Grutter v. Bollinger ( 2002 )


Menu:
  •                     RECOMMENDED FOR FULL-TEXT PUBLICATION
    Pursuant to Sixth Circuit Rule 206
    ELECTRONIC CITATION: 
    2002 FED App. 0170P (6th Cir.)
    File Name: 02a0170p.06
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    ____________________
    BARBARA GRUTTER,
    Plaintiff-Appellee,
    v.                                                Nos. 01-1447/1516
    LEE BOLLINGER, et al.,
    Defendants-Appellants (01-1447),
    KIMBERLY JAMES, et al.,
    Intervening
    Defendants-Appellants (01-1516).
    /
    Appeal from the United States District Court for the Eastern District of Michigan at Detroit.
    No. 97-75928—Bernard A. Friedman, District Judge.
    Argued: December 6, 2001
    Decided and Filed: May 14, 2002
    Before: MARTIN, Chief Circuit Judge; BOGGS, SILER, BATCHELDER, DAUGHTREY,
    MOORE, COLE, CLAY, and GILMAN, Circuit Judges.
    ____________________
    COUNSEL
    ARGUED: John Payton, WILMER, CUTLER & PICKERING, Washington, D.C., Miranda K.S.
    Massie, SCHEFF & WASHINGTON, Detroit, Michigan, for Defendants. Kirk O. Kolbo,
    MASLON, EDELMAN, BORMAN & BRAND, Minneapolis, Minnesota, for Plaintiff. ON BRIEF:
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 2
    John Payton, John H. Pickering, Craig Goldblatt, Stuart F. Delery, Robin A. Lenhardt, WILMER,
    CUTLER & PICKERING, Washington, D.C., Philip J. Kessler, BUTZEL LONG, Detroit, Michigan,
    Leonard M. Niehoff, BUTZEL LONG, Ann Arbor, Michigan, Miranda K.S. Massie, George B.
    Washington, Jodi-Marie Masley, SCHEFF & WASHINGTON, Detroit, Michigan, for Defendants.
    Kirk O. Kolbo, David F. Herr, R. Lawrence Purdy, Michael C. McCarthy, Kai H. Richter,
    MASLON, EDELMAN, BORMAN & BRAND, Minneapolis, Minnesota, Michael E. Rosman,
    CENTER FOR INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS, Washington, D.C., for Plaintiff. Rowan D. Wilson, Paul
    M. Dodyk, Charles J. Ha, Farah S. Brelvi, Alexandra S. Wald, Kenneth E. Lee, CRAVATH,
    SWAINE & MOORE, New York, New York, Martha W. Barnett, AMERICAN BAR
    ASSOCIATION, Chicago, Illinois, Kumiki Gibson, WILLIAMS & CONNOLLY, Washington,
    D.C., Neal K. Katyal, GEORGETOWN UNIVERSITY LAW CENTER, Washington, D.C., Martin
    Michaelson, HOGAN & HARTSON, Washington, D.C., Thomas J. Henderson, LAWYERS’
    COMMITTEE FOR CIVIL RIGHTS UNDER LAW, Washington, D.C., John S. Skilton, HELLER,
    EHRMAN, WHITE & McAULIFFE, Washington, D.C., Kenneth S. Geller, Eileen Penner, MAYER,
    BROWN & PLATT, Washington, D.C., Martha F. Davis, Spenta R. Cama, NOW LEGAL
    DEFENSE AND EDUCATION FUND, New York, New York, Susan I. Leffler, OFFICE OF THE
    ATTORNEY GENERAL, Lansing, Michigan, Fred G. Pressley, Jr., PORTER, WRIGHT, MORRIS
    & ARTHUR, Columbus, Ohio, Jeffrey S. Silver, JENNER & BLOCK, Chicago, Illlinois, Deanne
    E. Maynard, Shilpa S. Satoskar, David W. DeBruin, Daniel Mach, JENNER & BLOCK,
    Washington, D.C., Yong Lee, CAMERON & HORNBOSTEL, Washington, D.C., Catherine J.
    Trafton, Daniel W. Sherrick, ASSOCIATE GENERAL COUNSEL, INTERNATIONAL UNION,
    UAW, Detroit, Michigan, John H. Findley, PACIFIC LEGAL FOUNDATION, Sacramento,
    California, Keith A. Noreika, Brice M. Clagett, COVINGTON & BURLING, Washington, D.C., C.
    Mark Pickrell, Nashville, Tennessee, Michael K. Lee, AMBERG, FIRESTONE & LEE, Southfield,
    Michigan, for Amici Curiae.
    MARTIN, C. J., delivered the opinion of the court, in which, DAUGHTREY, MOORE,
    COLE, and CLAY, JJ., joined. MOORE, J. (pp. 21-27), delivered a separate concurring opinion,
    in which DAUGHTREY, COLE, and CLAY, JJ., joined. CLAY, J. (pp. 28-44), delivered a separate
    concurring opinion, in which DAUGHTREY, MOORE, and COLE, JJ., joined. BOGGS, J. (pp. 45-
    89), delivered a separate dissent, in which SILER, J., joined in part, and BATCHELDER, J., joined.
    SILER, J. (p. 90), BATCHELDER, J. (p. 91), and GILMAN, (pp. 92-94), also delivered separate
    dissenting opinions.
    _________________
    OPINION
    _________________
    BOYCE F. MARTIN, JR., Chief Circuit Judge. Lee Bollinger, Jeffrey Lehman, Dennis
    Shields, the Regents of the University of Michigan and the University of Michigan Law School
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 3
    appeal the district court’s determination that the Law School’s consideration of race and ethnicity
    in its admissions decisions violates the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment and
    Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964.1 The Law School contends that its interest in achieving a
    diverse student body is compelling under Regents of the University of California v. Bakke, 
    438 U.S. 265
    , 
    98 S.Ct. 2733
    , 
    57 L.Ed.2d 750
     (1978), and that its admissions policy is narrowly tailored to
    serve that interest. On appeal, the Law School is joined by the Intervenors: forty-one individuals and
    three student groups, United for Equality and Affirmative Action, the Coalition to Defend
    Affirmative Action By Any Means Necessary, and Law Students for Affirmative Action. The
    Intervenors offer an additional justification for the Law School’s consideration of race and ethnicity
    – remedying past discrimination. Barbara Grutter, an unsuccessful applicant to the Law School, on
    behalf of herself and others similarly situated, urges us to affirm the district court’s decision. For
    the reasons set forth below, we REVERSE the judgment of the district court.2
    I.
    The Law School drafted its admissions policy to comply with the Supreme Court’s opinion
    in Bakke. Adopted by the full faculty in 1992, the policy states that the Law School’s “goal is to
    admit a group of students who individually and collectively are among the most capable students
    applying to American law schools in a given year.” It further provides that the Law School “seek[s]
    a mix of students with varying backgrounds and experiences who will respect and learn from each
    other.” As part of the Law School’s policy of evaluating each applicant individually, its officials read
    each application and factor all of the accompanying information into their decision.
    In identifying applicants who can be expected to succeed academically, the Law School
    evaluates a composite of the applicant’s Law School Admissions Test and undergraduate grade-point
    average. This composite can be visualized as a grid with standardized test scores on the horizontal
    axis and grade-point average on the vertical axis. Every combination of standardized test score and
    undergraduate grade-point average is shown in a cell on this grid. Each cell reports the number of
    applicants with that particular combination of numerical qualifications, as well as the number of
    offers of admission made to the applicants in that cell. Constructed in this manner, the highest
    combination of test scores and undergraduate grade-point averages are found in the grid’s upper
    right-hand corner. Thus, an applicant’s chance of being admitted generally increases as he or she
    1
    Until recently, Lee Bollinger was the president of the University of Michigan. Prior to his
    presidency, he was dean of the Law School. His successor as dean was Jeffrey Lehman. Dennis
    Shields was the director of the Law School’s admission program until 1998.
    2
    Our decision only pertains to the case involving the Law School. We will address the
    challenge to the University of Michigan’s admissions policy, Gratz v. Bollinger, Nos. 01-1333, 01-
    1416, 01-1418, 01-1438, in a forthcoming opinion.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 4
    moves into the grid’s upper right-hand corner. There is no combination of grades and test scores,
    however, below which an applicant will automatically be denied admission, or above which
    admission is guaranteed.
    The Law School also considers “soft” variables like the enthusiasm of the recommenders,
    the quality of the undergraduate institution, the quality of the applicant’s essay, residency, leadership
    and work experience, unique talents or interests, and the areas and difficulty of undergraduate course
    selection. After taking these additional “soft” variables into account, the Law School sometimes
    admits students with relatively low index scores. Its admissions policy describes two general
    varieties of students who may be admitted with such scores – (1) “students for whom [there is] good
    reason to be skeptical of an index score based prediction” (e.g., a student with a track record of poor
    standardized test performance, but who has an outstanding academic record) and (2) students who
    “may help achieve that diversity which has the potential to enrich everyone’s education and thus
    make a law school class stronger than the sum of its parts.”
    The Law School’s admissions policy explains that “[t]here are many possible bases for
    diversity admissions.” For example, the policy states that particular weight might be given to “an
    Olympic gold medal, a Ph.D. in physics, the attainment of age 50 in a class that otherwise lacked
    anyone over 30, or the experience of having been a Vietnamese boat person.” The policy also offers
    three examples of actual diversity admissions. One student was born in Bangladesh, graduated from
    Harvard with a 2.67 grade-point average, received “outstanding references” from his professors, had
    an “exceptional record of extracurricular activity,” and had Law School Admission Test scores at
    the 46th percentile and 52nd percentile. Another was an Argentinian single mother with extensive
    business experience, who graduated summa cum laude from the University of Cincinnati, who was
    fluent in four languages, and scored at the 52nd percentile on the Law School Admission Test. The
    third applicant had a 3.99 grade-point average from the University of Florida, a Law School
    Admission Test score at the 90th percentile, and as the daughter of Greek immigrants was “immersed
    in a significantly ethnic home life,” and fluent in three languages.
    Reflecting the Law School’s goal of enrolling a diverse class, its admissions policy describes
    “a commitment to racial and ethnic diversity with special reference to the inclusion of students from
    groups which have been historically discriminated against, like African-Americans, Hispanics and
    Native Americans, who without this commitment might not be represented in our student body in
    meaningful numbers.” Students from such racial and ethnic groups “are particularly likely to have
    experiences and perspectives of special importance to our mission.” Professor Richard Lempert, the
    chair of the faculty committee that drafted the admissions policy, explained that the Law School’s
    commitment to such diversity was not intended as a remedy for past discrimination, but as a means
    of including students who may bring a different perspective to the Law School.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 5
    In considering race and ethnicity, the Law School does not set aside or reserve seats for
    under-represented minority students. As Dean Jeffrey Lehman testified: “We do not have a portion
    of the class that is set aside for a critical mass of under-represented minority students.” This
    testimony was echoed by Dennis Shields, the Law School’s former admissions director, and Erica
    Munzel, the current director of admissions, both of whom testified that the Law School does not
    strive to admit a particular percentage of under-represented minority students. The Law School does,
    however, consider the number of under-represented minority students, and ultimately seeks to enroll
    a meaningful number, or a “critical mass,” of under-represented minority students. According to
    Director Munzel, “critical mass” is a number sufficient to enable under-represented minority students
    to contribute to classroom dialogue without feeling isolated. Similarly, Dean Lehman equated
    “critical mass” with sufficient numbers to ensure under-represented minority students do not feel
    isolated or like spokespersons for their race, and do not feel uncomfortable discussing issues freely
    based on their personal experiences. Professor Lempert and Kent Syverud, the current dean of
    Vanderbilt Law School and a former Michigan Law School professor, offered similar definitions of
    “critical mass.” The Law School’s witnesses also testified that “critical mass” was not a set number
    or percentage. Director Munzel stated that there is no number or percentage, or range of numbers
    or percentages, that constitute a “critical mass.” Likewise, Dean Lehman stated that “critical mass”
    could not be fixed in terms of number or percentage.
    Both the Law School and the unsuccessful applicants presented expert testimony regarding
    the Law School’s use of race in admissions decisions. Analyzing grids of the Law School’s
    admissions data from 1995-2000, the unsuccessful applicants’ statistical expert testified that the
    relative odds of acceptance for Native American, African-American, Mexican-American and Puerto
    Rican applicants were many times greater than for Caucasian applicants and concluded that members
    of these groups were “given an extremely large allowance for admission.”
    According to the Law School’s statistical expert, eliminating race as a factor in the
    admissions process would dramatically lower minority admissions. He predicted, for example, that
    if the Law School could not consider race, under-represented minority students would have
    constituted only 4% of the entering class in 2000, instead of the actual enrollment figure of 14.5%.
    Citing the experience of the University of California at Berkeley after the passage of Proposition 209,
    Dean Lehman echoed these predictions, testifying that he feared under-represented minority
    enrollment would drop to “token” levels if race and ethnicity could not be considered.
    II.
    This Court reviews de novo the district court’s finding that the Law School’s efforts to
    achieve a diverse student body through the consideration of race and ethnic origin is unconstitutional
    and violates Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964. Johnson v. Econ. Dev. Corp., 
    241 F.3d 501
    ,
    509 (6th Cir. 2001); see also Women's Med. Prof. Corp. v. Voinovich, 
    130 F.3d 187
    , 192 (6th Cir.
    1997) (“[A]n appellate court is to conduct an independent review of the record when constitutional
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 6
    facts are at issue.”). To survive constitutional review, the Law School’s consideration of race must
    (1) serve a compelling state interest and (2) be narrowly tailored to achieve that interest. See
    Adarand v. Peña, 
    515 U.S. 200
    , 227, 
    115 S.Ct. 2097
    , 
    132 L.Ed.2d 158
     (1995).3
    A.
    To determine whether the Law School’s interest in achieving a diverse student body is
    compelling, we turn to Bakke. In Bakke, a fragmented Court determined that the Medical School of
    the University of California at Davis, which justified its race-conscious admissions program, in part,
    as necessary to achieve a diverse student body, could not be permanently enjoined from considering
    its applicants’ race because “the State has a substantial interest that legitimately may be served by
    a properly devised admissions program involving the competitive consideration of race and ethnic
    origin.” 
    Id. at 320
    .
    Two distinct opinions support Bakke’s judgment on this issue: Justice Powell’s opinion
    announcing the judgment of the Court, 
    id. at 269-324
    , and Justice Brennan’s opinion concurring in
    the judgment in part and dissenting in part, in which Justices White, Marshall, and Blackmun joined,
    
    id. at 324-79
    .
    Applying intermediate scrutiny, the Brennan concurrence found Davis could constitutionally
    justify its consideration of race as an effort to remedy the effects of societal discrimination. Id. at
    362. Applying strict scrutiny, Justice Powell found “the attainment of a diverse student body . . .
    clearly is a constitutionally permissible goal for an institution of higher education.” Id. at 311-312.
    Justice Powell recognized that a diverse student body promotes an atmosphere of
    “speculation, experiment and creation” that is “essential to the quality of higher education.” Id. at
    312 (quoting Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 
    354 U.S. 234
    , 263, 
    77 S.Ct. 1203
    , 
    1 L.Ed.2d 1311
     (1957)
    (Frankfurter, J. concurring)). Moreover, he noted that, by enriching students’ education with a
    variety of perspectives, experiences, and ideas, a university with a diverse student body helps equip
    its students to be productive members of society. Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 313
     (“[I]t is not too much to
    say that the ‘nation’s future depends upon leaders trained through wide exposure’ to the ideas and
    mores of students as diverse as this Nation of many peoples.”) (quoting Keyishian v. Board of
    Regents, 
    385 U.S. 589
    , 603, 
    87 S.Ct. 675
    , 
    17 L.Ed.2d 629
     (1967)). Accordingly, he concluded “the
    interest of diversity is compelling in the context of a university’s admission program.” 
    Id. at 314
    .
    3
    Because Title VI, which prohibits racial discrimination in programs receiving federal funds,
    proscribes only those racial classifications that would violate the Equal Protection Clause, this court
    need only address whether the Law School’s admissions program is constitutional. See Alexander
    v. Sandoval, 
    532 U.S. 275
    , 282, 
    121 S.Ct. 1511
    , 
    149 L.Ed.2d 517
     (2001).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 7
    Justice Powell’s recognition of the compelling nature of the state’s interest in a diverse
    student body was not limited to undergraduate admissions: “[E]ven at the graduate level, our
    tradition and experience lend support to the view that the contribution of diversity is substantial.”
    
    Id.
     Quoting Sweatt v. Painter, 
    339 U.S. 629
    , 634, 
    70 S.Ct. 848
    , 
    94 L.Ed. 1114
     (1950), he observed:
    “The law school, the proving ground for legal learning and practice, cannot be effective in isolation
    from the individuals and institutions with which the law interacts.” Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 314
    .
    The district court did not dispute the merits of student body diversity. Rather, it
    acknowledged “[t]he evidence defendants submitted . . . demonstrated that the educational
    atmosphere at the law school is improved by the presence of students who represent the greatest
    possible variety of backgrounds and viewpoints.” Grutter v. Bollinger, 
    137 F. Supp. 2d 821
    , 849
    (E.D. Mich. 2001). Nevertheless, it held that achieving a diverse student body is not a compelling
    state interest because (1) it was not bound by Justice Powell’s conclusion in Bakke, and (2) achieving
    a diverse student body cannot be a compelling state interest because the Supreme Court has
    suggested that the only such interest is remedying specific instances of discrimination. See 
    id. at 847-48
    .
    Because Justice Powell’s opinion is binding on this court under Marks v. United States, 
    430 U.S. 188
    , 193, 
    97 S.Ct. 990
    , 
    51 L.Ed.2d 260
     (1977), and because Bakke remains the law until the
    Supreme Court instructs otherwise, we reject the district court’s conclusion and find that the Law
    School has a compelling interest in achieving a diverse student body. 4
    1.
    “When a fragmented Court decides a case and no single rationale explaining the result enjoys
    the assent of five Justices, the holding of the Court may be viewed as that position taken by those
    Members who concurred in the judgments on the narrowest grounds.” Marks, 
    430 U.S. at 193
    (citation and internal punctuation omitted). In Marks, the Court interpreted its fragmented decision
    in Memoirs v. Massachusetts, 
    383 U.S. 413
    , 
    86 S.Ct. 975
    , 
    16 L.Ed.2d 1
     (1966), reversing the
    Massachusetts Supreme Court’s holding that a book depicting a prostitute’s life was suppressible
    obscenity. Three distinct rationales supported Memoirs’s judgment, each representing a different
    view as to the scope of First Amendment protection afforded sexually explicit expression:
    (1) Justices Brennan and Fortas and the Chief Justice found the book was not suppressible obscenity
    because it was not “utterly without redeeming social value,” see 
    id. at 419
    ; (2) Justice Stewart found
    the book was not suppressible obscenity because it was not hardcore pornography, see 
    id. at 421
    ; and
    (3) Justices Black and Douglas did not reach the issue of whether the book was suppressible
    4
    Because we hold that the Law School has a compelling interest in achieving a diverse
    student body, we do not address whether the Intervenors’ proffered interest – an interest in
    remedying past discrimination – is sufficiently compelling for equal protection purposes.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 8
    obscenity because they believed the First Amendment provides an absolute shield against
    government regulation of expression, see 
    id. at 421, 424-28
     (opinions of Black, J. and Douglas, J.).
    See also Marks, 
    430 U.S. at 194
    . The Marks Court determined that the Brennan plurality opinion,
    which provided the most limited First Amendment protection, “constituted the holding of the
    [Memoirs] Court and provided the governing standards” because it was the narrowest rationale for
    the Memoirs judgment.5 
    Id. at 193-94
    .
    The district court declined to apply the Marks analysis to Bakke because Justice Powell’s
    rationale was not “subsumed” in that of the Brennan concurrence. See Grutter, 
    137 F. Supp. 2d at
    5
    Because the Marks Court identified the Memoirs opinion with the most limited scope of
    First Amendment protection as the “narrowest,” the dissent suggests that the most narrow opinion
    under Marks must invariably be “that which construe[s] the constitutional provision in question less
    potently.” Dissenting Op. at 52 (Boggs, J.). Application of the dissent’s cookie-cutter conception
    of Marks narrowness would preclude consideration of a given decision’s actual gravamen.
    Moreover, the dissent’s narrowness conception conflicts with both Supreme Court precedent, see
    City of Lakewood v. Plain Dealer Co., 
    486 U.S. 750
    , 764-65 n.9, 
    108 S.Ct. 2138
    , 
    100 L.Ed.2d 771
    (1988), and our own, see Simmons-Harris v. Zelman, 
    234 F.3d 945
    , 956-57 (6th Cir. 2000).
    In Lakewood, the Court examined Kovacs v. Cooper, 
    336 U.S. 77
    , 
    69 S.Ct. 448
    , 
    93 L.Ed. 513
    (1948). In Kovacs, a plurality of the Court found that an ordinance flatly prohibiting the use of
    sound trucks was constitutional. 
    Id. at 82-85, 89
     (plurality opinion of Reed, J.). Two Justices agreed
    that the flat-prohibition ordinance was constitutional, but reasoned that an ordinance giving a
    licensing official unfettered discretion to prohibit the use of sound trucks – that is, an ordinance that
    would be more conducive to content-based censorship – would also be constitutional. 
    Id. at 89-90, 98
     (opinions of Frankfurter, J. and Jackson, J.). Because the plurality would find discretionary-
    prohibition statutes unconstitutional but would permit flat-prohibition statutes and the concurring
    Justices would find both statutes constitutional, the concurring opinions would be “narrower” under
    the dissent’s conception of Marks. The Supreme Court applied Marks differently: “Clearly, in
    Kovacs, the plurality opinion puts forth the narrowest rationale for the Court’s judgment.”
    Lakewood, 
    486 U.S. at
    764 n.9; see also Zelman, 
    234 F.3d at 956-57
     (examining Mitchell v. Helms,
    
    530 U.S. 793
    , 
    120 S.Ct. 2530
    , 
    147 L.Ed.2d 660
     (2000), and concluding that Justice O’Connor’s
    concurrence – which would require more than a showing of neutrality to find government aid to
    religious schools constitutional – was narrower than the plurality opinion – which would apparently
    find that neutrality alone renders such aid constitutional); cf. Discovery Network, Inc. v. City of
    Cincinnati, 
    946 F.2d 464
    , 470 n.9 (6th Cir. 1991) (examining Metromedia, Inc. v. City of San Diego,
    
    453 U.S. 490
    , 
    101 S.Ct. 2882
    , 
    69 L.Ed.2d 800
     (1981)), and citing Lakewood and Marks for the
    proposition that this court is not bound by the Metromedia plurality’s reasoning that an ordinance,
    which unconstitutionally regulated non-commercial speech, would be constitutional as applied to
    commercial speech because the concurrence argued that the ordinance was unconstitutional as
    applied to both commercial and non-commercial speech).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 9
    847 (“There is simply no overlap between the two rationales”). Accordingly, it found that “Justice
    Powell's discussion of the diversity rationale is not among the governing standards to be gleaned
    from Bakke.” 
    Id.
    The Marks Court’s treatment of the divergent Memoirs rationales, however, demonstrates
    that the rationales supporting the Court’s judgment need not overlap on essential points in order to
    provide a holding that binds lower courts. Indeed, if the Justices agreed on essential points, the
    Marks analysis would be unnecessary. Cf. Alexander v. Sandoval, 
    532 U.S. 275
    , 282, 
    121 S.Ct. 1511
    , 
    149 L.Ed.2d 517
     (2001) (citing discrete portions of the opinions of Justice Powell and the
    Brennan concurrence for the proposition that the Bakke Court determined Title VI’s coverage is
    coextensive with that of the Equal Protection Clause).
    The Marks Court adopted the “utterly without redeeming social value” test as the Memoirs
    holding even though, by rejecting the possibility of suppression, Justices Black and Douglas rejected
    the possibility of any test for identifying suppressible obscenity. In contrast to Justices Black and
    Douglas in Memoirs, the Brennan concurrence did not assert that Davis’s admissions program was
    wholly insulated from review. In fact, the Brennan concurrence agreed with Justice Powell that
    Davis’s admissions program was subject to heightened scrutiny, see Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 359
    (advocating intermediate scrutiny); it expressly disagreed only with his application of strict scrutiny.
    Because Bakke is, if anything, more susceptible to the Marks analysis than the case examined in
    Marks itself, we find the district court erred in failing to analyze Bakke under Marks.
    The Bakke Court addressed the permissibility of racial classifications in academic admissions
    programs. Under the Brennan concurrence’s rationale, the more permissive intermediate scrutiny
    standard would apply to “benign” racial classifications. 
    Id.
     Under Justice Powell’s rationale, strict
    scrutiny would apply to all racial classifications. 
    Id. at 304-07
    . Because the set of constitutionally
    permissible racial classifications under intermediate scrutiny by definition includes those
    classifications constitutionally permissible under strict scrutiny, Justice Powell’s rationale would
    permit the most limited consideration of race; therefore, it is Bakke’s narrowest rationale.
    Accordingly, Justice Powell’s opinion constitutes Bakke’s holding and provides the governing
    standard here.6 See Marks, 
    430 U.S. at 193-94
    ; see also Triplett Grille, Inc. v. City of Akron, 
    40 F.3d 6
    The “narrowest” rationale of a case under Marks must be one capable of supporting the
    Court’s judgment in that case. See Marks, 
    430 U.S. at 193
     (“[T]he holding of the Court may be
    viewed as that position taken by those Members who concurred in the judgments on the narrowest
    grounds.”) (emphasis added) (citation and internal punctuation omitted); see also Triplett Grille, 40
    F.3d at 133-34 (noting that the articulated standard must “necessarily produce results with which a
    majority of the Court from that case would agree”). Therefore, we reject the Eleventh Circuit’s
    suggestion in Johnson v. Board of Regents of the University of Georgia, 
    263 F.3d 1234
    , 1247 (11th
    Cir. 2001), that “the narrowest - i.e, less far-reaching - common ground of the Brennan and Powell
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 10
    129, 134 (6th Cir. 1994) (“While there is some awkwardness in attributing precedential value to an
    opinion of one Supreme Court justice to which no justice adhered, it is the usual practice when that
    is the determinative opinion.”); Smith v. Univ. of Washington, 
    233 F.3d 1188
    , 1200 (9th Cir. 2000).
    Because this court is bound by Justice Powell’s Bakke opinion, we find that the Law School
    has a compelling state interest in achieving a diverse student body.
    2.
    Our determination that Justice Powell’s diversity conclusion binds this court also finds some
    support in the Brennan concurrence’s qualified approval of the Harvard plan in the first footnote of
    its opinion: “We also agree with Mr. Justice POWELL that a plan like the ‘Harvard’ plan . . . is
    constitutional under our approach, at least so long as the use of race to achieve an integrated student
    body is necessitated by the lingering effects of past discrimination.” Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at
    326 n.1
    (Brennan, J., concurring) (citation omitted) (emphasis added). Under the Harvard plan, Harvard
    College justified its race-conscious admissions policy solely on the basis of its efforts to achieve a
    diverse student body. See 
    id. at 316
    . Harvard’s consideration of race could not be constitutional if
    it did not further a constitutionally permissible goal; therefore, by indicating that the Harvard plan
    could be constitutional under its approach, the Brennan concurrence implicitly – but unequivocally
    opinions on the specific subject of student body diversity is that diversity is [only] an ‘important’
    interest,” because application of an “important interest” rationale to Bakke’s facts would produce a
    judgment contrary to that actually reached by the Bakke Court. If student body diversity were only
    an “important” interest, Justice Powell could not join in the Court’s decision to permit “the
    competitive consideration of race and ethnicity” because a plan serving a merely important interest
    would not survive strict scrutiny.
    Moreover, under Marks, this court must follow the reasoning of the concurring opinion with
    the narrowest line of reasoning on the issue of why the California Supreme Court could not
    permanently enjoin Davis from considering race, not – as the dissent suggests – the narrowest line
    of reasoning capable of being gleaned from a conglomeration of the opinions. DLS, Inc. v. City of
    Chattanooga, 
    107 F.3d 403
    , 408-09 n.4 (6th Cir. 1997) ( noting that “with respect to a particular
    issue, [this court] must follow the reasoning of the concurring opinion with the narrowest line of
    reasoning on that issue”) (emphasis added). Because Justice Powell’s opinion provides the
    narrowest support for Bakke’s judgment, we are bound by his reasoning in that opinion; we cannot
    cobble together a holding from various rationales in the discrete Bakke opinions. 
    Id.
     (noting that “we
    do not have the freedom to pick and choose which premises and conclusions we will follow”).
    Accordingly, we cannot accept the dissent’s invitation to extract two holdings from Bakke by
    merging analogous portions of the opinions of Justice Powell and the Brennan concurrence. See
    Dissenting Op. at 55-56 (Boggs, J.).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 11
    – signaled its agreement with Justice Powell’s conclusion that achieving a diverse student body is
    a constitutionally permissible goal.7
    Although there is no support – either within or without the footnote – for the contention that
    the Brennan concurrence believed that the desirability of an “integrated student body” turns on
    whether the consideration of race is necessary to achieve that integration, some courts have read the
    Harvard footnote’s qualifying language, “at least so long as the use of race to achieve an integrated
    student body is necessitated by the lingering effects of past discrimination,” to suggest that the
    Brennan concurrence implicitly rejected the goal of achieving student body diversity. See Hopwood
    v. Texas, 
    78 F.3d 932
    , 944 (5th Cir. 1996).
    It is a mistake, however, to read the qualifying language as a rejection of any rationale. “[A]t
    least so long as” simply does not mean “only if.” Moreover, the qualifying language modifies when
    race may be used: ‘at least so long as . . . necessitated by the lingering effects of past discrimination.’
    It does not modify why.8 This Court cannot ignore the distinction between a constitutionally
    permissible goal – ‘achieving an integrated student body’ – and a constitutionally permissible use
    of race to achieve that goal – ‘so long as necessitated by the lingering effects of past discrimination.’
    7
    Unless one assumes that the Brennan concurrence would have approved the use of race to
    further an unconstitutional goal, the dissent’s aprioristic assertion that the Brennan concurrence
    “certainly did not endorse [Justice Powell’s diversity rationale]” flouts logic. See Dissenting Op.
    at 53 n.6 (Boggs, J.). The operative syllogism is uncomplicated: (1) Under no circumstances may
    race be used to further unconstitutional goals. (2) The Brennan concurrence agrees, at least under
    certain circumstances, that Harvard may use race to further its goal. Thus, the Brennan concurrence
    agrees that Harvard’s goal, ‘achieving an integrated student body,’ is constitutional.
    In fact, just as the Supreme Court was bound by statements from discrete Bakke opinions
    indicating that Title VI’s coverage mirrors that of the Equal Protection Clause, see, e.g., Guardians
    Ass’n v. Civil Service Comm. of New York City, 
    463 U.S. 582
    , 610, 612, 642, 
    103 S.Ct. 3221
    , 
    77 L.Ed.2d 866
     (1983) and Alexander v. Sandoval, 
    532 U.S. 275
    , 282, 
    121 S.Ct. 1511
    , 
    149 L.Ed.2d 517
    (2001), this court would be bound by five Bakke Justices’ agreement that Harvard’s diversity goal
    is constitutional, but for the – unclear – distinction between an “important interest” under
    intermediate scrutiny and a “compelling” interest” under strict scrutiny.
    8
    Hopwood’s reading is akin to construing the sentence “we agree that automobile drivers may
    drive with their lights on, at least so long as the use of lights to see the road is necessitated by the
    effects of nightfall” to suggest seeing the road is a permissible goal only at night. Just as whether
    or not it is night does not qualify the permissibility of trying to see the road, whether or not the use
    of race is necessitated by past discrimination does not qualify the permissibility of seeking “an
    integrated student body.”
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 12
    Therefore, we cannot read the Harvard footnote’s qualifying language to detract from the Brennan
    concurrence’s agreement with Justice Powell’s diversity conclusion.
    3.
    The Court’s subsequent characterization of Bakke further supports our determination that
    Justice Powell’s conclusion is binding. See Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v. FCC, 
    497 U.S. 547
    , 568,
    
    110 S.Ct. 2997
    , 
    111 L.Ed.2d 445
     (1990), overruled on other grounds, Adarand, 
    515 U.S. at 227
    .
    In Metro Broadcasting, Justice Brennan, speaking for the Court in an opinion joined by Justices
    White, Blackmun, Marshall, and Stevens, cited Bakke for the proposition that “‘a diverse student
    body’ contributing to a ‘robust exchange of ideas’ is a ‘constitutionally permissible goal’ on which
    race-conscious university admissions program may be predicated.” Metro Broadcasting, 
    497 U.S. at 568
     (quoting Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 311-13
     (Opinion of Powell, J.)). Metro Broadcasting’s insight
    into Bakke’s holding is persuasive authority, which this court may not ignore. See Wright v. Morris,
    
    111 F.3d 414
    , 419 (6th Cir. 1997).
    4.
    Relying on Adarand and City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., 
    488 U.S. 469
    , 493, 
    109 S.Ct. 706
    , 
    102 L.Ed.2d 854
     (1989), the district court found that “racial classifications are unconstitutional
    unless they are intended to remedy carefully documented effects of past discrimination” and
    therefore concluded that the Law School’s interest in achieving a diverse student body “is not a
    compelling state interest because it is not a remedy for past discrimination.” See Grutter, 
    137 F. Supp. 2d at 849
    . Because the Supreme Court alone retains the ability to overrule its decisions, we
    reject the district court’s conclusion.
    In Bakke, the Supreme Court determined that Davis – an institution that did not purport to
    justify its race-conscious admissions program as necessary to remedy specific past discrimination
    – could consider its applicants’ race. See Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 320
    . Thus, if the only constitutionally
    permissible reason to consider race is remedying specific past discrimination, Bakke’s judgment is
    no longer good law. In other words, adopting the district court’s conclusion that the Law School
    could only justify race-conscious admissions decisions as a remedy for specific past discrimination
    would necessitate a finding that the Supreme Court has implicitly overruled Bakke.
    The Supreme Court, however, has explicitly prohibited just such a finding. See Agostini v.
    Felton, 
    521 U.S. 203
    , 237, 
    117 S. Ct. 1997
    , 
    138 L.Ed.2d 391
     (1997). Rather, “[i]f a precedent of
    [the] Court has direct application in a case, yet appears to rest on reasons rejected in some other line
    of decisions, the Court of Appeals should follow the case which directly controls, leaving to [the
    Supreme] Court the prerogative of overruling its own decisions.” 
    Id.
     (quoting Rodriguez de Quijas
    v. Shearson/Am. Express, Inc., 
    490 U.S. 477
    , 484, 
    109 S.Ct. 1917
    , 
    104 L.Ed.2d 526
     (1989)).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 13
    Moreover, given that (1) Bakke’s judgment suggests that remedying specific past
    discrimination cannot be the only constitutional justification for a race-conscious admissions
    program, and (2) institutions of higher education have been relying on Bakke for more than twenty
    years, see, e.g., Kenneth L. Karst & Harold W. Horowitz, The Bakke Opinions and Equal Protection
    Doctrine, 
    14 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 7
    , 7 (1979) (noting that Bakke provides a “how-to-do-it manual
    for the admission of minority applicants to professional schools”), we are unwilling to infer an intent
    to overrule Bakke – implicitly or otherwise – into the Court’s Adarand decision. See, e.g., Planned
    Parenthood v. Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
    , 855, 
    112 S.Ct. 2791
    , 
    120 L.Ed.2d 674
     (1992) (noting that the
    Court must consider “the cost of a rule’s repudiation as it would fall on those who have relied
    reasonably on the rule’s continued application” and suggesting that stare decisis precludes overruling
    a decision that cannot be overruled “without serious inequity to those who have relied upon it or
    significant damage to the stability of the society governed by it”); see also Dickerson v. United
    States, 
    530 U.S. 428
    , 443, 
    120 S.Ct. 2326
    , 
    147 L.Ed.2d 405
     (2000).
    B.
    Although he found that achieving a diverse student body was a compelling interest, Justice
    Powell declared Davis’s admissions system unconstitutional because it was not narrowly tailored.
    Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 319-20
    . Davis operated a dual-track admissions system featuring a separate
    admissions committee and separate review process for minority applicants. 
    Id. at 273-74
    . Davis also
    established a quota for minority students – for example, in 1974, Davis reserved sixteen spots for
    minority applicants. 
    Id. at 275
    . According to Justice Powell, the critical defect in Davis’s program
    was that non-minority students were “totally excluded from a specific percentage of seats in an
    entering class.” 
    Id. at 319
    .
    As an example of a constitutionally permissible admissions plan, Justice Powell advanced
    the Harvard plan in which race or ethnicity was deemed a “plus,” but did not insulate a minority
    applicant from comparison with other applicants. 
    Id. at 316
    . Under the Harvard plan, an institution
    could consider the race and ethnicity of applicants, but race and ethnicity alone were not the
    exclusive components of academic diversity. 
    Id. at 317
    . Thus, a black applicant could be “examined
    for his potential contribution to diversity without the factor of race being decisive when compared,
    for example, with . . . an Italian-American if the latter is thought to exhibit qualities more likely to
    promote beneficial educational pluralism.” 
    Id.
     According to Justice Powell, such qualities included
    “exceptional personal talents, unique work or service experience, leadership potential, maturity,
    demonstrated compassion, a history of overcoming disadvantage, ability to communicate with the
    poor, or other qualifications deemed important.” 
    Id.
     The Harvard plan was “flexible enough to
    consider all pertinent elements of diversity in light of the particular qualifications of each applicant,
    and to place them on the same footing for consideration, although not necessarily according them
    the same weight.” 
    Id.
     Race could “tip the balance” in an applicant’s favor, but so could other factors
    like “geographic origin or a life spent on a farm.” 
    Id. at 316
    .
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 14
    Above all, the Harvard plan “treat[ed] each applicant as an individual in the admissions
    process.” 
    Id. at 318
    . “The applicant who loses out on the last available seat to another candidate
    receiving a ‘plus’ on the basis of ethnic background will not have been foreclosed from all
    consideration for that seat simply because he was not the right color or had the wrong surname.” 
    Id.
    Rather, his denied admission “would mean only that his combined qualifications, which may have
    included similar nonobjective factors, did not outweigh those of the other applicant.” 
    Id.
    In endorsing the Harvard plan, Justice Powell accepted that a university could not provide
    “a truly heterogen[e]ous environment . . . without some attention to numbers.” 
    Id. at 323
    . As the
    Harvard plan detailed:
    10 or 20 black students could not begin to bring to their classmates and to each other
    the variety of points of view, backgrounds and experiences of blacks in the United
    States. Their small numbers might also create a sense of isolation among the black
    students themselves and thus make it more difficult for them to develop and achieve
    their potential. Consequently, when making its decisions, the Committee on
    Admissions is aware that there is some relationship between numbers and achieving
    the benefits to be derived from a diverse student body, and between numbers and
    providing a reasonable environment for those students admitted. But that awareness
    does not mean that the Committee sets a minimum number of blacks or of people
    from west of the Mississippi who are to be admitted. It means only that in choosing
    among thousands of applicants who are not only ‘admissible’ academically but have
    other strong qualities, the Committee, with a number of criteria in mind, pays some
    attention to distribution among many types and categories of students.
    
    Id. at 323-24
    .
    Justice Powell rejected Justice Brennan’s contention that the distinction between a quota and
    a program that considered race and ethnicity as a potential “plus” was largely illusory. In Justice
    Powell’s view, a “plus” program – unlike a quota – lacked a “facial intent to discriminate.” 
    Id. at 318
    . Emphasizing that the fine distinction between a “plus” and quota system was both discernible
    and constitutionally significant, Justice Powell recalled Justice Frankfurter’s declaration that “‘[a]
    boundary line is none the worse for being narrow.’” 
    Id.
     (quoting McLeod v. Dilworth, 
    322 U.S. 327
    ,
    329, 
    64 S.Ct. 1023
    , 
    88 L.Ed. 1304
     (1944)). Justice Powell added that “a court would not assume that
    a university, professing to employ a facially nondiscriminatory admissions policy, would operate it
    as a cover for the functional equivalent of a quota system.” Id.; see also Johnson v. Transp. Agency,
    
    480 U.S. 616
    , 656, 
    107 S.Ct. 1442
    , 
    94 L.E.2d 615
     (1987) (O’Connor, J., concurring) (approving
    gender-conscious promotion where defendant “tried to look at the whole picture, the combination
    of [her] qualifications and [plaintiff’s] qualifications, their test scores, their experience, their
    background, [and] affirmative action matters”).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 15
    In summary, Justice Powell’s opinion sets forth two guidelines regarding race-conscious
    admissions policies – (1) segregated, dual-track admissions systems utilizing quotas for under-
    represented minorities are unconstitutional; and (2) an admissions policy modeled on the Harvard
    plan, where race and ethnicity are considered a “plus,” does not offend the Equal Protection Clause.
    Neither party questions the applicability of Justice Powell’s opinion regarding the narrowly tailored
    component of strict scrutiny, and it is our view that whether the Law School’s admissions policy
    passes constitutional muster turns on Justice Powell’s opinion.9
    1.
    Drafted to comply with Bakke, the Law School’s consideration of race and ethnicity does not
    use quotas and closely tracks the Harvard plan. Race and ethnicity, along with a range of other
    factors, are potential “plus” factors in a particular applicant’s file, but they do not insulate an under-
    represented minority applicant from competition or act to foreclose competition from non-minority
    applicants. As part of its policy of evaluating each applicant individually, the Law School’s officials
    read each application and factor all of the accompanying information into their decision. The Law
    School, like Harvard, attends to the numbers and distribution of under-represented minority
    applicants in an effort to ensure all of its students obtain the benefits of an academically diverse
    student body.
    The record demonstrates that the Law School does not employ a quota for under-represented
    minority students. The Law School’s witnesses, including the current and former admissions
    directors, all testified that the Law School does not reserve or set aside seats. For example, Dean
    Lehman testified: “We do not have a portion of the class that is set aside for a critical mass of under-
    represented minority students.” Moreover, the Law School operates a single admissions system;
    there is no separate track for minority applicants insulating them from comparison with non-minority
    applicants. Thus, the Law School’s admissions policy avoids the critical defect of the Davis
    admissions program.
    The Law School’s competitive consideration of the race and ethnicity of African-Americans,
    Hispanics and Native Americans closely tracks the Harvard plan. In its admission policy, quoted in
    Bakke, Harvard details that race is a “factor in some admissions decisions” and that “the race of an
    applicant may tip the balance in his favor just as geographic origin or a life spent on a farm may tip
    9
    We recognize that the Eleventh Circuit dismissed Justice Powell’s endorsement of the
    Harvard plan as dicta. See Johnson, 
    263 F.3d at 1261
    . Even if this portion of Justice Powell’s
    opinion could be labeled dicta, it is nevertheless dicta from the determinative opinion in the only
    Supreme Court case to address the consideration of race and ethnicity in academic admissions.
    Accordingly, Justice Powell’s endorsement of the Harvard plan carries considerable persuasive
    authority and provides a more appropriate basis for our opinion than any test we might fashion.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 16
    the balance in other candidates’ cases.” Id. at 316. Explaining the rationale behind this policy,
    Harvard highlighted that a “black student can usually bring something [to Harvard] that a white
    person cannot offer.” Id. The Law School considers an applicant’s race and ethnicity as a potential
    “plus” factor, or as Professor Lempert testified, as one element among other elements. Because race
    and ethnicity are a “plus,” they undoubtedly “tip the balance” in some applicants’ favor. Importantly,
    however, the Law School’s consideration of race and ethnicity does not operate to insulate any
    prospective student from competition with any other applicants. The Law School’s explanation for
    its consideration of race and ethnicity also mirrors the Harvard plan. According to the Law School,
    students from these groups “are particularly likely to have experiences and perspectives of special
    importance to [the Law School’s] mission.”
    In seeking an academically diverse class, the record indicates that the Law School considers
    more than an applicant’s race and ethnicity. In Bakke, Justice Powell stressed factors in addition to
    race and ethnicity that could contribute to academic diversity. See id. at 317. He cited “exceptional
    personal talents, unique work or service experience, leadership potential, maturity, demonstrated
    compassion, a history of overcoming disadvantage, ability to communicate with the poor, or other
    qualifications deemed important.” Id. Mirroring Justice Powell’s discussion, the Law School’s
    admissions policy states that “[t]here are many possible bases for diversity admissions” and that in
    evaluating “soft” variables, it considers a range of factors such as leadership, work experience,
    unique talents or interests and the enthusiasm of an applicant’s letters of recommendation.
    Illustrating this range, the policy provides that particular weight might be given to “an Olympic gold
    medal, a Ph. D in physics, the attainment of age 50 in a class that otherwise lacked anyone over 30,
    or the experience of having been a Vietnamese boat person.”
    The Law School’s pursuit of a “critical mass” of under-represented minority students also
    tracks the Harvard plan’s pursuit of a class with meaningful numbers of minority students.
    Explaining its attention to the numbers and distribution of minority students, Harvard emphasized
    that “10 or 20 black students could not begin to bring to their classmates and to each other the variety
    of points of view, backgrounds and experiences of blacks in the United States.” Id. at 323.
    Moreover, “[t]heir small numbers might also create a sense of isolation among the black students
    themselves and thus make it more difficult for them to develop and achieve their potential.” Id. In
    defining the term “critical mass,” the Law School’s witnesses voiced virtually identical concerns.
    Director Munzel testified that “critical mass” is a number sufficient so that under-represented
    minority students can contribute to classroom dialogue and not feel isolated. Dean Lehman similarly
    equated “critical mass” with sufficient numbers to ensure under-represented minority students do
    not feel isolated or like spokespersons for their race, and feel comfortable discussing issues freely
    based on their personal experiences. Professor Lempert and Kent Syverud, the current dean of
    Vanderbilt Law School and a former Michigan Law School professor, offered similar explanations
    for the Law School’s pursuit of a “critical mass” of under-represented minority students. Essentially,
    both the Law School’s admission policy and the Harvard plan attend to the numbers of under-
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 17
    represented minority students to ensure that all students – minority and majority alike – will be able
    to enjoy the educational benefits of an academically diverse student body.
    In light of the foregoing, we find that the Law School’s consideration of race and ethnicity
    is virtually indistinguishable from the Harvard plan Justice Powell approved in Bakke.
    2.
    The unsuccessful applicants focus principally on the effects of the Law School’s policy,
    contending first that the Law School’s pursuit of a “critical mass” is the functional equivalent of a
    quota because it has resulted in a range of under-represented minority enrollment from 10%-17%.
    As a matter of definition, we are satisfied that the Law School’s “critical mass” is not the equivalent
    of a quota, because unlike Davis’s reservation of sixteen spots for minority candidates, the Law
    School has no fixed goal or target. That the Law School’s pursuit of a “critical mass” has resulted
    in an approximate range of under-represented minority enrollment does not transform “critical mass”
    into a quota. Because Bakke allows institutions of higher education to pay some attention to the
    numbers and distribution of under-represented minority students, see id. at 316-17, over time,
    reliance on Bakke will always produce some percentage range of minority enrollment. And that
    range will always have a bottom, which, of course, can be labeled the “minimum.” These results are
    the logical consequence of reliance on Bakke and establishment of an admissions policy, like the
    Harvard plan, that attends to the numbers and distribution of under-represented minority students.
    As such, they cannot serve as the basis for a charge that the Law School’s admissions policy is
    unconstitutional.
    In analyzing actual admissions data, the dissent tries out a variation of the unsuccessful
    applicants’ contention and focuses only on the years 1995 through 1998. Dissenting Op. at 75
    (Boggs, J.). Based on this grouping, the tightest four-year range available, the dissent concludes that
    the Law School seeks a “critical mass” of forty-four to forty-seven under-represented minorities per
    class, or “around 13.5%.” But as the dissent confesses in a footnote, the rest of the picture
    “deviate[s] a bit.” Id. at 75 n.29. From 1987 to 1994, under-represented minority enrollment was
    12.3%, 13.6%, 14.3%, 13.4%, 19.1%, 19.8%, 14.5%, 20.1%, respectively. More importantly for
    present purposes, if we examine under-represented minority enrollment from 1993 until 1998, we
    see that the Law School’s under-represented minority enrollment ranged from 13.5% to 20.1%. In
    light of (1) the overwhelming testimony by Law School professors, admissions counselors and deans
    that the Law School does not employ a quota or otherwise reserve seats for under-represented
    minority applicants and (2) Justice Powell’s instruction that lower courts presume that academic
    institutions act in good faith in operating their “plus” programs, we simply cannot conclude that the
    Law School is using the “functional equivalent” of the Davis Medical School quota struck down in
    Bakke.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 18
    Relying on statistical evidence that under-represented minority students are admitted to the
    Law School with comparatively lower undergraduate grade-point averages and standardized test
    scores, the unsuccessful applicants also argue that the Law School considers race and ethnicity too
    much.10 Although they concede that all admitted students are qualified, the unsuccessful applicants
    contend that this disparity evidences an unconstitutional double standard for admission of under-
    represented minority applicants and non-minority applicants. Upon inspection, however, the
    unsuccessful applicants’ statistical evidence demonstrates just what one would expect a plan like the
    Harvard plan to demonstrate – that race and ethnicity, as “plus” factors, play an important role in
    some admissions decisions. As the logical result of reliance on the Harvard plan, the unsuccessful
    applicants’ statistical evidence accordingly cannot sustain their contention that the Law School’s
    admissions policy is unconstitutional.
    In advancing the Harvard plan, Justice Powell, unfortunately, did not define or discuss a
    permissible “plus” with respect to the test scores and high school grades of under-represented
    minority Harvard applicants. And Harvard did not append a statistical comparison of minority and
    non-minority standardized test scores and/or grades to its admissions plan. Perhaps Harvard, in
    enrolling meaningful numbers of under-represented minority students, could select under-represented
    minority applicants with test scores or high school grades equivalent to their non-minority
    counterparts. And then again, perhaps Harvard grappled with some of the same admissions
    challenges as the Law School does today. Of course, such admissions statistics are neither in the
    record before us nor explicitly incorporated into Justice Powell’s opinion. Under these
    circumstances, we cannot hold that the Law School’s admissions program, which is virtually
    identical to the Harvard plan, would nevertheless fail Justice Powell’s test for constitutionality.
    Without some indication that Justice Powell specifically meant to limit the consideration of race or
    ethnicity – as a “plus,” to “tip the balance,” or as a “factor in some admissions decisions” – to
    instances where standardized test scores or high school grade-point averages were equivalent, we
    cannot adopt the limited definition of “plus” urged by the dissenting opinions. See Dissenting Op.
    at 71-73 (Boggs, J.); Dissenting Op. at 93 (Gilman, J.). And thus, we cannot conclude that the
    difference, on average, between the standardized test scores and/or undergraduate grades of qualified
    under-represented minority students and qualified non-minority students renders the Law School’s
    admissions policy unconstitutional.
    3.
    The district court relied on five factors in concluding that the Law School’s consideration of
    race and ethnicity was not narrowly tailored: (1) the Law School did not define “critical mass” with
    sufficient clarity; (2) the apparent lack of a time limit on the Law School’s consideration of race and
    10
    The district court credited plaintiffs’ statistical conclusions, but did not incorporate them
    into its discussion of whether the Law School’s admission policy was sufficiently narrowly tailored.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 19
    ethnicity; (3) the admissions policy was “practically indistinguishable” from a quota system; (4) the
    Law School did not have a logical basis for considering the race and ethnicity of African-Americans,
    Native Americans and Puerto Ricans; (5) the Law School did not “investigate alternative means for
    increasing minority enrollment.” Grutter, 
    137 F. Supp. 2d at 850-52
    . As a initial matter, we have
    serious reservations regarding the district court’s consideration of five factors not found in Bakke,
    which, as we have stated, is the only Supreme Court case to directly address the consideration of race
    and ethnicity in academic admissions. Nevertheless, we are satisfied that the remaining factors relied
    on by the district court cannot sustain its holding.
    Although not addressed in Bakke, subsequent Supreme Court opinions suggest consideration
    of race-neutral means is necessary to satisfy the narrowly tailored component of strict scrutiny. E.g.,
    Croson, 
    488 U.S. at 507
     (“In determining whether race-conscious remedies are appropriate, we look
    to several factors, including the efficacy of alternative remedies.”) (quoting United States v.
    Paradise, 
    480 U.S. 149
    , 171, 
    107 S.Ct. 1053
    , 
    94 L.Ed.2d 203
     (1987)). Although the Law School’s
    consideration of race and ethnicity differs from the racial classifications at issue in Croson, and the
    context of higher education differs materially from the government contracting context, see, e.g.,
    Hopwood, 
    78 F.3d at
    965 n.21 (Wiener, J., concurring) (“This unique context, first identified by
    Justice Powell, differs from the employment context, differs from the minority business set aside
    context, and differs from the re-districting context; it comprises only the public education context
    and implicates the uneasy marriage of the First and Fourteenth Amendments.”), we nevertheless
    assess whether the Law School adequately considered race-neutral alternatives.
    The district court acknowledged that the Law School introduced evidence indicating that
    under-represented minority students could not be enrolled in significant numbers without explicit
    consideration of race and ethnicity, but ruled that the Law School “fail[ed] to investigate alternative
    means for increasing minority enrollment.” 
    137 F. Supp. 2d at 852
    . Upon examination, however,
    the record does indicate the Law School considered and ultimately rejected various race-neutral
    alternatives to the consideration of race and ethnicity. Director Munzel, former Director Shields and
    Dean Lehman all testified that the Law School engaged in both pre- and post- admission recruiting
    activities but that such activities were not enough to enroll a “critical mass” of under-represented
    minority students. Additionally, Professor Lempert testified regarding the lottery system, in which
    the Law School would lower its admissions standards, establish a numerical cut-off for “qualified”
    applicants, and then select randomly from among those applicants. According to Professor Lempert,
    such a system would admit greater numbers of non-minority students, but would not yield
    meaningful racial and ethnic diversity. Given the Law School’s consideration of race-neutral
    alternatives and the evidence that “under-represented minority students cannot be enrolled in
    significant numbers unless their race is explicitly considered in the admissions process,” we find that
    the Law School has adequately considered race-neutral alternatives.
    The dissent proposes the Law School pursue “experiential diversity in a race-neutral manner”
    and characterizes such an approach as a superior alternative to the Law School’s current admissions
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 20
    system. Dissenting Op. at 80-81 (Boggs, J.). In effect, then, the dissent proposes that the Law
    School only focus on its race-neutral bases of diversity admissions. But as the dissent essentially
    acknowledges, this proposed alternative could not possibly achieve the same robust academic
    diversity currently sought and obtained by the Law School. The dissent says that it is “fully willing
    to stipulate that race does matter in American society, and that, on average, it matters more
    negatively for some, if not all, of the groups favored by the Law School than it does for some, if not
    all disfavored by the Law School.” Id. at 82. As to the impact of income, the dissent also offers to
    “stipulate that such impact or disadvantage is not strictly limited by present income or status.” Id.
    Yet the dissent nevertheless proposes that the Law School ignore the influence of race and ethnicity
    in pursuing a broad “pluralism of ideas and experiences” and, at the same time, reassures us that the
    pursuit of race-neutral diversity will still somehow produce the broadest “pluralism of ideas and
    experiences.” Id. at 81. In reality, by reducing the range of experiences the Law School can consider
    - namely, the experience of being an African-American, Hispanic or Native American in a society
    where race matters - the dissent proposes only a narrowed and inferior version of the academic
    diversity currently sought by the Law School.
    Lastly, we note that we do not read Bakke and the Supreme Court’s subsequent decisions to
    require the Law School to choose between meaningful racial and ethnic diversity and academic
    selectivity. An institution of higher education must consider race-neutral alternatives, but it need
    not abandon its academic mission to achieve absolute racial and ethnic neutrality. Thus, in applying
    strict scrutiny we cannot ignore the educational judgment and expertise of the Law School’s faculty
    and admissions personnel regarding the efficacy of race-neutral alternatives. We are ill-equipped
    to ascertain which race-neutral alternatives merit which degree of consideration or which alternatives
    will allow an institution such as the Law School to assemble both a highly qualified and richly
    diverse academic class. See Regents of the Univ. of Michigan v. Ewing, 
    474 U.S. 214
    , 226, 
    106 S.Ct. 507
    , 
    88 L.Ed.2d 523
     (1985) (noting that a federal court is ill-suited “to evaluate the substance of the
    multitude of academic decisions that are made daily by faculty members of public education
    institutions – decisions that require an expert evaluation of cumulative information and are not
    readily adapted to the procedural tools of judicial or administrative decisionmaking.”) (citations and
    internal punctuation omitted). Mindful of both our constitutional obligations and our practical
    limitations, we also assume – along the lines suggested by Justice Powell – that the Law School acts
    in good faith in exercising its educational judgment and expertise. See Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 318-19
    .
    4.
    We are not persuaded by the remaining factors that the district court relied on to invalidate
    the Law School’s admissions policy. First, the district court’s conclusion that the term “critical
    mass” is not sufficiently defined is at odds with the extensive record in this case, and the district
    court’s own characterization of “critical mass” as the functional equivalent of a quota. See Grutter,
    
    137 F. Supp. 2d at 850
    . Numerous law school witnesses testified regarding the meaning of the term
    “critical mass.” For example, Dean Lehman equated “critical mass” with sufficient numbers such
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 21
    that under-represented minority students do not feel isolated or like spokespersons for their race, and
    do not feel uncomfortable discussing issues freely based on their personal experiences. We also
    emphasize the considerable tension between the district court’s findings that “critical mass” is both
    insufficiently defined and the functional equivalent of a quota. In any event, the district court’s
    apparent insistence that “critical mass” correspond with a more definite percentage is also fatally at
    odds with Bakke’s prohibition of fixed quotas. See Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 319
    .
    Second, the district court’s statement that “there is no logical basis for the law school to have
    chosen the particular groups which receive special attention under the admissions policy,” Grutter,
    
    137 F. Supp. 2d at 851-52
    , ignores both the Harvard plan and the Law School’s admissions policy.
    The Harvard plan specifically identified “blacks and Chicanos and other minority students” among
    the under-represented groups that Harvard sought to enroll through its admissions policy. Bakke,
    
    438 U.S. at 322
    . The Law School’s similar reference to African-Americans, Hispanics and Native
    Americans accordingly cannot be faulted in this respect. Moreover, the policy itself supplies the
    logical basis for considering the race and ethnicity of these groups – without such consideration, they
    would probably not be represented in the Law School’s student body in “meaningful numbers.” As
    with the formulation and consideration of race-neutral alternatives, some degree of deference must
    be accorded to the educational judgment of the Law School in its determination of which groups to
    target. See Ewing, 
    474 U.S. at 226
    .
    Finally, the district court’s determination that the Law School’s consideration of race and
    ethnicity lacks a definite stopping point also does not render the admissions policy unconstitutional.
    See Grutter, 131 F. Supp. 2d at 851. Although the district court correctly recited Adarand’s directive
    that a race-conscious remedial program must be limited so that it “will not last longer than the
    discriminatory effects it is designed to eliminate,” this directive does not neatly transfer to an
    institution of higher education’s non-remedial consideration of race and ethnicity. Unlike a remedial
    interest, an interest in academic diversity does not have a self-contained stopping point. Indeed, an
    interest in academic diversity exists independently of a race-conscious admissions policy.
    Nevertheless, even if we were to apply a durational constraint, we are satisfied that the Law School’s
    admissions policy sets appropriate limits on the competitive consideration of race and ethnicity. The
    record indicates that the Law School intends to consider race and ethnicity to achieve a diverse and
    robust student body only until it becomes possible to enroll a “critical mass” of under-represented
    minority students through race-neutral means. Thus, we are satisfied that the admissions policy is
    “sensit[ive] to the possibility that [it] might someday have satisfied its purpose.” See Associated Gen.
    Contractors of Ohio, Inc. v. Drabik, 
    214 F.3d 730
    , 737 (6th Cir. 2000), cert. denied, 
    121 S. Ct. 1089
    (2001).
    III.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 22
    For the foregoing reasons, we REVERSE the judgment of the district court and VACATE
    its injunction prohibiting the Law School from considering race and ethnicity in its admissions
    decisions.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 23
    _____________________
    CONCURRENCE
    _____________________
    KAREN NELSON MOORE, Circuit Judge, concurring. I write separately both to note my
    disapproval of Judge Boggs’s decision to include a “Procedural Appendix” as part of his dissenting
    opinion and to provide an accurate account of how this case came to be argued before the present
    en banc court.
    I.
    In publishing their “Procedural Appendix,” I believe that Judge Boggs and those joining his
    opinion have done a grave harm not only to themselves, but to this court and even to the Nation as
    a whole. A court’s opinions state the reasons for its holdings and provide the public with the
    principled justifications for them. Dissenting opinions typically present principled disagreements
    with the majority’s holding. Such disagreements over principle are perfectly legitimate and do not
    undermine public confidence in our ability as judges to do what we have sworn to do because, as a
    culture, we have long recognized that disagreements over principle are unavoidable. Given this
    cultural backdrop, disagreements over principle can be phrased in strong terms without damaging
    the court’s ability to function as a decision-making institution in a democratic society. Judges
    criticize their colleagues’ reasoning all the time, and, if they are to carry out their oaths of office, they
    must do so. This robust exchange of ideas sharpens the focus and improves our analysis of the legal
    issues.
    In the present case, Judge Boggs has written a lengthy and strongly worded critique of the
    substance of the majority’s holding in the present case. Although I disagree with his analysis and
    conclusions, I acknowledge his abilities as a jurist.
    The final section of Judge Boggs’s dissent, labeled “Procedural Appendix,” however,
    publicizes disagreements over the internal workings of the court, which, as my colleague states, “do
    not directly affect the legal principles discussed in this case.” Given that these procedural matters
    are, at best, peripheral to the matter at hand, the only reason that “it is important that they be placed
    in the record” is to declare publicly the dissent’s unfounded assertion that the majority’s decision
    today is the result of political maneuvering and manipulation. The baseless argument of the
    “Procedural Appendix” is that the decisions of this court are not grounded in principle and reasoned
    argument, but in power,1 and that the judges of this court manipulate and ignore the rules in order
    1
    Judge Boggs responds in his dissent that he does “not contend that the legal opinions of any
    member of this court do not represent that judge’s principled judgment in this case.” Dissenting Op.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 24
    to advance political agendas. I am saddened that Judge Boggs and those joining his opinion believe
    these things. But, more importantly, I am concerned that my dissenting colleagues’ actions will
    severely undermine public confidence in this court. Cf. Memphis Planned Parenthood, Inc. v.
    Sundquist, 
    184 F.3d 600
    , 608 (6th Cir. 1999) (Batchelder, J., separate statement on denial of
    rehearing en banc) (“Our dissenting colleague’s own purposes may be furthered by publicly
    impugning the integrity of his colleagues. Collegiality, cooperation and the court’s decision-making
    process clearly are not. And public confidence in the judicial system and in this court clearly are
    not.”).
    Because we judges are unelected and serve during good behavior, our only source of
    democratic legitimacy is the perception that we engage in principled decision-making. See Planned
    Parenthood v. Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
    , 865-66 (1992). This perception is based both in the reality of
    our practice — I believe that my colleagues, all of them, strive to decide cases in a principled manner
    — and in the presentation of our decisions to the public in written opinions.
    The decisions of this court are not self-executing but instead must be carried into practice by
    other actors. They will do so only as long as they regard us as legitimate, as we possess neither the
    purse nor the sword, but only judgment. For this reason, we are often described as the weakest
    branch, but a court without purse, sword, or legitimacy would be weaker still. This is not to argue
    that protecting the relative strength of the judicial branch should be our primary concern. Indeed,
    we have all sworn to uphold the Constitution, and the Nation needs a strong judiciary to check the
    occasional excesses of the other branches and, more importantly, to preserve the rule of law.
    Our ability to perform these crucial tasks is imperiled when members of this court take it
    upon themselves to “expose to public view” disagreements over procedure. The damage done by
    such exposés is, at least in part, the responsibility of those who report them, despite the efforts of
    Judge Boggs and those joining his opinion to disclaim responsibility for their own conduct. It is
    understandable, however, that they do so, as their conduct in the present case is nothing short of
    shameful.
    II.
    With great reluctance, I find myself forced to respond to Judge Boggs’s inaccurate and
    misleading account of the procedural facts underlying the present case.2 As discussed in Part I of
    at 89. He does contend, however, that the result in the present case represents unprincipled
    procedural maneuvering by members of this court. It is this contention to which I object.
    2
    This response is truly a recourse of last resort, as several members of this court have
    endeavored to persuade Judge Boggs to withdraw the “Procedural Appendix.” He has steadfastly
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 25
    this opinion, I firmly believe that matters of internal court procedure should not be exposed to public
    view. But when one is attacked in the way that the members of the majority have been attacked, it
    is necessary to present an accurate account of the events in question; to fail to do so would create the
    impression that Judge Boggs’s assertions are, in fact, correct.
    Judge Boggs and those joining his opinion have numerous complaints regarding the
    procedures that were followed in the present case. In the end, however, their chief complaint is that
    the present case has been decided by a nine-judge en banc court (“the particular decision-making
    body that has . . . decided [the case]”) rather than an eleven-judge en banc court, and that the
    members of the hearing panel originally assigned this case (Chief Judge Martin, Judge Daughtrey,
    and myself) purposefully engineered this result. A number of Judge Boggs’s unfounded assertions
    involve the May 14, 2001 petition for initial en banc hearing filed by Barbara Grutter. Judge Boggs
    repeatedly asserts that the “preselected” hearing panel withheld this petition from the other members
    of the court until after Judges Norris and Suhrheinrich took senior status, on July 1 and August 15,
    2001, respectively.
    The Sixth Circuit’s private docket, however, indicates that the May 14 petition for hearing
    en banc was first referred to the hearing panel on August 23, 2001, and it was not received by the
    panel until several days thereafter.3 By August 23, both Judges Norris and Suhrheinrich had taken
    senior status. Even if the hearing panel had taken immediate action to circulate the en banc petition
    to the whole court on that date, the case would have been heard by the same en banc court that in fact
    heard it on December 6, 2001. The record simply does not support any other conclusion on this
    point. Similarly, the June 4, 2001 order holding the en banc petition in abeyance was also referred
    to the hearing panel in August 2001. Thus, Judge Boggs’s claim that the June 4 order was not
    circulated to the en banc court, on June 4, is true, as far as it goes, but misleading, because that order
    was not circulated to any judges at that time, including the hearing panel. This ministerial order was
    signed by the clerk of the court and was not issued as a result of any action by the hearing panel.
    In addition, Judge Boggs’s assertion that the hearing panel violated the rules or internal
    operating procedures of the Sixth Circuit in not circulating the en banc petition to the entire court
    refused to do so. The three members of the hearing panel have also personally assured Judge Boggs
    that we did not engage in the manipulation of which he has accused us, but he has refused to accept
    our assurances.
    3
    My own records indicate that I first saw the May 14, 2001 petition on September 26, 2001,
    at which time I consulted with the other members of the hearing panel about circulating the petition
    to the whole court.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 26
    after August 23 but prior to October 15, 2001, is simply incorrect.4 On December 5, 2000, months
    before the filing of the petition in the present case, Chief Judge Martin instituted a policy regarding
    the treatment of petitions for initial hearing en banc. This change in policy was spurred by the
    increasing frequency of such petitions, especially in pro se appeals. In the letter detailing the policy,
    the chief judge instructed that, when such a petition is filed, the clerk of the court should enter an
    order, such as that issued in the present case, holding the petition in abeyance until the completion
    of briefing, and then refer the petition to the hearing panel assigned the cases. This procedure was
    followed in the present case. In each case, the assigned hearing panel would then decide, as an initial
    matter, whether to deny the petition and proceed with the scheduled panel consideration or, if the
    petition raised a legitimate ground for initial hearing en banc, to circulate the petition to the rest of
    the court. To my knowledge, no one raised any objection to this policy when it was circulated to the
    court for comment and instituted in December 2000. Pursuant to this policy, the hearing panel in
    the present case decided, in September 2001, not to circulate the en banc petition to the entire court.
    Whatever the prior practice of the Sixth Circuit with respect to the circulation of petitions for initial
    hearing en banc, see Dissenting Op. at 86 n.43 (discussing petitions filed in the year 2000), the
    hearing panel in the present case was not required to circulate the May 14 en banc petition under the
    policy in effect in September 2001.
    As Judge Boggs indicates in his dissent, an initial hearing of a case en banc is an extremely
    rare occurrence. See Dissenting Op. at 88 (“I have been on the court for [sixteen] years, and I do not
    recall an initial hearing en banc in my tenure.”). Thus, the hearing panel’s decision not to circulate
    the petition for an initial hearing en banc in the present case — prior to the events discussed infra
    — is perfectly understandable. Indeed, if the members of the hearing panel had circulated the May
    14 petition in September 2001, the other members of the court would have likely voted not to hear
    the case initially en banc, since Judge Boggs cannot recall any other instance of such a petition
    having been granted in the past sixteen years. In light of this consideration, however, I do not see
    how the hearing panel can be faulted for not circulating the petition.
    Judge Boggs also objects to the treatment of the present case as a “must panel” case, the
    composition of the “preselected” hearing panel, and the handling of all actions and motions related
    to this appeal by the “preselected” hearing panel. These objections are relatively minor, given the
    subsequent decision to hear the case initially en banc.5 Indeed, this court’s decision to hear the
    present case en banc was motivated by the concerns related to the composition of the hearing panel.
    4
    Of course, given the composition of the court on August 23, 2001, it would not have made
    any difference to the outcome of the case whether the en banc petition had been circulated on that
    date, or in September, or in early October 2001.
    5
    These objections are also minor in that Judge Boggs does not argue that any of the decisions
    with which he finds fault actually changed the outcome of the present case.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 27
    These concerns were raised by Senior Circuit Judge Ralph Guy in a letter to Chief Judge Martin,
    which was dated October 15, 2001. The poll letter, issued by the hearing panel to the en banc court
    that very day, stated the following rationale for circulating the petition for hearing en banc:
    Re: Petition for Initial Hearing En Banc; Request for a Poll
    Plaintiffs Gratz and Grutter have filed a petition for initial hearing en banc in
    these two cases concerning the admissions policies of the University of Michigan and
    its law school. Pursuant to the usual court policy, this petition for initial hearing en
    banc was referred to the panel hearing the case. The reasons stated for initial hearing
    en banc were the “exceptional importance” of the case, the “inevitable conflict” with
    another federal circuit’s opinion in view of the already conflicting decisions of the
    Fifth Circuit in Hopwood v. Texas, 
    78 F.3d 932
     (5th Cir. 1996), and 
    236 F.3d 256
    (5th Cir. 2000), and the Ninth Circuit in Smith v. University of Washington Law Sch.,
    
    233 F.3d 1188
     (9th Cir. 2000), and the need for expedited resolution.
    The panel that was assigned this case is Chief Judge Martin, Judge
    Daughtrey, and Judge Moore. The panel believed that the usual court policy referring
    a petition for initial hearing en banc should be followed, and that the reasons set forth
    for initial hearing en banc did not warrant such an initial hearing. The panel already
    had expedited the appeal process, the conflict between the circuits already existed,
    and we had not heard en banc any number of other exceptionally important cases.
    Because of a question that has been raised regarding the composition of the
    panel, the panel believes that the en banc court should vote on the petition for initial
    hearing en banc. Hence the petition is attached for a vote. Since the case is
    scheduled to be heard by the panel on Wednesday, October 23, time is of the essence
    in deciding whether to proceed initially en banc.
    Judges Daughtrey and Moore were on the initial panel in 1999 considering
    questions of intervention. Grutter v. Bollinger, 
    188 F.3d 394
     (6th Cir. 1999). The
    third judge was Judge Stafford, a Senior District Judge from the Northern District of
    Florida. Pursuant to our “must panel” practice, Judges Daughtrey and Moore have
    continued on this case. Chief Judge Martin was substituted for Judge Stafford.
    The panel requests that the en banc court be polled regarding the petition for
    initial hearing en banc.
    The vote for hearing en banc was seven in favor — Chief Judge Martin, Judges Siler, Daughtrey,
    Moore, Cole, Clay, and Gilman — with no votes cast against hearing en banc. Neither Judge Boggs
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 28
    nor Judge Batchelder voted in this matter, but, pursuant to our rules, their non-votes were in effect
    votes against the en banc hearing of the present case.
    This court voted to hear the present case en banc in order to resolve the concerns of certain
    members of the court about the composition of the hearing panel. Judge Boggs and those joining
    his opinion now complain about the composition of the en banc court. But, as I have demonstrated
    supra, these complaints are without merit. Moreover, even if the “preselected” hearing panel had
    acted as Judge Boggs claims, which it did not, it is important to note that this did not deprive Judge
    Boggs and the other dissenters of the opportunity to call for initial hearing en banc on their own
    initiative at any time.
    The internal operating procedures of this court permit any active judge to request a poll for
    hearing a case initially en banc, regardless of whether a party has filed a petition for hearing en banc.
    See 6 Cir. I.O.P. 35(c). If, then, Judges Boggs and others were concerned with the selection of the
    hearing panel in the present case at some point prior to October 15, 2001, there was an internal
    procedure by which they could have addressed those concerns. As the present appeal was filed on
    April 2, 2001, prompt action by Judges Boggs and the other dissenters would have resulted in an en
    banc hearing before a different en banc court — or, in other words, Judge Boggs and the other
    dissenters could have called for an en banc hearing before the eleven-judge en banc court they now
    argue was deprived of this opportunity.
    The simple fact of the matter is that the present case was treated as a “must panel” case as
    early as July 2000. In Grutter v. Bollinger, 
    188 F.3d 394
     (6th Cir. 1999), a panel consisting of Judge
    Daughtrey, myself, and Judge William H. Stafford, a senior district judge from the Northern District
    of Florida, reversed district court orders denying the motions of prospective intervenors to intervene
    in the present case and in its companion case, Gratz v. Bollinger. The opinion in the intervenors’
    case was issued on August 10, 1999. Subsequent to that decision, the defendants requested
    permission to appeal the district courts’ certification of plaintiff classes in Grutter and Gratz,
    pursuant to Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 23(f). On July 10, 2000, the clerk of the court contacted
    Judge Daughtrey and me regarding whether those appeals (Sixth Circuit docket numbers 00-0107
    and 00-0109), which were consolidated for purposes of appeal, represented a “must panel” situation.
    We decided that these cases did represent a “must panel” situation, where subsequent matters should
    be returned to the original panel due to their interrelatedness with the original matter, and these cases
    were transferred to a motions panel including Judge Daughtrey and myself.
    At that time, Chief Judge Martin was substituted for Judge Stafford on the motions panel.
    Sixth Circuit rules give the active members of a panel the option of recalling the district judge or
    senior circuit judge from another circuit who sat on the panel previously or replacing that judge with
    a third Sixth Circuit judge. See 6 Cir. I.O.P. 34(b)(2). Although that rule states that the third Sixth
    Circuit judge should be drawn at random, Chief Judge Martin has frequently substituted himself in
    a variety of matters, of varying degrees of importance, throughout his tenure as chief judge, in order
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 29
    to avoid inconveniencing other circuit judges. Thus, it was not unusual for him to place himself on
    the panel in July 2000. To my knowledge, no one has objected before to Chief Judge Martin’s filling
    of vacancies in other cases, even though his practice of doing so is a matter of common knowledge
    among the judges of this court.
    This motions panel denied the defendants’ request for permission to appeal the class
    certification decisions on September 26, 2000. The same motions panel also granted the parties’
    request for permission to file interlocutory appeals in Gratz, pursuant to 
    28 U.S.C. § 1292
    (b), on
    March 26, 2001 (Sixth Circuit docket numbers 01-0102 and 01-0104).
    When the appeal in the present case was filed, the defendants moved this court to stay the
    district court’s order enjoining the Law School from considering race as a factor in admissions. The
    panel of Chief Judge Martin, Judge Daughtrey, and myself granted this stay in a published order on
    April 5, 2001 (Sixth Circuit docket number 01-1447). See Grutter v. Bollinger, 
    247 F.3d 631
     (6th
    Cir. 2001). On that same date, the chief judge ordered that the appeals in Grutter and Gratz be
    expedited, setting August 1, 2001, as the deadline for the filing of briefs and appendices. Oral
    argument was set for the court’s October term.
    Thus, it should have been clear to the other members of the court, as of the published order
    of April 5, 2001, if not sooner, that the present case was being treated as a “must panel” case and that
    the hearing panel would consist of Chief Judge Martin, Judge Daughtrey, and myself. At any point
    thereafter, Judge Boggs or any other member of the en banc court — including Judges Norris and
    Suhrheinrich, before they took senior status — could have called for a poll to determine whether the
    case should be heard initially en banc. If there were questions regarding the composition of the
    hearing panel, then Judge Boggs and those joining his dissent could have raised those questions
    through this means at any time.
    Judge Boggs and those joining his dissent did not raise these concerns in this manner,
    however. In fact, the dissenters themselves did not raise any complaints with the composition of the
    en banc court when the en banc petition was circulated, when the case was argued before the en banc
    court, or even in the first circulated draft of Judge Boggs’s dissent. The lateness of their complaints
    suggests that their primary complaint is with the outcome of the present case rather than with the
    procedures that were followed in arriving at that outcome. But unhappiness over the outcome of the
    case cannot justify the dissenters’ “Procedural Appendix.” Judge Boggs’s opinion marks a new low
    point in the history of the Sixth Circuit. It will irreparably damage the already strained working
    relationships among the judges of this court, and, as discussed in Part I supra, serve to undermine
    public confidence in our ability to perform our important role in American democracy. And for what
    reason? What purpose does the “Procedural Appendix” serve? Its author does not defend its
    inclusion, except to suggest that by placing his version of events in the record, some “remediation”
    may be “possible.” Dissenting Op. at 89 n.49. Whatever “remediation” Judge Boggs may envision
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 30
    is properly the subject of a court meeting, but not the basis for an unprecedented “Procedural
    Appendix.”
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 31
    _____________________
    CONCURRENCE
    _____________________
    CLAY, Circuit Judge, concurring. I concur in Chief Judge Martin’s majority opinion, finding
    it correct and insightful in all respects. I write separately, however, for the purpose of speaking to
    the misrepresentations made by Judge Boggs in his dissenting opinion which unjustifiably distort
    and seek to cast doubt upon the majority opinion.1
    A.      Justice Powell’s Opinion in Bakke remains “the Law of the Land”
    The dissent’s many fallacies begin with its attempt to undermine the majority’s holding that
    Justice Powell’s opinion in Bakke is controlling. Indeed, now Supreme Court Justice Scalia once
    described Justice Powell’s opinion as “the law of the land.” See Antonin Scalia, Commentary, The
    Disease as Cure: “In order to get beyond racism, we must first take account of race.”, 1979 WASH .
    U. L.Q. 147, 148 (1979) (speaking then as Professor Scalia on Justice Powell’s opinion in Bakke).
    And significantly, since Bakke the Supreme Court has done nothing to render this description of
    Justice Powell’s opinion any different. See Agostini v. Felton, 
    521 U.S. 203
    , 237 (1997) (reaffirming
    that “‘[i]f a precedent of this Court has direct application in a case, . . . the Court of Appeals should
    follow the case which directly controls, leaving to this Court the prerogative of overruling its own
    decisions’”) (quoting Rodriquez de Quijas v. Shearson/Am. Express, Inc., 
    490 U.S. 477
    , 484 (1989));
    see also Wessmann v. Gittens, 
    160 F.3d 790
    , 796 (1st Cir. 1998) (recognizing that absent a clear
    holding from the Supreme Court, the precedential value of Justice Powell’s opinion in Bakke, that
    diversity is a sufficiently compelling governmental interest to justify a race-based classification,
    should not be disturbed, especially where various individual justices have “from time to time . . .
    written approvingly of ethnic diversity in comparable settings”); Mark R. Killenbeck, Pushing
    Things Up to Their First Principles: Reflections on the Values of Affirmative Action, 87 CAL. L.
    Rev. 1299, 1352 (1999) (illustrating why Justice Powell’s opinion in Bakke is controlling, and why
    any other conclusion elevates form over substance inasmuch as Justice Brennan’s opinion cannot
    be distinguished from Justice Powell’s opinion on the basis of the level of scrutiny applied, or on any
    other basis) (citing Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of Educ., 
    476 U.S. 267
    , 286 (1986) (O’Connor, J.,
    concurring) (finding that “[a]lthough Justice Powell’s formulation may be viewed as more stringent
    than that suggested by Justices Brennan, White, Marshall, and Blackmun, the disparities between
    the two tests do not preclude a fair measure of consensus[,]” particularly where “the distinction
    between a ‘compelling’ and an ‘important’ governmental purpose may be a negligible one”); Bush
    1
    Hereinafter, reference to “the dissent” shall be in regard to Judge Boggs’ dissent, while any
    reference to Judge Gilman’s dissent shall be specifically addressed as such. Judge Batchelder’s
    dissent is not referenced in this opinion.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 32
    v. Vera, 
    517 U.S. 952
    , 1010 (1996) (Stevens, J., dissenting) (noting that “all equal protection
    jurisprudence might be described as a form of rational basis scrutiny; we apply ‘strict scrutiny’ more
    to describe the likelihood of success than the character of the test to be applied”); United States v.
    Virginia, 
    518 U.S. 515
    , 567 (1996) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (contending that “[t]hese tests are no more
    scientific than their names suggest, and a further element of randomness is added by the fact that it
    is largely up to us which test will be applied in each case”)). One should therefore not be taken in
    by the dissent’s many contortions to convolute and undermine the majority’s holding that diversity
    in a student body is a recognized compelling governmental interest pursuant to Justice Powell’s
    controlling opinion in Bakke.2
    B.      The Evidence Supports Diversity as a Compelling Governmental Interest
    Likewise, one should not be led astray by the dissent’s contention that, Justice Powell’s
    opinion aside, developing a diverse student body cannot serve as a compelling state interest. While
    criticizing the majority and implying that it is simply huddling behind Justice Powell’s opinion, the
    dissent claims that “the majority has given us no argument as to why the engineering of a diverse
    student body should be a compelling state interest sufficient to satisfy strict scrutiny.” In an apparent
    attempt to elevate itself over the majority opinion, the dissent goes on to claim that it, on the other
    hand, considers “the arguments on both sides of this question . . . and conclude[s] that constructing
    a diverse educational environment is not a compelling state interest.” The dissent’s claim that it
    considers the arguments on both sides is suspect because conspicuously absent from its consideration
    of the benefits of a diverse student body is any meaningful recognition of the wealth of legal
    scholarship – including a study involving students at the University of Michigan – speaking of, as
    well as documenting through empirical data, the positive impact of diversity in education, not just
    for the student throughout the educational journey but for years after the educational process is
    completed. Although the dissent criticizes this study on various points, the fact remains that the
    study has been hailed on many fronts.
    Specifically, the major study conducted by University of Michigan Professor of Psychology
    and Women’s Studies Patricia Gurin, encompassed a wide scale analysis of the effects of a diverse
    learning environment, particularly that at the University of Michigan, on a student’s overall
    development, and included data from the Michigan Student Study, the study of Intergroup Relations,
    Conflict, and Community Program at the University of Michigan, and the 4-year and 9-year data on
    a large national sample of institutions and students from the Cooperative Institutional Research
    Program. See Patricia Gurin, Reports submitted on behalf of the University of Michigan: The
    Compelling Need for Diversity in Higher Education, 5 MICH. J. RACE & LAW 363, 364 (1999); see
    2
    In this regard, Judge Gilman’s dissent which “assumes without deciding that educational
    diversity as defined by Justice Powell in Bakke is a compelling governmental interest” is misguided
    as well.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 33
    also Steven A. Holmes, A New Turn in Defense of Affirmative Action, N.Y. TIMES, May 11, 1999,
    at A1 (citing Professor Gurin’s report and concluding that “the marshaling of statistical evidence of
    the benefits of racial diversity” distinguished the present case involving the University of Michigan
    from similar cases involving Universities in California and Texas inasmuch as these institutions
    defended their affirmative action policies with only “anecdotal evidence”).
    Professor Gurin’s studies, and resulting statistical data, led her to conclude as follows:
    A racially and ethnically diverse university student body has far-ranging and
    significant benefits for all students, non-minorities and minorities alike. Students
    learn better in a diverse educational environment, and they are better prepared to
    become active participants in our pluralistic, democratic society once they leave such
    a setting. In fact, patterns of racial segregation and separation historically rooted in
    our national life can be broken by diversity experiences in higher education. This
    Report describes the strong evidence supporting these conclusions derived from three
    parallel empirical analyses of university students, as well as from existing social
    science theory and research.
    Students come to universities at a critical stage of their development, a time
    during which they define themselves in relation to others and experiment with
    different social roles before making permanent commitments to occupations, social
    groups, and intimate personal relationships. In addition, for many students college
    is the first sustained exposure to an environment other than their communities.
    Higher education is especially influential when its social milieu is different from the
    community background from which the students come, and when it is diverse enough
    and complex enough to encourage intellectual experimentation. . . .
    Students learn more and think deeper, more complex ways in a diverse
    educational environment. Extensive research in social psychology demonstrates that
    active engagement in learning cannot be taken for granted. . . . Complex thinking
    occurs when people encounter a novel situation for which, by definition, they have
    no script, or when the environment demands more than their current scripts provide.
    Racial diversity in a college or university student body provides the very features that
    research has determined are central to producing the conscious mode of thought
    educators demand from their students. This is particularly true at the University of
    Michigan, because most of the University’s students come to Ann Arbor from
    segregated backgrounds. For most students, then, Michigan’s social diversity is new
    and unfamiliar, a source or multiple and different perspectives, and likely to produce
    contradictory expectations. Social diversity is especially likely to increase effortful,
    active thinking when institutions of higher education capitalize on these conditions
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 34
    in the classroom and provide a climate in which students from diverse backgrounds
    frequently interact with each other.
    Gurin, supra at 364-65. Professor Gurin backed these conclusions with “one of the most broad and
    extensive series of empirical analyses conducted on college students in relation to diversity.” Id. at
    365. For example, Professor Gurin examined “multi-institutional national data, the results of an
    extensive survey of students at the University of Michigan, and data drawn from a specific classroom
    program at the University of Michigan.” Id. All of these studies clearly indicated that interaction
    with peers from diverse racial backgrounds, both in the classroom and informally, positively led to
    what Professor Gurin referred to as “learning outcomes.” That is, “[s]tudents who experienced the
    most racial and ethnic diversity in classroom settings and in informal interactions with peers showed
    the greatest engagement in active thinking processes, growth in intellectual engagement and
    motivation, and growth in intellectual and academic skills.” Id.
    Professor Gurin’s study also indicated that the benefits of a racially diverse student body were
    seen in a second major area, that being preparing students for a meaningful role in a democratic
    society, or what Professor Gurin called positive “democracy outcomes.” Id. at 365-66. “Students
    educated in diverse settings are more motivated and better able to participate in an increasingly
    heterogeneous and complex democracy.” Id. at 366. The results of Professor Gurin’s empirical
    analysis indicated that these diversity experiences during college “had impressive effects on the
    extent to which graduates in the national study were living racially and ethnically integrated lives
    in the post-college world. Students with the most diversity experiences during college had the most
    cross-racial interactions five years after leaving college.” Id. The analysis also indicated that “[t]he
    long-term pattern of racial separation noted by many social scientists can be broken by diversity
    experiences in higher education.” Id.
    Counsel for Plaintiffs in these underlying actions have been critical of Professor Gurin’s
    study and conclusions, claiming that they do nothing to refute the contention that race plays a
    predominate role in the admissions process. As one legal commentator has replied to this criticism,
    [t]he critical question is not, however, whether or not race, or any other arguably
    ‘suspect’ group characteristic, plays a ‘predominate role’ in the admissions process.
    It is, rather, whether there is a compelling educational justification for allowing that
    characteristic to enter the decision-making mix, and it is in that specific context that
    the Gurin study makes a contribution.
    Killenbeck, supra at 1328. Professor Gurin possibly best illustrated the significance of her findings
    as to whether seeking a diverse student body may be considered a compelling state interest when she
    concluded that,
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 35
    [i]n the face of this research evidence, one can only remain unconvinced about the
    impact of diversity if one believes that students are “empty vessels” to be filled with
    specific content knowledge. Much to our chagrin as educators, we are compelled to
    understand that students’ hearts and minds may be impacted the most by what they
    learn from their peers. This is precisely why the diversity of the student body is
    essential to fulfilling higher education’s mission to enhance learning and encourage
    democratic outcomes and values.
    Gurin, supra at 422. In light of Gurin’s study and, perhaps more importantly, the data and empirical
    evidence backing her findings on the value of a diverse student body, those who like the dissent are
    skeptical of characterizing diversity as a compelling governmental interest because “diversity” is not
    defined or because they believe it to be a nebulous concept based on anecdotal evidence, find
    themselves standing on ill footings. See John Friedl, Making a Compelling Case for Diversity in
    College Admissions, 61 U. PITT. L. REV . 1, 29-32 (1999) (noting that “[t]o date, almost all of the
    evidence in support of diversity in higher education is anecdotal in nature[,]” while discussing the
    lack of concrete, empirical evidence substantiating the value of a diverse student body as a
    compelling state interest); see also Wessmann, 
    160 F.3d at 797
     (“[A]ny proponent of any notion of
    diversity could recite a . . . litany of virtues. Hence, an inquiring court cannot content itself with
    abstractions.”).
    Professor Gurin’s empirical evidence supports what Justice Powell found to be true in Bakke
    regarding diversity’s place as a compelling state interest. That is, regardless of whether one agrees
    that Justice Powell’s opinion in Bakke is controlling, the fact remains that Justice Powell recognized
    that a diverse student body is a compelling interest because it promotes the atmosphere of higher
    education to which our nation is committed inasmuch as it allows the students to train in an
    environment embodied with ideas and mores “as diverse as this Nation of many peoples.” See
    Regents of the Univ. of Calif. v. Bakke, 
    438 U.S. 265
    , 312-313 (1978) (Powell, J.) (citing Keyishian
    v. Bd. of Regents, 
    385 U.S. 589
    , 603 (1967)). And, along the lines of Professor Gurin’s study, it was
    expressly noted by Justice Powell that it is the student learning from the other student that makes a
    diverse student body a compelling need. See 
    id.
     at 313 n.48. Specifically, Justice Powell noted and
    embraced the comments of the president of Princeton University as follows:
    “[A] great deal of learning occurs informally. It occurs through interactions among
    students of both sexes; of different races, religions, and backgrounds; who come from
    cities and rural areas, from various states and countries; who have a wide variety of
    interests, talents, and perspectives; and who are able, directly or indirectly, to learn
    from their differences and to stimulate one another to reexamine even their most
    deeply held assumptions about themselves and their world. As a wise graduate of
    ours observed in commenting on this aspect of the educational process, ‘People do
    not learn very much when they are surrounded only the by the likes of themselves.’
    ***
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 36
    “In the nature of things, it is hard to know how, and when, and even if, this informal
    ‘learning through diversity’ actually occurs. It does not occur for everyone. For
    many, however, the unplanned, casual encounters with roommates, fellow sufferers
    in an organic chemistry class, student workers in the library, teammates on a
    basketball squad, or other participants in class affairs or student government can be
    subtle and yet powerful sources of improved understanding and personal growth.”
    
    Id.
     (quoting William Bowen, Admissions and the Relevance of Race, Princeton Alumni Weekly 7,
    9 (Sept. 26, 1977)). Justice Powell then expressly found that the benefits derived from a diverse
    student body apply with substantial force at the graduate level as well as the undergraduate level.
    See 
    id.
     Relying on Sweatt v. Painter, 
    339 U.S. 629
     (1950), he reiterated that the Court made a
    similar point with specific reference to legal education: “‘Few students and no one who has
    practiced law would choose to study in an academic vacuum, removed from the interplay of ideas
    and the exchange of views with which the law is concerned.’” Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 313-14
     (quoting
    Sweatt, 
    339 U.S. at 634
    ).
    In addition to the proffered, and indeed statistically proven, benefits of a diverse student body
    in order to fulfill higher education’s mission to enhance learning and encourage democratic
    outcomes and values, other reasons for justifying state imposed diversity in the educational realm
    have also been proposed. For example, supporters of diversity in the university setting have argued
    that seeking a diverse student body is consistent with this country’s historical commitment to
    absolute equality in education. See Association of American Universities, On the Importance of
    Diversity in University Admissions, N.Y. TIMES, April 24, 1997, at A17; see also Brown v. Bd. of
    Educ., 
    347 U.S. 483
    , 494-95 (1954) (rejecting the “separate but equal” doctrine of Plessy v.
    Ferguson, 
    163 U.S. 537
     (1896), while recognizing and rejecting the past practices of making it
    illegal to educate African Americans, or educating them in inferior surroundings). The law school’s
    concern with the impact of racial isolation and stigmatization when only a few “token” minorities
    are allowed to attend echos this point.
    It has also been argued that designing a system that takes into account factors other than
    traditional notions of merit is nothing new, inasmuch as the very reason affirmative action arose was
    because for years some groups – particularly white males – were provided an advantage over others.
    See Killenbeck, supra at 1320. In fact, as indicated in a detailed study conducted by Professor Linda
    F. Wightman, who at the time of her research served as Vice President for Testing, Operations, and
    Research, Law School Admission Council, Inc., on the realities of affirmative action – “perhaps the
    most compelling finding to emerge is not the extent to which affirmative action has opened the doors
    of legal education to African Americans and other minorities. Instead, it is the extent to which white
    law school applicants routinely benefit from the exceptions to the merit principle.” See id. at 1321
    (citing Linda F. Wightman, The Threat to Diversity in Legal Education: An Empirical Analysis of
    the Consequences of Abandoning Race as a Factor in Law School Admission Decisions, 72 N.Y.U.
    L. REV . 1, 16 tbl.2 (1997)). Killenbeck explains that “[d]ata in [table 2 of Wightman’s study]
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 37
    indicate that 14.9% of accepted white applicants would not have been predicted as suitable for
    acceptance based on the combination of their undergraduate grade point average and LSAT score.
    That is, if the purportedly objective merit criteria embraced by opponents of affirmative action were
    in fact dispositive, nearly one in every six white applicants actually accepted were arguably not
    ‘qualified’ in the traditional sense.” See id. at 1321 n.100. Accordingly, for these white applicants,
    something more than merit was considered in the admissions process, just as something more is
    considered in a program designed to promote diversity. See id.; see also Susan Sturm & Lani
    Guinier, The Future of Affirmative Action: Reclaiming the Innovative Ideal, 84 CALIF . L. REV . 953,
    968-80 (1996) (criticizing the use of standardized test scores as an indicator of candidates’ suitability
    for admission).
    In short, the legal scholarship has indicated that a diverse student body serves to promote our
    nation’s deep commitment to educational equality, provides significant benefits to all students –
    minorities and non-minorities alike, and does so using a system which is not foreign to the
    admissions process, but which allows for the benefit of all and not just some. Thus, although the
    majority does base its holding that diversity is a compelling governmental interest on Justice
    Powell’s opinion in Bakke, it is clear that contrary to the dissent’s criticism, this holding is not
    without foundation even when standing alone. On the other hand, the dissent’s conclusion that
    diversity cannot serve as a compelling state interest for purposes of surviving constitutional muster
    under the Equal Protection Clause, is supported by neither legal scholarship nor empirical evidence.
    For example, the dissent questions why race is at all relevant to promoting a student body
    rich in diversity of experience. Statistics have shown, however, that using factors other than race
    such as socioeconomic status, failed to produce the highly qualified, ethnically diverse student body
    achieved when race was also factored into the admissions process. See Wightman, supra at 39-45.
    The dissent’s position simply misses that point advanced by Defendants in this case at oral argument;
    that is, that a comparably-situated white applicant is a “different person” from the black applicant.
    This is obvious when one considers the dissent’s criticism that the University would give diversity
    preference to a “conventionally liberal” black student who is the child of “lawyer parents living in
    Grosse Pointe” (typically thought of as one of Michigan’s more affluent suburbs).3 Notwithstanding
    the fact that the black applicant may be similarly situated financially to the affluent white candidates,
    this black applicant may very well bring to the student body life experiences rich in the African-
    American traditions emulating the struggle the black race has endured in order for the black applicant
    even to have the opportunities and privileges to learn. See A. LEON HIGGINBOTHAM, JR., SHADES
    3
    The dissent originally characterized the black student as being “conventionally liberal.”
    Then, in response to the criticism that this was in itself stereotypical, the dissent added the
    parenthetical “or conventionally conservative” to its opinion. This addition, however, does nothing
    to change the fact that the dissent is engaging in stereotyping by labeling any minority group as
    “conventionally” of certain views.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 38
    OF FREEDOM, 195-96, 203 (Oxford University Press 1996) (formulating ten precepts of American
    slavery jurisprudence, with the seventh precept being the historical denial of any education to blacks
    and making it a crime to teach those who were slaves how to read and write); see also Frederick
    Douglass, What to the Slave is the Fourth of July? (1852) (addressing Rochester Ladies’ Anti-
    Slavery Society, and noting that “[i]t is admitted in the fact that Southern statute books are covered
    with enactments forbidding, under severe fines and penalties, the teaching of the slave to read or to
    write”).
    It is insulting to African Americans, or to any race or ethnicity that has known oppression and
    discrimination the likes of which slavery embodies, to think that a generation enjoying the end
    product of a life of affluence has forgotten or cannot relate the enormous personal sacrifice made by
    their family members and ancestors not all that long ago in order to make the end possible. Indeed,
    we in this country are only a generation or so removed from the legally enforced segregation which
    was used to discriminatorily deny African Americans and other minorities access to education, as
    well as employment, housing, health care and even basic public facilities. In addition, it is naive to
    believe that because an African American lives in an affluent neighborhood, he or she has not known
    or been the victim of discrimination such that he or she cannot relate the same life experiences as
    the impoverished black person. A well dressed black woman of wealthy means shopping at Neiman
    Marcus or in an affluent shopping center may very well be treated with the same suspect eye and
    bigotry as the poorly dressed black woman of limited means shopping at Target. See Elise
    O’Shaughnessy, Shopping While Black, GOOD HOUSEKEEPING, Nov. 2001, at 129 (recounting Oprah
    Winphrey’s experience of being turned away from an affluent store while she was shopping with a
    black female companion, even though white customers were allowed admittance, allegedly on the
    premise that the store employees were of the belief that Oprah and her friend were the black
    transsexuals who had previously tried to rob the store; also recounting the discrimination other
    successful black females such as Congresswoman Maxine Waters have experienced while shopping).
    Thus, the dissent’s arguments as to why diversity cannot serve as a compelling state interest
    constitute nothing more than myopic, baseless conclusions that ignore the daily affairs and
    interactions of society today which very well may be experienced by all. And the dissent’s offer to
    “stipulate” to the fact that race continues to play a negative role in the lives of minorities is nothing
    more than a mere expression of words made in an attempt to minimize the force of the many benefits
    of diversity as illustrated above. Anyone who has read the entire dissent quickly realizes that the
    dissent’s offer to stipulate that “race does matter,” constitutes a thinly-veiled offer of dubious
    sincerity, to say the least.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 39
    This is evident by the dissent’s contention that the arguments made in favor of diversity
    merely address societal ills that should not be confused with individual rights.4 The “societal ills”
    as characterized by the dissent are in fact borne out of the denial of individual rights such that the
    two cannot be separated. Indeed, history tells us that the Equal Protection Clause was enacted in an
    attempt to cure the “societal ills” that had denied African Americans the individual rights to which
    they were entitled, such as the right to an education. See ALBERT P. BLAUSTEIN & CLARENCE CLYDE
    FERGUSON, JR., DESEGREGATION AND THE LAW - THE MEANING AND EFFECT OF THE SCHOOL
    SEGREGATION CASES 59-67 (Rutgers University Press 1985) (1957). It has been recognized that “the
    evil to remedied by this clause” was the “gross injustice and hardship” faced by the “newly
    emancipated Negroes” as a class. See In re Slaughter-House Cases, 
    16 Wall. 36
    , 81 (1873). And
    it has been further recognized that the justifications for the Fourteenth Amendment’s ratification
    “retain their validity in modern times, for 114 years after the close of the War Between the States,
    . . . racial and other forms of discrimination still remain a fact of life, in the administration of justice
    as in our society as a whole.” See Vasquez v. Hillery, 
    474 U.S. 254
    , 264 (1986). Accordingly, for
    the dissent to claim that “people like Barbara Grutter” are being denied equal treatment under the
    law school’s admission policy such that the Equal Protection Clause is being “ignored,” particularly
    while irreverently invoking the name of Abraham Lincoln, is completely unfounded. The law
    school’s goal of creating a diverse student body, which has not existed previously and would not
    otherwise exist without its admissions policy, rests in the very heart of the Equal Protection Clause.
    Moreover, contrary to the dissent’s assertion, there is nothing to indicate that the law school’s
    admission’s policy has “taken” anything “from the Barbara Grutters of our society.” As one legal
    scholar has recently illustrated, the idea that an admissions policy which provides minority applicants
    with an advantage does so at the expense of white applicants is simply a myth. See Goodwin Liu,
    The Myth & Math of Affirmative Action, The Washington Post, April 14, 2002, at B01 (citing
    excerpts from his article “The Causation Fallacy: Bakke and the Basic Arithmetic of Selective
    Admissions” which is to be published in the upcoming edition of the Michigan Law Review). As
    Liu makes note,
    [f]or many Americans, the success of Bakke’s lawsuit has long highlighted what is
    unfair about affirmative action: Giving minority applicants a significant advantage
    4
    I bring to the fore the “societal ills” – as the dissent has couched it – of the past and present
    faced by minorities to illustrate that, contrary to the dissent’s assertion, a minority member of
    wealthy means may bring to the educational environment the same “life experiences” that a minority
    member of impoverished means may bring because the “societal ills” experienced by both transcend
    economic status. Once again, the reader should not be led astray by the dissent’s attempt to ignore
    or reframe an issue. While it is true that the Supreme Court has found that a generalized claim of
    past discrimination cannot serve as the basis for a remedial plan, no such claim is being made in this
    case.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 40
    causes deserving white applicants to lose out. But to draw such an inference in
    Bakke’s case – or in the case of the vast majority of rejected white applicants – is to
    indulge in . . . “the causation fallacy.”
    There’s no doubt, based on test scores and grades, that Bakke was a highly qualified
    applicant. Justice Lewis Powell, who authored the decisive opinion in the case,
    observed that Bakke’s Medical College Admission Test (MCAT) scores placed him
    in the top tier of test-takers, whereas the average scores of the quota beneficiaries in
    1974 placed them in the bottom third. Likewise, his science grade point average was
    3.44 on a 4.0 scale, compared with at 2.42 average for the special admittees, and his
    overall GPA was similarly superior. Given these numbers, the only reason for
    Bakke’s rejection was the school’s need to make room for less qualified minority
    applicants, right?
    Wrong. Although Justice Powell pointed out that minority applicants were admitted
    with grades and test scores much lower than Bakke’s, he did not discuss what I found
    to be the most striking data that appeared in his opinion: Bakke’s grades and scores
    were significantly higher than the average for the regular admittees. In other words,
    his academic qualifications were better than those of the majority of applicants
    admitted outside the racial quota. So why didn’t he earn one of the 84 regular
    places?
    It is clear that the medical school admitted students not only on the basis of grades
    and test scores, but on other factors relevant to the study and practice of medicine,
    such as compassion, communication skills and commitment to research. Justice
    Powell’s opinion does not tell us exactly what qualities the regular admittees had that
    Bakke lacked. But it notes that the head of the admissions committee, who
    interviewed Bakke, found him “rather limited in approach” to medical problems and
    thought he had “very definite opinions which were based more on his personal
    viewpoints than upon a study of the total problem.”
    Whatever Bakke’s weaknesses were, there were several reasons, apart from
    affirmative action, that might have led the medical school to reject his application.
    Grades and test scores do not tell us the whole story.
    
    Id.
    Liu went on to recognize that although affirmative action did lower Bakke’s chance of
    admission to the medical school, what was significant and most telling is “by how much?” 
    Id.
    Setting forth the statistical data Liu then observed:
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 41
    One way to answer this question is to compare Bakke’s chance of admission had he
    competed for all 100 seats in the class with his chance of admission competing for
    the 84 seats outside of the racial quota. To simplify, let’s assume none of the special
    applicants would have been admitted ahead of any regular candidate.
    In 1974, Bakke was one of 3,109 regular applicants to the medical school. With the
    racial quota, the average likelihood of admission for regular applicants was 2.7
    percent (84 divided by 3,109). With no racial quota, the average likelihood of
    admission would have been 3.2 percent (100 divided by 3,109). So the quota
    increased the average likelihood of rejection from 96.8 percent to 97.3 percent.
    To be sure, Bakke was not an average applicant. Only one-sixth of regular applicants
    (roughly 520) received an interview. But even among these highly qualified
    applicants, eliminating the racial quota would have increased the average rate of
    admission from 16 percent (84 divided by 520) to only 19 percent (100 divided by
    520). Certainly a few more regular applicants would have been admitted were it not
    for affirmative action. But Bakke, upon receiving his rejection letter, had no reason
    to believe he would have been among the lucky few.
    In fact, Bakke applied in both 1973 and 1974 and, according to evidence in the
    lawsuit, he did not even make the waiting list in either year.
    The statistical pattern in Bakke’s case is not an anomaly. It occurs in any selection
    process in which the applicants who do not benefit from affirmative action greatly
    outnumber those who do.
    Recent research confirms this point. Using 1989 data from a representative sample
    of selective schools, former university presidents William Bowen and Derek Bok
    showed in their 1998 book, “The Shape of the River,” that eliminating racial
    preferences would have increased the likelihood of admission for white
    undergraduate applicants from 25 percent to only 26.5 percent.
    The Mellon Foundation, which sponsored the study, provided me with additional
    data to calculate admission rates by SAT score. If the schools in the Bowen/Bok
    sample had admitted applicants with similar SAT scores at the same rate regardless
    of race, the chance of admission for white applicants would have increased by one
    percentage point or less at scores 1300 and above, by three to four percentage points
    at scores from 1150 to 1299, and by four to seven percentage points at scores below
    1150.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 42
    It is true that black applicants were admitted at much higher rates than white
    applicants with similar grades and test scores. But that fact does not prove that
    affirmative action imposes a substantial disadvantage on white applicants. The
    extent of the disadvantage depends on the number of blacks and whites in the
    applicant pool. Because the number of black applicants to selective institutions is
    relatively small, admitting them a higher rates does not significantly lower the chance
    of admission for the average individual in the relatively large sea of white applicants.
    
    Id.
     (emphasis added).
    Liu provided further statistical data to back this conclusion as follows:
    In the Bowen/Bok study, for example, 60 percent of black applicants scoring 1200-
    1249 on the SAT were admitted, compared with 19 percent of whites. In the 1250-
    1299 range, 74 percent of blacks were admitted, compared with 23 percent of whites.
    These data indicate – more so than proponents of affirmative action typically
    acknowledge – that racial preferences give minority applicants a substantial
    advantage. But eliminating affirmative action would have increased the admission
    rate for whites from 19 percent to only 21 percent in the 1200-1249 range, and from
    23 percent to only 24 percent in the 1250-1299 range.
    These figures show that rejected white applicants have every reason not to blame
    their misfortune on affirmative action. In selective admissions, the competition is so
    intense that even without affirmative action, the overwhelming majority of rejected
    white applicants still wouldn’t get in.
    
    Id.
     (emphasis added). And so, contrary to the dissent’s assertion, “the Barbara Grutters of our
    society” have no reason to claim that anything has been “taken” from them by virtue of the law
    school’s admission policy. In purporting otherwise, the dissent is simply advancing “the causation
    fallacy” which Liu exposes for the myth that it is.
    The dissent also contends that one cannot consider the remedial qualities of correcting past
    – or for that matter present – discrimination as a way of supporting the law school’s admissions
    policy because past discrimination is not the basis upon which the school claims that its admissions
    policy is operating. Once again, the dissent’s narrow-mindedness misses the point. While it is true
    that the law school’s policy is based upon its desire to achieve a diverse student body, the very
    reason that the law school is in need of a program to create a diverse environment is because the
    discrimination faced by African Americans and other minorities throughout the educational process
    has not produced a diverse student body in the normal course of things. Diversity in education, at
    its base, is the desegregation of a historically segregated population and, as the intervenors
    essentially argue, Bakke and Brown must therefore be read together so as to allow a school to
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 43
    consider race or ethnicity in its admissions for many reasons, including to remedy past discrimination
    or present racial bias in the educational system. See Trevor W. Coleman, A well-deserved honor for
    a lifelong legal barrier breaker, The Detroit Free Press, April 26, 2002, at 10A (chronicling the life
    of the Honorable William McClain, the University of Michigan’s oldest living African-American
    law graduate, and describing how, as the only black law student in his class at the University,
    McClain was “fed humiliation nearly every day,” was forbidden from living in the law quad, and was
    “prevented from joining study groups which are essential to a legal education”).
    In summary, the dissent’s attempt to cast the law school’s interest in achieving a diverse
    student body as anything but compelling simply cannot carry the day, and its claim that white
    applicants are being denied equal protection under the law as a result of the school’s attempt to
    achieve a diverse student body is fallacious. As next illustrated, the dissent’s arguments as to why
    the school’s admissions policy is not narrowly tailored to achieve this compelling interest are just
    as ill-conceived.
    C.      The Law School’s Policy is Narrowly Tailored
    The dissent quarters its argument as to why the law school’s admissions policy is not
    narrowly tailored to achieve the compelling interest of diversity. Each of the four subparts bear
    arguments that are unfounded and inflammatory. For example, in first discussing what the dissent
    characterizes as the true magnitude of the law school’s policy, the dissent focuses on LSAT and
    UGPA data. It then advances the outrageous contention that the law school’s policy allows for a
    minority applicant to put forth less effort than the otherwise similarly situated white applicant, and
    that somehow the minority will therefore use his race to compensate for his lack of effort. There is
    nothing whatsoever in the record to support the allegation that the law school’s admissions policy
    would be manipulated in this fashion by people of color or ethnicity.
    Similarly, the dissent’s assertion that the law schools treatment of numerical credentials
    (UGPA and LSAT scores) for purposes of admission is “shocking,” ignores the scholarly writings
    showing no correlation between these numerical credentials and success in law school or bar passage
    rates. See Wightman, supra at 1-2 (explaining that while a “numbers only” policy resulted in a sharp
    decline in the number of minority students who would have been admitted to law school, there were
    no significant differences in the graduation rates and bar passage rates between those minority
    students who would have been admitted and those who would not have been admitted, thus leading
    to the conclusion that a “numbers only” policy would deny a legal education to many minority
    students who were fully capable of the rigors of a legal education and of entering the legal
    profession); Sturm & Guinier, supra at 968-80 (explaining standardized test scores’ lack of
    predictive value with respect to students’ future performance). The law school’s effort to insure that
    its admissions process is inclusionary and is not substantively unfair should be viewed as an effort
    to advance the cause of both educational excellence and diversity, not as a counterpoint to a “merit”
    plan as suggested by the dissent. The case has not been convincingly made that conventional
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 44
    admissions plans which equate to higher socio-economic status persuasively correlate to
    consideration of “merit.” See id. at 992-96.
    The dissent barely conceals its disbelief in the truth of the law school’s assertion that its
    admissions officer reads every applicant’s file and makes an individualized determination regarding
    the applicant’s suitability for admission. Accepting the dissent’s argument requires, in part, rejecting
    the law school’s description of the manner in which its admissions program is administered without
    any adequate justifiable basis for doing so. The dissent goes so far as to claim the above-referenced
    criticisms of using standardized test scores such as the LSAT and numerical credentials as means
    to admission should be directed to the law school and not to the dissent inasmuch as the law school
    chooses to consider such credentials in its admission policy. However, the dissent’s claim in this
    regard misses the point, and is an example of the misrepresentations made by the dissent in an
    apparent attempt to reframe the issues. Criticism of the use of numerical credentials such as LSAT
    scores is made in this opinion to support the law school’s use of other criteria in its admission policy
    – one of which is race or ethnicity. And, contrary to the dissent’s inflammatory assertion, the law
    school relies upon many factors in addition to LSAT scores, UGPAs, and race in its admission
    process. Although this assertion undoubtedly bolsters the dissent’s position, it is unfounded and flies
    in the face of the record before us.
    The dissent next calls into question the law school’s designation of a “critical mass” of
    minority students in its student body. Claiming that the term “critical mass” is simply a phrase used
    to disguise what is actually an impermissible quota system, the dissent relies heavily upon the fact
    that the numbers of minorities admitted over the years has varied only sightly. There may be any
    number of likely benign explanations for the numerical configurations, including a consistency in
    the quality of minority applications for a few successive years and/or the application of a uniformity
    of perspective in evaluating the applications resulting from having the same evaluators read all the
    applications for admissions. Even idiosyncratic explanations for a relatively narrow numerical range
    for a number of years would be constitutionally acceptable in the absence of a quota or other
    invidious motivation on the part of the law school. The point is that on the record of this case, there
    are at least as many reasons to presume that there is not a quota as there are to presume that there is
    one, and the balance certainly tips in favor of the law school’s representation that it does not employ
    a quota in the absence of any evidence to the contrary.5
    Typically, the purpose of the narrow tailoring inquiry involves an evaluation of the fit
    between the compelling interest and the policy adopted to advance that interest. See Recent Cases,
    115 HARV . L. REV . 1239, 1244-45 (2002) (criticizing the Eleventh Circuit’s decision that found the
    University of Georgia’s race-conscious admissions policy unconstitutional, while noting that the
    5
    Inasmuch as Judge Gilman appears to rest his dissent on his belief that the law school’s
    policy results in an impermissible quota system, his conclusion is fallacious as well.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 45
    court’s opinion “reveals both overt and covert hostility toward affirmative action policies” and that
    “[b]y introducing its own substantive agenda under the guise of a narrow tailoring analysis, the court
    strayed from the purpose of the narrow tailoring inquiry”). Here, the dissent claims that the link
    between the law school’s “critical mass” and the values of diversity is lacking. Oddly, the dissent
    cites the report from Professor Gurin, the same report that others have hailed as showing documented
    evidence for the benefits of a diverse student body, claiming that the results indicate just the opposite
    of how Professor Gurin reports them. This contention, regardless of its accuracy, appears to be in
    criticism of the concept of diversity itself, and not of the process to achieve that end.
    Next, the dissent criticizes the relationship between diversity and the means to promote this
    interest as being dependent upon the psychological makeup of the people involved. The dissent
    refers to historical black leaders such as Frederick Douglass and Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr., opining
    that these men would have said their piece without regard to whether others thought them to be
    “representative.” Apparently, by using these black leaders to make its point, the dissent is claiming
    that the process employed by the law school is not necessary because if an African American, or
    other minority group member, has the “psychological” make-up to be a leader, he will be so
    regardless of whether he is one among ten or one among one hundred. Such an allegation misses
    the point of the many beneficial aspects of diversity in education to minorities and non-minorities
    alike, is an affront to the sacrifices and contributions made by these black leaders, and does nothing
    to show why the law school’s policy is not narrowly tailored. In fact, the dissent appears to be doing
    nothing more than “introducing its own substantive agenda under the guise of a narrow tailoring
    analysis” in making its arguments here. See Recent Cases, 
    supra at 1239
    .
    Finally, the dissent claims that because race-neutral means are available to achieve academic
    diversity, the law school’s program does not pass constitutional muster. In reaching this conclusion,
    the dissent completely ignores the evidence provided by the law school and its efforts to formulate
    a viable race-neutral policy. The dissent strongly suggests that it simply does not believe the law
    school’s representation that it considered and rejected as unworkable or impractical other admissions
    policies and procedures, either because the available alternatives would not result in the sort of
    competitive student body pursued by the law school overall, or because the number of qualified
    minority students attracted to the law school would be inadequate. The law school’s premise, which
    the dissent fails to convincingly dispute, is that the number of minority law students admitted would
    be inconsequential in the absence of the school’s current admissions program.
    Indeed, one of the dissent’s proposals as a “race-neutral” means of admission, using a lottery
    for all students above certain threshold figures for their GPA and LSAT, is in no way “race-neutral”
    as reflected in the record. For example, the record indicates (through the testimony of Jay Rosner,
    Martin Shapiro, and David White among others) that performance on tests such as the LSAT and the
    SAT correlates with an applicant’s race and gender. In other words, the record indicates that LSAT
    scores are neither race-neutral or gender-neutral criteria for admissions decisions. Consequently, the
    dissent’s proposal of using a lottery based upon scores resulting from these tests in order to achieve
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 46
    a race-neutral means of admission is inherently flawed, and would in no way reflect race-neutral
    merit. Instead, such a proposal would reflect a combination of subtle preferences based on race,
    gender, and even class, see Sturm & Guinier, supra at 992-96; see also supra text accompanying Part
    B, and are of limited utility for predicting meaningful success across racial lines.
    At its core, in purporting to suggest race-neutral methodologies, the dissent simply engages
    in an impermissible exercise of substituting its judgment in this regard for that of the educators who
    are the custodians and guardians of the law school’s mission and academic standards. See Regents
    of the Univ. of Mich. v. Ewing, 
    474 U.S. 214
    , 225 (1985); see generally Susan Stefan, Leaving Civil
    Rights to the “Experts”: From Deference to Abdication Under the Professional Judgment Standard,
    102 YALE L.J. 639 (1992) (providing a summary of the general doctrine of the rule of deference and
    the situations to which it has been applied). Indeed, on the record before us, any purportedly race-
    neutral policy could result in a de facto segregated law school, the deleterious results of which have
    long been known by society and rejected by the Court. See, e.g., Sweatt, 
    339 U.S. at 634-36
    .
    D.      Summary
    Chief Judge Martin’s majority opinion reversing the district court and finding the law
    school’s admissions policy constitutional under the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth
    Amendment provides a clear understanding and resolution of the issues involved. The dissent’s
    attempt to turn the majority opinion on its head and to reframe the issues does nothing to advance
    the jurisprudence on this very significant matter.
    E.      Response to the Dissent’s “Procedural Appendix”
    Although the dissent’s substantive attack, which is grounded in neither fact nor law, is
    disturbing, the dissent’s procedural attack, as set forth in its “Procedural Appendix,” constitutes an
    embarrassing and incomprehensible attack on the integrity of the Chief Judge and this Court as a
    whole. Apparently, the dissent’s strategy in this regard is that if its substantive basis for
    disagreement with the majority opinion is not convincing, then questioning the procedural posture
    of this case will be enough to forever cast doubt upon the outcome reached here today. This
    unfortunate tactic has no place in scholarly jurisprudence and certainly does not deserve to be
    dignified with a response. However, because of the magnitude of the issues involved, and because
    of the baseless nature of the allegations, this procedural attack cannot go unanswered.
    The dissent questions the appropriateness of hearing this case en banc, the course by which
    this case came to be heard by the en banc court, and the composition of the en banc court itself. It
    should be noted at the outset that throughout the pendency of this appeal, the dissent remained silent
    on all of these questions until now, and its concerns should therefore be regarded as having been
    waived or forfeited. It was not until the various opinions had been circulated throughout the Court
    and the votes cast by the panel members that the dissent revised its opinion by tacking on these
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 47
    complaints and allegations. And the dissent’s new-found allegations of impropriety as to the course
    this matter followed in reaching the en banc court simply defy belief. It is ludicrous to think that
    with our circuit operating with only one-half of the active judges’ positions filled, and with over
    4000 cases reaching our Court each year, the Chief Judge or any members of this Court would single
    out any one particular case and maneuver the system for a particular outcome. None of the decisions
    made by the Chief Judge in regard to the scheduling of this case or in relation to administering the
    Court’s docket, differ in any significant way from the decisions the Chief Judge and the Court’s staff
    routinely and frequently make with respect to pending matters. Given the voluminous nature of the
    Court’s docket and the shortage of judicial resources, the case management tasks performed by the
    Chief Judge are both necessary and appropriate, and were not in any sense improperly performed in
    relation to the instant case.
    Again, it is unfortunate that the dissent has chosen to stoop to such desperate and unfounded
    allegations which serve no useful purpose. The dissent’s claim that it is “legitimizing” the Court by
    revealing the procedural course of this matter is disingenuous, at best, when considering that the
    dissent (Judge Boggs) once scathingly attacked Judge Damon J. Keith for revealing the vote count
    in a case of major import wherein the denial for rehearing en banc was split seven-seven. See
    Memphis Planned Parenthood v. Sundquist, 
    184 F.3d 600
    , 605-07 (6th Cir. 1999) (published order)
    (Boggs, J.). Judge Keith wrote in Memphis that he revealed the seven-seven vote tally because it
    supported his belief that the majority’s opinion was result driven, and to encourage the litigant to
    possibly seek further review. See 
    id. at 601-02
     (Keith, J.). Judge Keith emphasized that in making
    the vote tally known, he had “not violated any rule of internal policy . . .; nor [had he] divulged any
    internal confidential communications[,]” and found “reprehensible” the “practices of secrecy and
    concealment advocated by Judge Boggs.” 
    Id. at 605
    . In response, Judge Boggs noted “with regret,
    [Judge Keith’s alleged] breach of the long-standing custom of this court that actions by a member
    of the court with respect to petitions for rehearing of en banc matters are matters of internal court
    procedure and are not made public by other judges.” 
    Id.
     (Boggs, J.) (emphasis added). Judge Boggs
    went so far as to question the accuracy of Judge Keith’s conveyance of the vote tally by writing that
    “our court, of course, makes no warranties as to the accuracy of the assertions made in statements
    by judges (including, of course, this one).” 
    Id. at 605
    .
    Despite his one-time “regret” for a fellow jurist’s decision to make the vote tally known in
    an en banc case, Judge Boggs now characterizes his flagrant disregard for the Court’s procedural
    measures with respect to this case as a form of “legitimacy.” Judge Boggs has revealed internal
    procedural matters to the public, particularly when he speaks of Senior Judge Ralph Guy’s internal
    communication to Chief Judge Martin in footnote 46 of his dissent. Furthermore, the remaining
    members of this Court have no way of responding to any inaccuracies by Judge Boggs regarding
    Judge Guy’s communication – or Judge Boggs’ characterization thereof – without themselves
    resorting to discussing the Court’s internal communications. Like many of the assertions made in
    his dissent as a whole, Judge Boggs’ renouncement of secrecy and claim that his procedural
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 48
    appendix “legitimizes” the Court, are hollow, particularly in light of his position in Memphis.
    Indeed, it was “secrecy” for which Judge Boggs so vehemently argued in Memphis.
    If anything, the fact that this significant matter was heard initially by the en banc court is a
    course of action advocated by justices of the United States Supreme Court. For example, in her letter
    to the White Commission, and several times in addressing the Ninth Circuit Judicial Conference,
    Justice O’Connor, circuit justice to the Ninth Circuit, has suggested that the courts of appeals sit en
    banc in matters they think are likely to reach the Supreme Court. See Stephen L. Wasby, How do
    Courts of Appeals En Banc Decisions Fare in the U.S. Supreme Court?, JUDICATURE , Jan. -Feb.
    2002, at 184 & n.6. Likewise, Justice Kennedy, himself a former member of the Ninth Circuit,
    suggested to the White Commission that “questions of exceptional importance” are not heard en
    banc nearly often enough. See 
    id.
     at 184 & n.7 (quoting Justice Anthony M. Kennedy, letter to
    Justice Bryon R. White, August 17, 1998).
    Here, in this matter of exceptional importance which may likely reach the Supreme Court,
    we as an en banc court have properly and carefully considered the issues involved. Chief Judge
    Martin’s thorough majority opinion in every regard reflects that careful consideration, such that the
    outcome reached today is one based upon nothing other than sound and scholarly deliberation.
    Despite its unfortunate and desperate attempts to portray the majority opinion as anything less, the
    dissent’s substantive and procedural attacks remain unpersuasive.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 49
    _____________
    DISSENT
    _____________
    BOGGS, Circuit Judge, dissenting. This case involves a straightforward instance of racial
    discrimination by a state institution. Other than in the highly charged context of discrimination in
    educational decisions in favor of “underrepresented minorities,” the constitutional justifications
    offered for this practice would not pass even the slightest scrutiny. See, e.g., Fullilove v. Klutznick,
    
    448 U.S. 448
    , 491 (1980) (Burger, concurring) (“Any preference based on racial or ethnic criteria
    must necessarily receive a most searching examination.”); Regents of the Univ. of Calif. v. Bakke,
    
    438 U.S. 265
    , 307 (1978) (Powell, concurring) (“Preferring members of any one group for no reason
    other than race or ethnic origin is discrimination for its own sake. This the Constitution forbids.”);
    Loving v. Virginia, 
    388 U.S. 1
    , 11 (1967) (“[T]his Court has consistently repudiated distinctions
    between citizens solely because of their ancestry as being odious to a free people whose institutions
    are founded upon the doctrine of equality.” (internal quotations omitted)); McLaughlin v. Florida,
    
    379 U.S. 184
    , 196 (1964) (invalidating a Florida state law against interracial cohabitation as “an
    exercise of the state police power which trenches upon the constitutionally protected freedom from
    invidious official discrimination based on race”). In our case, the intent of the framers of the policy,
    the statistics as to its impact and effect, and the history of its inception all point unmistakably to a
    denial of equal protection of the laws. I, therefore, dissent from our court’s decision today finding
    this discrimination to be constitutional.
    In tracing the intricacies of the argument presented by the court and by the Law School, we
    must be aware that the definitions and precise connotations of words are of crucial importance. As
    I shall demonstrate, in many critical instances, key words are used in ways contrary to their normal
    grammatical meaning, or with very specific qualifications attached sub silentio. In the words of
    George Orwell, in his famous essay Politics and the English Language, “a mass of Latin words falls
    upon the facts like soft snow, blurring the outline and covering up all the details.” George Orwell,
    Politics and the English Language, in 4 THE COLLECTED ESSAYS, JOURNALISM AND LETTERS OF
    GEORGE ORWELL : IN FRONT OF YOUR NOSE , 1945-1950 127 (Sonia Orwell and Ian Angus, eds.,
    Harcourt, Brace 1968).
    A very revealing example of this is the use of the term “affirmative action” to refer to the
    policies in question. See Majority Op. at 3 (discussing intervening student groups, including “United
    for Equality and Affirmative Action, the Coalition to Defend Affirmative Action By Any Means
    Necessary, and Law Students for Affirmative Action”). Standing alone, the term “affirmative
    action” might mean anything from affirmative action to study harder to affirmative action to exclude
    minorities. However, as used in the context of our society’s struggle against racial discrimination,
    the term first enters the public print and the national vocabulary in Executive Order 10925, issued
    by President John F. Kennedy on March 6, 1961 and subsequently incorporated into a wide variety
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 50
    of statutes and regulations. It ordered government contractors to “take affirmative action, to ensure
    that applicants are employed, and that employees are treated during employment, without regard to
    their race, creed, color, or national origin” 
    Ibid.
     (emphasis added). It is thus clear that whatever else
    Michigan’s policy may be, it is not “affirmative action.”1
    The Law School absolutely insists that it does not consider applicants “without regard to”
    their race. See, e.g., Admissions Policies, University of Michigan Law School, April 22, 1992, at
    12 (noting “a commitment to racial and ethnic diversity with special reference to the inclusion of
    students from groups which have been historically discriminated against . . . [and] who without this
    commitment might not be represented in our student body in meaningful numbers”). Instead, as is
    discussed by the majority and will be discussed at length below, Michigan considers all applicants
    with exquisite regard for their race and national origin. As I put it to the counsel for the Law School
    in oral argument, if Heman Sweatt, the plaintiff in the famous case of Sweatt v. Painter, 
    339 U.S. 629
     (1950), had been able to ask the Dean of the University of Texas Law School, “Dean, would you
    let me in if I were white?,” the dean, if he were honest, would surely have said “Yes.” I then asked
    counsel, “If Barbara Grutter walked in to whoever the current Dean of the Law School is and said,
    1
    I will occasionally use the phrases “race” and “racial” as a shorthand for the type of
    preference accorded by the Law School. In fact, the groups chosen for preference are a melange of
    groupings that are socially defined:
    by skin color (“black” or “African-American.” I note that the children of Boer or Berber
    immigrants are not conventionally given the latter label, which would surely apply to them
    as a linguistic matter.);
    by national origin (as the Census Bureau carefully notes, “Hispanics” can be of any race.
    Presumably, the children of the former Peruvian president, Alberto Fujimori, though
    ethnographically purely Japanese, would be considered “Hispanic.”);
    or by legal status (depending on whether Michigan limits “Native American” preference to
    legally enrolled tribal members, as opposed to those with sufficient ancestry of “Indian”
    status that would qualify a person with comparable black or Hispanic ancestry for those
    designations).
    Any shorthand use of those terms in this opinion should be understood to have all the
    relevant qualifiers. For similar precision by other universities with racial and ethnic preferences,
    see Brief of Amicus Curiae, Columbia Univ., Harvard Univ., Stanford Univ., and the Univ. of Penn.,
    in Regents of the Univ. of California v. Bakke, 99 LANDMA RK BRIEFS AND ARGUMENTS OF THE
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES : CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 1977 TERM SUPP . 689, 698 n.3
    (Phillip B. Kurland & Gerhard Casper, eds., 1978).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 51
    ‘Dean, would you let me in if I were black?’ wouldn’t he have to honestly say either ‘Yes’ or ‘pretty
    darn almost certain[ly]’?” Counsel agreed, but responded that “a black woman who had otherwise
    an application that looked like Barbara Grutter, that would be a different person.” Tr. at 38 (emphasis
    added).
    That answer puts starkly the policy of discrimination practiced throughout the ages.
    Throughout this discussion, my quarrel is with the constitutionality of the policy, not its
    proponents. In a related context, Robert’s Rules of Order gives a good rule for public disputation:
    those engaged in a debate “can condemn the nature or likely consequences of the proposed measure
    in strong terms, but . . . under no circumstances . . . attack or question the motives of another.”
    General Henry M. Robert, ROBERT ’S RULES OF ORDER 380 (10th ed. 2000). I have no doubt that
    the proponents of this discriminatory policy act with the most tender of motives. However, the noble
    motives of those propounding unconstitutional policies should not save those policies, just as some
    segregationists’ genuine belief that segregated education provided better education for both races was
    inadequate to justify those policies.
    Finally, I do not doubt that there are strong policy arguments for what Michigan has done.
    There is a plausible (though perhaps not a sound) policy argument that government should arrange
    social outcomes proportionally according to the race or ethnicity of its citizens, remedying, where
    it can, any pervasively unequal distribution of wealth, education, or status. There are many countries
    – India, Malaysia, and Serbia, to name a few – where such a policy is practiced. For more on
    “affirmative action” worldwide, see Thomas Sowell, RACE AND CULTURE : A WORLD VIEW 126-29
    (Basic 1994). However, so long as the Equal Protection Clause is a part of the United States
    Constitution, the United States is not one of those countries. The fact that some might think this
    society would be a better one if more governmental benefits were allocated, because of their racial
    or ethnic status, to blacks, Hispanics, or Native Americans and less to whites, Asians, or Jews, or
    vice-versa, does not make those policies permissible under our Constitution.
    Instead, the framers of the Fourteenth Amendment decided that our government should
    abstain from social engineering through explicit racial classifications. Thus, we subject every state
    racial classification to “strict scrutiny,” requiring that the state show both that the classification
    furthers a “compelling state interest” and that it is “narrowly tailored” to achieve that interest.
    Adarand Constructors v. Pena, 
    515 U.S. 200
    , 235 (1995). The Law School’s admissions scheme
    simply cannot withstand the scrutiny that the Constitution demands.
    My discussion of the reasons for that conclusion falls into two parts below. First, I examine
    why the majority’s reading of Bakke is erroneous. Read correctly, Bakke remains good law, but does
    not conclusively resolve the questions before this court. More recent decisions of the Supreme
    Court, contrary to Grutter’s argument and what the district court in this case held, place these
    questions in no greater relief.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 52
    We are therefore faced with resolving for ourselves the constitutionality of the Law School’s
    admissions scheme. Our inquiry must address at least one open question of law: can achieving
    diversity be a compelling state interest? On this open question, I have no argument to which to
    respond, as the majority never explains why “diversity” should be a compelling state interest, except
    to say that the conclusion is demanded by Bakke.2 After considering the arguments on both sides,
    I conclude that the state’s interest in a diverse student body, at least as articulated by the Law School,
    cannot constitute a compelling state interest sufficient to satisfy strict scrutiny.
    Second, much like Justice Powell’s in Bakke, my answer to whether the engineering of a
    racially diverse student body is a compelling state interest is not necessary to the resolution of the
    case before this court. Even if student diversity were a compelling state interest, the Law School’s
    admissions scheme could not be considered narrowly tailored to that interest. Even a cursory glance
    at the Law School’s admissions data reveals the staggering magnitude of the Law School’s racial
    preference. Its admissions officers have swapped tailor’s shears for a chainsaw.
    I. The State of the Current Law
    A. Bakke in a Nutshell
    The Law School and the majority of this court argue that the constitutionality of the Law
    School’s policy is mandated by Supreme Court precedent, engaging in a painstaking analysis of the
    Supreme Court’s decision in Regents of the University of California v. Bakke, 
    438 U.S. 265
     (1978),
    and the instructions given in Marks v. United States, 
    430 U.S. 188
     (1977), for attempting to discern
    a “holding” from decisions in which the Court is splintered. I will engage in an equally detailed
    counter-analysis; however, I begin with what is obvious from the face of the opinion.
    In Bakke, the Supreme Court held that the particular type of massive racial discrimination
    engaged in by the University of California at Davis – setting aside a certain number of seats each
    year and utilizing a separate admissions system for minority applicants – was illegal and that Allan
    Bakke had a right not to be so discriminated against.3 (This fact is not revealed until page 12 of the
    majority’s decision, and then only obliquely). However, five members of the Court agreed that a
    2
    The concurring opinion does present substantive arguments on this point, which are
    considered in Part II.A. Concurring Op. at 29-39 (Clay).
    3
    The judgment of the Court, affirming the judgment of the California Supreme Court and
    ordering UC Davis to admit Bakke, was supported by the opinions of Justice Powell, Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 320
    , who would have held that UC Davis’s program violated the Fourteenth Amendment,
    and Justice Stevens, Id. at 421, who was joined by Chief Justice Burger and Justices Stewart and
    Rehnquist in his argument that the program violated Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 53
    blanket injunction that race could never be considered in admissions programs was at least
    premature, and one of those members went on to state that race could be used to promote diversity
    and proffered the race-conscious admissions program briefly described in an amicus brief by Harvard
    University as a model of such a plan.4
    Unfortunately, no policy other than the specific one utilized by UC Davis was before the
    Court. Thus, no matter what analytical artillery is applied to deconstruct the various Bakke opinions,
    we cannot come up with a “holding” that is any more specific than that UC Davis’s plan (and all
    plans that absolutely reserve a specific number of seats for the racially favored) was unconstitutional,
    and that some type of racial preference may be constitutional.
    The majority in this case applies extremely subtle reasoning to come to the conclusion that
    Bakke should instead be read to hold that the use of race, no matter how extensive, is constitutional
    so long as it does not specify a number of seats to be reserved for minorities and so long as it
    arguably tracks the Harvard plan. The majority’s reasoning is problematic for several reasons.
    Consider an exact analogy in the field of criminal law. Let us assume that state C has a
    policy that its prison guards may beat prisoners to within “half an inch of their lives” for any
    disciplinary infraction. When that policy is challenged in the Supreme Court, the Court’s holding
    is that the particular policy is unconstitutional, but that it will not issue an injunction against guards
    ever touching a prisoner for any infraction. Four members of the court believe that the policy is
    constitutional in its entirety, and therefore dissent from the portion of the opinion holding C’s policy
    unconstitutional. Four other Justices argue that guards should never be allowed to punish prisoners
    physically, and therefore dissent from the portion of the opinion refusing to issue an injunction
    against guards ever touching prisoners. A swing Justice strikes down the policy before him, but
    argues that at some time, in some manner, physical discipline might be appropriate. In particular,
    he speaks favorably of the plan of a particular state (call it the “H” plan) where, under some
    circumstances not specifically delineated, a guard could administer some unspecified amount of
    physical chastisement.
    Following this decision, another state, call it M, defends its policy on the grounds that it
    merely authorizes guards to beat prisoners within “an inch of their lives” (as opposed to “half an
    inch”), and that it is specifically modeled after the H plan. Under the majority’s logic, any lower
    court confronted with this policy would be required to find it constitutional.
    4
    The description of the Harvard plan in this amicus brief was exceedingly short and
    undetailed, consisting of less than four pages. For the description, see LANDMA RK BRIEFS AND
    ARGUMENTS, supra n.1, 735-38.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 54
    It fails as a matter of simple logic to take a splintered result striking down one policy and
    essentially to glean from it a holding that any policy that falls short of the original policy is
    constitutional. Indeed, the Supreme Court has very recently warned courts of appeals against similar
    thinking. In United States v. Knights, 
    122 S. Ct. 587
     (2001), the Court rejected the Ninth Circuit’s
    reading of Griffin v. Wisconsin, 
    483 U.S. 868
     (1987), a case in which the Court approved a certain
    search-and-seizure policy for certain probationers. The Court noted that the court of appeals had
    apparently read Griffin to stand for the proposition that “a warrantless search of a probationer
    satisfies the Fourth Amendment only if it is just like the search at issue in Griffin.” See Knights, 
    122 S. Ct. at 590
    . In rejecting the Ninth Circuit’s gloss on Griffin, the Court called it “dubious logic —
    that an opinion upholding the constitutionality of a particular search implicitly holds unconstitutional
    any search that is not like it.” 
    Ibid.
     (emphasis added). In effect, the majority of this court today
    similarly holds incorrectly that an opinion denying the legality of a particular policy implicitly holds
    constitutional every policy that falls in the slightest degree short of the evils that were condemned
    in the first case.
    The court does this by going past the general, and thus unhelpful, propositions actually agreed
    to by a majority of the Court in Bakke and adopting and even expanding as the holding of the case
    every nuance of the opinion written by Justice Powell. In Part IV-D of his opinion, Justice Powell
    stated that race can be used as a factor in admissions decisions in order to further the objective of
    diversity in an academic setting because the state has a compelling interest in achieving a diverse
    student body. No other Justice joined that Part. Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 311-15
    . In Part V-A of his
    opinion, Justice Powell set out as a model of a constitutional plan a race-based admissions plan
    utilized by Harvard University, in which race was utilized as a “plus” factor that could “tip the
    balance” in an applicant’s favor. No other Justice joined that Part. 
    Id. at 315-20
    . The majority of
    this court holds that these are the precedential holdings to be found in the case because, by reading
    Bakke through the – in this case easily manipulated – lens of Marks, the court has determined that
    a certain reading of the language of Justice Powell’s opinion represents the holding of the Bakke
    Court.
    B. Bakke and Marks
    1. Marks
    Marks was an appeal from a conviction for transporting obscene materials in interstate
    commerce. The defendant challenged the use of a jury instruction defining obscene material that
    came from a Supreme Court case decided after the time of the defendant’s conduct, Miller v.
    California, 
    413 U.S. 15
     (1973). The defendant alleged that the new definition expanded the scope
    of prohibited conduct, and therefore could not be applied in his case without violating his Due
    Process rights. The Court therefore needed to determine what the operative definition of obscene
    material was before Miller.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 55
    The problem was that in the last obscenity case decided by the Court before Miller, Memoirs
    v. Massachusetts, 
    383 U.S. 413
     (1966), no opinion garnered a majority. In fact, the Court in
    Memoirs was deeply fragmented, and it was not facially clear that there was one definition for what
    constituted obscene material that could be derived from the various opinions. Two Justices
    expressed the view that all sexually explicit material was entitled to full First Amendment protection.
    
    Id. at 421
     (Black, dissenting). One Justice believed that only “hard core pornography” was
    unprotected. 
    Id. at 425
     (Stewart, dissenting). Three Justices joining a plurality opinion opined most
    importantly that material must be “utterly without redeeming social value” before it will be stripped
    of First Amendment protection. 
    Id. at 418
    . The remaining three Justices, writing in various dissents,
    would have set the bar lower for defining material as obscene. 
    Id. at 443
     (Clark, dissenting), 454-56
    (Harlan, dissenting), 460-61 (White, dissenting).
    The Court in Marks, viewing the divided landscape of Memoirs, stated famously that “[w]hen
    a fragmented Court decides a case and no single rationale explaining the result enjoys the assent of
    five Justices, ‘the holding of the Court may be viewed as that position taken by those Members who
    concurred in the judgments on the narrowest grounds.’” Marks, 
    430 U.S. at 193
     (quoting Gregg v.
    Georgia, 
    428 U.S. 153
    , 169 n.15 (1976)). In Marks itself, it was clear that the Memoirs plurality
    decision represented the narrowest grounds for the holding, as the plurality would have struck down
    the fewest state and federal statutes defining materials as obscene.
    Taken on its face, Marks might be read only for the limited proposition that a criminal
    defendant cannot be held liable for conduct that he did not have fair notice would be prohibited. 
    Id. at 192-93
    . However, Marks has been read much more broadly, to provide a basis for discerning the
    holding of the Court in circumstances where a majority of the Justices agree on an outcome but not
    on a rationale for the outcome. See, e.g., O'Dell v. Netherland, 
    521 U.S. 151
    , 160 (1997) (utilizing
    Marks analysis to discern a holding in Gardner v. Florida, 
    430 U.S. 349
     (1977)); Coe v. Bell, 
    209 F.3d 815
    , 818 (6th Cir. 2000) (using Marks to discern a holding from Ford v. Wainwright, 
    477 U.S. 399
     (1986)).
    2. The Problematic Application of Marks to Bakke
    In applying Marks to the various opinions in Bakke, the majority contends that Justice
    Powell’s opinion is necessarily the holding of the Court, because he concurred in the judgment of
    the Court on the narrowest grounds. Powell, applying strict scrutiny, held that the UC Davis
    affirmative action program was unconstitutional, but also asserted that race could be taken into
    account in admissions decisions in certain circumstances, namely to promote diversity. Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 314-15
    . Justice Stevens, in an opinion joined by three other Justices, did not reach the
    constitutional issue but concurred in the judgment on the basis that race could never be used without
    violating Title VI. 
    Id. at 408-21
    . Justice Brennan, concurring in part and dissenting in part and
    joined by three other Justices, would have upheld UC Davis’s program, subjecting it only to
    intermediate scrutiny. 
    Id. at 362
    . Justice Brennan wrote that race could be used in admissions
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 56
    programs “to remedy disadvantages cast on minorities by past racial prejudice, at least when
    appropriate findings have been made by judicial, legislative, or administrative bodies with
    competence to act in this area.” 
    Id. at 325
    . As such, Justice Brennan and the three Justices joining
    his opinion concurred with Justice Powell’s judgment overturning the California Supreme Court’s
    ruling that race could never be used in admissions programs, but would have found UC Davis’s
    program constitutional on the basis that it sought to remedy past discrimination and so dissented
    from Justice Powell’s holding on that score.
    Since Justice Brennan would have applied intermediate scrutiny to “benign” racial
    classifications, whereas Justice Powell would have applied strict scrutiny to all racial classifications,
    the majority holds that Justice Powell’s diversity rationale in Bakke is binding precedent.
    Specifically, they explain that “[b]ecause the set of constitutionally permissible racial classifications
    under intermediate scrutiny, by definition, includes those classifications constitutionally permissible
    under strict scrutiny, Justice Powell’s rationale would permit the most limited consideration of race;
    therefore, it is Bakke’s narrowest rationale.” Majority Op. at 9. In other words, the majority sees
    Justice Powell’s reasoning as a subset of Justice Brennan’s, and therefore reasons it to be the binding
    holding of Bakke, as Marks instructs us to glean it. There are, however, two fundamental problems
    with this argument.
    First, the majority’s analysis inverts the concept of “narrowness” in Marks. In Marks, the
    Memoirs plurality opinion was “narrowest” because its interpretation of the First Amendment
    invalidated a smaller set of laws. Marks, 
    430 U.S. at 193
    . In other words, the “narrower” opinion
    was that which construed the constitutional provision in question less potently. In Bakke, Justice
    Brennan’s opinion, by adopting intermediate scrutiny, would invalidate fewer racial preference
    policies than Justice Powell’s opinion which, through strict scrutiny, would invalidate more. Yet
    the majority applies its own concept of narrowness, with no grounding in Marks, and holds that the
    opinion that creates the more powerful Fourteenth Amendment is indeed the narrower.
    Second, the fact that Justice Powell’s reasoning on standards (that strict scrutiny should be
    used to evaluate the constitutionality of all racial preferences) is a subset of Justice Brennan’s
    (applying merely intermediate scrutiny) tells us nothing about the first question before this court
    today: whether diversity is a compelling state interest. At most, it might tell us that if the question
    before this court were whether to apply intermediate scrutiny or strict scrutiny to our analysis of the
    Law School’s admissions program, the answer would be strict scrutiny. However, that question is
    not before this court, because it has been conclusively answered, in favor of strict scrutiny. In
    Adarand, 
    515 U.S. at 227
    , the Supreme Court held that all racial classifications are subject to strict
    scrutiny.
    In trying to divine a holding from Bakke supporting the use of race for diversity purposes,
    we are not able to apply Marks on a surface level, relying only on the fact that Justice Powell would
    have applied a stricter standard of scrutiny to race-based classifications than would have Justice
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 57
    Brennan. The unavailability of a “surface-level” application of Marks may itself be dispositive.
    After all, Marks is merely a tool with which to determine the collective intent of a fractured court.
    Because the first-level Marks analysis has been displaced by intervening precedent, perhaps the
    application of Marks to the still-open questions raised by the Powell and Brennan opinions in Bakke
    can no longer serve its intended purpose of deriving the collective intent of the Court, as the
    assumptions of the Justices deciding Bakke no longer hold.
    The application of Marks to Bakke is also inapt because (1) the separate opinions in Bakke
    do not constitute a coherent set and subset of each other and cannot be placed on a logical
    continuum; (2) the application of Marks really yields two Marks holdings from Bakke; and (3) the
    Supreme Court and other courts have recognized that Bakke does not yield a useful holding on the
    constitutionally permissible use of race and that Marks ought not be applied in the circumstances that
    obtain here.
    a. No Set and Subset or Continuum Available in Bakke
    Nevertheless, if we are still to use the Marks apparatus, we need to examine the specific
    rationales offered by Justices Powell and Brennan to determine whether it is possible, in this court’s
    words, to characterize one Justice’s rationale supporting the judgment as a “coherent subset of the
    principles articulated” by the other’s rationale. Triplett Grille v. City of Akron, 
    40 F.3d 129
    , 134 (6th
    Cir. 1994).
    There are potentially two judgments in Bakke. One struck down UC Davis’s admissions
    program. The second purported to overturn an injunction against all use of race, after discussing
    possible permissible bases for utilizing race in admissions decisions. With respect to the latter issue,
    the majority in its Marks analysis defines the judgment as stating that race can be used in certain
    circumstances by educational institutions.5 See Majority Op. at 6.
    In order to view the rationale of Justice Powell’s concurrence as the narrowest grounds in
    support of this judgment, the court must read Justice Powell as embracing the use of race only for
    5
    The majority quotes from Section V-C of Justice Powell’s opinion, which was joined by the
    Brennan group and which states:
    In enjoining petitioner from ever considering the race of any applicant, however, the
    courts below failed to recognize that the State has a substantial interest that
    legitimately may be served by a properly devised admissions program involving the
    competitive consideration of race and ethnic origin. For this reason, so much of the
    California court's judgment as enjoins petitioner from any consideration of the race
    of any applicant must be reversed.
    
    438 U.S. at 320
     (emphasis added).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 58
    the limited purpose of promoting diversity, while Justice Brennan would have permitted the use of
    race more broadly, to promote diversity and to remedy past discrimination. On its face, Justice
    Brennan’s writing in Bakke does not support the use of race for both diversity and remedial purposes.
    Nowhere in Justice Brennan’s opinion does he mention the diversity rationale, and he explicitly did
    not join Part IV-D of Justice Powell’s opinion, discussing the diversity rationale. Further, as
    mentioned above, Justice Brennan clearly states that “the central meaning of today’s opinions” is that
    “[g]overnment may take race into account when it acts not to demean or insult any racial group, but
    to remedy disadvantages cast on minorities by past racial prejudice.” Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 325
    (emphasis added). Finally, in his now-famous first footnote, Justice Brennan, writing for himself
    and the three other Justices who joined his opinion, agrees that a plan like the Harvard plan set out
    as a model by Justice Powell would be “constitutional under our approach, at least so long as the use
    of race to achieve an integrated student body is necessitated by the lingering effects of past
    discrimination.” 
    Id.
     at 326 n.1 (emphasis added).6
    If one reads Justice Brennan’s opinion as approving the use of race for remedial purposes,
    but not for diversity, one could make the argument that Justice Powell’s opinion, which accepts the
    general concept of a diversity rationale, is broader than Justice Brennan’s, which accepts only a more
    specific “past discrimination” rationale. Indeed, in a world permitting the use of race in admissions
    decisions when it is used to promote diversity, educational institutions would merely have to place
    a label on their actions in order to pass constitutional muster. There is no facial limit on the use or
    6
    A normal reading of this sentence would be that if the policy in question were necessitated
    by the lingering effects of past discrimination, the Brennan group would hold it constitutional.
    Therefore, if the policy were not so necessitated, one might argue by expressio unius that the
    Brennan group would hold it unconstitutional; at most one might argue that they would be wholly
    agnostic on the constitutionality of such a policy. However, the majority’s grammatical
    deconstruction, arguing that the footnote somehow provides affirmative support for the proposition
    that diversity is a compelling state interest, simply does not bear examination. Majority Op. at 10.
    It is quite correct, as the majority points out, that “at least so long as” does not mean “only if.” 
    Ibid.
    However, it does mean “if,” which is all that is necessary to show that the Brennan concurrence –
    while not affirmatively rejecting the Powell diversity rationale – certainly did not endorse it.
    Further, the majority’s attempt to distinguish between the language modifying when race may
    be used and why it may be used adds nothing, because a temporal qualifier at least hints at some
    reasoning related to that limitation. If I am told I can only buy beer between the hours of nine and
    five, it may be because those are the hours when liquor stores are open, or it may be because of state
    legislation limiting beer sales, or it may be because liquor store owners fear shoplifting at other
    hours; however, each of these rationales is related in a causal way to the time limitation. In just the
    same way, it may be that Justice Brennan really meant only that race could be used when
    “necessitated by the lingering effects of past discrimination,” but this is still a qualification on the
    scope of Justice Powell’s diversity rationale.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 59
    the ends of a race-based admissions policy seeking “diversity.” The remedial rationale, on the other
    hand, would at least require some proof of past discrimination, and it would provide an obvious
    endpoint for the program, namely when that past discrimination has been remedied.
    At the very least, however, since Justice Powell rejected the past discrimination rationale and
    Justice Brennan can be read to have implicitly rejected the diversity rationale, there is no continuum
    to be found in Bakke; instead of a broader holding and a narrower holding, what we might have are
    two different and non-comparable holdings. If such a reading is adopted, the “holding” that the
    majority of this court has divined from the Supreme Court’s Bakke decision is a rationale set out by
    one Justice and rejected by eight. See Cass R. Sunstein, Public Deliberation, Affirmative Action, and
    the Supreme Court, 
    84 Calif. L. Rev. 1179
    , 1185 (1996) (noting that the “rule” in Bakke represented
    the thought of just one Justice, while “[t]he other eight participating justices explicitly rejected that
    rule”). This hardly can be consistent with the letter or the spirit of Marks.7
    Viewing the rationales for the use of race put forth by the Bakke concurrences not as a
    continuum (or a set and subset), but as several distinct and unrelated justifications, is one of the ways
    one might argue that Marks simply does not apply to Bakke. Indeed, this is precisely what the
    district court held in the present case. See Grutter v. Bollinger, 
    137 F. Supp. 2d 821
    , 847 (E.D.
    Mich. 2001) (“The Marks framework cannot be applied to a case like Bakke, where the various
    Justices' reasons for concurring in the judgment are not merely different by degree, as they were in
    Memoirs, but are so fundamentally different as to not be comparable in terms of ‘narrowness.’”).
    7
    Indeed, it is the rule in several of our sister circuits that Marks is simply inapplicable unless
    “one opinion is a logical subset of other, broader opinions.” See King v. Palmer, 
    950 F.2d 771
    , 781
    (D.C. Cir. 1991) (en banc). See also, e.g., Anker Energy Corp. v. Consolidation Coal Co., 
    177 F.3d 161
    , 170 (3rd Cir. 1999) (“the Marks rule is applicable only where one opinion can be meaningfully
    regarded as narrower than another and can represent a common denominator of the Court's
    reasoning.”); Homeward Bound, Inc. v. Hissom Memorial Center, 
    963 F.2d 1352
    , 1359 (10th Cir.
    1992) (quoting approvingly of the reasoning in King). Cf. Dague v. Burlington, 
    935 F.2d 1343
    , 1360
    (2d Cir. 1991) (noting “the anomaly of the views of one justice, with whom no one concurs, being
    the law of the land, where the Court is so divided on an issue and where there is no majority opinion
    at all”). The District of Columbia Circuit explained well the reason for such a rule:
    When, however, one opinion supporting the judgment does not fit entirely within a
    broader circle drawn by the others, Marks is problematic. If applied in situations
    where the various opinions supporting the judgment are mutually exclusive, Marks
    will turn a single opinion that lacks majority support into national law. When eight
    of nine Justices do not subscribe to a given approach to a legal question, it surely
    cannot be proper to endow that approach with controlling force, no matter how
    persuasive it may be.
    King, 
    950 F.2d at 782
    .
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 60
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 61
    b. The Potential for Two Marks Holdings
    Even if one gets past the conceptual hurdle of treating as a continuum (or a set and subset)
    two rationales that are not clearly related in scope, it is not clear that a Marks analysis of the
    rationales in Bakke would produce the holding that the majority claims it does.
    As mentioned, the majority defines the relevant judgment in Bakke abstractly, as holding that
    race can sometimes be used by educational institutions. Until now, we have assumed that the
    judgment in Bakke is as the majority defines it. Rather than adopting a broad statement providing
    no real guidance on when race can be used and for what purposes, we might look at what the two
    opinions that concur on the possibility of a constitutional use of race have to say about each of the
    two potential rationales, namely remedying past discrimination and diversity. If we do this, we are
    essentially left with two holdings in Bakke on the permissible rationales for the use of race: one
    holding permitting the use of race for diversity purposes sometimes and one permitting it for
    remedial purposes sometimes.8 See generally Lackland H. Bloom, Jr., Hopwood, Bakke and the
    Future of the Diversity Justification, 29 Tex. Tech. L. Rev. 1, 30-32 (1998).
    Justice Powell’s decision would be the narrowest grounds to support the holding that race
    can sometimes be used to remedy the effects of past discrimination. This is because the Brennan
    group would have allowed the use of race whenever there is a “sound basis for believing that the
    problem of underrepresentation of minorities . . . [is] attributable to handicaps imposed on minority
    applicants by past and present racial discrimination.” Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 369
    . On the other hand,
    Justice Powell expressed a more limited view of the permissible use of race in this regard in Section
    IV-B of his opinion. He agreed that “[t]he State certainly has a legitimate and substantial interest
    in ameliorating, or eliminating where feasible, the disabling effects of identified discrimination.” 
    Id. at 306
    . However, Justice Powell would not have permitted simple reliance on general past
    8
    The majority contends that by redefining the relevant judgment I impermissibly “cobble
    together a holding from various rationales in the discrete Bakke opinions.” See Majority Op. at 9 n.6.
    However, the majority misunderstands my aim. I am not suggesting we apply Marks to a given
    judgment and then pick and choose among the rationales to support that judgment. Instead, I am
    merely suggesting an analytical tool whereby we more accurately define the relevant holding before
    applying Marks. By defining the holding as stating that race can be used to promote diversity
    sometimes, I illustrate that Justice Brennan’s rationale is the narrowest in support of that holding and
    in so doing call into question the premise that Marks provides an answer to the threshold question
    facing this court.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 62
    discrimination, but instead would have required specific findings by a competent government body
    that the use of race is “responsive to identified discrimination” before race could be used remedially
    in admissions decisions. 
    Id. at 310
    .
    However, with respect to the redefined holding discussing diversity, the one relevant in this
    case, Justice Brennan’s opinion facially is the narrower. Justice Powell wrote broadly in his Section
    IV-D that “[t]he attainment of a diverse student body clearly is a constitutionally permissible goal
    for an institution of higher education.” 
    Id. at 312
    . Later, Powell wrote again that “the interest of
    diversity is compelling in the context of a university's admissions program.” 
    Id. at 314
    . Justice
    Brennan, on the other hand, specifically added a restriction to his expressed agreement. As discussed
    above, Justice Brennan would be willing to support the diversity rationale embodied in the Harvard
    diversity program set out by Justice Powell as a model, “at least so long as the use of race to achieve
    an integrated student body is necessitated by the lingering effects of past discrimination.” Bakke,
    
    438 U.S. at
    326 n.1. Since it put a limit on the utility of diversity as a rationale supporting the
    constitutionally permissible use of race in admissions programs where Justice Powell’s opinion
    expressed no limit, Justice Brennan’s opinion is narrower than Justice Powell’s on the use of race
    to encourage diversity. So by merely redefining the relevant holding more accurately, I have reached
    a result opposite that of the majority – Justice Brennan’s rationale becomes the narrower and
    therefore becomes the Marks holding to be gleaned from Bakke on the diversity issue. This further
    shows the error in relying on Marks to answer the question before this court.
    The above discussion is intended simply to illustrate that reasonable minds can and do differ
    on the holding, if any, to be found in Bakke with respect to the diversity rationale. Those holding
    different views on the subject could go back and forth endlessly, with no clear resolution. The
    reason for this – as almost all, wherever they stand on the argument, would agree – is that we are
    trying to divine a clear holding from a decidedly unclear decision.
    In this circumstance, the better view is that Marks simply fails to extract from Bakke a
    holding on the constitutionality of the diversity rationale. Indeed, the very fact that one must struggle
    to find a way to fit the Court’s Bakke writings into the Marks mold counsels against finding such a
    holding in Bakke.
    c. Subsequent Treatment of Bakke and Marks
    It is apparent that the Supreme Court has doubted that Bakke provided a holding beyond the
    obvious one that UC Davis’s system was illegal.9 Though only writing for four Justices, Justice
    9
    The majority finds support for its proposition that diversity is a compelling state interest in
    the fact that Justice Brennan in Metro Broadcasting cited Bakke for the proposition that “‘a diverse
    student body’ contributing to a ‘robust exchange of ideas’ is a ‘constitutionally permissible goal’ on
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 63
    Brennan wrote in the introduction to his Bakke concurrence that “[t]he difficulty of the issue
    presented . . . and the mature consideration which each of our Brethren has brought to it have
    resulted in many opinions, no single one speaking for the Court.” 
    438 U.S. at 324
    . Two years later,
    in the course of examining a minority business provision in the Public Works Employment Act of
    1977, the Court expressly refused to adopt “the formulas of analysis” set out in Bakke and did not
    discuss any holding coming from the case, but instead set out to show that the challenged provision
    “would survive judicial review under either ‘test’ articulated in the several Bakke opinions.”
    Fullilove v. Klutznick, 
    448 U.S. 448
    , 492 (1980). After Marks was decided, the Supreme Court in
    Adarand again expressed doubt that there is a comprehensive holding to be found in Bakke. See
    Adarand, 
    515 U.S. at 218
     (noting that “Bakke did not produce an opinion for the Court”).
    Further, there is Supreme Court precedent for the proposition that when it is so unclear what
    the Marks holding would be in a fractured court decision, there may not be one. For example, in
    Nichols v. United States, 
    511 U.S. 738
     (1994), the Court re-examined its prior, splintered decision
    in Baldasar v. Illinois, 
    446 U.S. 222
     (1980). After citing Marks and noting the varied possible
    holdings divined by different courts that had examined Baldasar, the Supreme Court declined to
    engage in a Marks analysis, stating:
    We think it not useful to pursue the Marks inquiry to the utmost logical possibility
    when it has so obviously baffled and divided the lower courts that have considered
    it. This degree of confusion following a splintered decision such as Baldasar is itself
    a reason for reexamining that decision.
    Nichols, 
    511 U.S. at 745-46
    . See also Johnson v. Board of Regents, 
    263 F.3d 1234
    , 1248 n.12 (11th
    Cir. 2001) (“The Supreme Court has not compelled us to find a ‘holding’ on each issue in each of
    its decisions. On the contrary, the Court has indicated that there may be situations where even the
    Marks inquiry does not yield any rule to be treated as binding in future cases.”). The fact that lower
    courts are unclear as to what holding – if any – can be garnered from Bakke on the diversity issue
    is clearly illustrated by the University of Michigan cases, where one district court at least found
    which a race-conscious university admissions program may be predicated.” 
    497 U.S. 547
    , 568
    (1990) (quoting Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 311-13
     (Powell, concurring)). Aside from the fact that Justice
    Brennan was applying intermediate scrutiny in Metro Broadcasting and therefore his views on the
    constitutionality of any policy or rationale would not speak to the present case where strict scrutiny
    is the standard, the statement is – as the majority itself notes – merely dicta. The majority attempts
    to salvage the usefulness of the statement to their argument by describing it is as “persuasive
    authority, which this court may not ignore.” Majority Op. at 11. Of course, this court ignores (or
    at least does not rule in accordance with) persuasive authority all the time. In particular, an ex post
    exegesis written by a different Justice of another Justice’s opinion that did not prevail on the point
    at issue is hardly the strongest type of persuasive authority.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 64
    viable the argument that Justice Powell’s rationale represented Bakke’s holding regarding the
    diversity issue under Marks, while the other district court found Marks inapplicable.
    C. The Dicta Problem
    Lastly, I pause to point out that, even if the majority’s application of Marks were correct, it
    would not be clear that the various discussions of permissible rationales to be found in Justices
    Powell and Brennan’s opinions are anything more than non-binding dicta. This is because there is
    an argument that Bakke does not have a “judgment” with respect to the permissible use of race in
    educational institutions’ admissions policies, so there would be no Marks holding on that issue.
    In order to understand the argument, it needs to be noted again that there were potentially two
    issues in Bakke – (1) whether state universities could use race at all in their admissions decisions,
    and (2) whether the university’s particular use of race was permissible. Justice Powell’s opinion
    stated the judgment of the Court on the first issue, because he was joined by Brennan’s group of four
    to make a majority for the proposition that state universities were not completely precluded from the
    use of race. Justice Powell’s opinion stated the judgment of the Court on the second issue, because
    he was joined by the other four Justices in finding that UC Davis’s particular system was
    impermissible.
    In his Bakke concurrence and dissent, Justice Stevens argued that Justice Powell’s discussion
    of the first issue was merely dicta, as the California Supreme Court did nothing more than strike
    down UC Davis’s program and neither had before it nor decided the question of whether state
    universities could ever use race. See Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 408
    . See also Earl M. Maltz, A Bakke
    Primer, 
    32 Okla. L. Rev. 119
    , 130 n.91 (1979) (making this argument). Allan Bakke’s suit was not
    a class action; Bakke sought merely his own admission. 
    Ibid.
     Therefore, once the Court ordered
    Bakke admitted, he no longer had any interest in UC Davis’s future admissions policy. 
    Ibid.
    Accordingly, Justice Stevens argued that the only judgment of the Court was that UC Davis’s system
    was impermissible, and the narrowest grounds for holding that would seem to be Justice Stevens’s
    finding that the system was impermissible under Title VI (due to the long-standing rule, cited by
    Justice Stevens, that the Court avoids constitutional issues if a case can fairly be decided on a
    statutory ground). See Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 411
    . See also Johnson v. Board of Regents, 
    106 F. Supp. 2d 1362
    , 1369 (S.D. Ga. 2000) (same argument), aff’d, 
    263 F.3d 1239
     (11th Cir. 2001).
    It is true that both Justice Powell and the Brennan group argued that the Court was issuing
    a judgment on the permissibility of the use of race, as they contended that the California Supreme
    Court did permanently enjoin any use of race. See Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at
    271 n.1 (Powell, concurring),
    325 (Brennan, concurring). Specifically, Justice Powell pointed out that the University had cross
    claimed in the trial court for a declaratory judgment that its program was constitutional, but that it
    had lost. See 
    id.
     at 271 n.1. Presumably, then, Justice Powell was arguing that unlike Bakke, the
    University had an ongoing interest in the content of its future policies. Further, Justice Powell
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 65
    argued that the California Supreme Court effectively enjoined the University from ever using race.
    Justice Powell quoted language from the California Supreme Court to the effect that UC Davis’s
    admissions policy was constitutionally impermissible to the extent that it was “utilized in a racially
    discriminatory manner.” Ibid., quoting 
    553 P.2d 1152
    , 1166 (Cal. 1976) (footnote omitted).
    At least one commentator has challenged Justice Powell’s contention that the Bakke
    discussion on the more general use of race represents a holding. See Maltz, 32 Okla. L. Rev. at 130
    n.91 (arguing that this portion of the Bakke decision is merely dicta). Maltz points out that while it
    is true that UC Davis cross claimed, seeking a declaratory judgment that its policies were legal, it
    did not request that the court in the alternative instruct it how to conform its policies to the law.
    Instead, according to Maltz, once the Court determined that UC Davis’s plan was infirm, it by
    implication disposed of the cross-claim and had fulfilled its function as a reviewing court. Ibid.
    Further, as Maltz points out, while the California Supreme Court did use the sweeping language cited
    by Justice Powell for the proposition that the court had enjoined any future use of race, the judgment
    of the California court was much narrower and included no such injunction. See 
    553 P.2d at 1172
    .
    More fundamentally, the holding/dicta distinction demands that we consider binding only
    that which was necessary to resolve the question before the Court. At most, the question before the
    Court in Bakke was whether race could ever be used in admissions decisions. To resolve that
    question, the Court only needed to answer that race could potentially be used. Any speculation
    regarding the circumstances under which race could be used was little more than an advisory
    opinion, as those circumstances were not before the court and need not be validated to overturn an
    injunction barring any use of race, to the extent one was in place.
    So, if we admit that a Marks analysis simply does not provide a binding holding on the
    diversity issue, we are left with precedent striking down UC Davis’s admissions system and either
    binding precedent or persuasive support (depending on whether one agrees with Justice Stevens’s
    argument in Bakke that the entire rationale discussion was dicta) for the proposition embodied in
    Section V-C of Justice Powell’s opinion, to which a majority of the Justices did subscribe, that “the
    State has a substantial interest that legitimately may be served by a properly devised admissions
    program involving the competitive consideration of race and ethnic origin.” 
    438 U.S. at 320
    .
    Unfortunately, we are not reviewing the UC Davis program, and the fact that a state has a
    “substantial interest” that “may” be constitutionally served by admissions programs utilizing race
    does not help us. We must determine whether the state has a “compelling interest” rather than a
    “substantial interest” and the fact that an interest “may” be served by a race-based system does
    nothing to tell us “how” it may be.
    D. Intervening Supreme Court Precedent
    Having held that Marks does not compel a Bakke holding, the district court in this case
    reviewed recent Supreme Court cases that have addressed racial classifications, and held that
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 66
    together they make clear that “racial classifications are unconstitutional unless they are intended to
    remedy carefully documented effects of past discrimination.” Grutter, 
    137 F. Supp. 2d 821
    , 849
    (E.D. Mich. 2001). The court found this holding to be required by two Supreme Court cases. First,
    the court cited Adarand Constructors v. Pena, 
    515 U.S. 200
    , 227 (1995), where the Court held that
    all racial classifications are subject to strict scrutiny and overturned Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v.
    FCC, 
    497 U.S. 547
     (1990), to the extent that it applied intermediate scrutiny to a plan that used racial
    classifications in awarding broadcast licenses in order to enhance broadcast diversity. Second, the
    court noted that in Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co., 
    488 U.S. 469
    , 493 (1989), the Court stated that:
    “Classifications based on race carry a danger of stigmatic harm. Unless they are strictly reserved for
    remedial settings, they may in fact promote notions of racial inferiority and lead to a politics of racial
    hostility.”10
    Taking together the Court’s overturning of the standard used to uphold the use of race to
    encourage diversity in Metro Broadcasting (thereby calling into question the permissibility of using
    race for diversity purposes) and its statement in Croson that race should only be used for remedial
    settings, the district court held that the only permissible use of race under strict scrutiny is to “remedy
    carefully documented effects of past discrimination,” and that since the diversity rationale proffered
    by the Law School was not tied to remedying past discrimination, it is an impermissible basis for the
    use of race. Grutter, 
    137 F. Supp. 2d at 849
    .
    The majority, as it does in the rest of its opinion, disregards the district court’s analysis by
    adherence to the mantra of a Bakke holding that diversity is a permissible rationale for the use of
    race. Accordingly, the majority states that the later Supreme Court cases pointed to by the district
    court can not possibly stand for the proposition the court said they do because that would require a
    finding that the Supreme Court silently overturned its holding in Bakke. As the majority points out,
    the Court has instructed lower courts not to find that it has implicitly overruled itself, but to let it do
    its own overruling. Majority Op. at 11. See also Agostini v. Feldman, 
    521 U.S. 203
    , 237 (1997).
    However, application of Agostini requires first that the Supreme Court have made a holding that a
    lower court is finding it to have implicitly overruled; in this case, Bakke provides no such holding.
    While I find persuasive the district court’s attempt to derive from the Supreme Court’s
    Adarand and Croson decisions a holding that diversity is not a permissible rationale, it would be
    somewhat disingenuous of me to fault the majority of this court for divining a firm and binding
    holding from Bakke while urging the court to do the same from Adarand and Croson. While the
    district court’s reading of these two cases is far from clearly wrong, it is also not required. In
    10
    Chief Justice Rehnquist, and Justices White and Kennedy joined this part of Justice
    O’Connor’s plurality opinion. Justice Scalia agreed that the use of race is only appropriate for
    remedial situations, but wrote separately to contend that it was appropriate only in a more limited
    set of situations than those approved by the plurality. See 
    488 U.S. at 735
     (Scalia, concurring).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 67
    Adarand, the Court overturned Metro Broadcasting to the extent that it utilized intermediate scrutiny
    in reviewing a classification plan intended to promote diversity. However, the Court did not
    explicitly state that diversity would not withstand strict scrutiny. Further, in Croson, while a
    majority of the Court could be read to suggest that only remedial justifications would be permissible,
    a diversity rationale was not at issue in the case.
    A better approach is simply to address the diversity rationale on the merits. Accordingly, I
    will seek to apply on the merits the rule on which we can all agree, as set forth by the Court in
    Adarand, and look to see (1) if the use of race in admissions for diversity purposes serves a
    compelling governmental interest, and (2) whether the Law School’s plan is narrowly tailored to
    achieve that interest. Adarand, 
    515 U.S. at 227
    .
    II. On the Merits
    Symptomatic of its deference to the advisory opinion of one Justice of the United States
    Supreme Court, the majority has given us no argument as to why the engineering of a diverse student
    body should be a compelling state interest sufficient to satisfy strict scrutiny. I, however, consider
    the arguments on both sides of this question below and conclude that constructing a diverse
    educational environment is not a compelling state interest. In explaining my conclusion below, I
    analyze why the nature and benefits of the experiential “diversity” that the Law School claims
    ultimately to seek is conceptually disconnected from the racial and ethnic diversity that it primarily
    seeks. I also demonstrate that the Law School’s concept of diversity permits no logical limitation
    and threatens to justify even more constitutionally unacceptable outcomes, counseling against
    recognizing its achievement as a compelling state purpose.
    If I were deciding this case for a majority, I likely would not have resolved the question of
    whether developing a diverse student body is a compelling state interest. Even if a racial
    classification is designed to achieve a compelling state interest, it must be narrowly tailored to that
    interest. While I could conceive of racial preferences in admission that are narrowly tailored to
    achieve some diversity in education, the Law School’s plan is not among those. The majority
    appears satisfied that the Law School’s program is narrowly tailored because the Law School has not
    articulated a precise numerical target for admitted minorities. By carefully avoiding the pernicious
    term “quota,” the Law School, for the majority, has withstood the constitutional strict scrutiny that
    we apply to racial preferences. For me, however, the Law School’s simple avoidance of an explicit
    numerical target does not meet the constitutional requirements of narrow tailoring. The Law
    School’s efforts to achieve a “critical mass” are functionally indistinguishable from a numerical
    quota.
    Moreover, the constitutional inquiry into narrow tailoring is not merely one into the form of
    the racial preference. The sheer magnitude of the Law School’s racial preference, a feature left
    completely unexamined by the majority, is simply too large to be considered narrowly tailored. Even
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 68
    “the Harvard Plan,” which the majority remarkably considers constitutional merely because Justice
    Powell in Bakke speculated that it might be constitutional, does not validate the amount of the Law
    School’s racial preference.
    I discuss the two parts of the strict scrutiny analysis – the existence of a compelling state
    interest and the employment of only those means narrowly tailored to that purpose – separately
    below.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 69
    A. Is Developing a Diverse Student Body a Compelling State Interest?
    1. The Nature of “Diversity”
    Holding that, generally speaking, “diversity in education” is a compelling state interest would
    not be terribly helpful. After all, it is not clear what the term means. From the outset therefore, it
    is crucial to be precise about the nature of the “diversity” that the Law School seeks to promote.
    Justice Powell discussed a diversity that would enrich the pedagogical activities of a school, a
    diversity of “experiences, outlooks, and ideas” that would challenge its students’ settled
    preconceptions and open them to new intellectual paradigms. Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 314
    . The Law
    School adopts this dialogic vision of diversity as the purpose behind its admissions program.
    Some versions of diversity are clearly not included in the Law School’s vision. For example,
    the Law School does not seem to promote the potential for moral education in racial tolerance
    created by a more diverse student body. On this view, the mere presence of minority students may
    indeed be sufficient to enhance the educational experience. Similarly, the Law School does not seem
    to rely on the promotion of post-graduation diversity in the legal profession.
    Instead, the Law School rests its claim to the benefits of a diverse student body on the unique
    experiences that students from under-represented groups will be able to share with their fellow
    students. Closely related, the Law School implies that a student body diverse with regard to race is
    one diverse with regard to viewpoint, experience, and opinion. Through the Socratic Method, the
    keystone of legal education, the students from groups otherwise “over-represented” will be pressed
    to consider new ideas as their previously under-represented minority colleagues discuss the legal
    questions at issue.
    For all these educational benefits to diversity, the majority uses the shorthand “academic
    diversity.” Majority Op. at 15. From the implementation of the Law School’s program, however,
    it is perfectly clear that academics has nothing to do with the type of diversity sought. After listening
    to the Law School extoll the virtues of educational diversity, one might think that preference would
    be given across the board for “life experiences.” The Law School’s rhetoric implies that it is
    searching tirelessly for the applicant with the most unique of experiences: for example, the Mormon
    missionary in Uganda, the radical libertarian or Marxist, the child of subsistence farmers in
    Arkansas, or perhaps the professional jazz musician. The Law School, however, never claims that
    there is any similarity between the preference given to those with such unique experiences and that
    bestowed upon those it considers “under-represented” racial minorities.
    Most poignantly, the Law School’s offering of non-racial exemplars for such non-racial
    diversity betrays the profound and experientially unrelated preference that the Law School places on
    race. Mentioning status as an under-represented minority in the same breath, the Law School
    generalizes, in the abstract, that it would also give a preference to an applicant with “an Olympic
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 70
    gold medal, a Ph.D in physics, the attainment of age 50 in a class otherwise lacking anyone over 30,
    or the experience of having been a Vietnamese boat person.” Admissions Policies, University of
    Michigan Law School, April 22, 1992, JA at 4240. Yet to equate bare racial status with the
    experiential gains of these generally remarkable (and exceedingly rare) achievements demonstrates
    that the Law School’s desired diversity is unrelated to the experiences of its applicants. After
    reading the description of its admissions criteria, a Michigan law student might yearn to meet the
    mere Olympian who failed to medal and was thus considered insufficiently interesting by the Law
    School.
    The disjunction between the Law School’s preference for the race of “under-represented
    minorities” and what happened to be those applicants’ experiences came through very clearly in an
    exchange at oral argument. Counsel for the Law School agreed that it was true that Ms. Grutter
    would have been admitted had she been of a different race, but strongly asserted that she would have
    then been “a different person.” Tr. at 38. Of course, in a trivial way, that is true of every change in
    any of us. Had she grown up in New York or had a mother or father who did or did not work outside
    the home, she would also have been a different person. However, none of those changes, all of
    which would have made her “diverse” in some different fashion, would have enhanced or determined
    her chances of admission. When I then asked counsel whether, if she were of a different race, she
    would have been admitted whether she had come of age in inner-city Detroit or in Grosse Pointe, he
    answered: “That’s probably right.” Id. at 39.
    When it comes to a choice between admitting a conventionally liberal (or conventionally
    conservative) black student who is the child of lawyer parents living in Grosse Pointe, just like the
    previous ten white admittees, the black student will be given a diversity preference that would not
    be given to a white or Asian student, her unique experiences notwithstanding.11 Similarly, it is not
    at all clear how true diversity is served by giving massive preference to a student whose parents or
    grandparents came from an upper-class suburb of Buenos Aires, over those whose grandparents
    immigrated from similar areas of Paris, Munich, or Tokyo or, indeed, over a person whose
    grandparents survived the labor camps of Hitler or Stalin or the conformity regime of Brezhnev’s
    Kazakhstan. Even Justice Powell in his Bakke opinion recognized that an admissions program
    “focused solely on ethnic diversity, would hinder rather than further attainment of genuine diversity.”
    Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 315
     (Powell, concurring).
    Perhaps the one unifying feature of the minority groups that the Law School heavily prefers
    in admissions is that they all, on average, have had some experience with being the object of racial
    discrimination. For law students, this might bring an understanding of the purposes behind the anti-
    discrimination laws that they might study. It is hard, however, to believe that the Law School’s
    11
    With respect to the concurring opinion’s criticism of this example, Concurring Op. at n.3
    (Clay), see n.21 infra.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 71
    admissions scheme is terribly sensitive to this interest. If the Law School were truly interested in
    those with profound experience with discrimination, it would be sensitive to differences within the
    affected groups. An African-American applicant who comes to the Law School by way of Choate
    and Harvard12 may well have quite a different experience of discrimination than one from a rural
    public school. Even if one were to believe that the Law School’s racial preference were carefully
    designed to add such experience to the Law School mixing pot, one could wonder why an experience
    with discrimination would be so much more important than any other experience germane to other
    legal issues.
    Indeed, one should wonder why race is at all relevant to the Law School if it only is
    concerned about the diversity of experience. It is likely that an admissions scheme that sought true
    experiential diversity, without regard to race, would provide some systematic advantage for racial
    or ethnic minorities. See also Part II.B.4 (discussing race-neutral means). Under-represented life
    experiences – primary or secondary education at an under-funded public school, struggling with
    relative poverty, a childhood spent in urban rather than suburban areas – may correlate to some
    degree with under-represented racial or ethnic minorities.13
    Such a system of seeking experiential diversity would be unlikely to raise significant
    constitutional problems, unless it were clear that an institution manipulated these factors to admit
    members of a particular race. However, the Law School certainly does not seek to implement an
    experientially based admissions system or even to assert that if it did, the preference given for such
    factors could explain its current results. Instead, it is clear that the only type of diversity that is given
    more than modest, if any, weight is based on assigned racial categories. The Law School cannot
    plausibly maintain that the system would be impractical, especially because, as they elsewhere
    remind us for purposes of distinguishing its preference from a quota, only one admissions officer
    reads all applications, makes all decisions, and therefore is capable of considering candidates
    individually. The possibility of an experientially based admissions system and the Law School’s
    apparent disinterest in such a system, indicate that the Law School grants preference to race, not as
    a proxy for a unique set of experiences, but as a proxy for race itself.
    12
    Indeed, it is likely such minorities – those who have been relatively well-educated at elite
    schools, but who have not performed terribly well there – that the Law School’s preference policy
    most benefits.
    13
    In fact, these factors may also correlate to unrealized academic ability, if the student has not
    had sufficient resources, educational or financial, to blossom intellectually. In this sense, an
    admissions system truly sensitive to experiential diversity may also select the more intellectually
    talented.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 72
    Accordingly, even if we were to consider binding on this court Justice Powell’s opinion in
    Bakke that the achievement of some form of diversity in education is a compelling state interest, we
    would not ipso facto find compelling the type of diversity that the Law School apparently seeks. For
    Justice Powell in Bakke, race or ethnicity was only “one element in a range of factors” that an
    educational institution may consider to develop an experientially heterogeneous environment.
    Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 314
    . The Law School’s consideration of race, for the sake of race, is not the type
    of pedagogical diversity thought potentially compelling in Powell’s opinion.
    There are yet more fundamental problems with the broad-brush rationale of diversity. The
    fundamental premise of our society is that each person is equally “diverse” exactly because of her
    equality before God and the law. The very words of the Declaration of Independence are: “All men
    are created equal . . . and are endowed by their Creator with certain inalienable rights.” Thus, the
    starting basis is one of equality, not of separately assigned categories that are used to measure
    diversity. From that starting point, every person’s experiences are “diverse” from those of every
    other. The very measure of diversity as used by the University is to say that some of those
    differences do not count. Thus, to the Law School, ten under-represented-minority students, each
    a child of two-parent lawyer families, are considered to be diverse, while children whose parents are
    Chinese merchants, Japanese farmers, white steel workers, or any combinations of the above are all
    considered to be part of a homogeneous (and “over-represented”) mass. And, of course, that
    categorization then strongly determines the odds of admission. A child with one parent of Chinese
    ancestry and one of Chilean would find that his level of “diversity” depends wholly on whether the
    Law School chooses to assign him based on one parent or the other.14
    The Law School gives no explanation of how it defines the groups to be favored. This means
    that ultimately it must make, on some basis, a decision on who is, and is not, an “African-American,
    Hispanic, or Native American.” See JA at 1957 (discussing the groups to be favored). Such
    judgments, of course, have a long and sordid history. The classic Southern Rule was that any
    African ancestry, or “one drop” of African blood, made one black.15 The Nazi Nuremberg laws
    14
    A personal observation makes clear for me the problematic nature of such definitions. My
    daughter has one grandparent who was a Cuban immigrant, two grandparents of Russian Jewish
    origin, and one grandparent who could be characterized as a Euro-American mixture. I would hate
    to think that her life chances were significantly altered, favorably or unfavorably, because a
    government body applied a “grandfather clause” that focused on one rather than another of her
    grandparents.
    15
    For more on the one-drop rule, see A. Leon Higginbotham, Jr. & F. Michael Higginbotham,
    “Yearning to Breathe Free”: Legal Barriers Against and Options in Favor of Liberty in Antebellum
    Virginia, 68 N.Y.U.L. Rev. 1213, 1243 n.163 (1993).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 73
    made the fatal decision turn on the number of Jewish grandparents.16 “Hispanic” background may,
    I suppose, depend on which side of a pass in the Pyrenees your great-grandfather came from. This
    Christmas, my wife and I received a card, containing a lovely picture of a friend and his spouse, their
    two children and their spouses, and four grandchildren. I asked a sample of people, in and out of my
    chambers, how many of the ten people in the picture should receive racial preference under
    Michigan’s policy. I received answers ranging from one to ten.
    A moment’s contemplation of these examples shows another serious problem with
    Michigan’s policies. On the one hand, all the evidence is that race and ethnicity are considered on
    an “all or nothing” basis. But the actual experience, diverse or otherwise, of a person who is “one-
    half” or “one-quarter” of one ethnicity, is likely to be, on average, different from one whose ancestry
    is relatively uniform. On the other hand, to apply boldly a system of half- or quarter-credit for
    assigned status would reveal the racist nature of the system to a degree from which even its
    proponents would shrink.
    Thus, even if we give full force to Justice Powell’s discussion of “the virtues of diversity,”
    the Law School’s program provides the linguistic term, but not the substance.
    2. No Logical Limitation
    We are not completely at sea regarding how to discern a compelling state interest. The
    Supreme Court has consistently rejected those purposes that lack a “logical stopping point.” Croson,
    
    488 U.S. at 498
    ; Wygant v. Jackson Bd. of Educ., 
    476 U.S. 267
    , 275 (1986) (plurality opinion). Such
    vague and ill-defined purposes, if considered compelling, would eviscerate the constitutional
    protection that strict scrutiny provides. The two requirements of strict scrutiny – the identification
    of a compelling state interest and the use of only those means narrowly tailored to serve that interest
    – are designed to be independently meaningful rather than mere redundancies. Yet it is meaningless
    to require that a state narrowly tailor its suspect policies to a purpose that itself is poorly defined.
    Requiring a well-defined purpose to be compelling reflects the Supreme Court’s judgment
    that racial classifications ought to be used sparingly. The Law School’s repeated incantation of
    “developing a diverse student body” suffers from this vice of vagueness. These same words, together
    with the discussion of promoting a more intriguing student body, could be used, and indeed have
    been used not invalidly on their face, to justify ethnic classifications that seem patently
    unconstitutional.
    16
    See, e.g., Lucy S. Dawidowicz, THE WAR AGAINST THE JEWS: 1933-45 91 (Bantam 1975);
    Nora Levin, THE HOLOCAUST 69-70 (Schocken 1973).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 74
    It may be instructive to compare the actual implementation of and articulated rationale behind
    the Michigan plan with another, possibly well-intentioned, attempt to manipulate admissions criteria
    to achieve a diverse student body. I refer to the “religious-conscious” policies, adopted by a number
    of Ivy League universities of which Harvard was the most notable, to give preference in admissions
    to Gentiles as opposed to Jews. The policies were also designed to produce a mixture of students
    in the school that was closer to the proportion that prevailed in society, and a proportion that was
    thought to be socially and educationally beneficial.
    The reasons for the policy offered by then-President Lowell of Harvard are hauntingly similar
    to the rationale given here. As Lowell explained, without the policies “Harvard would lose its
    character as a democratic national university drawing from all classes of the community and
    promoting a sympathetic understanding among them.” Letter from President Lowell, reprinted in
    Henry Aaron Yeomans, ABBOTT LAWRENCE LOWELL , 1856-1943 209 (Arno 1977). Lowell worried
    that “race feeling would become intense” if numbers of students were not more proportional to the
    general population, and that if the numerical imbalance could be rectified, “it would eliminate race
    feeling among the students, and ‘as these students passed out into the world, eliminating it in the
    community.’” Nitza Rosovsky, THE JEWISH EXPERIENCE AT HARVARD AND RADCLIFFE 15 & n.2
    (Harvard 1986) (quoting A. Lawrence Lowell Papers # 1056). Lowell also believed that his policy
    would be “in the interests of Jews, as well as of everyone else.” 
    Ibid.
    The weighted preference system at Harvard then worked much the same as Michigan’s. The
    “Harvard plan” of its day also considered each applicant individually. Some Jews were admitted,
    some were not. Their religion was only one factor among many that were considered. It was
    perfectly clear, in the words of Justice Powell, that “the applicant who loses out on the last available
    seat to another candidate receiving a ‘plus’ on the basis of ethnic background will not have been
    foreclosed from all consideration for that seat.” Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 318
    . Those who were not
    admitted could not be certain that their ethnicity had been decisive. All applicants admitted were
    certainly “qualified,” by the same standards as the Michigan plan.
    Perhaps the crucial distinction comes from the notion that a true “plus” program would lack
    a “facial intent to discriminate.” 
    Ibid.
     This could only be the case if the plus was in some fashion
    modest, and calibrated truly in connection with other comparable characteristics. The fact that the
    “Harvard plan” of the 1930's basically cut Jewish numbers by half or more would belie the lack of
    a “facial intent to discriminate.” See generally Marcia Graham Synnott, THE HALF -OPENED DOOR
    96, 108, 110, 115 (Greenwood 1979). The University of Michigan’s plan, which by its own
    calculations inflates the numbers of students from favored groups approximately three-to-four fold,
    similarly betrays a “facial intent to discriminate.” See JA at 6047.
    It is thus important to note that the Michigan policy, though unintentionally, has an effect
    similar to that of the Harvard plan of old. The effect is similar, in my view, because a significant
    proportion of those persons who are excluded because of racial discrimination in favor of under-
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 75
    represented minorities are Jews. While no specific numbers have been given, a wide variety of
    sources indicate that Jewish representation in general in law schools is several multiples of the
    proportion of Jews in the general population. There is no reason to believe that as a proportion of
    those excluded by Michigan’s policies, the impact would be any different.
    If policies like the Law School’s are permitted, the adverse effect on “over-represented”
    minorities will only grow more grave because such policies inexorably drive toward a philosophy
    in which admissions are parceled out roughly in proportion to representation in the general
    population. The Law School may deny this, and argue that the policy is only for “under-represented”
    minorities. But, if suitably divided, any group can become a minority. If one distinguishes between
    denominations of Christianity, no religion is a majority in America. Using only the constitutionally
    protected classes of national origin, no ethnic background is a majority. Thus, by the rationale of
    Michigan’s policy, every group suitably defined could be entitled to “a critical mass” of its members
    so that those students, too, should “not feel isolated or like spokespersons” nor “feel uncomfortable
    discussing issues freely based on their personal experiences.” Majority Op. at 15. And then, by the
    inexorable laws of mathematics, the existence of a critical mass or rough proportionality for each
    group so considered means that what is left for the remainder of the groups (those formerly “over-
    represented”) is no more than its own critical mass of “rough proportionality.” And there lies the rub.
    Being relegated to rough proportionality brings Jewish applicants full circle to their chances under
    Lowell’s “Harvard Plan,” or even worse, as Jews today constitute only 2-3% of the total population.
    The Law School and the court will certainly deny this, but that is where the figures unavoidably lead
    us.
    These prospects for such uninhibited racial and ethnic discrimination are especially important
    because the Law School has declined to justify its policy as remedying past discrimination.17 There
    is no limiting principle preventing the Law School from employing ethnic or religious preferences
    to arrange its student body by critical mass. In short, the compelling state interest of developing a
    17
    The Law School’s disavowal is why I do not discuss whether the remediation of past
    discrimination is a compelling state interest that could justify the Law School’s actions. Not only
    must a state interest be compelling to satisfy strict scrutiny, but it must also be the interest that
    motivated the classification in the first instance. While we have been reluctant to determine what
    actually motivated legislative bodies, see, e.g., Federal Communications Comm’n v. Beach
    Communications, Inc., 
    508 U.S. 307
    , 315 (1993), the Law School administration is the sole creator
    of the admissions policy at issue here and we can rely on its assurance (as compared to the statement
    of a particular legislator or an incomplete statutory preamble) that such remediation is not the
    purpose of its admissions policy.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 76
    diverse student body would justify an infinite amount of engineering with respect to every racial,
    ethnic, and religious class.18
    B. Is the Law School’s Admissions Policy Narrowly Tailored?
    If pressed, however, it would be unnecessary to determine whether promoting diversity in
    education constitutes a compelling state interest because we, just as Justice Powell in Bakke, are not
    faced with an admissions scheme that is narrowly tailored to achieve the compelling state interest
    of diversity in education. For the majority, the inquiry into narrow tailoring begins and ends with
    a determination that the Law School neither “sets aside” an exact number of seats for racial or ethnic
    minorities nor admits minorities with a specific quota of admittees in mind. The distinction of
    quotas from other preferences is the dividing line between constitutional and unconstitutional
    admissions policies, on this view. For this position, the majority points to the Harvard plan, not of
    Lowell’s time, but the one of which Justice Powell, on the basis of no factual record but only a bland
    description appended to an amicus brief, spoke approvingly in Bakke. That plan, using race only as
    a “plus,” does not offend the Constitution according to the majority because of Powell’s advisory
    opinion on its constitutionality. Therefore, the majority would hold that all plans that merely use
    race as a “plus” are constitutional. Yet, the constitutional analysis of racial preferences appears to
    be binary for the majority in that a preference is either a forbidden quota or a permissible plus.
    We must be, however, concerned about the magnitude of this preference. Even assuming,
    against all doubt, that Justice Powell’s opinion on the constitutionality of a plan not any part of the
    18
    Because of our society’s history of religious discrimination and religion’s continuing
    salience, I have at times recognized the analogy between religious preference and the racial and
    ethnic preference bestowed in this case. For example, at oral argument I questioned counsel about
    the constitutionality of engineering a critical mass of Southern Baptists at the Law School. Counsel
    for the Law School attempted to deflect this analogy by arguing that a religious preference of the
    same form as the Law School’s racial and ethnic preference would raise “special” constitutional
    problems of “getting entangled” with religion in violation of the “First Amendment.” Tr. at 16-17.
    In essence, counsel’s argument was that an admissions policy with religious preferences that would
    comport with the Equal Protection Clause could nevertheless violate the Establishment Clause. I
    could find no case or even analytic argument for the proposition that a policy, pursuing a compelling
    state interest and tailored narrowly to that interest, could violate the Establishment Clause. Cf. Droz
    v. CIR, 
    48 F.3d 1120
    , 1122 (9th Cir. 1995) (noting the relevance of the strict scrutiny framework to
    the First Amendment inquiry). With as much justification as the Law School disclaims any invidious
    animus toward “over-represented” groups in its policy, comparable discrimination against “over-
    represented” religious groups could be said not to represent the establishment of all other religions
    or the irreligious. I am convinced that the analogy, and therefore the inevitable implications, of the
    Law School’s constitutional argument here, hold.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 77
    case or controversy before the Court could be a holding binding on this court, I cannot believe that
    a “plus” of any size, no matter how large, would be therefore constitutional. I believe that the Law
    School’s preference is just too large to be narrowly tailored.
    My analysis of the narrow tailoring defects of the Law School admissions scheme falls into
    four parts. First, I detail the true magnitude of the Law School’s preference. Second, I explain why
    we cannot draw a meaningful distinction between the Law School’s attempts to achieve a “critical
    mass” of under-represented minorities and the quotas that the majority concedes to be
    unconstitutional. Third, I question whether a strong racial preference bears any demonstrable
    relationship to the claimed benefits of educational pluralism. Fourth and finally, I suggest some
    race-neutral means of achieving the Law School’s avowed ends that the Law School has not pursued.
    1. The True Magnitude of the Law School’s Racial Preference
    Because the majority has not laid out the magnitude of the discrimination revealed by the
    record, it is important to detail it here. An examination of the admissions data shows that even the
    most qualified majority19 students (those with an LSAT over 170 and a GPA over 3.75) do not
    achieve the perfect admissions percentages for under-represented minority students with a GPA
    nearly a point less and an LSAT score in the 164-66 range. More roughly speaking, under-
    represented minorities with a high C to low B undergraduate average are admitted at the same rate
    as majority applicants with an A average with roughly the same LSAT scores.20 Along a different
    axis, minority applicants with an A average and an LSAT score down to 156 (the 70th percentile
    nationally) are admitted at roughly the same rate as majority applicants with an A average and an
    LSAT score over a 167 (the 96th percentile nationally).
    The figures indicate that race is worth over one full grade point of college average or at least
    an 11-point and 20-percentile boost on the LSAT. In effect, the Law School admits students by
    giving very substantial additional weight to virtually every candidate designated as an “under-
    represented minority” or, equivalently, by substantially discounting the credentials earned by every
    student who happens to fall outside the Law School’s minority designation.
    For the potential applicant, the Law School’s system creates very different dilemmas
    depending on his race. If confronted a year before they applied to the Law School with the records
    of two students, whose non-racial credentials were equivalent, we might evaluate their prospects for
    admission as follows: Student A could work harder and raise her GPA by a full point. Student B
    19
    Meaning, for these purposes, those students who are not “under-represented minorities.”
    20
    JA at 603, 605. Comparison between students in the 167-169 LSAT range in 1997.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 78
    could reveal the fact of his skin color or ethnicity, it being in one of the preferred categories.21 The
    Law School’s admissions officer, who before both changes would have rated the students equally,
    would now find the students equal, the effort of the one being counterbalanced by the background
    of the other.
    More shocking is the comparison of the chances of admission for applicants with the same
    academic credentials (at least numerically). Taking a middle-range applicant with an LSAT score
    164-66 and a GPA of 3.25-3.49, the chances of admission for a white or Asian applicant are around
    22 percent. For an under-represented minority applicant, the chances of admission (100%) would
    be better called a guarantee of admission.
    At some point, however, comparison of the admissions rates of white, Asian, and other
    unselected ethnic applicants and the minority groups designated for preference becomes impossible.
    The Law School simply stops meaningful consideration of non-minority candidates below certain
    grade point and LSAT figures,22 a practice demonstrated by admissions rates well below 10 percent,
    and often the absence of a single admitted student, in these credential categories. “Under-
    represented minorities,” on the other hand, not only continue to have respectable chances of
    admission in these categories, but in most cases enjoy rates of admission in excess of 80 percent.23
    Far from receiving “competitive consideration,” majority applicants are all but summarily rejected
    with credentials, but not ethnicity, identical to their under-represented minority “competitors” who
    are virtually guaranteed admission. The Law School’s admissions practices betray its claim that it
    gives meaningful individual consideration to every applicant notwithstanding their race.
    21
    While it should not be necessary to make this point, the use of hypotheticals or examples
    that illustrate the effective impact of the policies under consideration is in no way a commentary on
    specific persons. If a policy has real effects that seem impolite or offensive, that is a result of the
    policy, not of those who point it out.
    22
    Majority applicants with an A average and LSAT over 164 enjoy admission rates over 40%.
    As their grades slide to a high B average and an LSAT over 164, their admission rates drop to around
    20%. Below a 164, majority applicants are not admitted at a rate any more than 10%, regardless of
    their grade point average.
    23
    By comparison, designated minorities are not only considered, but admitted in rates over
    60%, and usually over 80%, with LSAT scores down to 154 and grade point averages in the low B
    range. Even below these figures, designated minorities are still admitted at rates nearing 30% in
    many categories of LSAT and GPA. Not until the designated minorities’ LSAT drops below 150
    (47th percentile nationally) or a GPA of 2.5 do we see admission rates under 10% for designated
    minorities.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 79
    The sharp threshold for admission that the Law School appears to establish for majority
    applicants reveals the emptiness of another purported justification for its racial preference. The Law
    School justifies its stark preference, in part, by claiming that all the applicants admitted, even those
    admitted because of its preference, are “qualified.” If the Law School actually believed that all
    applicants, with combinations of credentials sufficient for admission for minorities, were truly
    “qualified,” it would likely be willing at least to consider admitting majority applicants who were
    equally “qualified.” Instead, the Law School reveals its true views regarding the necessary
    credentials for its law students through its clear line in its admission of majority candidates: students
    below the credential threshold either diminish the educational environment of the school or spare
    it only if kept to a small percentage of the class.
    In the alternative, the Law School’s process designates as “qualified” virtually all who apply
    for admission. If the Law School is being honest, it considers every last under-represented minority
    admitted “qualified.” Indeed, the admissions data reveal that the Law School admits nearly every
    minority student who meets threshold credentials, as there appears to be a sharp cliff in rates of
    admission between extremely small variations in objective credentials.24 If the Law School considers
    everyone above this minority threshold “qualified,” it must also consider the 89 percent of the
    applicant pool above this threshold “qualified.” Yet it is clear that the Law School would not be
    comfortable with the random admission of any of the 89% of its applicant pool. The Law School
    does not truly consider majority applicants toward the bottom half of this 89% “qualified” – it admits
    almost none of them.
    The Law School’s use of the term “qualified” reveals its slipperiness. The court majority
    reveals the Law School’s shift in usage when it explains the rejection of a more random selection
    method because the school seeks to assemble “both a highly qualified and richly diverse academic
    class.” Majority Op. at 19. The Law School appears to be all too cognizant of the difference
    between “highly qualified” and merely “qualified” applicants. Its two steep cliffs in the admissions
    rate, one for under-represented minority applicants and one for majority applicants, demonstrate that
    the Law School maintains a “two-track,” indeed separated, system for admissions. Using its under-
    represented minority threshold, the Law School fills its seats reserved for “qualified” candidates.
    Using its majority threshold, the Law School completes the balance of its class with “highly
    qualified” applicants. That the Law School merely seeks to insure that “all its students are qualified”
    is an empty claim.
    24
    For example, there is a sharp drop in rates of admission between under-represented minority
    applicants with a 154 to a 155 LSAT score and those with a 151 to a 153. With a 154 to a 155, we
    see admission rates in excess of 60%. With a 151 to a 153, however, minorities are admitted at rates
    below 20%.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 80
    The Law School argues, however, that these overwhelming data are illusions produced
    through the smoke of litigation. These data, standing alone, the Law School seems to claim, could
    be produced by very small differences in actual qualifications. Taking certain hypothetical statistics,
    the Law School’s contention could certainly hold. For example, if for some reason every applicant
    had the same LSAT score, but every white had a GPA of 3.50 and every black had a GPA of 3.49,
    a “racial preference” would be required to obtain any admission of black students, but the degree of
    that preference would obviously be very small. The difference in chances of admission for the black
    and white applicants would still be very large, but the practical amount of preference would be very
    small.
    However, such are not the admissions statistics in this case. As the statistics show, the
    degree of preference can be characterized, in the benign words of Justice Powell and Harvard, as a
    “tip” only with some considerable violence to terminological exactitude.25 The term “tip” would
    convey to the average reasonable person something that overbalances a fairly closely divided or
    nearly evenly balanced choice. A seesaw with roughly equivalent children on either end can be
    “tipped” from one side to the other with a small weight. However, if a boulder must be placed on
    one side to shift the balance, the term “tip” would apply only if it were infinitely elastic. A common-
    sense view of a “tip” might be that in a zone where 80 or 90% of majority applicants are admitted,
    100% of minorities would be favored. Or, in a zone where only 10 or 20% of majority applicants
    are admitted, 30 or 40% of minorities might be. If Justice Powell’s words are to be used as anything
    more than a subterfuge, that would be the kind of preference that a fair reading of his opinion might
    endorse.
    The majority responds that there is no evidence in Bakke about how large the racial
    preference was in the Harvard plan of which Justice Powell spoke approvingly. Majority Op. at 25-
    26. As a result, it is impossible to know whether the Law School’s alleged “plus” was larger than
    Harvard’s. Majority Op. at 17. Immediately thereafter, the majority concludes that the Law School’s
    admission scheme is “virtually identical to the Harvard plan,” and that therefore the Law School’s
    system must be constitutional. 
    Ibid.
     How does the majority know that the Law School’s system is
    “virtually identical” to Harvard’s? I am deeply puzzled regarding how the majority could place both
    its confession of ignorance regarding the details of the Harvard plan and its claim that the two plans
    are identical in the same paragraph. The majority’s argument, yet again, simply elides empirical
    premises necessary to sustain what it claims to be the controlling analogy between the Law School
    and Harvard plans.
    And indeed the majority’s recognition that there is no factual record regarding the Harvard
    plan in Bakke echoes the reason why federal courts do not issue advisory opinions on cases not
    before them and why we find binding only the holdings, but not the dicta, of prior cases. Without
    25
    Cf. United States v. Allen, 
    211 F.3d 970
    , 976 (6th Cir. 2000) (en banc).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 81
    an actual case or controversy before it, a court is not able to develop a factual record and to
    determine which facts would be legally relevant. The absence of a factual record on the Harvard
    plan reinforces the reasons that Justice Powell’s thoughts regarding its potential constitutionality are
    not binding.
    Even if we know nothing of the absolute magnitude of the Harvard plan other than its
    description as merely a “tip” or a “plus,” we have some evidence regarding its relative magnitude.
    As described in the amicus brief before the Court in Bakke, the Harvard plan provided that “the race
    of an applicant may tip the balance in his favor just as geographic origin or life spent on a farm may
    tip the balance in other candidates’ cases.” LANDMA RK BRIEFS AND ARGUMENTS, supra n.1, at 736
    (emphasis added). From the description, it would seem that Harvard’s racial preference would be
    similar in magnitude to the preference given other soft factors. We know, however, from the
    indisputable statistical evidence in this case and the Law School’s own admission that no other soft
    factor is even remotely as significant as race in its admission decisions. Additionally, there is
    nothing in the Harvard description that even hints that its preferences for race or others factors of
    diversity are of the magnitude here, taking the chance of admission from near zero to near 100%, in
    many cases.
    It is clear from the Law School’s statistics that under-represented minority students are nearly
    automatically admitted in zones where white or Asian students with the same credentials are nearly
    automatically rejected. Indeed, the Law School concedes that its racial preference is sufficiently
    heavy that 3 out of 4 under-represented minority students would not be admitted if all students were
    truly considered without regard to race. JA at 6047. The characterization of the Law School’s
    preference as only a “tip” or “plus” would eviscerate those words, and transform Powell’s thoughful
    discussion into a carte blanche for adopting the UC Davis system with only a few cosmetic changes.
    One might wonder why I focus so heavily on the LSAT and GPA admissions data provided
    by the Law School. Of course, the constitutional deficiencies of the Michigan policy have nothing
    to do with the question of how and whether universities should consider academic measures such
    as GPA and LSAT in their admissions policies. Michigan is perfectly free to abandon or to
    restructure those measures. However, those are the standards it has chosen to distinguish among
    majority candidates, and to distinguish among minority candidates. Equal protection of the laws
    demands that the objective standards that the Law School chooses are applied with some modicum
    of equality, and they are not here.26
    26
    The concurring opinion criticizes this statistical analysis by noting scholarship suggesting
    no good link between “numerical credentials,” presumably meaning LSAT and GPA, and “success
    in Law School.” Concurring Op. at 39-40 (Clay). My only point here is that, notwithstanding the
    debate over more accurate measures of educational merit, the Law School undoubtedly thinks LSAT
    and GPA are most important. The only other credential that appears to be systematically important
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 82
    Michigan argues, with some justification, that it also considers a wide variety of “soft”
    factors. And nothing in this opinion denigrates the use of such factors, or even changing or
    increasing them, so long as they are applied equally. However, it is of the greatest importance to
    note that Michigan does not contend, in any way, that the consideration of those factors explains any
    advantage, systematic or otherwise, for minority candidates. It does not make that claim in its filings
    or briefs, and I specifically put the question in oral argument: “Do you assert that under-represented
    minorities systematically have stronger [soft factors] than non-minority students?” Counsel
    responded with a firm “no.” Tr. at 41. Thus, the issue is not the merits behind one combination of
    qualifications or another. The constitutional dilemma presented is the use, or at least the degree of
    use, of race to overcome qualifications, however defined.
    2. Differentiating a “Critical Mass,” a “Plus” and a “Quota”
    As I have just explained, the preference accorded minorities in the Law School’s admissions
    scheme is different in magnitude from the “plus” or the “tip” that Justice Powell thought might be
    permissible under certain conditions. The Law School’s racial preference, however, suffers from
    deeper problems – as it appears calibrated to admit a certain percentage of under-represented
    minority students. The Law School concedes that the preference is designed to admit a “critical
    mass” of under-represented minority students. Of course, the term “critical mass” is intentionally
    vague. When pressed, the Law School will explain that a “critical mass” is that number of students
    necessary to enable “minority students [to] contribute to classroom dialogue and not feel isolated.”
    Majority Op. at 5. Pressed further, the Law School will not say that any particular number of
    minority students constitutes a critical mass. It seems obvious to me, however, that the Law School
    has an opinion as to what that number is and attempts to achieve it.27
    The majority summarily dispenses with this problem, approvingly quoting the comforting
    reassurances of Dean Lehman (“We do not have a portion of the class that is set aside for a critical
    mass”) without noting that in fact a critical mass is always obtained. Majority Op. at 14. And
    comforting those words must be, as a contrary response would have produced what appears to be the
    only manner in which a racial preference in admissions could be unconstitutional for the majority:
    a quota system. Yet Harvard in the 1930's did not have to say that exactly 87 percent of the seats
    is race, and I think we should at least be candid about how much emphasis that the Law School
    places on race. To the extent that the concurrence mounts a more substantial attack on the use of
    numerical credentials generally, its quarrel is with the Law School, not with my position.
    27
    See, e.g., Tr. at 21-24, where counsel for the Law School admitted that 3-5% would not be
    enough and that “clearly we care about the number.”
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 83
    were set aside for Gentiles – it just had to apply an admissions system based on “character” that
    achieved roughly the same result.28
    The results of the Law School’s system to produce a “critical mass” reassure us that the Law
    School really seeks to enroll a critical number of minority students. Between 1995 and 1998, the last
    four years for which we have data, the Law School consistently enrolled a number of under-
    represented minorities constituting 13.5 to 13.7 percent of the class enrolled. The absolute numbers
    are just as consistent: 47 of 341 in 1998, 46 of 339 in 1997, 44 of 319 in 1996, and 46 of 340 in
    1995. University of Michigan Law School’s Report to the ABA, JA at 643. The statistics
    demonstrate that the Law School was more successful at enrolling a precise number of under-
    represented minorities than a precise number of total students.29 It seems clear to me, at least, that
    the “critical mass” the Law School seeks to achieve is only vague and flexible for outsiders not
    looking at its enrollment statistics.30 The Law School’s “critical mass” of designated minorities is
    44-47 per class, or around 13.5%.
    The majority and the Law School stress that minority enrollment numbers have varied,
    indicating that the Law School does not maintain a fixed target for minority admissions. The fact
    28
    The percentage of Harvard students who were Jewish varied between 1933-42, but was
    quite stable and well below the percentages in the 1920's. In the 1920's, the percentage consistently
    approached 30%. A glance at the 1933-42 Harvard figures, with percentages of 12.4, 9.9, 10.9, 14.8,
    14.0, 15.4, 14.4, 16.0, 14.1, and 16.1, reveals a chart that looks very much like Michigan’s with
    respect to under-represented minorities. Synnott, THE HALF -OPENED DOOR at 115, Table 4.8 (1971).
    29
    Admittedly, these percentages did deviate a bit from this tight grouping in some years
    before 1995 being, respectively, 12%, 14%, 14%, 13%, 19%, 20%, 14%, 20%, for the years 1987-94.
    These deviations, however, do not muddle the extraordinarily tight grouping in the last four years
    and primarily show what may have been, in the Law School’s view, “excessive” percentages in three
    of the years. Nevertheless, the lowest percentage never falls below 12%, while the Law School
    acknowledges that three-fourths of that number is accounted for by the application of its preference
    policy.
    Of course, even these early numbers are consistent with the Law School’s maintaining a
    numerical target. Perhaps the Law School had a different target in those years. It is hard to know,
    because the Law School has failed to specify its view of “critical mass.” Perhaps the Law School
    simply got better at exactly achieving its target.
    30
    There is little solace in the Law School’s unwillingness to reveal its quota. I share Justice
    Brennan’s view: “there is no basis for preferring a particular preference program simply because in
    achieving the same goals [as a quota system], it proceeds in a manner that is not immediately
    apparent to the public.” Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 379
    .
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 84
    that there has been any variation (.2% over four years), trivial though it may be, in the percentage
    of students admitted who are minorities satisfies the majority that the Law School does not maintain
    a quota. After all, the majority instructs us, variation produces a range, and a range will always have
    a “minimum,” that might look like a number below which the Law School will not go. Majority Op.
    at 16. Such is the nature of a range, the majority says, almost suggesting that it was foolish to be
    concerned about the question. 
    Ibid.
    I am not concerned just with the bottom of the range, but also its top. The range, as I have
    demonstrated, is remarkably tight. Admittedly, it is not identical from year to year – but the lack of
    identity does not seem enough to demonstrate that the Law School does not have an exceedingly
    precise numerical target in mind when admitting its students. The fact that a quota is a range rather
    than one specific number certainly does not insulate a program from constitutional scrutiny. In
    Bakke, had UC Davis said “We’re going to reserve, oh, about 14 to 18 seats, maybe give or take a
    few,” for minority students – and then, indeed hit that range every year, I doubt that anyone can
    seriously believe that the outcome of that case would have been different.
    The majority’s reliance on such slight variations also ignores the imprecision involved in
    producing enrollment. A law school does not admit students with perfect information regarding its
    yield, that is the percentage of students that will accept offers of admission. The yield is radically
    dependent on the idiosyncratic preferences of the students admitted. Accordingly, in a given year,
    highly selective law schools may have ten percent variations in the overall sizes of their enrolled
    classes, much less any desired component part. The University of Michigan Law School is no
    exception, enrolling 341 students in 1998, 339 in 1997, 319 in 1996, 340 in 1995, 363 in 1994.
    Given these uncertainties, the quite narrow range of minority enrollment percentages that the Law
    School achieves is remarkable for its consistency, and it seems to me that the Law School is doing
    all it can to achieve a target number of minorities. I take no comfort in the statistically minor
    variations in minority enrollment.
    Indeed, the record makes it clear that, to take a hypothetical example, if the Law School were
    to discover near the end of its process that a large number of its admitted minority students had all
    decided to attend other schools, thus leaving both a block of empty seats and a huge deficit in the
    sought-for “critical mass,” the Law School would bend every effort to fill those seats with minority
    students. Before all offers of admission are made, substantial numbers of applicants accept,
    clarifying the likely composition of each class. Law School officials testified that they vigorously
    monitor the acceptance data with regard to race on a daily basis, see Depo. of Dennis Shields, JA at
    2219-20, perhaps to admit minorities that it otherwise would not have or perhaps to admit minorities
    on the waiting list. This, of course, is the practical equivalent of the “segregated waiting lists”
    condemned in other cases. See, e.g., Hopwood v. Texas, 
    78 F.3d 932
    , 938 (5th Cir. 1996).
    The combination of the Law School’s thinly veiled references to such a target, its “critical
    mass,” and relatively consistent results in achieving a particular enrollment percentage, should
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 85
    convince us that the Law School’s admissions scheme is functionally, and even nominally,
    indistinguishable from a quota system. At the very least, however, the Law School’s admission plan
    seems far from employing the mere “plus” or “tip” that the majority characterizes its racial
    preference to be.
    In order for the language of “plus” or “tip” to have real meaning, there would have to be
    some indication that the other, allegedly similar, plus factors were also of a strength that were
    anywhere near the potency of the preference here. After all, Justice Powell himself contended that,
    to be only his “plus,” race would need to be just one among many factors. As Justice Powell wrote,
    “The file of a particular black applicant may be examined for his potential
    contribution to diversity without the factor of race being decisive when compared,
    for example, with that of an applicant identified as an Italian-American if the latter
    is thought to exhibit qualities more likely to promote beneficial educational
    pluralism. Such qualities could include exceptional personal talents, unique work or
    service experience, leadership potential, maturity, demonstrated compassion, a
    history of overcoming disadvantage, ability to communicate with the poor, or other
    qualifications deemed important.”
    Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 317
     (Powell, concurring). The majority is content to accept the Law School’s
    claim that it considers some of these “soft” factors. Majority Op. at 15. I would ask whether any
    of them are remotely comparable in weight. While not every factor would be required to bear equal
    weight under the Powell view, it seems clear that at least some of these other factors would need to
    be capable of taking a student’s chances from virtual certainty of rejection to virtual certainty of
    admission. There is no such evidence as to any race-neutral factor, but there is repeated and
    consistent evidence of such a treatment of race and ethnicity.
    3. Achieving the Benefits of a Diverse Educational Environment
    Even if I were not convinced that the Law School’s pursuit of a “critical mass” of minority
    students is a constitutionally invalid means to achieve diversity, I would still find the empirical link
    between such “critical mass” and the values of diversity lacking. 31 The Law School never provided
    31
    This discussion highlights the overlapping nature of the two-step equal protection analysis.
    One might think that a discussion of the benefits of diversity would be better placed in the analysis
    of whether diversity in education is a compelling state interest. At this point, it is important to be
    precise. No one, not even the Law School or Justice Powell, claims that diversity for its own sake
    can constitute a compelling state interest. Instead, the claim is that diversity yields race-neutral
    benefits that are themselves compelling. More precisely speaking, diversity in education is a means
    of achieving the compelling state interest in the benefits of diversity.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 86
    any evidence that the existence of the “critical mass” would in fact contribute to classroom dialogue
    or would lessen feelings of isolation or alienation. The only evidence at all bearing on this is from
    the Gurin Report.
    The Gurin report is questionable science, was created expressly for litigation, and its
    conclusions do not even support the Law School’s case. The benefits of a diverse student body that
    the study purports to prove, essentially better learning32 and increased democratic participation,33 are
    themselves vague to a degree that we would never accept to satisfy strict scrutiny in any other
    context. The concurring opinion34 contends that this opinion ignores the Gurin report in discussing
    diversity’s capacity to deliver its claimed benefits. Concurring Op. at 29 (Clay). The concurring
    opinion, however, does not even mention, much less analyze, the strength of Gurin’s proof. The
    “study” suffers from profound empirical and methodological defects that lead me to doubt its
    probative value. And certainly neither the trial court as finder of fact nor the majority opinion take
    the report’s conclusions as fact.
    First, the report falls well short of making the Law School’s case, even if we simply accept
    it without scrutinizing its conclusions. The report takes no position on how much diversity is
    required to yield the claimed benefits, and thus does not even purport to substantiate the Law
    School’s claim that a “critical mass” of minorities is required to achieve the educational benefits of
    diversity.35
    32
    The report claims that the educational benefits that positively correlate with diversity
    include “graduate degree aspirations,” “drive to succeed,” and “academic ability.” Gurin also notes,
    in passing, that the favorable outcomes for African-American students, with which she reports a
    correlation to her diversity measures, do not include actual learning as measured by grade point
    average. See JA at 2355; Patricia Gurin, The Compelling Need for Diversity in Higher Education,
    5 Mich. J. of Race and L. 363, 391 (1999).
    33
    The democratic benefits include “influencing social values,” “helping others in difficulty,”
    and “being involved in environmental activities.”
    34
    Although there are two concurring opinions in this case, only Judge Clay’s addresses the
    substantive portion of this dissent. My references in the text to the “Concurring Opinion” refer to
    Judge Clay’s. I will make a more specific reference when referring to Judge Moore’s concurring
    opinion.
    35
    The relationship between diversity and these assorted educational benefits could be
    proportional, exponential, or stepwise. If it were merely proportional, there would appear to be no
    basis for the Law School’s attempts to achieve a “critical mass,” rather than each marginal “under-
    represented minority” bringing equal benefit.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 87
    Second, the report’s aspirations to empiricism are undermined by the subjectivity of its data.
    After all, the report bases its claimed educational benefits on only the subjective self-reports of
    students.
    Third and most importantly, the statistical regressions relied on by the report never examine
    the statistical link between having a more diverse student body and the benefits that it claims.
    Instead, the regressions investigate only the correlation between the claimed benefits and two proxy
    variables for diversity: “classroom diversity” and “informal interactional diversity.” See Gurin
    Report, JA at 2434, 2437, 2441, 2446. “Classroom diversity” is defined as the responding student
    having taken an ethnic studies class, and “informal interactional diversity” as a student having had
    social interaction with or about minorities in college. 
    Ibid.
     Both of these variables, however, are
    independent of having a more racially or ethnically diverse student body, and appear to make the
    case for more ethnic studies classes or informational seminars about ethnic issues, instead of greater
    numbers of minority students. In fact, one wonders why Gurin did not directly correlate her benefits
    to the much less complex, but infinitely more relevant, variable of participation in a more diverse
    student body: I fear that Gurin used the proxies because a study of mere student body diversity either
    did not or would not produce the results that she sought.36 In any event, we lack any even
    purportedly empirical evidence demonstrating a correlation between increasing the number of under-
    represented minorities enrolled and the vague benefits of diversity claimed by the Law School.37
    36
    I am not alone in questioning the conclusions of the Gurin Report and the poverty of the
    empirical evidence presented. A social scientist and supporter of affirmative action in education
    evaluating some of the same data that Gurin used, but also examining actual student body diversity,
    concluded that “academic outcomes are generally not affected” by student body diversity, and that
    the effects that are indicated are “very weak and indirect.” Alexander W. Astin, WHAT MATTERS IN
    COLLEGE ? 362 (Jossey-Bass 1993). As we might expect from the vague list of claimed benefits, this
    researcher’s study concluded that “[t]he values, attitudes, and socioeconomic status of the peer group
    are much more important determinants of how the individual student will develop than are the peer
    group’s abilities, religious orientation, or racial composition.” 
    Id. at 363
    . Accordingly, a candid and
    empirically rigorous affirmative action supporter has admitted that a link between racial diversity
    and improved educational results has “yet to be convincingly demonstrated” and that “[t]he research
    still needs to be done that would demonstrate the link.” Peter Schmidt, Debating the Benefits of
    Affirmative Action, CHRON. OF HIGHER EDUC. A25 (May 18, 2001).
    37
    Even more fundamentally, social science data as to the efficacy, in the eyes of one or
    another researcher, of policies of discrimination are themselves of limited utility in resolving the
    ultimate constitutional issue. At the time of Brown v. Board of Education, 
    347 U.S. 483
     (1954),
    there were certainly researchers with academic degrees who argued that segregated education would
    provide greater educational benefits for both races. Does anyone think that a factual belief in such
    analyses would have, or should have, led to a different constitutional outcome in Brown? I very
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 88
    The Gurin Report aside, the link between the Law School’s diversity and its claimed benefits
    is conceptually flawed. The relationship between a “critical mass” and the values of diversity would
    depend on contingencies nearly impossible to predict. The Law School’s definition seems to depend
    wholly on the psychological makeup of the people involved, whether labeled as majority or minority.
    Certainly history is replete with examples of members of minority groups, from Frederick Douglass
    to Martin Luther King to Thomas Sowell, who have said their piece and stood for what they believed
    in without regard to whether others thought them to be a “representative.” Eleanor Roosevelt is
    quoted as having said that “no one can make you feel inferior without your consent.” The same is
    true of representativeness. Apparently, by this measure, if and as members of the under-represented
    group become psychologically stronger, and thus more able or willing to speak as individuals, the
    Law School needs less and less of them.
    On the other hand, if the measurement is based on the attitudes of the “non-minority”
    students, there again is little concreteness to the measure. This would seem to mean that if those
    outside the minority groups were all paragons of tolerance, then there would be no need for any
    preference, because all students would uphold the precepts of the Constitution and major religions
    to treat each person as an individual. Conversely, if the majority student body stubbornly persisted
    (following the Law School’s lead) in attributing the experiences and opinions of their classmates to
    their racial identity, the critical mass would need to expand and expand, presumably until most or
    all of the recalcitrant majority students had been driven from campus. In short, any sort of rationale-
    based definition of “critical mass” seems hopeless.
    “Critical mass” also has difficulties if it is defined in a way divorced from some notion of
    the “proper” representation of the particular group. Since the Law School gives no principles,
    sociological or otherwise, by which the “non-representativeness” of individual group members can
    be judged, we would have to assume that a “critical mass” would be of approximately the same size
    for any designated group. Thus, Afghans, Orthodox Jews, Appalachian Celts, or fundamentalist
    Christians might also feel that their remarks were being taken as representative, rather than
    strongly doubt it. Similarly, research asserting that Jews and Gentiles in fact interacted more
    harmoniously under Lowell’s Harvard plan would not justify that policy either.
    I note that this question is not simply of academic or antiquarian interest. Questions have
    been raised as to the ability or desirability of school districts implementing all-black academies in
    order to improve educational performance. See Wil Haygood, Rethinking Integration: On Schools,
    Many Blacks Return to Roots, BOSTON GLOBE (Nov. 16, 1997). I sincerely doubt that the factual
    outcome of conflicts between social scientists as to varying studies of the educational effect of such
    policies would be dispositive of the constitutional question that might be raised. See Drew S. Days,
    III, Brown Blues: Rethinking the Integrative Ideal, in REDEFINING EQUALITY (Neal Deavins and
    Davison M. Douglas, eds., Oxford 1998) (noting, while discussing the possibility of all-black public
    educational institutions, that “[e]xpedience cannot legitimize racial segregation”).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 89
    individually, unless they, too, had a “critical mass.” Then, the makeup of the entering class could
    be wholly determined by those groups that the Law School chose to classify as appropriate for
    worrying about their “under-represented status.” Indeed, the Law School does not appear to believe
    that the critical mass for Native Americans, for example, is nearly as large as it is for blacks and
    Hispanics. Thus, some measure of rough proportionality inevitably creeps in as the measure of what
    is the “critical mass.” Although the Law School’s deponents tried very hard to avoid any specificity
    in their responses (“A mass of Latin words falls upon the facts like soft snow”), it was clear both in
    the trial record and at oral argument that a number that was only half or less of a group’s
    representation in some national measure of population would not be considered a “critical mass.”
    Also problematic is how the Law School has selected the minorities entitled to a preference
    in terms of fostering a diverse educational environment. The Law School’s statement that its actions
    are justified because members of under-represented minorities are “particularly likely to have
    experiences and perspectives of special importance” raises the question of whether it can determine
    that other groups, such as Americans of Japanese or Welsh ancestry, are “particularly unlikely” to
    have such experiences and perspectives. In practical effect, that is what the Law School has decided,
    and without any specific basis. Either the experiences and perspectives are themselves valuable, in
    which case they could be judged on that basis without reference to skin color or parentage, or the
    Law School is assuming a heterogeneity among widely diversified groups.
    4. Potential Race-Neutral Means
    In order for its racial classifications to survive strict scrutiny, the state must first look to race-
    neutral means to achieve even compelling state interests. The Supreme Court has made clear that
    courts must determine whether a state’s racial classification is necessary with reference to the
    efficacy of race-neutral alternatives. See, e.g., Croson, 
    488 U.S. at 507
    ; United States v. Paradise,
    
    480 U.S. 149
    , 171 (1987); Associated Gen. Contractors of Ohio, Inc. v. Drabik, 
    214 F.3d 730
    , 736
    (6th Cir. 2000).
    What is not crystal clear, however, is the nature of the consideration that reviewing courts
    must undertake. Yet only one tack makes analytical sense. In order to prevail under strict scrutiny,
    the state must demonstrate not only that its racial classification achieves compelling state benefits,
    but also that these benefits may only be obtained by the shift from a well-designed, race-neutral
    alternative. Put differently, the state must demonstrate that the marginal benefits gained from
    employing the racial classification over the next most efficacious race-neutral alternative are
    themselves compelling. Any other standard would make success under strict scrutiny a mere exercise
    in question framing. The interest vindicated by a racial classification would look very large, perhaps
    even compelling, when compared to the benefits delivered by some dismal alternative. Instead, we
    should require that before we find marginal benefits reflective of a compelling state interest, they
    must be those gained over the best race-neutral alternatives.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 90
    Consider some of the race-neutral alternatives available in this case. The gradient of benefits,
    along which the race-conscious and race-neutral means are judged, is “academic diversity,” or
    achieving a pluralism of experiences and ideas. See Part III.A.1. Earlier in this opinion, I discussed
    the possibility of considering experiential diversity in a race-neutral manner. Swamped with the
    children of wealthy suburbanites, the Law School could seek out applicants who were raised amidst
    relative poverty, who attended under-funded or failing schools, who walked to school past
    warehouses instead of coffeehouses, who experienced but conquered extreme emotional trauma, like
    the loss of a parent, who prevailed over a profound childhood illness, who have dedicated years to
    helping the poor in the Jesuit Volunteer Corps, or, even less stirringly, who have a strong accounting
    background among a raft of history majors. If it really is a diversity of experiences and viewpoints
    that the Law School seeks, why cannot the Law School just seek those experiences and viewpoints?
    Instead, the Law School searches for particular races and ethnicities as a means of securing
    a diversity of experience, and, so they say, for no other purpose. A well-functioning search for
    experiential diversity would certainly yield the greatest measure of it. After all, even the Law School
    would admit that race is an imperfect proxy for experiential diversity. Next-door neighbors in
    Grosse Pointe, separated only by 30 yards and the color of their skin, would not necessarily be
    significantly different from each other. In principle at least, the race-neutral means of seeking the
    experiences themselves would seem superior to the Law School’s race-conscious means, if its aim
    is as it professes. This is quite the opposite of the woeful inadequacy of race-neutral means that we
    generally require to consider a racial classification narrowly tailored.
    In practice, the Law School could make all sorts of arguments about the inadequacy of merely
    seeking experience. For example, admissions officers would have to read (and seriously consider)
    more text in an application if it were seeking experience rather than race. The medium for
    communicating this quality, of course, lacks the efficient simplicity of the racial check-box. Yet,
    over and over again, the Law School has reassured us that its exquisitely meticulous admissions
    officers already consider each application individually and thoroughly. Such is the luxury, the Law
    School tells us, of so few applications and spots to fill. I am willing to take the Law School at its
    word, and believe that it is fully capable of undertaking this searching review of individual
    experience.
    Also, a system seeking experiential diversity might increase the risk of applicant fraud. It
    might be somewhat easier to verify that some individuals were truly of the right group than the
    details of their life stories. This comparative ease should not be overstated, however, as the
    distinctions between the Law School’s “under-represented minorities,” from various types of
    Hispanics to the marginally African-American, and the rest of society can be very subtle indeed. See
    Part III.B.2. Moreover, there are all sorts of readily identifiable indicia of experiential diversity.
    One’s home mailing address gives quite a bit away. Law schools already ask for detailed financial
    information to make financial aid judgments, permitting a review of the relative poverty to which
    the applicant was subjected. If the Law School were interested in the student’s secondary education,
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 91
    and the experiences that it imparted, it would not be outrageous to ask for a high school transcript.
    Indeed, as a good portion of the Law School’s student body hails from Michigan, see JA at 1947,
    the Law School’s seasoned admissions officers could probably develop a pretty intimate
    understanding of the state’s high schools.
    In short, the ready availability of seeking unique experiences themselves, rather than an
    imperfect proxy for them, demonstrates that the marginal benefits of the Law School using its
    suspect racial preference instead of the available race-neutral means are far from compelling. In fact,
    because it seems to me that selecting on the basis of race is actually a more poorly calibrated means
    of achieving the experiential diversity that it allegedly seeks, I doubt that the Law School is really
    interested in “academic diversity.” And this “academic diversity” is the only diversity that will
    satisfy the Powell opinion that the majority considers outcome-determinative. Instead, it is more
    likely that the Law School’s preference for certain races is an interest in race itself.
    Another race-neutral alternative mentioned is conducting a lottery for all students above
    certain threshold figures for their GPA and LSAT. This would insure a student body as diverse as
    the “qualified” applicant pool itself. As demonstrated above, the Law School’s unwillingness to
    conduct a lottery among all those students that it considers “qualified” reveals that it really maintains
    a two-track admissions system, one for the “highly-qualified” students of all races that it generally
    seeks, and another for under-represented minorities who are only “qualified.”38
    The availability of such race-neutral means, especially in dealing with the manageably small
    applicant pool of the Law School, reveals that the Law School’s talk of desiring only “academic
    diversity” is only window dressing for sheer racial discrimination.
    III
    Many commentators have observed that America is still a society in which “race [as well as
    ethnicity, religion and other ancestral characteristics] matters.” But we can not simply suspend the
    Equal Protection Clause until race no longer matters. Nor has the Supreme Court authorized us to
    do so. One need not advocate literal “color-blindness,” where we neither notice nor appreciate the
    differing experiences and communities of others, to hold that our Constitution forbids the
    government from assigning massive advantages and disadvantages based on a naked assignment of
    racial labels.
    38
    The concurring opinion suggests that evidence of racial and gender bias in LSAT and GPA
    figures would render the lottery race-conscious. Concurring Op. at 42 (Clay). Of course, the lottery
    itself would be completely race-neutral. I do not see how using the Law School’s “qualification”
    threshold, with which no party or judge has heretofore quarreled, to restrict the lottery would make
    the lottery race-conscious.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 92
    A significant amount of the analysis at pages 34-35 of the concurring opinion is directed to
    the point that race continues to be a factor that operates in American society in many negative, as
    well as positive, ways. I do not deny that. I am fully willing to stipulate that race does matter in
    American society and that, on average, it matters more negatively for some, if not all, of the groups
    favored by the Law School than it does for some, if not all, of the groups disfavored by the Law
    School. And I will also stipulate that such impact or disadvantage is not strictly limited by present
    income or status. But a defense of the Law School’s policies on the basis of remediating generalized
    past discrimination has several problems.
    First, the Supreme Court has firmly rejected the remediation of general “societal ills” and
    past discrimination as a justification for racial classifications. Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., 
    488 U.S. 468
    , 498 (1989). Second, it is not the basis on which the Law School has stated that it operates,
    nor was the question litigated (except by intervenors), either at the trial level or the appellate level,
    or addressed in the majority opinion. More fundamentally, however, such an approach confuses
    societal ills, that may be addressed by societal means, with the rights of individuals. Julian Bond,
    certainly a person who has been knowledgeable and engaged in this issue for decades, wrote in the
    Gonzaga Law Review that policies like those in question here are the “just spoils of a righteous war.”
    Julian Bond, Lecture: A Call in Defense of Affirmative Action: Just Spoils of a Righteous War, 
    34 Gonz. L. Rev. 1
    , 9 (1998). The struggle for civil rights in America, going back well over a century,
    can certainly be characterized as a righteous war. However, the earlier set of just spoils from a
    righteous, actual war, the American Civil War, had two characteristics. First, they were enshrined
    by changing the charter of our society, through the Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and Fifteenth
    Amendments to the Constitution. Second, the “spoils” embodied in those amendments were taken
    from slaveholders themselves, or from social and political structures in which the entire society (or
    the entire majority society) paid the bill.
    In this case, the “spoils” that are involved are the individual rights to equal treatment of real
    people like Barbara Grutter. If, in the words of Abraham Lincoln, society chooses that “every drop
    of blood drawn by the lash shall be paid by another,”39 then that bill should be paid by the whole
    society, and by considered alteration of our Equal Protection Clause, not by ignoring it. Though the
    war may be righteous, such spoils taken from the Barbara Grutters of our society are not just.40
    39
    Abraham Lincoln, Second Inaugural Address, March 4, 1865.
    40
    The concurring opinion responds that, in a world without affirmative action, applicants like
    Grutter will not be much better off. Concurring Op. at 36-38 (Clay). To make its point, the
    concurring opinion quotes at length the opinion, interlaced with some statistics, set forth in a recent
    Washington Post column. See Goodwin Liu, The Myth and Math of Affirmative Action, WASH . POST
    B1 (April 14, 2002). The concurring opinion asserts, on the basis of this evidence, that Athe idea that
    an admissions policy does so at the expense of white applicants is simply a myth.@ Concurring Op.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 93
    It can hardly be doubted that, on average, those students who are admitted to Michigan Law
    School despite the policies in question will have been more favorably situated, economically and
    socially, than those such as the plaintiff whose chances of admission have been reduced or
    eliminated by those policies.
    Similarly, because academic credentials are significantly correlated with parental income,
    social status, and education,41 the malign effects of discriminatory policies like the Law School’s will
    at 36.
    The Liu analysis simply does not support the concurring opinion=s conclusion. First, the
    article explicitly states that its argument applies just as forcefully to Alan Bakke. But the Supreme
    Court certainly did not deny Bakke’s claim because he could not prove with mathematical certainty
    that he would have received one of the sixteen places improperly segregated from the general
    applicant pool.
    Second, the article gives the game away when it candidly states that its statistical conclusion
    “occurs in any selection process in which the applicants who do not benefit from affirmative action
    greatly outnumber those who do.” Liu, supra, at B1; Concurring Op. at 15 (emphasis added).
    It is true that there is a very real sense in which the wrong committed against a person
    absolutely barred from consideration for a governmental benefit is greater than the wrong committed
    against a person only deprived of a fair chance of consideration.
    But a wrong has still been committed. The concurring opinion and Liu may not characterize
    that wrong as a “substantial disadvantage,” ibid., but the deprivation of equal consideration is a
    wrong to which the Constitution is opposed.
    There may have been hundreds of Jews each year who were denied a fair chance for
    consideration by the Harvard quota plan, even though a far smaller number of actual seats were
    involved and most such applicants could not have been certain of admission. They would not have
    been comforted by the force of Liu’s arguments.
    To say that it is a matter of less importance that ten people are each deprived of a one-tenth
    chance of admission because of race than if one person is completely excluded from admission is
    to ignore both mathematics and our system of deciding cases and controversies. If Grutter’s rights
    have been violated, the degree of the violation and the proper remedy are matters for the district
    court to determine in the first instance. To say that Grutter’s claims are to be ignored because the
    whole system that she has challenged has a relatively small discriminatory impact or because the
    magnitude of the violation as to her is small is to say that she has no rights that this court is bound
    to respect. I decline to take that attitude.
    41
    See, e.g., R. Richard Banks, Meritocratic Values and Racial Outcomes: Defending Class-
    Based College Admissions, 79 N.C.L. Rev. 1029, 1062 (2001) (noting that “[a] variety of studies
    have demonstrated positive relationships between early academic achievement and parental income,
    education, and occupation.”); Tomiko Brown-Nagin, "Broad Ownership" of the Public Schools: An
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 94
    rarely fall upon the children of the educators who craft them or the judges who rule upon them. The
    statistical region where those policies really bite, and where people like Barbara Grutter are excluded
    from equal consideration based on their race, are areas likely to be more heavily populated by
    persons whose income, ethnicity, social standing, and religious preferences are not those of the
    academic, legislative, and judicial decision-makers who support those policies. Thus Michigan’s
    policy can not be seen simply as a good-hearted effort by one group to forego opportunities for itself
    for the greater good.
    Michigan’s plan does not seek diversity for education’s sake. It seeks racial numbers for the
    sake of the comfort that those abstract numbers may bring. It does so at the expense of the real rights
    of real people to fair consideration. It is a long road from Heman Sweatt to Barbara Grutter. But
    they both ended up outside a door that a government’s use of racial considerations denied them a fair
    chance to enter. I therefore respectfully dissent from the court’s legitimation of this unconstitutional
    policy.
    Analysis of the "T-Formation" Process Model for Achieving Educational Adequacy and Its
    Implications for Contemporary School Reform Efforts, 
    27 J.L. & Educ. 343
    , 385 (1998) (noting that
    “comparative indicia showing the relationship between socioeconomic background and academic
    performance continues to reveal a persistent gap in achievement between wealthier and poorer
    students”).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 95
    PROCEDURAL APPENDIX
    Although the following procedural matters do not directly affect the legal principles
    discussed in this case, it is important that they be placed in the record as an explanation of the
    manner in which this case came before the particular decision-making body that has now decided
    it. Since a person reading these opinions in sequential order will have read a variety of complicated
    responses attempting to defend what happened procedurally in this case, it may be well to begin with
    the plainest possible statement of undisputed primary facts. The panel that considered this case prior
    to, and certainly following, the filing of the present appeals was not constituted in conformity with
    6th Cir. I.O.P. 34(b)(2) of this court’s rules, or any other rule. A motion that counsel made on
    May 14, 2001, for initial hearing en banc was not transmitted to most members of the court for five
    months, and was not treated as stated in the court’s order of June 4, 2001. These facts speak for
    themselves, however each of us may choose to characterize them.
    The appeals regarding the Law School’s admissions program that we have today decided
    were filed as follows: case number 01-1447 on April 2, 2001, and case number 01-1516 on April
    18, 2001.
    Under this court’s rules, these cases generally would have been assigned to a panel chosen
    at random. See 6th Cir. I.O.P. 34(b)(1). This was not done. Instead, as a result of a series of
    decisions in contravention of our rules and policies, we arrived at the present configuration.
    In August 1999, a panel of this court, consisting of Circuit Judges Daughtrey and Moore and
    visiting Senior District Judge Stafford, in case number 98-2009, decided an appeal concerning the
    rights of certain parties to intervene in the district court case underlying the current appeal, but did
    not address the merits of the case. See Grutter v. Bollinger, 
    188 F.3d 394
     (6th Cir. 1999).
    Upon the filing of the instant appeals, a question could have arisen regarding whether these
    appeals, seeking review of cases already returned to the district court by a panel of this court, were
    “must panel” cases. See 6th Cir. I.O.P. 34(b)(2). It is absolutely clear that the applicable procedures
    for potential “must panel” cases were not followed to determine whether and how these cases should
    be heard as a “must panel.”
    If a panel has “returned a case to the district court for further proceedings” and another
    appeal has been taken from those further proceedings, the original panel “determine[s] whether the
    second appeal should be submitted to it for decision, or assigned to a panel at random.” 
    Ibid.
     If a
    district judge, as in this case, was on the original panel, the remaining two circuit judges from the
    original panel are required to decide whether the district judge should be recalled for the panel or
    whether a third circuit judge “should be drawn to fill out the panel; provided that, if oral argument
    is scheduled, the draw shall be made from the judges of this Court scheduled to sit at that time.” 
    Ibid.
    These procedures were not followed in this case.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 96
    While these cases were before the district court, several interlocutory motions were, in the
    usual course of our policies, referred to a weekly motions panel chosen at random. However, even
    though no second appeal had been filed, the motions were then redirected to the earlier panel, which
    had been augmented, at the direction of the Chief Judge, by the addition of the Chief Judge, not a
    randomly chosen judge.42 Following the filing of the current appeals, all further actions regarding
    those appeals, including a motion to stay the district court’s order, were handled by this preselected
    panel.
    This was the situation when, on May 14, 2001, counsel petitioned the entire court, pursuant
    to Fed. R. App. P. 35(b)(1)(B), asking that the cases be heard by the en banc court in the first
    instance. At this point, the en banc court consisted of eleven active judges: the nine judges who
    ultimately heard this case plus then-active Judges Norris and Suhrheinrich. The petition was not
    circulated to the entire court.
    Instead, on June 4, 2001, an order was issued, at the direction of the Chief Judge and in the
    name of the court, stating that the motion “c[ame] before the court,” but holding the petition for
    hearing en banc in abeyance “until such time as the briefs of the parties have been filed, after which
    the court will make a determination on whether the cases should be submitted to a three-judge panel
    for adjudication or be referred to the en banc court.” (emphasis added). This order was also not
    circulated to the en banc court. The Appellee’s proof brief was filed on June 18, 2001.43 The
    petition was still not circulated to the court. On July 1, Judge Norris took senior status. All briefing
    in the case was certainly completed by July 30, 2001. Even still, the petition was not circulated to
    the court. On August 15, Judge Suhrheinrich took senior status.44 The petition was still not
    42
    It is not clear that preliminary motions can be redirected from a randomly selected motions
    panel to a purported “must panel” when no appeal has been filed.
    43
    Petitions for initial hearing en banc were filed in nine cases in the year 2000. Two of the
    cases, both filed pro se, were disposed of without circulating the en banc petition to the court. See
    Docket Sheets in Naturalite v. Ciarlo, No. 00-2106, decided under Rule 34, 
    22 Fed. Appx. 506
    (2001) and in Griffin v. Warren, No. 00-4552 (petition for certificate of appealability denied).
    In each of the other seven cases, the petition for initial hearing en banc was circulated to the
    court no later than two days after the appellee’s proof brief was filed. All were disposed of by the
    full court before the final briefs were filed.
    44
    The question of the circumstances under which Judge Norris and/or Judge Suhrheinrich
    could have sat on a potential en banc court hearing the case could be a matter of some contention.
    Under the circuit rule in place at the time, “any judge who had been in regular active service at the
    time a poll was requested on the petition” for an en banc hearing would be a member of the en banc
    court hearing the case. 6th Cir. I.O.P. 35(a) (1998) (emphasis added). As Judge Gilman discussed
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 97
    circulated to the court. On August 23, 2001, according to our internal docket, the petition was
    “referred” to the specially constituted panel. I have no reason to doubt that Judges Moore and
    Daughtrey had not known of the petition prior to that time. The special panel still did not circulate
    the petition for an en banc hearing to the full court.45
    Rather than circulating the still pending petition, the special panel scheduled the case for oral
    argument before itself, and again not a normally selected panel. According to the order, issued
    August 27, oral argument was to be held on October 23, fifty-seven days away. Forty-nine of those
    fifty-seven days passed, with no action being taken to circulate the still pending petition for hearing
    in his separate opinion in Popovich v. Cuyahoga Cty. Ct. of Common Pleas, 
    276 F.3d 808
    , 829 (6th
    Cir. 2002) (en banc), there is a substantial question regarding whether our rule in effect at the time
    was consistent with 
    28 U.S.C. § 46
    (c), governing the composition of courts of appeals en banc.
    Nevertheless, that was the rule we followed until October 31, 2001. We subsequently changed our
    rule to compose the en banc court of all judges in regular active service “at the time of oral argument
    en banc.” 6th Cir. I.O.P. 35(a) (2002).
    The old rule would have governed all the relevant en banc court composition issues that I
    have raised here. From Popovich, we know that this court’s precedent is, at least by permitting
    Judge Merritt to sit in that case, that our old Policy 35(a) is not statutorily invalid. Thus, both Judges
    Norris and Suhrheinrich could have sat on the en banc court if the petition had been circulated
    earlier. Judge Norris would have been a part of the en banc court in this case if a vote on the petition
    had been requested by July 1, over 45 days after the petition had been filed. Judge Suhrheinrich
    would have been a part of the court if a vote had been requested by August 15, over 90 days after the
    petition was filed and more than 15 days after the completion of briefing. The specially constituted
    panel’s withholding the petition from the court until October 15, 2001, 150 days after it had been
    filed and 75 days after the completion of briefing, had the effect of potentially keeping both judges
    off an en banc court.
    45
    Judge Moore’s reference to a December 5, 2000 policy imposed by the Chief Judge omits
    several important features of the policy. See Concurring Op. at 23-24. First, the policy states that
    it was prompted by petitions for initial hearing en banc from “pro se litigants, mainly prisoners,” not
    from counsel in important cases. It specifically states that it does not apply if the Chief Judge and
    clerk agree that “it is an unusual case.” I think we can all agree that this case was unusually
    important. Second, the policy authorized two and only two actions by the hearing panel to which
    the case and the petition is referred. The panel could either “deny the petition” and schedule the case
    for argument before the panel or “send the petition out to the en banc court.” Neither occurred here.
    The policy never authorized the panel to schedule argument and not to decide the petition. Third,
    the policy directed the panel to circulate the petition to the en banc court if it saw “some legitimate
    argument for hearing en banc.” It strains credulity to argue now, after the petition has been granted,
    that the petition contained no “legitimate argument” for its granting.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 98
    en banc, even though all briefing certainly had been completed. Suddenly, with the panel hearing
    just eight days away, a decision was made finally to circulate the pending petition to the nine active
    judges of our court.46 The petition was circulated without any explanation for the delay, and without
    even any notation that a delay had occurred. In addition, the statement accompanying the circulation
    neither recommended an en banc hearing nor indicated why the issue was raised, at that time, as
    opposed to a time more proximate to the filing of the petition, though it did state that the full court
    was being advised because “a question . . . has been raised regarding the composition of the panel.”47
    In any event, sufficient members of the active court voted to have the case heard en banc, and an
    order was issued on October 19, 2001, canceling the panel hearing scheduled to occur in only four
    days and instituting an en banc hearing before the now-reduced court.48
    Judge Moore’s concurrence makes several remarkable points. She first notes that the irregular
    constitution of the panel can be excused because “Chief Judge Martin has frequently substituted
    himself in a variety of matters, of varying degrees of importance, throughout his tenure as chief
    judge, in order to avoid inconveniencing other circuit judges.” Concurring Op. at 26 (Moore). But,
    of course, the very point is that such a practice, to the extent it exists, was unknown to the other
    members of the court, who had every reason to believe that the panel had been regularly constituted.
    46
    In early October, one senior judge of our court became concerned about the procedures that
    had been followed in this case, namely the specially constituted panel that had taken over this case.
    After that judge made several unsuccessful efforts to speak with the Chief Judge, on October 15 he
    faxed to the Chief Judge a letter setting forth his concerns as to whether court rules and policies had
    been followed in this case. He received no response or any other communication regarding this letter
    (and has not, to this day). However, on the same day that he sent that letter, with the hearing only
    eight days away, a decision was made to circulate the petition for an en banc hearing.
    47
    Judge Clay’s concurring opinion suggests that I “question[] the appropriateness of hearing
    this case en banc” and then argues why hearing important cases en banc is good. Concurring Op.
    at 43, 44. I have no opinion on the substance of the decision to hear this case en banc, only the
    procedures used to dictate its timing.
    48
    There is precedent for the special administration of a high-profile case. In Mozert v.
    Hawkins Cty. Bd. of Educ., 
    827 F.2d 1058
     (6th Cir. 1987), then-Chief Judge Lively took the case out
    of the normal hearing schedule because of educational time constraints and its importance. Rather
    than personally constituting a special panel, the Chief Judge, after suggesting the procedure to all
    the active judges on the court, had the clerk conduct a random draw of circuit judges to constitute
    the panel. Pursuant to the drawing, the Chief Judge, as a matter of coincidence, was randomly
    selected. This process occurred in a matter of days, and never threatened to delay the case. If such
    a transparent process had been followed here, the procedural issues noted in this appendix probably
    would not have arisen.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 99
    There was no reason to know of the unusual handling of the motions in 2000. There was no reason
    to know that there was any relation between the constitution of the “must panel” in 2001 and the
    activities in 2000. And there was no reason to know that anything was going on that was not in strict
    conformity with 6th Cir. I.O.P. 34(b)(2). Thus, there was no reason to take any unusual action in
    response, whether before or after “April 5, 2001.” Concurring Op. at 27.
    Judge Moore also contends that the Chief Judge regularly fills “vacancies in other cases,” that
    no one has previously objected to his practice, and that his practice has become “a matter of common
    knowledge among the judges of this court.” Concurring Op. at 26. I absolutely deny that this judge
    has had any “knowledge” of, or that the Chief Judge has announced or admitted to, any such practice
    of inserting himself onto panels without a random draw.
    The notion that other members of the court were in some way derelict in not sua sponte
    calling for an initial hearing en banc as soon as the appeal was filed is both remarkable and misses
    the point. Concurring Op. at 25-26, 27. There would be no particular reason for an initial hearing
    en banc unless there were some extraordinary circumstance, as the document Judge Moore has
    quoted obliquely indicates. Concurring Op. at 24-25.
    I have been on the court for 16 years, and I do not recall an initial hearing en banc in my
    tenure. The concatenation of the irregular panel, the withholding, by whatever mechanism, of the
    motion addressed to the court, and the later granting of that motion in haste, are matters for which
    the other members of the court are certainly not responsible.
    Judge Moore suggests that my objections to the composition of the three-judge panel are
    “minor” because the decisions regarding the composition did not “actually change[] the outcome of
    the present case.” Concurring Op. at 24 n.5 (Moore). But as I have always made clear, it is difficult
    to know what body would have decided this case if the rules had been correctly implemented.
    Further, to the extent that the Judge Moore claims that the irregularities in the hearing panel’s
    composition were the only reason for granting the en banc petition, those irregularities existed at the
    time the petition was filed, and thus it is difficult also to argue that they did not affect the
    composition of the panel that ultimately decided this case. Most importantly, however, the rights
    of litigants and the members of this court to scrupulous compliance with the rules are not dependent
    on the likely – or even certain – substantive outcomes of particular matters before the court.
    Contrary to Judge Moore’s concurring opinion, I do not contend that the legal opinions of
    any member of this court do not represent that judge’s principled judgment in this case. Concurring
    Op. at 21-22 (Moore). However, under these circumstances, it is impossible to say what the result
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 100
    would have been had this case been handled in accordance with our long-established rules. The case
    might have been heard before a different panel, or before a different en banc court.49
    49
    Neither of the concurring opinions addressing this appendix disputes any of the factual
    circumstances described.
    Judge Clay argues that no negative conclusions regarding any member of this court can be
    drawn from the handling of this case. Concurring Op. at 44 (Clay). I draw no such conclusions in
    this appendix. It may be possible that each of these events occurred without conscious direction.
    Each reader can make an independent judgment from the apparently undisputed facts that I have laid
    out here. Frankly, I would have been most pleased if my statement of apparent facts had been proven
    wrong. Unfortunately, that has not occurred.
    Judge Moore correctly states that our “only source of democratic legitimacy is the perception
    that we engage in principled decision-making.” Concurring Op. at 22 (Moore). If actions are taken
    that may imperil that legitimacy, a member of this court who observes them is left with two
    alternatives, both unpalatable. One is to allow the actions to pass in silence, even after explanations
    have been requested, but have not been produced. Silence simply allows those actions to continue
    and to be repeated, with real consequences for both the court and the litigants who appear before it.
    The other alternative is to place the actions on the record, for such remediation as may be
    possible.
    I have not revealed the substance of any internal communications on this case between
    members of our court, with the exception of the letter of one senior judge who asked me to do so.
    See n.46 supra. Compare Concurring Op. at 43 & 34 n.3 (Clay); Concurring Op. at 27 (Moore). As
    to Judge Clay’s discussion of my opinion in Memphis Planned Parenthood v. Sundquist, 
    184 F.3d 600
    , 605-07 (6th Cir. 1999) (Boggs, concurring in the denial of rehearing en banc), Concurring Op.
    at 43-44 (Clay), I will leave to the candid reader to consider the distinction between laying out very
    significant and obvious violations of rights of members of this court, and revealing, in contravention
    of long-honored custom, the internal votes of members of this court.
    Legitimacy protected only by our silence is fleeting. If any damage has been done to the
    court, it is the work of the actors, not the reporters.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 101
    _________________
    DISSENT
    _________________
    SILER, Circuit Judge, dissenting. I concur in the dissent by Judge Boggs on the merits. I
    write separately for the reason that I do not concur in the addition of the procedural appendix, not
    because I question its accuracy, but because I feel that it is unnecessary for the resolution of this case.
    If the procedural appendix were not filed, then the responses filed in the concurrences by Judges
    Moore and Clay would also have been unnecessary.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 102
    _______________
    DISSENT
    _______________
    ALICE M. BATCHELDER, Circuit Judge, dissenting. I concur in Judge Boggs’s careful and
    scholarly dissent. I write separately to say that I concur in all of that dissent, including the exposition
    of the procedural history of the case. In her separate concurrence, Judge Moore expresses her belief
    that by revealing that history, Judge Boggs—and I, by concurring—undermine the legitimacy of the
    court and do harm to ourselves, this court and the nation. I believe that exactly the opposite is true.
    Public confidence in this court or any other is premised on the certainty that the court follows the
    rules in every case, regardless of the question that a particular case presents. Unless we expose to
    public view our failures to follow the court’s established procedures, our claim to legitimacy is
    illegitimate.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 103
    _______________
    DISSENT
    _______________
    RONALD LEE GILMAN, Circuit Judge, dissenting. Both the majority opinion and Judge
    Boggs’s dissent address the two key issues in this case: (1) whether diversity in higher education,
    including racial and ethnic diversity, is a compelling government interest, and (2) whether the
    University of Michigan Law School’s admissions policy is narrowly tailored to further that goal.
    There is much to be said for each viewpoint, but there are aspects of both opinions with which I do
    not agree. The majority opinion, in particular, reaches what I believe to be an erroneous conclusion
    regarding the narrow-tailoring challenge to the Law School’s admissions policy. Judge Boggs’s
    dissent, on the other hand, includes arguments in support of his position that the Law School’s
    admissions policy is not narrowly tailored that I find troublesome. Specifically, I am unpersuaded
    by his critique that no empirical link exists between a critical mass of minority students and the
    perceived educational benefits or his belief that race-neutral factors would be more likely to achieve
    the desired diversity of experience than reliance on an applicant’s race. I therefore feel compelled
    to write a separate dissenting opinion.
    The facts of the present case, in my opinion, eliminate the need to decide whether or not this
    court is bound by Justice Powell’s conclusion in Regents of the University of California v. Bakke,
    
    438 U.S. 265
     (1978), that educational diversity is a compelling government interest. Indeed, the
    principled disagreement between the majority opinion and Judge Boggs’s dissent as to the proper
    resolution of this issue underscores the confusion created by the various opinions in Bakke. No one
    disputes, however, that Bakke stands for the proposition that an admissions policy designed to further
    the interest of educational diversity is not narrowly tailored if it creates a two-track system for
    evaluating prospective students, where minorities are effectively insulated from competition with
    other applicants. 
    Id. at 319-20
     (holding that the University of California’s admissions system, which
    reserved a fixed number of places specifically for minority students, violated the Equal Protection
    Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment).
    The Law School’s admissions policy, in my view, creates such an impermissible system. I
    therefore believe that this court should assume, without deciding, that educational diversity—as
    defined by Justice Powell in Bakke—is a compelling government interest. Lyng v. Northwest Indian
    Cemetery Prot. Ass’n, 
    485 U.S. 439
    , 445 (1988) (“A fundamental and longstanding principle of
    judicial restraint requires that courts avoid reaching constitutional questions in advance of the
    necessity of deciding them.”). Several of our sister circuits have taken a similar approach. Johnson
    v. Bd. of Regents of Univ. of Georgia, 
    263 F.3d 1234
    , 1251 (11th Cir. 2001) (assuming that
    educational diversity is a compelling interest, but holding that the school’s admissions policy was
    not narrowly tailored); Tuttle v. Arlington County Sch. Bd., 
    195 F.3d 698
    , 705 (4th Cir. 1999) (per
    curiam) (same); Wessmann v. Gittens, 
    160 F.3d 790
    , 796 (1st Cir. 1998) (same).
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 104
    The primary problem with the Law School’s admissions policy is that the “critical mass” of
    minority students that it seeks to enroll is functionally indistinguishable from a quota. Whether
    viewed as a percentage or as an absolute number, the consistency in the minority student enrollment
    demonstrates that the Law School has for all practical purposes set aside a certain number of seats
    for minority students. See Judge Boggs’s discussion in Part II.B.2. of his dissent. The “critical
    mass” therefore appears to be a euphemism for the quota system that Bakke explicitly prohibits.
    I believe that the Law School’s pursuit of a critical mass of minority students has led to the
    creation of a two-track admissions system, not only in the sense that a minimum percentage of seats
    is set aside for under-represented minorities, but also because the Law School gives grossly
    disproportionate weight to race and ethnicity in order to achieve this critical mass. Judge Boggs’s
    discussion of the vastly divergent admissions rates for minority students as compared to all other
    applicants to the Law School, a divergence that cannot be ascribed to any factor other than their race
    or ethnicity, demonstrates this reality. In my view, Justice Powell’s opinion in Bakke unequivocally
    prohibits such a de facto dual admission system that applies one standard for minorities and another
    for all other students. Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 317
     (indicating approval of Harvard’s admissions plan,
    where “race or ethnic background may be deemed a ‘plus’ in a particular applicant’s file, yet it does
    not insulate the individual from comparison with all other candidates for the available seats”).
    Moreover, like Judge Boggs, I believe that the record establishes that race-neutral factors are
    nowhere near as significant in determining admissions as whether the applicant is an under-
    represented minority. The Law School’s policy of achieving a critical mass of minority students
    without giving comparable consideration to other aspects of diversity is irreconcilable with Justice
    Powell’s explanation of why a quota system represents an impermissible use of race in the
    admissions process:
    In a most fundamental sense the argument misconceives the nature of the state
    interest that would justify consideration of race or ethnic background. It is not an
    interest in simple ethnic diversity, in which a specified percentage of the student body
    is in effect guaranteed to be members of selected ethnic groups, with the remaining
    percentage an undifferentiated aggregation of students. The diversity that furthers
    a compelling state interest encompasses a far broader array of qualifications and
    characteristics of which racial or ethnic origin is but a single though important
    element. Petitioner’s special admission program, focused solely on ethnic diversity,
    would hinder rather than further attainment of genuine diversity.
    
    Id. at 315
     (Powell, J.) (emphasis omitted). In my view, this compels the conclusion that the Law
    School’s admissions policy is not narrowly tailored to serve the presumptively compelling
    government interest in a diverse student body. Simply put, an applicant’s race or ethnicity, even if
    not the only factor (other than LSAT scores and GPAs) that is taken into account, receives such
    grossly disproportionate weight as to violate the Equal Protection Clause.
    Nos. 01-1447/1516
    Grutter v. Bollinger
    Page 105
    The Law School, as the preceding discussion suggests, attempts to equate attaining a “critical
    mass” of minority students with the goal of achieving a diverse student body. But because the Law
    School’s goal of achieving a critical mass results in a two-track system that is functionally equivalent
    to a quota, its admissions policy is prohibited by Bakke. This is a quandry that admits of no easy
    solution.
    Is there any way, then, that race or ethnicity can ever be taken into account in a narrowly
    tailored manner that would survive strict scrutiny? Surely the answer is “Yes.” For example, in
    differentiating between two applicants with essentially equal LSAT scores and GPAs, where one is
    Caucasian and the other African-American, I have little doubt that favoring the under-represented
    African-American applicant would pass constitutional muster if educational diversity is recognized
    as a compelling government interest. This would clearly fall within the scope of what I believe
    Justice Powell had in mind when discussing the appropriate use of a “plus” for diversity in Bakke.
    The problem, according to the Law School, is that limiting the conscious favoritism of
    minorities to situations where the factor is a “plus among equals” would not likely produce the
    critical mass that it earnestly believes is essential to achieve a truly diverse student body. On the
    other hand, such an admissions policy would presumably avoid the animosities stirred up by the
    common perception that admitted minority students are less qualified than their nonminority peers.
    See Bakke, 
    438 U.S. at 298
     (Powell, J.) (“[P]referential programs may only reinforce common
    stereotypes holding that certain groups are unable to achieve success without special protection based
    on a factor having no relationship to individual worth.”) (citing DeFunis v. Odegaard, 
    416 U.S. 312
    ,
    343 (1974) (Douglass, J., dissenting)).
    But these competing considerations are matters that need not, and cannot, be resolved by the
    case before us. Based on the record presented, I am convinced that the Law School’s admissions
    policy that results in a de facto quota in favor of minority students is far closer to the rigid set-aside
    squarely prohibited by Bakke than it is to the “plus among equals” that I believe would be clearly
    constitutional. How close the Law School would have to come to the latter end of the spectrum in
    order for its admissions policy to survive the strict-scrutiny test should, in my opinion, await another
    day, a day when a more narrowly tailored policy is formulated and presented for resolution. In the
    meantime, I respectfully dissent.
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 01-1516

Filed Date: 5/14/2002

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 3/3/2016

Authorities (54)

McLeod v. J. E. Dilworth Co. , 64 S. Ct. 1023 ( 1944 )

Brown v. Board of Education , 74 S. Ct. 686 ( 1954 )

Regents of the University of California v. Bakke , 98 S. Ct. 2733 ( 1978 )

A Book Named "John Cleland's Memoirs of a Woman of Pleasure"... , 86 S. Ct. 975 ( 1966 )

Gregg v. Georgia , 96 S. Ct. 2909 ( 1976 )

United States v. Paradise , 107 S. Ct. 1053 ( 1987 )

womens-medical-professional-corporation-martin-haskell-md-v-george , 130 F.3d 187 ( 1997 )

joseph-m-popovich-plaintiff-appelleecross-appellant-v-cuyahoga-county , 276 F.3d 808 ( 2002 )

doris-simmons-harris-marla-franklin-steven-behr-rev-sue-gatton-mary , 234 F.3d 945 ( 2000 )

Griffin v. Wisconsin , 107 S. Ct. 3164 ( 1987 )

Lyng v. Northwest Indian Cemetery Protective Assn. , 108 S. Ct. 1319 ( 1988 )

City of Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co. , 109 S. Ct. 706 ( 1989 )

Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey , 112 S. Ct. 2791 ( 1992 )

Grutter v. Bollinger , 137 F. Supp. 2d 821 ( 2001 )

Triplett Grille, Inc., D/B/A the Back Door v. City of Akron , 40 F.3d 129 ( 1994 )

John L. Wright v. Terry L. Morris , 111 F.3d 414 ( 1997 )

dls-inc-dba-diamonds-and-lace-showbar-a-tennessee-corporation-ann , 107 F.3d 403 ( 1997 )

bob-alice-mozert-individually-and-as-guardians-ad-litem-for-travis , 827 F.2d 1058 ( 1987 )

Sweatt v. Painter , 70 S. Ct. 848 ( 1950 )

Agostini v. Felton , 117 S. Ct. 1997 ( 1997 )

View All Authorities »