321122
    , at *8-10 (S.D. W. Va. Jan. 29, 2014).
    Windsor concerned whether section 3 of the federal Defense
    of    Marriage     Act    (DOMA)   contravened      the    Constitution’s            due
    process   and    equal    protection      guarantees.       Section       3    defined
    “marriage” and “spouse” as excluding same-sex couples when those
    terms appeared in federal statutes, regulations, and directives,
    rendering legally married same-sex couples ineligible for myriad
    federal benefits.         
    133 S. Ct. at 2683, 2694
    .               When it decided
    the case below, the Second Circuit concluded that Baker was no
    longer precedential, Windsor v. United States, 
    699 F.3d 169
    ,
    178-79 (2d Cir. 2012), over the dissent’s vigorous arguments to
    35
    the contrary, see 
    id. at 192-95
     (Straub, J., dissenting in part
    and   concurring       in    part).    Despite          this    dispute,     the   Supreme
    Court     did    not   discuss     Baker     in     its    opinion      or   during      oral
    argument. 5
    The Supreme Court’s willingness to decide Windsor without
    mentioning Baker speaks volumes regarding whether Baker remains
    good law.        The Court’s development of its due process and equal
    protection jurisprudence in the four decades following Baker is
    even more instructive.              On the Due Process front, Lawrence v.
    Texas,     
    539 U.S. 558
        (2003),        and   Windsor      are     particularly
    relevant.         In   Lawrence,      the    Court        recognized       that    the    Due
    Process Clauses of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments “afford
    constitutional         protection     to     personal       decisions        relating      to
    marriage,        procreation,       contraception,             family      relationships,
    child rearing, and education. . . . Persons in a homosexual
    relationship       may      seek   autonomy       for     these   purposes,        just    as
    5
    The constitutionality of a law that prohibited marriage
    from encompassing same-sex relationships was also at issue in
    Hollingsworth v. Perry, 
    133 S. Ct. 2652
     (2013), a case that the
    Supreme Court ultimately decided on standing grounds.   Although
    the petitioners’ attorney attempted to invoke Baker during oral
    argument, Justice Ginsburg interjected:     “Baker v. Nelson was
    1971.   The Supreme Court hadn’t even decided that gender-based
    classifications get any kind of heightened scrutiny. . . .
    [S]ame-sex intimate conduct was considered criminal in many
    states in 1971, so I don’t think we can extract much in Baker v.
    Nelson.” Oral Argument at 11:33, Hollingsworth v. Perry, 
    133 S. Ct. 2652
     (No. 12-144), available at 
    2013 WL 1212745
    .
    36
    heterosexual persons do.”             
    Id. at 574
    .             These considerations led
    the Court to strike down a Texas statute that criminalized same-
    sex sodomy.        
    Id. at 563, 578-79
    .               The Windsor Court based its
    decision     to    invalidate         section       3     of        DOMA     on   the        Fifth
    Amendment’s       Due    Process      Clause.           The     Court       concluded        that
    section 3 could not withstand constitutional scrutiny because
    “the principal purpose and the necessary effect of [section 3]
    are    to   demean      those   persons    who          are    in     a    lawful     same-sex
    marriage,” who—like the unmarried same-sex couple in Lawrence—
    have a constitutional right to make “moral and sexual choices.”
    133 S. Ct. at 2694-95.                These cases firmly position same-sex
    relationships        within     the   ambit     of      the     Due        Process    Clauses’
    protection.
    The Court has also issued several major equal protection
    decisions since it decided Baker.                The Court’s opinions in Craig
    v. Boren, 
    429 U.S. 190
     (1976), and Frontiero v. Richardson, 
    411 U.S. 677
     (1973), identified sex-based classifications as quasi-
    suspect, causing them to warrant intermediate scrutiny rather
    than    rational        basis   review,       see       Craig,        
    429 U.S. at 218
    (Rehnquist,       J.,    dissenting)      (coining            the    term     “intermediate
    level scrutiny” to describe the Court’s test (internal quotation
    marks   omitted)).        Two   decades    later,         in    Romer        v.   Evans,       the
    Supreme Court struck down a Colorado constitutional amendment
    that    prohibited       legislative,      executive,            and       judicial      action
    37
    aimed at protecting gay, lesbian, and bisexual individuals from
    discrimination.         
    517 U.S. 620
    ,    624,     635   (1996).        The   Court
    concluded that the law violated the Fourteenth Amendment’s Equal
    Protection Clause because “its sheer breadth is so discontinuous
    with   the    reasons    offered      for     it   that      the    amendment     seems
    inexplicable     by     anything      but     animus      toward     the    class   it
    affects,” causing the law to “lack[] a rational relationship to
    legitimate state interests.”            
    Id. at 632
    .          Finally, the Supreme
    Court couched its decision in Windsor in both due process and
    equal protection terms.          133 S. Ct. at 2693, 2695.                 These cases
    demonstrate     that,    since       Baker,    the     Court       has   meaningfully
    altered the way it views both sex and sexual orientation through
    the equal protection lens.
    In light of the Supreme Court’s apparent abandonment of
    Baker and the significant doctrinal developments that occurred
    after the Court issued its summary dismissal in that case, we
    decline to view Baker as binding precedent and proceed to the
    meat of the Opponents’ Fourteenth Amendment arguments.
    IV.
    A.
    Our analysis of the Opponents’ Fourteenth Amendment claims
    has    two   components.         First,       we   ascertain        what    level   of
    constitutional scrutiny applies:               either rational basis review
    38
    or some form of heightened scrutiny, such as strict scrutiny.
    Second, we apply the appropriate level of scrutiny to determine
    whether the Virginia Marriage Laws pass constitutional muster.
    Under both the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses,
    interference with a fundamental right warrants the application
    of strict scrutiny. 6         Washington v. Glucksberg, 
    521 U.S. 702
    ,
    719-20 (1997); Zablocki v. Redhail, 
    434 U.S. 374
    , 383 (1978).
    We therefore begin by assessing whether the Virginia Marriage
    Laws infringe on a fundamental right.           Fundamental rights spring
    from       the   Fourteenth   Amendment’s     protection      of     individual
    liberty, which the Supreme Court has described as “the right to
    define      one’s   own   concept   of   existence,   of    meaning,    of   the
    universe, and of the mystery of human life.”               Planned Parenthood
    of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
    , 851 (1992).                     This liberty
    includes the fundamental right to marry.              Zablocki, 
    434 U.S. at 383
    ; Loving v. Virginia, 
    388 U.S. 1
    , 12 (1967); see Griswold v.
    6
    The Equal Protection Clause also dictates that some form
    of heightened scrutiny applies when a law discriminates based on
    a suspect or quasi-suspect classification, such as race or
    gender. See City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 
    473 U.S. 432
    , 440-41 (1985); Mass. Bd. of Ret. v. Murgia, 
    427 U.S. 307
    ,
    313-14 (1976) (per curiam).    This Court previously declined to
    recognize sexual orientation as a suspect classification in
    Thomasson v. Perry, 
    80 F.3d 915
    , 928 (4th Cir. 1996) (en banc),
    and Veney v. Wyche, 
    293 F.3d 726
    , 731-32 (4th Cir. 2002).
    Because we conclude that the Virginia Marriage Laws warrant
    strict scrutiny due to their infringement of the fundamental
    right to marry, we need not reach the question of whether
    Thomasson and Veney remain good law.
    39
    Connecticut, 
    381 U.S. 479
    , 485-86 (1965) (placing the right to
    marry within the fundamental right to privacy); see also Skinner
    v.   Oklahoma      ex    rel.        Williamson,        
    316 U.S. 535
    ,     541    (1942)
    (characterizing marriage as “one of the basic civil rights of
    man”);      Maynard     v.     Hill,    
    125 U.S. 190
    ,    205    (1888)        (calling
    marriage      “the      most     important         relation      in     life”    and     “the
    foundation of the family and of society, without which there
    would be neither civilization nor progress”).
    The   Opponents         and    Proponents        agree    that    marriage        is   a
    fundamental right.             They strongly disagree, however, regarding
    whether that right encompasses the right to same-sex marriage.
    The Opponents argue that the fundamental right to marry belongs
    to the individual, who enjoys the right to marry the person of
    his or her choice.             By contrast, the Proponents point out that,
    traditionally, states have sanctioned only man-woman marriages.
    They contend that, in light of this history, the right to marry
    does not include a right to same-sex marriage.
    Relying on Washington v. Glucksberg, the Proponents aver
    that   the    district         court    erred      by    not    requiring       “a    careful
    description of the asserted fundamental liberty interest,” 
    521 U.S. at 721
         (internal        quotation      marks      omitted),       which    they
    characterize as the right to “marriage to another person of the
    same sex,” not the right to marry.                       In Glucksberg, the Supreme
    Court described the right at issue as “a right to commit suicide
    40
    with another’s assistance.”           
    Id. at 724
    .       The Court declined to
    categorize this right as a new fundamental right because it was
    not, “objectively, deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and
    tradition.”        See 
    id. at 720-21
     (quoting Moore v. City of E.
    Cleveland, 
    431 U.S. 494
    , 503 (1977)) (internal quotation marks
    omitted).     The Proponents urge us to reject the right to same-
    sex marriage for the same reason.
    We do not dispute that states have refused to permit same-
    sex marriages for most of our country’s history.                    However, this
    fact is irrelevant in this case because Glucksberg’s analysis
    applies    only     when   courts    consider      whether   to   recognize    new
    fundamental rights.         See id. at 720, 727 & n.19 (identifying the
    above     process     as   a   way    of     “expand[ing]     the    concept    of
    substantive due process” beyond established fundamental rights,
    such as the right to marry (quoting Collins v. City of Harker
    Heights, 
    503 U.S. 115
    , 125 (1992)) (internal quotation marks
    omitted)).        Because we conclude that the fundamental right to
    marry encompasses the right to same-sex marriage, Glucksberg’s
    analysis is inapplicable here.
    Over the decades, the Supreme Court has demonstrated that
    the right to marry is an expansive liberty interest that may
    stretch to accommodate changing societal norms.                     Perhaps most
    notably, in Loving v. Virginia, the Supreme Court invalidated a
    Virginia    law     that   prohibited      white   individuals    from   marrying
    41
    individuals of other races.                
    388 U.S. at 4
    .             The Court explained
    that “[t]he freedom to marry has long been recognized as one of
    the vital personal rights essential to the orderly pursuit of
    happiness by free men” and that no valid basis justified the
    Virginia     law’s     infringement           of       that     right.         
    Id. at 12
    .
    Subsequently,        in       Zablocki      v.        Redhail,       the    Supreme         Court
    considered    the     constitutionality               of   a   Wisconsin       statute       that
    required people obligated to pay child support to obtain a court
    order granting permission to marry before they could receive a
    marriage    license.           
    434 U.S. at 375, 383-84
    .        The     statute
    specified     that        a    court      should        grant        permission       only    to
    applicants who proved that they had complied with their child
    support obligations and demonstrated that their children were
    not likely to become “public charges.”                           
    Id. at 375
     (internal
    quotation    marks        omitted).         The       Court    held     that   the     statute
    impermissibly infringed on the right to marry.                             See 
    id.
     at 390-
    91.   Finally, in Turner v. Safley, the Court determined that a
    Missouri    regulation         that       generally        prohibited      prison      inmates
    from marrying was an unconstitutional breach of the right to
    marry.   
    482 U.S. 78
    , 82, 94-99 (1987).
    These cases do not define the rights in question as “the
    right to interracial marriage,” “the right of people owing child
    support to marry,” and “the right of prison inmates to marry.”
    Instead,    they     speak      of    a    broad      right     to    marry    that    is     not
    42
    circumscribed based on the characteristics of the individuals
    seeking       to    exercise          that     right.             The     Supreme          Court’s
    unwillingness        to    constrain         the        right     to     marry      to    certain
    subspecies of marriage meshes with its conclusion that the right
    to marry is a matter of “freedom of choice,” Zablocki, 
    434 U.S. at 387
    , that “resides with the individual,” Loving, 
    388 U.S. at 12
    .     If courts limited the right to marry to certain couplings,
    they    would      effectively         create       a    list     of     legally         preferred
    spouses, rendering the choice of whom to marry a hollow choice
    indeed.
    The Proponents point out that Loving, Zablocki, and Turner
    each involved opposite-sex couples.                       They contend that, because
    the     couples     in     those       cases        chose       to     enter     opposite-sex
    marriages, we cannot use them to conclude that the Supreme Court
    would grant the same level of constitutional protection to the
    choice to marry a person of the same sex.                              However, the Supreme
    Court’s decisions in Lawrence and Windsor suggest otherwise.                                    In
    Lawrence, the Court expressly refused to narrowly define the
    right    at    issue      as    the    right       of    “homosexuals          to    engage    in
    sodomy,” concluding that doing so would constitute a “failure to
    appreciate the extent of the liberty at stake.”                                  
    539 U.S. at 566-67
    .       Just as it has done in the right-to-marry arena, the
    Court identified the right at issue in Lawrence as a matter of
    choice,    explaining          that    gay   and        lesbian      individuals—like          all
    43
    people—enjoy         the     right    to     make       decisions        regarding         their
    personal relationships.               
    Id. at 567
    .                 As we note above, the
    Court reiterated this theme in Windsor, in which it based its
    conclusion that section 3 of DOMA was unconstitutional, in part,
    on     that    provision’s         disrespect       for      the     “moral       and     sexual
    choices” that accompany a same-sex couple’s decision to marry.
    133 S. Ct. at 2694.                 Lawrence and Windsor indicate that the
    choices       that   individuals        make       in     the      context       of     same-sex
    relationships enjoy the same constitutional protection as the
    choices accompanying opposite-sex relationships.                                 We therefore
    have no reason to suspect that the Supreme Court would accord
    the choice to marry someone of the same sex any less respect
    than the choice to marry an opposite-sex individual who is of a
    different       race,        owes     child        support,         or     is     imprisoned.
    Accordingly,         we      decline        the      Proponents’           invitation          to
    characterize the right at issue in this case as the right to
    same-sex marriage rather than simply the right to marry.
    Of course, “[b]y reaffirming the fundamental character of
    the right to marry, we do not mean to suggest that every state
    regulation      which       relates    in   any     way      to    the   incidents        of   or
    prerequisites         for     marriage      must        be    subjected          to     rigorous
    scrutiny.”       Zablocki, 
    434 U.S. at 386
    .                   Strict scrutiny applies
    only    when    laws       “significantly         interfere”        with     a    fundamental
    right.         See    
    id. at 386-87
    .         The      Virginia        Marriage       Laws
    44
    unquestionably satisfy this requirement:                          they impede the right
    to     marry      by    preventing      same-sex          couples      from   marrying       and
    nullifying        the    legal     import     of       their     out-of-state      marriages.
    Strict scrutiny therefore applies in this case.
    B.
    Under      strict    scrutiny,         a    law    “may    be    justified     only    by
    compelling        state     interests,         and       must    be    narrowly     drawn    to
    express       only      those    interests.”             Carey    v.    Population     Servs.
    Int’l, 
    431 U.S. 678
    , 686 (1977).                       The Proponents bear the burden
    of demonstrating that the Virginia Marriage Laws satisfy this
    standard, see Fisher v. Univ. of Tex. at Austin, 
    133 S. Ct. 2411
    ,      2420    (2013),       and   they       must    rely    on    the   laws’   “actual
    purpose[s]” rather than hypothetical justifications, see Shaw v.
    Hunt, 
    517 U.S. 899
    , 908 n.4 (1996).                       The Proponents 7 contend that
    five compelling interests undergird the Virginia Marriage Laws:
    (1) Virginia’s federalism-based interest in maintaining control
    over    the    definition        of    marriage        within     its    borders,     (2)    the
    history and tradition of opposite-sex marriage, (3) protecting
    the     institution         of     marriage,           (4)      encouraging       responsible
    7
    Although some of these arguments appear only in McQuigg’s
    briefs, we attribute them to the Proponents because Schaefer
    “reserved the right to adopt and incorporate in whole or in
    part” McQuigg’s discussion of the rationales underlying the
    Virginia Marriage Laws.
    45
    procreation,         and    (5)      promoting     the     optimal       childrearing
    environment.      We discuss each of these interests in turn.
    1.     Federalism
    The Constitution does not grant the federal government any
    authority      over    domestic      relations    matters,      such    as   marriage.
    Accordingly,      throughout         our    country’s     history,       states    have
    enjoyed the freedom to define and regulate marriage as they see
    fit.       See Windsor, 
    133 S. Ct. at 2691-92
    .                 States’ control over
    marriage      laws     within     their      borders     has    resulted     in    some
    variation      among       states’       requirements.         For     example,    West
    Virginia      prohibits     first     cousins     from   marrying,      
    W. Va. Code § 48-2-302
    , but the remaining states in this Circuit allow first
    cousin marriage, see 
    Md. Code Ann., Fam. Law § 2-202
    ; 
    N.C. Gen. Stat. § 51-3
    ; 
    S.C. Code Ann. § 20-1-10
    ; 
    Va. Code Ann. § 20-38.1
    .
    States’ power to define and regulate marriage also accounts for
    their differing treatment of same-sex couples.
    The Windsor decision rested in part on the Supreme Court’s
    respect for states’ supremacy in the domestic relations sphere. 8
    8
    In Windsor, the Court did not label the type of
    constitutional scrutiny it applied, leaving us unsure how the
    Court would fit its federalism discussion within a traditional
    heightened scrutiny or rational basis analysis.     The lower
    courts have taken differing approaches, with some discussing
    Windsor and federalism as a threshold matter, see, e.g., Wolf,
    
    2014 WL 2558444
    , at *8-12; Bishop v. United States ex rel.
    46
    The Court recognized that section 3 of DOMA upset the status quo
    by robbing states of their ability to define marriage.                          Although
    states could legalize same-sex marriage, they could not ensure
    that the incidents, benefits, and obligations of marriage would
    be uniform within their borders.                      See Windsor, 
    133 S. Ct. at 2692
    .       However, the Court did not lament that section 3 had
    usurped states’ authority over marriage due to its desire to
    safeguard federalism.            
    Id.
     (“[T]he State’s power in defining the
    marital     relation      is   of    central        relevance    in   this   case   quite
    apart from the principles of federalism.”).                       Its concern sprung
    from section        3’s   creation        of    two   classes    of   married    couples
    within states that had legalized same-sex marriage:                           opposite-
    sex couples, whose marriages the federal government recognized,
    and    same-sex     couples,        whose      marriages   the    federal    government
    ignored.      
    Id.
        The resulting injury to same-sex couples served
    as    the   foundation     for      the     Court’s    conclusion     that   section    3
    violated the Fifth Amendment’s Due Process Clause.                       
    Id. at 2693
    .
    Holder, 
    962 F. Supp. 2d 1252
    , 1277-79 (N.D. Okla. 2014); Kitchen
    v. Herbert, 
    961 F. Supp. 2d 1181
    , 1193-94 (D. Utah 2013), and
    others—such as the district court in this case—considering
    federalism as a state interest underlying the same-sex marriage
    bans at issue, see, e.g., Latta, 
    2014 WL 1909999
    , at *25-26;
    DeBoer, 973 F. Supp. 2d at 773-75; Bostic, 970 F. Supp. 2d at
    475-77.    Although we follow the district court’s lead and
    situate our federalism discussion within our application of
    strict scrutiny, our conclusion would remain the same even if we
    selected an alternate organizational approach.
    47
    Citing Windsor, the Proponents urge us to view Virginia’s
    federalism-based        interest       in    defining        marriage        as    a   suitable
    justification for the Virginia Marriage Laws.                           However, Windsor
    is actually detrimental to their position.                          Although the Court
    emphasized     states’      traditional            authority       over       marriage,      it
    acknowledged        that    “[s]tate          laws       defining           and     regulating
    marriage, of course, must respect the constitutional rights of
    persons.”     Id. at 2691 (citing Loving, 
    388 U.S. 1
    ); see also id.
    at 2692 (“The States’ interest in defining and regulating the
    marital relation[] [is] subject to constitutional guarantees.”).
    Windsor does not teach us that federalism principles can justify
    depriving      individuals        of        their     constitutional              rights;    it
    reiterates     Loving’s     admonition            that    the    states       must     exercise
    their    authority      without      trampling           constitutional            guarantees.
    Virginia’s      federalism-based             interest        in     defining           marriage
    therefore     cannot    justify        its    encroachment         on       the    fundamental
    right to marry.
    The    Supreme      Court’s       recent          decision       in        Schuette   v.
    Coalition to Defend Affirmative Action, 
    134 S. Ct. 1623
     (2014),
    does    not   change    the    conclusion           that     Windsor         dictates.       In
    Schuette,     the   Court     refused        to     strike      down    a    voter-approved
    state constitutional amendment that barred public universities
    in Michigan from using race-based preferences as part of their
    admissions processes.          
    Id. at 1629, 1638
    .                The Court declined to
    48
    closely scrutinize the amendment because it was not “used, or
    . . . likely to be used, to encourage infliction of injury by
    reason of race.”       See 
    id. at 1638
    .          Instead, the Court dwelled
    on the need to respect the voters’ policy choice, concluding
    that “[i]t is demeaning to the democratic process to presume
    that the voters are not capable of deciding an issue of this
    sensitivity on decent and rational grounds” and the judiciary’s
    role was not to “disempower the voters from choosing which path
    to follow.”      
    Id. at 1635-38
    .
    The      Proponents    emphasize   that    Virginia’s   voters   approved
    the Marshall/Newman Amendment.               Like the Michigan amendment at
    issue    in     Schuette,    the   Marshall/Newman       Amendment    is   the
    codification of Virginians’ policy choice in a legal arena that
    is fraught with intense social and political debate.              Americans’
    ability to speak with their votes is essential to our democracy.
    But the people’s will is not an independent compelling interest
    that warrants depriving same-sex couples of their fundamental
    right to marry.
    The very purpose of a Bill of Rights 9 was to withdraw
    certain subjects from the vicissitudes of political
    9
    Of course, the Fourteenth Amendment is not part of the
    Bill of Rights.     This excerpt from Barnette is nevertheless
    relevant here due to the Fourteenth Amendment’s similar goal of
    protecting unpopular minorities from government overreaching,
    see Regents of Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke, 
    438 U.S. 265
    , 293 (1978),
    and its role in rendering the Bill of Rights applicable to the
    states, see Duncan v. Louisiana, 
    391 U.S. 145
    , 147-48 (1968).
    49
    controversy, to place them beyond the reach of
    majorities and officials and to establish them as
    legal principles to be applied by the courts. One’s
    right to life, liberty, and property, to free speech,
    a free press, freedom of worship and assembly, and
    other fundamental rights may not be submitted to vote;
    they depend on the outcome of no elections.
    W. Va. State Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 
    319 U.S. 624
    , 638 (1943)
    (footnote added); see also Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 623
     (invalidating
    a voter-approved amendment to Colorado’s constitution); Lucas v.
    Forty-Fourth Gen. Assembly of Colo., 
    377 U.S. 713
    , 736-37 (1964)
    (“A       citizen’s    constitutional            rights    can   hardly      be    infringed
    simply because a majority of the people choose that it be.”).
    Accordingly,          neither      Virginia’s          federalism-based       interest    in
    defining marriage nor our respect for the democratic process
    that codified that definition can excuse the Virginia Marriage
    Laws’ infringement of the right to marry.
    2.     History and Tradition
    The Proponents also point to the “history and tradition” of
    opposite-sex marriage as a compelling interest that supports the
    Virginia Marriage Laws.                  The Supreme Court has made it clear
    that, even under rational basis review, the “[a]ncient lineage
    of    a    legal   concept        does     not    give    it   immunity     from    attack.”
    Heller      v.   Doe    ex    rel.    Doe,       
    509 U.S. 312
    ,   326    (1993).      The
    closely       linked      interest         of     promoting      moral      principles    is
    similarly        infirm      in    light    of    Lawrence:       “the      fact   that   the
    50
    governing    majority      in   a     State       has    traditionally   viewed    a
    particular practice as immoral is not a sufficient reason for
    upholding a law prohibiting the practice; neither history nor
    tradition    could    save      a    law    prohibiting       miscegenation      from
    constitutional attack.”             
    539 U.S. at 577-78
     (quoting Bowers v.
    Hardwick, 
    478 U.S. 186
    , 216 (1986) (Stevens, J., dissenting))
    (internal quotation marks omitted); see also id. at 601 (Scalia,
    J., dissenting) (“But ‘preserving the traditional institution of
    marriage’ is just a kinder way of describing the State’s moral
    disapproval of same-sex couples.”).                     Preserving the historical
    and   traditional     status        quo    is     therefore    not   a   compelling
    interest that justifies the Virginia Marriage Laws.
    3.   Safeguarding the Institution of Marriage
    In   addition   to     arguing       that    history    and    tradition    are
    compelling interests in their own rights, the Proponents warn
    that deviating from the tradition of opposite-sex marriage will
    destabilize the institution of marriage.                   The Proponents suggest
    that legalizing same-sex marriage will sever the link between
    marriage and procreation:            they argue that, if same-sex couples—
    who cannot procreate naturally—are allowed to marry, the state
    will sanction the idea that marriage is a vehicle for adults’
    emotional fulfillment, not simply a framework for parenthood.
    According to the Proponents, if adults are the focal point of
    51
    marriage, “then no logical grounds reinforce stabilizing norms
    like sexual exclusivity, permanence, and monogamy,” which exist
    to benefit children.
    We   recognize          that,    in   some    cases,      we    owe    “substantial
    deference to the predictive judgments” of the Virginia General
    Assembly,    for       whom    the    Proponents     purport     to    speak.           Turner
    Broad. Sys., Inc. v. FCC, 
    520 U.S. 180
    , 195 (1997).                                 However,
    even if we view the Proponents’ theories through rose-colored
    glasses,     we       conclude       that   they    are   unfounded         for     two    key
    reasons.      First,          the    Supreme     Court    rejected      the       view    that
    marriage is about only procreation in Griswold v. Connecticut,
    in which it upheld married couples’ right not to procreate and
    articulated       a    view    of     marriage     that   has   nothing       to    do    with
    children:
    Marriage is a coming together for better or for worse,
    hopefully enduring, and intimate to the degree of
    being sacred. It is an association that promotes a way
    of life, not causes; a harmony in living, not
    political faiths; a bilateral loyalty, not commercial
    or social projects. Yet it is an association for as
    noble a purpose as any involved in our prior
    decisions.
    
    381 U.S. at 485-86
    ;       see    also    Turner,     
    482 U.S. at 95-96
    (describing       many    non-procreative          purposes     of    marriage).            The
    fact that marriage’s stabilizing norms have endured in the five
    decades since the Supreme Court made this pronouncement weakens
    52
    the argument that couples remain in monogamous marriages only
    for the sake of their offspring.
    Second, the primary support that the Proponents offer for
    their theory is the legacy of a wholly unrelated legal change to
    marriage:           no-fault    divorce.        Although      no-fault   divorce
    certainly altered the realities of married life by making it
    easier for couples to end their relationships, we have no reason
    to think that legalizing same-sex marriage will have a similar
    destabilizing effect.          In fact, it is more logical to think that
    same-sex couples want access to marriage so that they can take
    advantage      of     its      hallmarks,      including     faithfulness    and
    permanence, and that allowing loving, committed same-sex couples
    to   marry     and    recognizing    their     out-of-state     marriages   will
    strengthen the institution of marriage.                We therefore reject the
    Proponents’ concerns.
    4.    Responsible Procreation
    Next,   the    Proponents    contend     that   the   Virginia    Marriage
    Laws’ differentiation between opposite-sex and same-sex couples
    stems from the fact that unintended pregnancies cannot result
    from    same-sex      unions.        By     sanctioning      only   opposite-sex
    marriages, the Virginia Marriage Laws “provid[e] stability to
    the types of relationships that result in unplanned pregnancies,
    thereby   avoiding      or     diminishing     the   negative   outcomes    often
    53
    associated    with    unintended       children.”           The    Proponents      allege
    that children born to unwed parents face a “significant risk” of
    being raised in unstable families, which is harmful to their
    development.        Virginia, “of course, has a duty of the highest
    order to protect the interests of minor children, particularly
    those of tender years.”              Palmore v. Sidoti, 
    466 U.S. 429
    , 433
    (1984).        However,        the     Virginia       Marriage       Laws     are     not
    appropriately tailored to further this interest.
    If Virginia sought to ensure responsible procreation via
    the      Virginia      Marriage        Laws,        the     laws      are     woefully
    underinclusive.        Same-sex couples are not the only category of
    couples     who     cannot    reproduce          accidentally.         For    example,
    opposite-sex      couples     cannot     procreate        unintentionally       if   they
    include a post-menopausal woman or an individual with a medical
    condition that prevents unassisted conception.
    The Proponents attempt to downplay the similarity between
    same-sex    couples    and     infertile         opposite-sex      couples    in     three
    ways.      First,    they    point    out    that    sterile       individuals       could
    remedy their fertility through future medical advances.                               This
    potentiality,       however,    does     not      explain    why    Virginia       should
    treat    same-sex    and     infertile      opposite-sex      couples       differently
    during the course of the latter group’s infertility.                            Second,
    the Proponents posit that, even if one member of a man-woman
    couple is sterile, the other member may not be.                         They suggest
    54
    that,     without        marriage’s          monogamy      mandate,        this      fertile
    individual is more likely to have an unintended child with a
    third party.          They contend that, due to this possibility, even
    opposite-sex      couples        who     cannot      procreate      need     marriage       to
    channel    their       procreative          activity    in    a    way     that    same-sex
    couples    do     not.          The      Proponents’         argument      assumes       that
    individuals      in    same-sex       relationships        never    have     opposite-sex
    sexual    partners,       which    is       simply   not     the   case.       Third,      the
    Proponents       imply     that,       by    marrying,       infertile       opposite-sex
    couples    set     a     positive       example      for     couples     who      can     have
    unintended children, thereby encouraging them to marry.                              We see
    no reason why committed same-sex couples cannot serve as similar
    role models.           We therefore reject the Proponents’ attempts to
    differentiate         same-sex     couples      from    other      couples     who      cannot
    procreate accidentally.               Because same-sex couples and infertile
    opposite-sex          couples      are       similarly        situated,        the      Equal
    Protection       Clause     counsels          against      treating        these        groups
    differently.       See City of Cleburne, 
    473 U.S. at 439
     (explaining
    that the Equal Protection Clause “is essentially a direction
    that all persons similarly situated should be treated alike”).
    Due to the Virginia Marriage Laws’ underinclusivity, this
    case resembles City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Center, Inc.
    In City of Cleburne, the Supreme Court struck down a city law
    that required group homes for the intellectually disabled to
    55
    obtain a special use permit.                   
    Id. at 447-50
    .             The city did not
    impose       the    same    requirement        on    similar    structures,          such   as
    apartment complexes and nursing homes.                      
    Id. at 447
    .          The Court
    determined         that    the   permit      requirement       was    so    underinclusive
    that the city’s motivation must have “rest[ed] on an irrational
    prejudice,” rendering the law unconstitutional.                            
    Id. at 450
    .       In
    light of the Virginia Marriage Laws’ extreme underinclusivity,
    we are forced to draw the same conclusion in this case.
    The    Proponents’        responsible         procreation          argument   falters
    for another reason as well.                     Strict scrutiny requires that a
    state’s means further its compelling interest.                              See Shaw, 
    517 U.S. at 915
        (“Although        we    have    not   always         provided   precise
    guidance on how closely the means . . . must serve the end (the
    justification or compelling interest), we have always expected
    that the legislative action would substantially address, if not
    achieve, the avowed purpose.”).                      Prohibiting same-sex couples
    from marrying and ignoring their out-of-state marriages does not
    serve    Virginia’s         goal       of    preventing     out-of-wedlock           births.
    Although      same-sex      couples         cannot   procreate       accidentally,       they
    can and do have children via other methods.                               According to an
    amicus brief filed by Dr. Gary J. Gates, as of the 2010 U.S.
    Census, more than 2500 same-sex couples were raising more than
    4000    children      under      the    age     of   eighteen        in    Virginia.        The
    56
    Virginia Marriage Laws therefore increase the number of children
    raised by unmarried parents.
    The    Proponents       acknowledge          that       same-sex       couples       become
    parents.       They contend, however, that the state has no interest
    in   channeling         same-sex        couples’       procreative         activities          into
    marriage      because        same-sex      couples        “bring    children          into    their
    relationship[s] only through intentional choice and pre-planned
    action.”        Accordingly,            “[t]hose      couples       neither      advance        nor
    threaten       society’s       public       purpose         for     marriage”—stabilizing
    parental relationships for the benefit of children—“in the same
    manner, or to the same degree, that sexual relationships between
    men and women do.”
    In       support    of    this      argument,         the    Proponents          invoke    the
    Supreme Court’s decision in Johnson v. Robison, 
    415 U.S. 361
    (1974).       Johnson concerned educational benefits that the federal
    government granted to military veterans who served on active
    duty.     
    Id. at 363
    .              The government provided these benefits to
    encourage enlistment and make military service more palatable to
    existing       servicemembers.             
    Id. at 382-83
    .         A    conscientious
    objector—who       refused         to   serve    in       the    military       for    religious
    reasons—brought          suit,       contending           that    the   government            acted
    unconstitutionally            by    granting         benefits      to   veterans        but    not
    conscientious objectors.                 
    Id. at 363-64
    .              The Court explained
    that,    “[w]hen,       as    in    this    case,         the    inclusion      of     one    group
    57
    promotes a legitimate governmental purpose, and the addition of
    other    groups       would       not,    we    cannot        say    that       the    statute’s
    classification             of     beneficiaries          and        nonbeneficiaries            is
    invidiously         discriminatory.”            
    Id. at 383
    .          Because     offering
    educational         benefits       to     conscientious             objectors         would     not
    incentivize         military      service,       the    federal           government’s        line-
    drawing was constitutional.                    Johnson, 
    415 U.S. at 382-83
    .                     The
    Proponents claim that treating opposite-sex couples differently
    from    same-sex       couples      is    equally       justified           because     the    two
    groups       are     not    similarly       situated          with        respect      to     their
    procreative potential.
    Johnson applied rational basis review, 
    id. at 374-75
    , so we
    strongly       doubt       its     applicability         to         our     strict      scrutiny
    analysis.          In any event, we can easily distinguish Johnson from
    the instant case.               In Johnson, offering educational benefits to
    veterans who served on active duty promoted the government’s
    goal    of    making       military      service       more    attractive.             Extending
    those     benefits         to    conscientious         objectors,           whose      religious
    beliefs       precluded         military       service,        did        not   further       that
    objective.           By     contrast,      a    stable        marital       relationship        is
    attractive          regardless       of    a     couple’s           procreative         ability.
    Allowing infertile opposite-sex couples to marry does nothing to
    further the government’s goal of channeling procreative conduct
    into marriage.             Thus, excluding same-sex couples from marriage
    58
    due to their inability to have unintended children makes little
    sense.      Johnson therefore does not alter our conclusion that
    barring same-sex couples’ access to marriage does nothing to
    further Virginia’s interest in responsible procreation.
    5.    Optimal Childrearing
    We    now     shift      to     discussing            the     merit     of        the     final
    compelling         interest         that    the       Proponents        invoke:                optimal
    childrearing.            The Proponents aver that “children develop best
    when   reared       by    their      married      biological         parents        in    a     stable
    family      unit.”         They      dwell       on     the    importance           of     “gender-
    differentiated           parenting”        and    argue      that     sanctioning          same-sex
    marriage will deprive children of the benefit of being raised by
    a mother and a father, who have “distinct parenting styles.”                                       In
    essence, the Proponents argue that the Virginia Marriage Laws
    safeguard children by preventing same-sex couples from marrying
    and starting inferior families.
    The Opponents and their amici cast serious doubt on the
    accuracy of the Proponents’ contentions.                              For example, as the
    American      Psychological                Association,            American         Academy         of
    Pediatrics,          American          Psychiatric                 Association,            National
    Association         of    Social       Workers,         and        Virginia     Psychological
    Association        (collectively,           the       APA)    explain     in    their           amicus
    brief,      “there        is    no     scientific             evidence       that         parenting
    59
    effectiveness is related to parental sexual orientation,” and
    “the      same      factors”—including                  family        stability,        economic
    resources,       and     the      quality    of     parent-child           relationships—“are
    linked     to    children’s          positive          development,         whether    they    are
    raised by heterosexual, lesbian, or gay parents.”                                According to
    the APA, “the parenting abilities of gay men and lesbians—and
    the positive outcomes for their children—are not areas where
    most credible scientific researchers disagree,” and the contrary
    studies that the Proponents cite “do not reflect the current
    state of scientific knowledge.”                         See also DeBoer, 973 F. Supp.
    2d   at   760-68       (making       factual      findings         and     reaching    the    same
    conclusion).            In    fact,    the       APA    explains      that,     by    preventing
    same-sex        couples       from    marrying,          the       Virginia    Marriage       Laws
    actually harm the children of same-sex couples by stigmatizing
    their     families          and   robbing        them    of    the        stability,    economic
    security, and togetherness that marriage fosters.                                    The Supreme
    Court     reached       a    similar    conclusion            in    Windsor,     in    which    it
    observed         that        failing        to     recognize              same-sex     marriages
    “humiliates tens of thousands of children now being raised by
    same-sex    couples”          and    “makes       it    even       more    difficult    for    the
    children to understand the integrity and closeness of their own
    family and its concord with other families in their community
    and in their daily lives.”               133 S. Ct. at 2694.
    60
    We find the arguments that the Opponents and their amici
    make on this issue extremely persuasive.                          However, we need not
    resolve        this     dispute        because        the      Proponents’           optimal
    childrearing argument falters for at least two other reasons.
    First, under heightened scrutiny, states cannot support a law
    using “overbroad          generalizations          about     the    different    talents,
    capacities, or preferences of” the groups in question.                                United
    States    v.    Virginia,      
    518 U.S. 515
    ,       533-34     (1996)    (rejecting
    “inherent differences” between men and women as a justification
    for excluding all women from a traditionally all-male military
    college); see also Stanley v. Illinois, 
    405 U.S. 645
    , 656-58
    (1972) (holding that a state could not presume that unmarried
    fathers     were       unfit    parents).            The     Proponents’      statements
    regarding same-sex couples’ parenting ability certainly qualify
    as   overbroad        generalizations.             Second,    as    we    explain     above,
    strict scrutiny requires congruity between a law’s means and its
    end.     This congruity is absent here.                      There is absolutely no
    reason     to    suspect       that     prohibiting          same-sex      couples     from
    marrying and refusing to recognize their out-of-state marriages
    will cause same-sex couples to raise fewer children or impel
    married    opposite-sex         couples       to    raise     more       children.      The
    Virginia       Marriage    Laws       therefore      do     not    further     Virginia’s
    interest in channeling children into optimal families, even if
    61
    we were to accept the dubious proposition that same-sex couples
    are less capable parents.
    Because the Proponents’ arguments are based on overbroad
    generalizations about same-sex parents, and because there is no
    link    between      banning      same-sex     marriage     and   promoting    optimal
    childrearing,        this   aim     cannot     support      the   Virginia    Marriage
    Laws.       All of the Proponents’ justifications for the Virginia
    Marriage Laws therefore fail, and the laws cannot survive strict
    scrutiny.
    V.
    For the foregoing reasons, we conclude that the Virginia
    Marriage      Laws      violate    the   Due      Process   and   Equal    Protection
    Clauses      of   the    Fourteenth      Amendment    to    the   extent     that   they
    prevent      same-sex     couples     from     marrying     and   prohibit    Virginia
    from        recognizing      same-sex          couples’      lawful    out-of-state
    marriages.        We therefore affirm the district court’s grant of
    the Plaintiffs’ motion for summary judgment and its decision to
    enjoin enforcement of the Virginia Marriage Laws. 10
    10
    Because we are able to resolve the merits of the
    Opponents’ claims, we need not consider their alternative
    request for a preliminary injunction.       We assume that the
    district court’s decision to enjoin enforcement of the Virginia
    Marriage Laws encompassed a permanent injunction, which the
    Plaintiffs requested in connection with their motion for summary
    judgment.
    62
    We   recognize    that      same-sex     marriage   makes    some    people
    deeply uncomfortable.            However, inertia and apprehension are
    not legitimate bases for denying same-sex couples due process
    and equal protection of the laws.             Civil marriage is one of the
    cornerstones    of   our   way   of   life.     It   allows   individuals     to
    celebrate and publicly declare their intentions to form lifelong
    partnerships,        which        provide        unparalleled        intimacy,
    companionship, emotional support, and security.                  The choice of
    whether and whom to marry is an intensely personal decision that
    alters the course of an individual’s life.                 Denying same-sex
    couples this choice prohibits them from participating fully in
    our society, which is precisely the type of segregation that the
    Fourteenth Amendment cannot countenance.
    AFFIRMED
    63
    NIEMEYER, Circuit Judge, dissenting:
    To be clear, this case is not about whether courts favor or
    disfavor      same-sex         marriage,         or    whether         States       recognizing      or
    declining to recognize same-sex marriage have made good policy
    decisions.         It is much narrower.                 It is about whether a State’s
    decision       not       to     recognize        same-sex             marriage       violates       the
    Fourteenth         Amendment         of    the       U.S.    Constitution.                Thus,     the
    judicial       response         must      be    limited          to    an    analysis          applying
    established constitutional principles.
    The    Commonwealth           of    Virginia         has       always       recognized      that
    “marriage” is based on the “mutual agreement of a man and a
    woman to marry each other,” Burke v. Shaver, 
    23 S.E. 749
    , 749
    (Va. 1895), and that a marriage’s purposes include “establishing
    a    family,       the    continuance           of    the    race,          the    propagation       of
    children,       and      the     general         good       of    society,”          Alexander       v.
    Kuykendall, 
    63 S.E.2d 746
    , 748 (Va. 1951).                                  In recent years, it
    codified      that       understanding           in    several         statutes,          which   also
    explicitly exclude from the definition of “marriage” the union
    of   two     men    or    two    women.          Moreover,            in    2006    the    people    of
    Virginia       amended         the     Commonwealth’s             Constitution            to     define
    marriage as only between “one man and one woman.”                                         Va. Const.
    art. I, § 15-A.
    The         plaintiffs,            who         are        in        long-term           same-sex
    relationships,            are        challenging            the        constitutionality             of
    Virginia’s      marriage       laws      under    the     Due       Process    and     Equal
    Protection Clauses of the U.S. Constitution.                         The district court
    sustained their challenge, concluding that the plaintiffs have a
    fundamental     right     to     marry    each    other       under   the     Due    Process
    Clause   of     the     Fourteenth       Amendment       and    therefore       that     any
    regulation      of     that    right      is     subject       to     strict    scrutiny.
    Concluding that Virginia’s definition of marriage failed even
    “to display a rational relationship to a legitimate purpose and
    so must be viewed as constitutionally infirm,” the court struck
    down Virginia’s marriage laws as unconstitutional and enjoined
    their enforcement.            Bostic v. Rainey, 
    970 F. Supp. 2d 456
    , 482
    (E.D. Va. 2014).
    The majority agrees.                 It concludes that the fundamental
    right to marriage includes a right to same-sex marriage and that
    therefore Virginia’s marriage laws must be reviewed under strict
    scrutiny.       It     holds     that    Virginia       has    failed    to    advance     a
    compelling state interest justifying its definition of marriage
    as between only a man and a woman.                 In reaching this conclusion,
    however,      the     majority    has     failed     to       conduct    the    necessary
    constitutional         analysis.          Rather,       it     has    simply        declared
    syllogistically that because “marriage” is a fundamental right
    protected by the Due Process Clause and “same-sex marriage” is a
    form of marriage, Virginia’s laws declining to recognize same-
    65
    sex marriage infringe the fundamental right to marriage and are
    therefore unconstitutional.
    Stated   more    particularly,        the      majority’s       approach   begins
    with the parties’ agreement that “marriage” is a fundamental
    right.       Ante at 40.           From there, the majority moves to the
    proposition that “the right to marry is an expansive liberty
    interest,” ante at 41, “that is not circumscribed based on the
    characteristics        of    the   individuals          seeking   to    exercise     that
    right,” ante at 42-43.             For support, it notes that the Supreme
    Court has struck down state restrictions prohibiting interracial
    marriage, see Loving v. Virginia, 
    388 U.S. 1
     (1967); prohibiting
    prison    inmates      from     marrying     without       special      approval,     see
    Turner v. Safley, 
    482 U.S. 78
     (1987); and prohibiting persons
    owing child support from marrying, see Zablocki v. Redhail, 
    434 U.S. 374
        (1978).         It   then   declares,        ipse   dixit,      that   “the
    fundamental right to marry encompasses the right to same-sex
    marriage” and is thus protected by the substantive component of
    the    Due   Process        Clause.       Ante     at    41.      In    reaching     this
    conclusion, the majority “decline[s] the Proponents’ invitation
    to characterize the right at issue in this case as the right to
    same-sex marriage rather than simply the right to marry.”                            Ante
    at 44.       And in doing so, it explicitly bypasses the relevant
    constitutional      analysis       required      by     Washington      v.   Glucksberg,
    
    521 U.S. 702
     (1997), stating that a Glucksberg analysis is not
    66
    necessary because no new fundamental right is being recognized.
    Ante at 41-42.
    This analysis is fundamentally flawed because it fails to
    take    into    account        that     the    “marriage”         that     has     long     been
    recognized      by     the     Supreme     Court      as    a     fundamental       right     is
    distinct from the newly proposed relationship of a “same-sex
    marriage.”          And this failure is even more pronounced by the
    majority’s acknowledgment that same-sex marriage is a new notion
    that    has     not     been     recognized         “for     most     of     our    country’s
    history.”       Ante at 41.           Moreover, the majority fails to explain
    how this new notion became incorporated into the traditional
    definition of marriage except by linguistic manipulation.                                 Thus,
    the    majority       never    asks     the   question       necessary       to     finding    a
    fundamental right -- whether same-sex marriage is a right that
    is “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition” and
    “implicit in the concept of ordered liberty, such that neither
    liberty       nor     justice     would       exist    if       [it   was]     sacrificed.”
    Glucksberg, 
    521 U.S. at 721
     (quoting Moore v. East Cleveland,
    
    431 U.S. 494
    ,     503      (1977)       (plurality          opinion);        Palko     v.
    Connecticut, 
    302 U.S. 319
    , 325-26 (1937)) (internal quotation
    marks omitted).
    At bottom, in holding that same-sex marriage is encompassed
    by    the   traditional         right    to    marry,       the    majority        avoids   the
    necessary constitutional analysis, concluding simply and broadly
    67
    that the fundamental “right to marry” -- by everyone and to
    anyone -- may not be infringed.                   And it does not anticipate or
    address       the   problems   that     this       approach    causes,     failing   to
    explain, for example, why this broad right to marry, as the
    majority defines it, does not also encompass the “right” of a
    father to marry his daughter or the “right” of any person to
    marry multiple partners.
    If     the   majority     were     to       recognize      and     address    the
    distinction between the two relationships -- the traditional one
    and the new one -- as it must, it would simply be unable to
    reach the conclusion that it has reached.
    I respectfully submit that, for the reasons that follow,
    Virginia was well within its constitutional authority to adhere
    to its traditional definition of marriage as the union of a man
    and a woman and to exclude from that definition the union of two
    men or two women.          I would also agree that the U.S. Constitution
    does    not    prohibit    a   State    from      defining    marriage     to    include
    same-sex marriage, as many States have done.                            Accordingly, I
    would    reverse     the   judgment     of       the   district   court    and   uphold
    Virginia’s marriage laws.
    I
    As the majority has observed, state recognition of same-sex
    marriage is a new phenomenon.                    Its history began in the early
    68
    2000s with the recognition in some States of civil unions.                            See,
    e.g., 
    Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 15, §§ 1201-1202
     (2000); 
    D.C. Code § 32-701
     (1992) (effective in 2002); 
    Cal. Fam. Code §§ 297-298
    (2003); 
    N.J. Stat. Ann. § 26
    :8A-2 (2003); Conn. Gen. Stat. Ann.
    § 46b-38nn (2006), invalidated by Kerrigan v. Comm’r of Pub.
    Health, 
    957 A.2d 407
     (Conn. 2008).                 And the notion of same-sex
    marriage   itself       first     gained       traction     in     2003,       when     the
    Massachusetts       Supreme           Judicial      Court         held        that      the
    Commonwealth’s prohibition on issuing marriage licenses to same-
    sex   couples     violated      the    State’s     Constitution          --   the     first
    decision holding that same-sex couples had a right to marry.
    See   Goodridge    v.   Dep’t     of    Pub.     Health,    
    798 N.E.2d 941
    ,     968
    (Mass. 2003).      In 2009, Vermont became the first State to enact
    legislation recognizing same-sex marriage, and, since then, 11
    other States and the District of Columbia have also done so.
    See Conn. Gen. Stat. §§ 46b-20 to 46b-20a; 
    Del. Code Ann. tit. 13, § 101
    ; 
    D.C. Code § 46-401
    ; 
    Haw. Rev. Stat. § 572-1
    ; 750 Ill.
    Comp. Stat. 5/201; Me. Rev. Stat. tit. 19-A, § 650-A; 
    Md. Code Ann., Fam. Law §§ 2-201
     to 2-202; 
    Minn. Stat. Ann. §§ 517.01
     to
    517.03; 
    N.H. Rev. Stat. Ann. §§ 457:1
    -a to 457:2; 
    N.Y. Dom. Rel. Law § 10
    -a; R.I. Gen. Laws § 15-1-1 et seq.; 
    Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 15, § 8
    ; 
    Wash. Rev. Code §§ 26.04.010
     to 26.04.020.                            Moreover,
    seven other States currently allow same-sex marriage as a result
    of court rulings.        See Hollingsworth v. Perry, 
    133 S. Ct. 2652
    69
    (2013); Varnum v. Brien, 
    763 N.W.2d 862
     (Iowa 2009); Goodridge,
    
    798 N.E.2d 941
    ; Garden State Equality v. Dow, 
    79 A.3d 1036
     (N.J.
    2013); Griego v. Oliver, 
    316 P.3d 865
     (N.M. 2013); Geiger v.
    Kitzhaber, ___ F. Supp. 2d ___, No. 6:13-CV-01834-MC, 
    2014 WL 2054264
     (D. Or. May 19, 2014); Whitewood v. Wolf, ___ F. Supp.
    2d ___, No. 1:13-CV-1861, 
    2014 WL 2058105
     (M.D. Pa. May 20,
    2014).    This is indeed a recent phenomenon.
    Virginia only recognizes marriage as between one man and
    one woman, and, like a majority of States, it has codified this
    view.      See   
    Va. Code Ann. § 20-45.2
       (prohibiting   same-sex
    marriage and declining to recognize same-sex marriages conducted
    in other States); 
    id.
     § 20-45.3 (prohibiting civil unions and
    similar arrangements between persons of the same sex).             The bill
    originally proposing what would become § 20-45.3 noted the basis
    for Virginia’s legislative decision:
    [H]uman marriage is a consummated two in one communion
    of male and female persons made possible by sexual
    differences which are reproductive in type, whether or
    not they are reproductive in effect or motivation.
    This present relationship recognizes the equality of
    male and female persons, and antedates recorded
    history.
    Affirmation of Marriage Act, H.D. 751, 2004 Gen. Assembly, Reg.
    Sess. (Va. 2004).       The bill predicted that the recognition of
    same-sex marriage would “radically transform the institution of
    marriage with serious and harmful consequences to the social
    order.”    Id.   Virginia also amended its Constitution in 2006 to
    70
    define marriage as only between “one man and one woman” and to
    prohibit    “a     legal    status       for   relationships        of     unmarried
    individuals that intends to approximate the design, qualities,
    significance, or effects of marriage.”                Va. Const. art. I, § 15-
    A.   The    plaintiffs      commenced      this     action    to    challenge    the
    constitutionality of Virginia’s marriage laws.
    Plaintiffs Timothy B. Bostic and Tony C. London have lived
    in a committed same-sex relationship since 1989 and have lived
    in Virginia since 1991.         The two desired to marry in Virginia,
    and on July 1, 2013, when they applied for a marriage license at
    the office of the Clerk of the Circuit Court for the City of
    Norfolk,    they   were    denied    a    license     and    told   that    same-sex
    couples are ineligible to marry in Virginia.                  In their complaint
    challenging Virginia’s marriage laws, they alleged that their
    inability to marry has disadvantaged them in both economic and
    personal ways -- it has prevented them from filing joint tax
    returns, kept them from sharing health insurance on a tax-free
    basis, and signaled that they are “less than” other couples in
    Virginia.
    Plaintiffs     Carol    Schall      and   Mary    Townley      likewise    have
    lived in a committed same-sex relationship since 1985 and have
    lived in Virginia throughout their 29-year relationship.                         In
    1998, Townley gave birth to a daughter, E.S.-T., whom Schall and
    Townley have raised together, and in 2008, the two traveled to
    71
    California where they were lawfully married.                             They alleged in
    their complaint that because Virginia does not recognize their
    marriage       as    valid,     they    have    been       injured      in    several      ways.
    Schall    is    unable     to    legally       adopt      E.S.-T.,      and    the    two    are
    unable to share health insurance on a tax-free basis.                                 The two
    also claimed that they and E.S.-T. have experienced stigma as a
    result of Virginia’s nonrecognition of their marriage.
    The plaintiffs’ complaint, filed in July 2013, alleged that
    Virginia’s          marriage    laws    violate          their    constitutional        rights
    under    the    Due     Process        and    Equal       Protection     Clauses       of    the
    Fourteenth          Amendment.         They    named       as     defendants        George    E.
    Schaefer, III, Clerk of Court for the Norfolk Circuit Court, and
    Janet M. Rainey, the State Registrar of Vital Records.                                A third
    Virginia official, Michèle B. McQuigg, Clerk of Court for the
    Prince William County Circuit Court, was permitted to intervene
    as a defendant.           As elected circuit court clerks, Schaefer and
    McQuigg are responsible for issuing individual marriage licenses
    in the localities in which they serve.                       And Rainey, as the State
    Registrar       of      Vital    Records,           is    responsible         for     ensuring
    compliance      with     Virginia’s          marriage      laws,    including        the     laws
    challenged in this case.
    After the parties filed cross-motions for summary judgment,
    Virginia underwent a change in administrations, and the newly
    elected    Attorney       General       of    Virginia,          Mark   Herring,      filed    a
    72
    notice of a change in his office’s legal position on behalf of
    his    client,    defendant     Janet     Rainey.       His   notice       stated   that
    because, in his view, the laws at issue were unconstitutional,
    his office would no longer defend them on behalf of Rainey.                            He
    noted, however, that Rainey would continue to enforce the laws
    until the court’s ruling.              The other officials have continued to
    defend Virginia’s marriage laws, and, for convenience, I refer
    to the defendants herein as “Virginia.”
    Following a hearing, the district court, by an order and
    memorandum       dated   February       14,    2014,   granted       the    plaintiffs’
    motion for summary judgment and denied Virginia’s cross-motion.
    The court concluded that same-sex partners have a fundamental
    right to marry each other under the Due Process Clause of the
    Fourteenth     Amendment,       thus    requiring      that   Virginia’s      marriage
    laws    restricting      that    right    be    narrowly      drawn    to    further    a
    compelling state interest.              It concluded that the laws did not
    meet    that     requirement     and,     indeed,      “fail[ed]      to    display     a
    rational relationship to a legitimate purpose, and so must be
    viewed as constitutionally infirm under even the least onerous
    level of scrutiny.”         Bostic, 970 F. Supp. 2d at 482.                    Striking
    down Virginia’s marriage laws, the court also issued an order
    enjoining      their     enforcement      but     stayed      that    order     pending
    appeal.    This appeal followed.
    73
    II
    The     plaintiffs       contend          that,    as    same-sex     partners,        they
    have    a    fundamental        right       to    marry    that     is   protected       by    the
    substantive          component    of    the       Due     Process    Clause      of   the     U.S.
    Constitution, U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 1 (prohibiting any State
    from    depriving        “any     person         of     life,     liberty,    or      property,
    without due process of law”), and that Virginia’s laws defining
    marriage as only between a man and a woman and excluding same-
    sex    marriage        infringe        on    that        right.       The    constitutional
    analysis for adjudging their claim is well established.
    The Constitution contains no language directly protecting
    the right to same-sex marriage or even traditional marriage.
    Any    right    to     same-sex    marriage,             therefore,      would    have    to   be
    found, through court interpretation, as a substantive component
    of     the     Due     Process     Clause.               See    Planned      Parenthood         of
    Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
    , 846 (1992) (“Although a
    literal reading of the Clause might suggest that it governs only
    the procedures by which a State may deprive persons of liberty,
    for at least 105 years . . . the Clause has been understood to
    contain a substantive component as well”).
    The substantive component of the Due Process Clause only
    protects “fundamental” liberty interests.                           And the Supreme Court
    has held that liberty interests are only fundamental if they
    are, “objectively, ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and
    74
    tradition,’ and ‘implicit in the concept of ordered liberty,’
    such that ‘neither liberty nor justice would exist if they were
    sacrificed.’”        Glucksberg, 
    521 U.S. at 720-21
     (citation omitted)
    (quoting Moore, 
    431 U.S. at 503
     (plurality opinion); Palko, 
    302 U.S. at 325-26
    ).         When determining whether such a fundamental
    right exists, a court must always make “a ‘careful description’
    of   the    asserted    fundamental    liberty     interest.”        Id.    at   721
    (emphasis     added)    (quoting    Reno    v.   Flores,    
    507 U.S. 292
    ,   302
    (1993)).      This “careful description” involves characterizing the
    right asserted in its narrowest terms.                  Thus, in Glucksberg,
    where the Court was presented with a due process challenge to a
    state      statute   banning   assisted      suicide,      the    Court    narrowly
    characterized the right being asserted in the following manner:
    The Court of Appeals stated that “[p]roperly analyzed,
    the first issue to be resolved is whether there is a
    liberty interest in determining the time and manner of
    one’s death,” or, in other words, “[i]s there a right
    to die?”   Similarly, respondents assert a “liberty to
    choose how to die” and a right to “control of one’s
    final days,” and describe the asserted liberty as “the
    right to choose a humane, dignified death,” and “the
    liberty to shape death.”    As noted above, we have a
    tradition of carefully formulating the interest at
    stake in substantive-due-process cases. . . .      The
    Washington statute at issue in this case prohibits
    “aid[ing] another person to attempt suicide,” and,
    thus, the question before us is whether the “liberty”
    specially protected by the Due Process Clause includes
    a right to commit suicide which itself includes a
    right to assistance in doing so.
    Glucksberg,      
    521 U.S. at 722-23
          (alterations      in     original)
    (emphasis added) (citations omitted).
    75
    Under this formulation, because the Virginia laws at issue
    prohibit “marriage between persons of the same sex,” 
    Va. Code Ann. § 20-45.2
    , “the question before us is whether the ‘liberty’
    specially protected by the Due Process Clause includes a right”
    to same-sex marriage.            Glucksberg, 
    521 U.S. at 723
    ; see also
    Jackson v. Abercrombie, 
    884 F. Supp. 2d 1065
    , 1095 (D. Haw.
    2012) (“[M]issing from Plaintiffs’ asserted ‘right to marry the
    person of one’s choice’ is its centerpiece:                the right to marry
    someone of the same gender”).
    When a fundamental right is so identified, then any statute
    restricting the right is subject to strict scrutiny and must be
    “narrowly      tailored    to    serve    a   compelling    state    interest.”
    Flores, 
    507 U.S. at 302
    .           Such scrutiny is extremely difficult
    for a law to withstand, and, as such, the Supreme Court has
    noted   that    courts    must   be   extremely   cautious    in    recognizing
    fundamental rights because doing so ordinarily removes freedom
    of choice from the hands of the people:
    [W]e “ha[ve] always been reluctant to expand the
    concept of substantive due process because guideposts
    for responsible decisionmaking in this unchartered
    area are scarce and open-ended.”          By extending
    constitutional protection to an asserted right or
    liberty interest, we, to a great extent, place the
    matter outside the arena of public debate and
    legislative action.   We must therefore “exercise the
    utmost care whenever we are asked to break new ground
    in this field,” lest the liberty protected by the Due
    Process Clause be subtly transformed into the policy
    preferences of the Members of this Court.
    76
    Glucksberg,    
    521 U.S. at 720
            (second     alteration        in   original)
    (emphasis added) (quoting Collins v. City of Harker Heights, 
    503 U.S. 115
    , 125 (1992)).
    The   plaintiffs       in    this    case,      as    well      as    the   majority,
    recognize that narrowly defining the asserted liberty interest
    would require them to demonstrate a new fundamental right to
    same-sex marriage, which they cannot do.                         Thus, they have made
    no attempt to argue that same-sex marriage is, “objectively,
    deeply   rooted    in    this       Nation’s         history     and    tradition,”      and
    “implicit in the concept of ordered liberty.”                               Glucksberg, 
    521 U.S. at 720-21
     (internal quotation marks omitted).                             Indeed, they
    have acknowledged that recognition of same-sex marriage is a
    recent development.           See ante at 41; see also United States v.
    Windsor, 
    133 S. Ct. 2675
    , 2689 (2013) (“Until recent years, many
    citizens had not even considered the possibility of [same-sex
    marriage]”     (emphasis           added));          
    id. at 2715
            (Alito,    J.,
    dissenting) (noting that it is “beyond dispute that the right to
    same-sex marriage is not deeply rooted in this Nation’s history
    and tradition”); Baehr v. Lewin, 
    852 P.2d 44
    , 57 (Haw. 1993)
    (“[W]e do not believe that a right to same-sex marriage is so
    rooted in the traditions and collective conscience of our people
    that   failure    to    recognize          it    would      violate     the     fundamental
    principles of liberty and justice that lie at the base of all
    our civil and political institutions”).
    77
    Instead, the plaintiffs and the majority argue that the
    fundamental     right        to   marriage     that    has     previously      been
    recognized by the Supreme Court is a broad right that should
    apply to the plaintiffs without the need to recognize a new
    fundamental right to same-sex marriage.                 They argue that this
    approach is supported by the fact that the Supreme Court did not
    narrowly   define      the    right    to   marriage    in   its   decisions    in
    Loving, 
    388 U.S. at 12
    ; Turner, 
    482 U.S. at 94-96
    ; or Zablocki,
    
    434 U.S. at 383-86
    .
    It    is   true    that,     in   those   cases,    the    Court    did   not
    recognize new, separate fundamental rights to fit the factual
    circumstances in each case.            For example, in Loving, the Court
    did not examine whether interracial marriage was, objectively,
    deeply rooted in our Nation’s history and tradition.                 But it was
    not required to do so.            Each of those cases involved a couple
    asserting a right to enter into a traditional marriage of the
    type that has always been recognized since the beginning of the
    Nation -- a union between one man and one woman.                        While the
    context for asserting the right varied in each of those cases,
    it varied only in ways irrelevant to the concept of marriage.
    The type of relationship sought was always the traditional, man-
    woman relationship to which the term “marriage” was theretofore
    always assumed to refer.           Thus, none of the cases cited by the
    plaintiffs and relied on by the majority involved the assertion
    78
    of a brand new liberty interest.                 To the contrary, they involved
    the assertion of one of the oldest and most fundamental liberty
    interests in our society.
    To now define the previously recognized fundamental right
    to    “marriage”    as    a    concept    that    includes     the    new    notion     of
    “same-sex marriage” amounts to a dictionary jurisprudence, which
    defines terms as convenient to attain an end.
    It   is    true    that    same-sex      and   opposite-sex      relationships
    share many attributes, and, therefore, marriages involving those
    relationships would, to a substantial extent, be similar.                              Two
    persons     who     are       attracted    to     each     other     physically       and
    emotionally and who love each other could publicly promise to
    live    with      each    other     thereafter        in   a   mutually          desirable
    relationship.        These aspects are the same whether the persons
    are    of   the    same     sex    or    different       sexes.       Moreover,      both
    relationships       could      successfully      function      to    raise       children,
    although children in a same-sex relationship would come from one
    partner     or    from    adoption.        But    there     are     also    significant
    distinctions        between       the     relationships        that        can     justify
    differential treatment by lawmakers.
    Only the union of a man and a woman has the capacity to
    produce children and thus to carry on the species.                               And more
    importantly, only such a union creates a biological family unit
    that also gives rise to a traditionally stable political unit.
    79
    Every       person’s      identity     includes       the     person’s        particular
    biological        relationships,      which      create     unique    and     meaningful
    bonds of kinship that are extraordinarily strong and enduring
    and    that    have     been    afforded   a     privileged    place     in    political
    order      throughout     human     history.        Societies     have      accordingly
    enacted laws promoting the family unit -- such as those relating
    to sexual engagement, marriage rites, divorce, inheritance, name
    and title, and economic matters.                  And many societies have found
    familial bonds so critical that they have elevated marriage to
    be    a    sacred   institution      trapped      with    religious     rituals.      In
    these       respects,     the      traditional      man-woman        relationship     is
    unique.
    Thus, when the Supreme Court has recognized, through the
    years, that the right to marry is a fundamental right, it has
    emphasized        the    procreative       and    social     ordering       aspects   of
    traditional marriage.            For example, it has said:             “[Marriage] is
    an institution, in the maintenance of which in its purity the
    public is deeply interested, for it is the foundation of the
    family      and   of    society,    without      which    there   would     be   neither
    civilization nor progress,” Maynard v. Hill, 
    125 U.S. 190
    , 211
    (1888) (emphasis added); Marriage is “one of the basic civil
    rights of man.          Marriage and procreation are fundamental to the
    very existence and survival of the race,” Skinner v. Oklahoma ex
    rel. Williamson, 
    316 U.S. 535
    , 541 (1942); “It is not surprising
    80
    that the decision to marry has been placed on the same level of
    importance     as    decisions        relating       to    procreation,          childbirth,
    childrearing, and family relationships. . . .                          [Marriage] is the
    foundation of the family in our society,” Zablocki, 
    434 U.S. at 386
    .
    Because there exist deep, fundamental differences between
    traditional       and      same-sex     marriage,          the     plaintiffs      and     the
    majority   err      by     conflating        the    two    relationships          under    the
    loosely drawn rubric of “the right to marriage.”                                 Rather, to
    obtain constitutional protection, they would have to show that
    the right to same-sex marriage is itself deeply rooted in our
    Nation’s history.              They have not attempted to do so and could
    not succeed if they were so to attempt.
    In an effort to bridge the obvious differences between the
    traditional relationship and the new same-sex relationship, the
    plaintiffs argue that the fundamental right to marriage “has
    always been based on, and defined by, the constitutional liberty
    to select the partner of one’s choice.”                      (Emphasis added).            They
    rely heavily on Loving to assert this claim.                               In Loving, the
    Court   held     that      a    state      regulation       restricting          interracial
    marriage     infringed          on   the     fundamental          right     to    marriage.
    Loving, 
    388 U.S. at 12
    .                 But nowhere in Loving did the Court
    suggest    that      the       fundamental         right    to     marry    includes       the
    unrestricted        right       to   marry     whomever          one   chooses,     as     the
    81
    plaintiffs claim.            Indeed, Loving explicitly relied on Skinner
    and    Murphy,       and   both       of   those    cases    discussed        marriage     in
    traditional, procreative terms.                   
    Id.
    This reading of Loving is fortified by the Court’s summary
    dismissal       of   Baker       v.    Nelson,     
    191 N.W.2d 185
           (Minn.    1971),
    appeal dismissed, 
    409 U.S. 810
     (1972), just five years after
    Loving    was    decided.             In   Baker,    the    Minnesota        Supreme     Court
    interpreted a state statute’s use of the term “marriage” to be
    one of common usage meaning a union “between persons of the
    opposite sex” and thus not including same-sex marriage.                                
    Id. at 186
    .     On appeal, the Supreme Court dismissed the case summarily
    “for want of a substantial federal question.”                           409 U.S. at 810.
    The Court’s action in context indicates that the Court did not
    view    Loving       or    the    cases     that    preceded      it    as    providing     a
    fundamental right to an unrestricted choice of marriage partner.
    Otherwise, the state court’s decision in Baker would indeed have
    presented a substantial federal question.
    In short, Loving simply held that race, which is completely
    unrelated to the institution of marriage, could not be the basis
    of    marital    restrictions.              See    Loving,   
    388 U.S. at 12
    .      To
    stretch Loving’s holding to say that the right to marry is not
    limited    by    gender      and       sexual      orientation     is    to    ignore     the
    inextricable, biological link between marriage and procreation
    that the Supreme Court has always recognized.                           See Windsor, 133
    82
    S. Ct. at 2689 (recognizing that throughout history, “marriage
    between a man and a woman no doubt had been thought of by most
    people as essential to the very definition of that term and to
    its role and function”).          The state regulation struck down in
    Loving, like those in Zablocki and Turner, had no relationship
    to the foundational purposes of marriage, while the gender of
    the individuals in a marriage clearly does.                Thus, the majority
    errs, as did the district court, by interpreting the Supreme
    Court’s marriage cases as establishing a right that includes
    same-sex marriage.
    The plaintiffs also largely ignore the problem with their
    position that if the fundamental right to marriage is based on
    “the    constitutional   liberty    to     select   the    partner    of   one’s
    choice,” as they contend, then that liberty would also extend to
    individuals    seeking    state     recognition       of    other     types    of
    relationships that States currently restrict, such as polygamous
    or incestuous relationships.        Cf. Romer v. Evans, 
    517 U.S. 620
    ,
    648-50 (1996) (Scalia, J., dissenting).             Such an extension would
    be     a   radical    shift   in     our     understanding       of     marital
    relationships.       Laws restricting polygamy are foundational to
    the Union itself, having been a condition on the entrance of
    Arizona, New Mexico, Oklahoma, and Utah into statehood.                       
    Id.
    While the plaintiffs do attempt to assure us that such laws are
    safe because “there are weighty government interests underlying”
    83
    them, such an argument does not bear on the question of whether
    the   right    is   fundamental.         The    government’s       interests    would
    instead be relevant only to whether the restriction could meet
    the requisite standard of review.                And because laws prohibiting
    polygamous or incestuous marriages restrict individuals’ right
    to choose whom they would like to marry, they would, under the
    plaintiffs’ approach, have to be examined under strict scrutiny.
    Perhaps    the   government’s        interest     would    be    strong    enough    to
    enable such laws to survive strict scrutiny, but regardless,
    today’s decision would truly be a sweeping one if it could be
    understood to mean that individuals have a fundamental right to
    enter into a marriage with any person, or any people, of their
    choosing.
    At   bottom,     the       fundamental    right     to    marriage    does    not
    include    a   right   to    same-sex    marriage.         Under    the    Glucksberg
    analysis that we are thus bound to conduct, there is no new
    fundamental      right      to     same-sex     marriage.          Virginia’s      laws
    restricting marriage to man-woman relationships must therefore
    be upheld if there is any rational basis for the laws.
    III
    Under rational-basis review, courts are required to give
    heavy deference to legislatures.               The standard
    simply requires courts to                  determine       whether the
    classification in  question                 is,   at       a   minimum,
    84
    rationally related to legitimate governmental goals.
    In other words, the fit between the enactment and the
    public purposes behind it need not be mathematically
    precise.     As long as [the legislature] has a
    reasonable basis for adopting the classification,
    which can include “rational speculation unsupported by
    evidence or empirical data,” the statute will pass
    constitutional muster.     The rational basis standard
    thus embodies an idea critical to the continuing
    vitality of our democracy:       that courts are not
    empowered to “sit as a superlegislature to judge the
    wisdom   or    desirability   of   legislative  policy
    determinations.”
    Wilkins v. Gaddy, 
    734 F.3d 344
    , 347-48 (4th Cir. 2013) (emphasis
    added) (citations omitted) (quoting FCC v. Beach Commc’ns, Inc.,
    
    508 U.S. 307
    , 315 (1993); City of New Orleans v. Dukes, 
    427 U.S. 297
    , 303 (1976)).      Statutes subject to rational-basis review
    “bear[] a strong presumption of validity, and those attacking
    the rationality of the legislative classification have the
    burden ‘to negative every conceivable basis which might support
    [them].’”   Beach Commc’ns, 
    508 U.S. at 314-15
     (emphasis added)
    (citation omitted) (quoting Lehnhausen v. Lake Shore Auto Parts
    Co., 
    410 U.S. 356
    , 364 (1973)).
    In   contending    that   there    is   a   rational   basis   for   its
    marriage laws, Virginia has emphasized that children are born
    only to one man and one woman and that marriage provides a
    family structure by which to nourish and raise those children.
    It claims that a biological family is a more stable environment,
    and it renounces any interest in encouraging same-sex marriage.
    It argues that the purpose of its marriage laws “is to channel
    85
    the presumptive procreative potential of man-woman relationships
    into enduring marital unions so that if any children are born,
    they   are   more       likely    to     be    raised      in     stable    family       units.”
    (Emphasis omitted).              Virginia highlights especially marriage’s
    tendency     to     promote       stability          in     the    event        of    unplanned
    pregnancies, asserting that it has “a compelling interest in
    addressing the particular concerns associated with the birth of
    unplanned      children.      .    .     .         [C]hildren      born     from       unplanned
    pregnancies where their mother and father are not married to
    each   other      are    at   significant           risk    of    being     raised       outside
    stable family units headed by their mother and father jointly.”
    Virginia     states        that       its     justifications           for     promoting
    traditional       marriage        also       explain       its    lack     of    interest    in
    promoting same-sex marriage.                    It maintains that a traditional
    marriage       is       “exclusively           [an]        opposite-sex              institution
    . . . inextricably            linked          to     procreation           and        biological
    kinship,” Windsor, 133 S. Ct. at 2718 (Alito, J., dissenting),
    and that same-sex marriage prioritizes the emotions and sexual
    attractions of the two partners without any necessary link to
    reproduction.       It asserts that it has no interest in “licensing
    adults’ love.”
    The plaintiffs accept that family stability is a legitimate
    state goal, but they argue that licensing same-sex relationships
    will   not   burden       Virginia’s          achievement         of   that      goal.     They
    86
    contend that “there is simply no evidence or reason to believe
    that     prohibiting           gay    men      and    lesbians         from      marrying    will
    increase ‘responsible procreation’ among heterosexuals.”
    But    this    argument         does     not    negate      any      of    the   rational
    justifications for Virginia’s legislation.                             States are permitted
    to    selectively         provide      benefits       to    only    certain         groups    when
    providing those same benefits to other groups would not further
    the State’s ultimate goals.                     See Johnson v. Robinson, 
    415 U.S. 361
    , 383 (1974) (“When . . . the inclusion of one group promotes
    a legitimate governmental purpose, and the addition of other
    groups       would        not,       we     cannot         say     that       the       statute's
    classification            of      beneficiaries            and     nonbeneficiaries            is
    invidiously discriminatory”).                    Here, the Commonwealth’s goal of
    ensuring that unplanned children are raised in stable homes is
    furthered only by offering the benefits of marriage to opposite-
    sex    couples.           As    Virginia       correctly         asserts,        “the    relevant
    inquiry      here    is    not       whether     excluding        same-sex        couples    from
    marriage     furthers          [Virginia’s]          interest     in    steering        man-woman
    couples into marriage.”                 Rather, the relevant inquiry is whether
    also    recognizing            same-sex     marriages       would       further      Virginia’s
    interests.          With       regard     to    its    interest        in     ensuring      stable
    families in the event of unplanned pregnancies, it would not.
    The plaintiffs reply that even if this is so, such “line-
    drawing” only makes sense if the resources at issue are scarce,
    87
    justifying      the    State’s     limited         provision     of    those    resources.
    They   argue    that    because      “[m]arriage          licenses . . . are         not   a
    remotely scarce commodity,” the line-drawing done by Virginia’s
    marriage       laws     is       irrational.             But      this      fundamentally
    misunderstands        the    nature      of    marriage         benefits.         When   the
    Commonwealth     grants      a    marriage,        it    does    not   simply     give   the
    couple a piece of paper and a title.                            Rather, it provides a
    substantial subsidy to the married couple -- economic benefits
    that, the plaintiffs repeatedly assert, are being denied them.
    For example, married couples are permitted to file state income
    taxes jointly, lowering their tax rates.                           See 
    Va. Code Ann. § 58.1-324
    .           Although     indirect,         such       benefits    are     clearly
    subsidies that come at a cost to the Commonwealth.                             Virginia is
    willing    to    provide         these   subsidies          because      they     encourage
    opposite-sex couples to marry, which tends to provide children
    from   unplanned       pregnancies        with       a   more     stable    environment.
    Under Johnson, the Commonwealth is not obligated to similarly
    subsidize same-sex marriages, since doing so could not possibly
    further its interest.             This is no different from the subsidies
    provided in other cases where the Supreme Court has upheld line-
    drawing, such as Medicare benefits, Matthews v. Diaz, 
    426 U.S. 67
    , 83-84 (1976), or veterans’ educational benefits, Johnson,
    
    415 U.S. at 383
    .
    88
    As an additional argument, Virginia maintains that marriage
    is   a    “[c]omplex      social    institution[]”             with    a    “set    of    norms,
    rules, patterns, and expectations that powerfully (albeit often
    unconsciously)           affect        people’s          choices,            actions,        and
    perspectives.”            It   asserts       that    discarding             the    traditional
    definition of marriage will have far-reaching consequences that
    cannot easily be predicted, including “sever[ing] the inherent
    link      between       procreation . . . and              marriage . . . [and]               in
    turn . . . powerfully             convey[ing]        that        marriage          exists     to
    advance        adult    desires     rather        than    [to]        serv[e]       children’s
    needs.”
    The   plaintiffs      agree     that       changing          the     definition       of
    marriage may have unforeseen social effects, but they argue that
    such      predictions      should      not    be     enough       to        save    Virginia’s
    marriage laws because similar justifications were rejected in
    Loving.        The Loving Court, however, was not applying rational-
    basis review.           See Loving, 
    388 U.S. at 11-12
    .                            We are on a
    different        footing       here.           Under           rational-basis             review,
    legislative         choices    “may     be    based       on     rational          speculation
    unsupported by evidence or empirical data.”                           Beach Commc’ns, 
    508 U.S. at 315
    .           “Sound policymaking often requires legislators to
    forecast future events and to anticipate the likely impact of
    these      events      based   on   deductions           and    inferences          for    which
    complete empirical support may be unavailable.”                               Turner Broad.
    89
    Sys., Inc. v. FCC, 
    512 U.S. 622
    , 665 (1994) (plurality opinion).
    And the legislature “is far better equipped than the judiciary”
    to make these evaluations and ultimately decide on a course of
    action based on its predictions.                   
    Id. at 665-66
    .          In enacting
    its     marriage     laws,       Virginia        predicted      that   changing         the
    definition of marriage would have a negative effect on children
    and on the family structure.               Although other States do not share
    those    concerns,        such    evaluations       were       nonetheless      squarely
    within the province of the Commonwealth’s legislature and its
    citizens, who voted to amend Virginia’s Constitution in 2006.
    Virginia     has    undoubtedly      articulated         sufficient      rational
    bases for its marriage laws, and I would find that those bases
    constitutionally justify the laws.                  Those laws are grounded on
    the biological connection of men and women; the potential for
    their    having     children;       the    family     order      needed    in       raising
    children; and, on a larger scale, the political order resulting
    from    stable     family    units.        Moreover,       I   would   add      that   the
    traditional marriage relationship encourages a family structure
    that is intergenerational, giving children not only a structure
    in    which   to    be    raised    but     also    an   identity      and      a    strong
    relational context.              The marriage of a man and a woman thus
    rationally promotes a correlation between biological order and
    political     order.             Because    Virginia’s          marriage     laws      are
    90
    rationally related to its legitimate purposes, they withstand
    rational-basis scrutiny under the Due Process Clause.
    IV
    The majority does not substantively address the plaintiffs’
    second    argument    --   that     Virginia’s      marriage    laws    invidiously
    discriminate on the basis of sexual orientation, in violation of
    the Equal Protection Clause -- since it finds that the laws
    infringe on the plaintiffs’ fundamental right to marriage.                         But
    because I find no fundamental right is infringed by the laws, I
    also address discrimination under the Equal Protection Clause.
    The Equal Protection Clause, which forbids any State from
    “deny[ing]    to     any   person    within    its    jurisdiction        the     equal
    protection of the laws,” U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 1, prohibits
    invidious     discrimination        among     classes     of    persons.          Some
    classifications -- such as those based on race, alienage, or
    national origin -- are “so seldom relevant to the achievement of
    any   legitimate      state   interest       that     laws     grounded      in    such
    considerations are deemed to reflect prejudice and antipathy --
    a view that those in the burdened class are not as worthy or
    deserving as others.”         City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr.,
    
    473 U.S. 432
    , 440 (1985).              Any laws based on such “suspect”
    classifications are subject to strict scrutiny.                       See 
    id.
         In a
    similar     vein,    classifications        based    on      gender    are    “quasi-
    91
    suspect”      and      call    for     “intermediate       scrutiny”         because    they
    “frequently         bear[]      no   relation       to   ability        to    perform     or
    contribute to society” and thus “generally provide[] no sensible
    ground      for   differential         treatment.”         
    Id. at 440-41
         (quoting
    Frontiero v. Richardson, 
    411 U.S. 677
    , 686 (1973) (plurality
    opinion)); see also Craig v. Boren, 
    429 U.S. 190
    , 197 (1976).
    Laws   subject         to    intermediate       scrutiny    must      be     substantially
    related to an important government objective.                         See United States
    v. Virginia, 
    518 U.S. 515
    , 533 (1996).
    But when a regulation adversely affects members of a class
    that     is    not      suspect      or   quasi-suspect,         the       regulation    is
    “presumed         to    be     valid      and    will      be    sustained         if    the
    classification drawn by the statute is rationally related to a
    legitimate state interest.”                City of Cleburne, 
    473 U.S. at 440
    (emphasis added).             Moreover, the Supreme Court has made it clear
    that
    where individuals in the group affected by a law have
    distinguishing characteristics relevant to interests
    the State has the authority to implement, the courts
    have been very reluctant, as they should be in our
    federal system and with our respect for the separation
    of powers, to closely scrutinize legislative choices
    as to whether, how, and to what extent those interests
    should be pursued.       In such cases, the Equal
    Protection Clause requires only a rational means to
    serve a legitimate end.
    
    Id. at 441-42
            (emphasis     added).        This      is      based   on   the
    understanding that “equal protection of the laws must coexist
    92
    with the practical necessity that most legislation classifies
    for    one    purpose      or    another,       with      resulting    disadvantage        to
    various groups or persons.”               Romer, 
    517 U.S. at 631
    .
    The plaintiffs contend that Virginia’s marriage laws should
    be subjected to some level of heightened scrutiny because they
    discriminate        on    the    basis    of     sexual     orientation.           Yet    they
    concede that neither the Supreme Court nor the Fourth Circuit
    has ever applied heightened scrutiny to a classification based
    on sexual orientation.               They urge this court to do so for the
    first time.        Governing precedent, however, counsels otherwise.
    In Romer v. Evans, the Supreme Court did not employ any
    heightened         level    of       scrutiny        in     evaluating        a     Colorado
    constitutional           amendment       that       prohibited       state        and    local
    governments from enacting legislation that would allow persons
    to    claim    “any      minority     status,       quota    preferences,          protected
    status, or . . . discrimination” based on sexual orientation.
    Romer,       
    517 U.S. at 624
    .            In     holding     the        amendment
    unconstitutional under the Equal Protection Clause, the Court
    applied rational-basis review.                  See 
    id. at 631-33
    .
    And the Supreme Court made no change as to the appropriate
    level of scrutiny in its more recent decision in Windsor, which
    held Section 3 of the Defense of Marriage Act unconstitutional.
    The    Court    was      presented       an    opportunity      to    alter       the    Romer
    standard but did not do so.                   Although it did not state the level
    93
    of scrutiny being applied, it did explicitly rely on rational-
    basis cases like Romer and Department of Agriculture v. Moreno,
    
    413 U.S. 528
     (1973).          See Windsor, 
    133 S. Ct. at 2693
    .               In his
    dissenting opinion in Windsor, Justice Scalia thus noted, “As
    nearly    as   I   can   tell,   the    Court    agrees     [that   rational-basis
    review applies]; its opinion does not apply strict scrutiny, and
    its   central      propositions       are   taken   from    rational-basis    cases
    like Moreno.”       
    Id. at 2706
     (Scalia, J., dissenting).
    Finally,      we   have     concluded      that      rational-basis    review
    applies to classifications based on sexual orientation.                          See
    Veney v. Wyche, 
    293 F.3d 726
    , 731-32 (4th Cir. 2002).                    In Veney,
    a prisoner filed a § 1983 action alleging that he had been
    discriminated       against     on    the   basis   of    sexual    preference   and
    gender.     Id. at 729-30.           We noted that the plaintiff “[did] not
    allege that he [was] a member of a suspect class.                       Rather, he
    claim[ed] that he ha[d] been discriminated against on the basis
    of sexual preference and gender.                 Outside the prison context,
    the former is subject to rational basis review, see Romer v.
    Evans, 
    517 U.S. 620
    , 631-32 (1996).”                     
    Id. at 731-32
     (footnote
    omitted).
    The vast majority of other courts of appeals have reached
    the same conclusion.            See Cook v. Gates, 
    528 F.3d 42
    , 61 (1st
    Cir. 2008) (“Romer nowhere suggested that the Court recognized a
    new suspect class.         Absent additional guidance from the Supreme
    94
    Court, we join our sister circuits in declining to read Romer as
    recognizing homosexuals as a suspect class for equal protection
    purposes”); Price-Cornelison v. Brooks, 
    524 F.3d 1103
    , 1113-14 &
    n.9       (10th         Cir.          2008)            (“A       government               official
    can . . . distinguish           between          its     citizens       on     the       basis     of
    sexual    orientation,         if     that       classification          bears       a    rational
    relation       to    some     legitimate          end”       (internal       quotation       marks
    omitted)); Citizens for Equal Prot. v. Bruning, 
    455 F.3d 859
    ,
    865-66    (8th       Cir.     2006)       (discussing         Romer      and    reaching          the
    conclusion       that       “[t]hough       the       most    relevant       precedents          are
    murky,    we    conclude      for     a    number       of    reasons     that       [Nebraska’s
    same-sex       marriage       ban]    should          receive    rational-basis             review
    under    the    Equal       Protection          Clause,      rather     than    a     heightened
    level of judicial scrutiny”); Johnson v. Johnson, 
    385 F.3d 503
    ,
    532 (5th Cir. 2004) (“[A] state violates the Equal Protection
    Clause if it disadvantages homosexuals for reasons lacking any
    rational relationship to legitimate governmental aims”); Lofton
    v. Sec’y of Dep’t of Children & Family Servs., 
    358 F.3d 804
    , 818
    (11th    Cir.       2004)    (“[A]ll       of     our     sister       circuits       that       have
    considered the question have declined to treat homosexuals as a
    suspect    class.           Because       the    present       case    involves          neither    a
    fundamental          right      nor         a         suspect         class,        we      review
    the . . . statute under the rational-basis standard” (footnote
    omitted)); Equal. Found. of Greater Cincinnati, Inc. v. City of
    95
    Cincinnati, 
    128 F.3d 289
    , 294, 300 (6th Cir. 1997) (applying
    rational-basis       review       in    upholding     a    city    charter        amendment
    restricting homosexual rights and stating that in Romer, the
    Court     “did    not     assess       Colorado      Amendment      2     under    ‘strict
    scrutiny’    or     ‘intermediate         scrutiny’        standards,       but    instead
    ultimately       applied      ‘rational    relationship’          strictures       to    that
    enactment and resolved that the Colorado state constitutional
    provision    did    not       invade    any     fundamental       right    and     did    not
    target any suspect class or quasi-suspect class”); Ben-Shalom v.
    Marsh, 
    881 F.2d 454
    , 464 (7th Cir. 1989) (applying rational-
    basis review prior to the announcement of Romer); Woodward v.
    United    States,       
    871 F.2d 1068
    ,      1076   (Fed.    Cir.     1989)       (“The
    Supreme Court has identified only three suspect classes:                             racial
    status,    national       ancestry      and     ethnic    original,       and     alienage.
    Two other classifications have been identified by the Court as
    quasi-suspect:          gender and illegitimacy.            [Plaintiff] would have
    this court add homosexuality to that list.                        This we decline to
    do”    (citations       and    footnote       omitted)).       But      see     SmithKline
    Beecham Corp. v. Abbott Labs., 
    740 F.3d 471
    , 481 (9th Cir. 2014)
    (applying heightened scrutiny to a Batson challenge that was
    based on sexual orientation); Windsor v. United States, 
    699 F.3d 169
    ,     180-85    (2d     Cir.    2012)        (finding    intermediate           scrutiny
    appropriate in assessing the constitutionality of Section 3 of
    the Defense of Marriage Act).
    96
    Thus, following Supreme Court and Fourth Circuit precedent,
    I   would   hold    that   Virginia’s         marriage   laws    are   subject    to
    rational-basis review.           Applying that standard, I conclude that
    there is a rational basis for the laws, as explained in Part
    III, above.        At bottom, I agree with Justice Alito’s reasoning
    that   “[i]n    asking     the    court    to    determine      that   [Virginia’s
    marriage laws are] subject to and violate[] heightened scrutiny,
    [the plaintiffs] thus ask us to rule that the presence of two
    members of the opposite sex is as rationally related to marriage
    as white skin is to voting or a Y-chromosome is to the ability
    to administer an estate.            That is a striking request and one
    that unelected judges should pause before granting.”                        Windsor,
    133 S. Ct. at 2717-18 (Alito, J., dissenting).
    V
    Whether to recognize same-sex marriage is an ongoing and
    highly engaged political debate taking place across the Nation,
    and the States are divided on the issue.                 The majority of courts
    have   struck   down     statutes    that      deny   recognition      of   same-sex
    marriage, doing so almost exclusively on the idea that same-sex
    marriage is encompassed by the fundamental right to marry that
    is protected by the Due Process Clause.                    While I express no
    viewpoint on the merits of the policy debate, I do strongly
    disagree with the assertion that same-sex marriage is subject to
    97
    the same constitutional protections as the traditional right to
    marry.
    Because there is no fundamental right to same-sex marriage
    and there are rational reasons for not recognizing it, just as
    there are rational reasons for recognizing it, I conclude that
    we,   in   the   Third    Branch,   must     allow   the    States    to   enact
    legislation on the subject in accordance with their political
    processes.       The   U.S.   Constitution    does   not,   in   my   judgment,
    restrict the States’ policy choices on this issue.               If given the
    choice, some States will surely recognize same-sex marriage and
    some will surely not.         But that is, to be sure, the beauty of
    federalism.
    I would reverse the district court’s judgment and defer to
    Virginia’s political choice in defining marriage as only between
    one man and one woman.
    98
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 14-1167

Filed Date: 7/28/2014

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 10/30/2014

Authorities (52)

Varnum v. Brien , 2009 Iowa Sup. LEXIS 31 ( 2009 )

Lexmark Int'l, Inc. v. Static Control Components, Inc. , 134 S. Ct. 1377 ( 2014 )

Regents of the University of California v. Bakke , 98 S. Ct. 2733 ( 1978 )

Lucas v. Forty-Fourth General Assembly of Colorado , 84 S. Ct. 1459 ( 1964 )

Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey , 112 S. Ct. 2791 ( 1992 )

Hollingsworth v. Perry , 133 S. Ct. 2652 ( 2013 )

Horne v. Flores , 129 S. Ct. 2579 ( 2009 )

Ohio Ex Rel. Eaton v. Price , 79 S. Ct. 978 ( 1959 )

Port Authority Bondholders Protective Committee, Henry W. ... , 387 F.2d 259 ( 1967 )

equality-foundation-of-greater-cincinnati-inc-richard-buchanan-chad-bush , 128 F.3d 289 ( 1997 )

miriam-ben-shalom-v-john-o-marsh-jr-secretary-of-the-army-vance , 881 F.2d 454 ( 1989 )

Village of Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing ... , 97 S. Ct. 555 ( 1977 )

Reno v. Flores , 113 S. Ct. 1439 ( 1993 )

Washington v. Glucksberg , 117 S. Ct. 2258 ( 1997 )

Mathews v. Diaz , 96 S. Ct. 1883 ( 1976 )

West Virginia State Board of Education v. Barnette , 63 S. Ct. 1178 ( 1943 )

Stanley v. Illinois , 92 S. Ct. 1208 ( 1972 )

Collins v. City of Harker Heights , 112 S. Ct. 1061 ( 1992 )

Federal Communications Commission v. Beach Communications, ... , 113 S. Ct. 2096 ( 1993 )

Northeastern Florida Chapter of the Associated General ... , 113 S. Ct. 2297 ( 1993 )

View All Authorities »