United States v. Billy Jo Lara ( 2003 )


Menu:
  •                      United States Court of Appeals
    FOR THE EIGHTH CIRCUIT
    ___________
    No. 01-3695
    ___________
    United States of America,                *
    *
    Appellee,                   *
    * Appeal from the United States
    v.                                 * District Court for the
    * District of North Dakota.
    Billy Jo Lara, also known as             *
    Billy Joe Lara,                          *
    *
    Appellant.                  *
    ___________
    Submitted: September 11, 2002
    Filed: March 24, 2003
    ___________
    Before HANSEN, Chief Judge, McMILLIAN, BOWMAN, WOLLMAN, LOKEN,
    MORRIS SHEPPARD ARNOLD, MURPHY, BYE, RILEY, MELLOY,
    and SMITH, Circuit Judges, En Banc.
    ___________
    WOLLMAN, Circuit Judge.
    After a Spirit Lake Nation Reservation tribal court convicted him of assaulting
    a police officer, Billy Jo Lara was indicted by the federal government for assault on
    a federal officer in violation of 
    18 U.S.C. § 111
    (a)(1). Lara moved to dismiss the
    indictment on double jeopardy and selective prosecution grounds. Following the
    district court’s denial of the motion, Lara entered a conditional plea of guilty to the
    indictment, reserving his right to appeal the denial of his motion to dismiss. A panel
    of this court affirmed, holding that because the power of the Spirit Lake Nation
    derives from its retained sovereignty and not from Congressionally delegated
    authority, Lara’s conviction on the federal charge did not run afoul of the Double
    Jeopardy Clause. We granted Lara’s petition for rehearing en banc, vacating the
    panel’s opinion and judgment. We now reverse.
    I.
    While on the Spirit Lake Nation Reservation on June 13, 2001, Lara was
    arrested for public intoxication by Bureau of Indian Affairs police officers. The
    officers informed Lara, who is not a member of the Spirit Lake Nation, of an
    exclusion order prohibiting him from entering the reservation. Upon hearing of the
    exclusion order, Lara struck one of the officers with his fist. Lara was charged with
    five violations of Spirit Lake Tribal Code: violence to a policeman, resisting lawful
    arrest, public intoxication, disobedience to a lawful order of the tribal court, and
    trespassing. On June 15, Lara pled guilty to the first three charged offenses and was
    sentenced to a jail term of 155 days. On August 29, a federal grand jury returned an
    indictment charging Lara with assault on a federal officer in violation of 
    18 U.S.C. § 111
    (a)(1). After consenting to proceed before a United States Magistrate Judge,
    Lara moved to dismiss the indictment on double jeopardy and selective prosecution
    grounds or, in the alternative, that discovery be allowed on the claim of selective
    prosecution. As recounted above, the magistrate judge denied the motions, and Lara
    entered a plea of guilty conditioned on his right to seek appellate review of his motion
    to dismiss the indictment.
    II.
    We review de novo the denial of a motion to dismiss on double jeopardy
    grounds. United States v. Alverez, 
    235 F.3d 1086
    , 1089-90 (8th Cir. 2000). The
    Double Jeopardy Clause of the Fifth Amendment provides that no person shall “be
    -2-
    subject for the same offence to be twice put in jeopardy of life or limb.” The right to
    be free from multiple prosecutions is limited by the dual sovereignty doctrine, which
    permits an independent sovereign to prosecute an individual who has been prosecuted
    by another sovereign for the same act. One who violates the laws of two independent
    sovereigns commits an offense against each, and thus a second prosecution is not for
    “the same offence.” Heath v. Alabama, 
    474 U.S. 82
    , 88 (1985).
    The application of the dual sovereignty doctrine “turns on whether the two
    entities draw their authority to punish the offender from distinct sources of power.”
    
    Id.
     The Double Jeopardy Clause does not permit successive prosecutions under the
    dual sovereignty doctrine where the authority for the prosecution derives from the
    same sovereign source. See, e.g., Waller v. Florida, 
    397 U.S. 387
    , 393-95 (1970) (a
    city and its parent state); Puerto Rico v. Shell Co., 
    302 U.S. 253
    , 264-66 (1937) (the
    federal government and a territorial government); Unites States v. Mills, 
    964 F.2d 1186
    , 1193 (D.C. Cir. 1992) (en banc) (the federal government and the District of
    Columbia). Conversely, the dual sovereignty doctrine permits a state to prosecute a
    defendant who has previously been prosecuted for the same act by another state or the
    federal government. Heath, 
    474 U.S. at 93
     (two states); Bartkus v. Illinois, 
    359 U.S. 121
    , 139 (1959) (upholding state prosecution following federal prosecution); United
    States v. Williams, 
    104 F.3d 213
    , 216 (8th Cir. 1997) (upholding federal prosecution
    following state prosecution). Consequently, whether the dual sovereignty doctrine
    applies to Lara’s double jeopardy challenge turns on whether the Spirit Lake Nation
    exercised sovereign authority emanating from a sovereign source distinct from that
    of the overriding federal sovereign.
    In Oliphant v. Suquamish Indian Tribe, 
    435 U.S. 191
     (1978), the Supreme
    Court held that a tribe had no inherent power to prosecute non-Indian residents of its
    reservation. “By submitting to the overriding sovereignty of the United States, Indian
    tribes therefore necessarily give up their power to try non-Indian citizens of the
    United States except in a manner acceptable to Congress.” 
    Id. at 210
    . In United
    -3-
    States v. Wheeler, the defendant raised a double jeopardy challenge to a federal
    prosecution commenced after Wheeler, an enrolled member of the tribe, had been
    convicted in tribal court on a lesser included offense. 
    435 U.S. 313
    , 315-16 (1978).
    Wheeler argued that because Congress has plenary authority to abrogate tribal
    sovereignty, the tribe was in effect an arm of the federal government. 
    Id. at 319
    . The
    Court explained that its dual sovereignty precedents did not turn on the extent of
    control one sovereign had over another, but whether the two prosecutions exercised
    authority derived from the same ultimate source of power. 
    Id. at 319-20
    . The Court
    held that among the “unique and limited” sovereign powers retained by the tribe was
    the power to punish “members of the Tribe for violations of tribal law.” 
    Id.
     at 323-
    24. The distinction expressly and repeatedly drawn by the Court was not premised
    on the racial status of the defendant but on his membership status. Although tribes
    retained authority over their internal affairs, they had been implicitly or explicitly
    divested of authority over nonmembers. 
    Id. at 324-25
    . “The areas in which such
    implicit divestiture of sovereignty has been held to have occurred are those involving
    the relations between an Indian tribe and nonmembers of the tribe.” 
    Id. at 326
    .
    Because Wheeler was an enrolled member of the tribe, he was prosecuted pursuant
    to an inherent sovereign power that had never been divested from the tribe, and thus
    subsequent federal prosecution for the same act was not barred. 
    Id. at 332
    .
    In Montana v. United States, 
    450 U.S. 544
     (1981), the Court again emphasized
    the distinction between the retained or inherent sovereignty over internal relations
    between members of the tribe and the sovereignty over external relations that
    necessarily had been divested from the tribes. “[T]he dependent status of Indian
    tribes within our territorial jurisdiction is necessarily inconsistent with their freedom
    independently to determine their external relations.” 
    Id. at 564
     (quoting Wheeler,
    
    435 U.S. at 326
    , emphasis added by Montana Court). The Court held that the tribe’s
    retained inherent sovereignty did not authorize it to regulate hunting and fishing by
    nonmembers on reservation land owned in fee by nonmembers. Id. at 564-65.
    -4-
    The question of what power a tribe has over nonmember Indians was addressed
    in Duro v. Reina, 
    495 U.S. 676
     (1990). Duro, an enrolled member of a different tribe,
    was charged in Pima-Maricopa Indian Community Court with unlawful firing of a
    weapon, a misdemeanor, in connection with the death of an Indian boy. 
    Id. at 679-81
    .
    His motion to dismiss for lack of jurisdiction was denied. 
    Id. at 681-82
    . Because the
    Salt River Pima-Maricopa Indian Community did not claim that its jurisdiction over
    Dura stemmed from Congressionally delegated authority, the Court was faced with
    the question whether the tribe’s retained or inherent sovereignty provided it with
    jurisdiction over a nonmember Indian. The Court held that it did not. 
    Id. at 688
     (“In
    the area of criminal enforcement, however, tribal power does not extend beyond
    internal relations among members.”).
    In response to the decision in Duro, Congress amended the Indian Civil Rights
    Act (ICRA), 
    25 U.S.C. § 1301
    , by revising the definition of “powers of self-
    government” to include “the inherent power of Indian tribes, hereby recognized and
    affirmed, to exercise criminal jurisdiction over all Indians.” 
    25 U.S.C. § 1301
    (2).
    The amendment also defined “Indian” to include all Indians subject to federal
    jurisdiction under the Indian Major Crimes Act, 
    18 U.S.C. § 1153
    . 
    25 U.S.C. § 1301
    (4). Thus, under the ICRA amendments, Indians who are enrolled members of
    a federally recognized tribe are subject to the jurisdiction of all tribes.
    Although the Supreme Court has not yet construed the post-Duro ICRA
    amendments, it has repeatedly reaffirmed its holdings limiting tribal sovereign
    authority to tribe members. Atkinson Trading Co. v. Shirley, 
    532 U.S. 645
     (2001)
    (rejecting under the Montana test the imposition of a hotel occupancy tax on
    nonmember-owned reservation hotel on non-Indian fee land); Nevada v. Hicks, 
    533 U.S. 353
    , 358-59 (2001) (citing Oliphant for the general rule that “the inherent
    sovereign powers of an Indian tribe do not extend to the activities of nonmembers of
    the tribe”).
    -5-
    Although Indian tribes retain inherent authority to punish members who
    violate tribal law, to regulate tribal membership, and to conduct internal
    tribal relations, United States v. Wheeler, 
    435 U.S. 313
    , 326 (1978), the
    “exercise of tribal power beyond what is necessary to protect tribal self-
    government or to control internal relations is inconsistent with the
    dependent status of the tribes, and so cannot survive without express
    congressional delegation.” Montana, 
    450 U.S. at 564
    .
    South Dakota v. Bourland, 
    508 U.S. 679
    , 694-95 (1993).
    In United States v. Weaselhead, 
    156 F.3d 818
     (8th Cir. 1998), we construed the
    ICRA amendments in a double jeopardy case factually similar to the present case.
    The district court had held that Duro and Oliphant were federal common law
    decisions within the ultimate authority of Congress to overrule. 
    36 F. Supp. 2d 908
    ,
    914-15 (D. Neb. 1997). A divided panel of this court reversed, concluding that
    “ascertainment of first principles regarding the position of Indian tribes within our
    constitutional structure of government is a matter ultimately entrusted to the Court
    and thus beyond the scope of Congress’s authority to alter retroactively by legislative
    fiat.” 
    156 F.3d at 824
    . On rehearing en banc, the panel opinion was vacated and the
    district court affirmed by an evenly divided court. 
    165 F.3d 1209
     (8th Cir. 1999).
    The Ninth Circuit has held Duro to be a common law decision that Congress
    had the power to override via the ICRA amendments. United States v. Enas, 
    255 F.3d 662
     (9th Cir. 2001) (en banc), cert. denied 
    534 U.S. 1115
     (2002). Although the Enas
    court conceded that sovereignty has “constitutional implications,” 
    id. at 673
    , it
    concluded that the lack of an express citation to a constitutional provision indicated
    that Duro was a common law decision, an area in which Congress is supreme. 
    Id. at 674-75
    .
    With all due respect to the holding in Enas, we conclude that the distinction
    between a tribe’s inherent and delegated powers is of constitutional magnitude and
    -6-
    therefore is a matter ultimately entrusted to the Supreme Court. Absent a delegation
    from Congress, a tribe’s powers are those “inherent powers of a limited sovereignty
    which has never been extinguished.” Wheeler, 435 U.S. at 322 (quoting F. Cohen,
    Handbook of Federal Indian Law 122 (1945)) (emphasis omitted). Once the federal
    sovereign divests a tribe of a particular power, it is no longer an inherent power and
    it may only be restored by delegation of Congress’s power.
    Congress’s broad authority over Indian affairs derives from and is limited by
    the Constitution. Some decisions root this power in the Indian Commerce Clause.
    Alaska v. Native Village of Venetie Tribal Government, 
    522 U.S. 520
    , 531 n.6
    (1998); McClanahan v. Arizona, 
    411 U.S. 164
    , 172 n.7 (1973). Prior to 1903, the
    federal government negotiated agreements with Indian tribes pursuant to its treaty
    power, U.S. Const. art. II, § 2, cl. 2, but the combination of an 1871 statute and the
    development of the plenary power doctrine ended this process. Antoine v.
    Washington, 
    420 U.S. 194
    , 201-04 (1975). The Supreme Court has suggested that
    we must be guided in part by structural principles that are both implicit and explicit
    in the Constitution. See Seminole Tribe v. Florida, 
    517 U.S. 44
     (1996); see also
    Duro, 
    495 U.S. at 684
     (“The question we must answer is whether the sovereignty
    retained by the tribes in their dependent status within our scheme of government
    includes the power of criminal jurisdiction over nonmembers.”). Some decisions
    have found plenary authority in the government’s trust responsibility, Stephens v.
    Cherokee Nation, 
    174 U.S. 445
    , 478 (1899), or in the guardian-ward relationship
    between the federal government and the tribes, Morton v. Mancari, 
    417 U.S. 535
    , 551
    (1974), but references to these non-constitutional sources of power have largely been
    supplanted by a reliance on the commerce power. See, e.g., Alaska v. Native Village,
    
    522 U.S. at
    531 n.6.
    The ICRA amendments are “a legislative enactment purporting to recast history
    in a manner that alters the Supreme Court’s stated understanding of the organizing
    principles by which the Indian tribes were incorporated into our constitutional system
    -7-
    of government.” Weaselhead, 
    156 F.3d at 823
    . In exercising its commerce power,
    Congress may not “override a constitutional decision by simply rewriting the history
    upon which it is based.” Enas, 
    255 F.3d at 675
    . Duro’s determination of first
    principles regarding Indian sovereignty within the federal system of government is
    ultimately one for the Court. The Court reaffirmed this principle subsequent to the
    ICRA amendments:
    The dissent’s complaint that we give “barely a nod” to the Tribe’s
    inherent sovereignty argument is simply another manifestation of its
    disagreement with Montana, which announced “the general proposition
    that the inherent sovereign powers of an Indian tribe do not extend to the
    activities of nonmembers of the tribe[.]” 
    450 U.S. at 565
    . While the
    dissent refers to our “myopic focus” on the Tribe’s prior treaty right to
    “absolute and undisturbed use and occupation” of the taken area, it shuts
    both eyes to the reality that after Montana, tribal sovereignty over
    nonmembers “cannot survive without express congressional delegation,”
    
    450 U.S. at 564
    , and is therefore not inherent.
    Bourland, 
    508 U.S. at
    695 n.15 (internal citations omitted). Thus the ICRA
    amendments cannot have the effect that they plainly sought to achieve: a retroactive
    legislative reversal of Duro. We need not construe the ICRA amendments as a legal
    nullity, however. It is apparent that Congress wished to allow tribes to exercise
    criminal misdemeanor jurisdiction over nonmember Indians. See Hicks, 
    533 U.S. at
    377 n.2 (“In response to our decision in Duro, . . . Congress passed a statute expressly
    granting tribal courts [jurisdiction over nonmember Indians].”) (Souter, J.,
    concurring). Nothing in our decision today in any way circumscribes the jurisdiction
    so conferred.
    The Spirit Lake Nation exercises authority over external relations only to the
    extent that such a power has been delegated to it by Congress. As a nonmember, Lara
    was necessarily prosecuted pursuant to that delegated power. Because the dual
    sovereignty doctrine does not apply where the ultimate source of power is the same,
    -8-
    the Double Jeopardy Clause bars the government from maintaining a second
    prosecution for the same act. Accordingly, the motion to dismiss the indictment
    should have been granted.
    The order denying the motion to dismiss on double jeopardy grounds is
    reversed, and the case is remanded to the district court with directions to dismiss the
    indictment.
    MORRIS SHEPPARD ARNOLD, Circuit Judge, dissenting, in which BOWMAN,
    MURPHY, and SMITH, Circuit Judges, join.
    The essential difficulty that I see with the result that the court reaches today is
    that the Supreme Court in Duro v. Reina, 
    495 U.S. 676
     (1990), did not base its
    decision on the Constitution, nor did the Constitution require the result that the Court
    reached there. The result in that case was instead based on federal common law,
    nothing more and nothing less, and in the ICRA amendments Congress exercised its
    plenary legislative power over federal common law in general and Indian affairs in
    particular to define the scope of inherent Indian sovereignty. In other words,
    Congress restored to the tribes a power that they had previously exercised but had lost
    over the years as a result of Supreme Court decisions. Because the Spirit Lake
    Nation, in trying Mr. Lara, was simply exercising its own sovereignty, and not a
    power that Congress delegated to it, Mr. Lara’s double jeopardy rights were not
    violated.
    I.
    According to current legal thought, Indian tribes possessed criminal
    jurisdiction over nonmember Indians as part of their full territorial sovereignty prior
    to colonization by us or our European predecessors. See Duro, 
    495 U.S. at 685-86
    .
    The Supreme Court held in Duro, however, that the Indians had lost this aspect of
    -9-
    their sovereignty because of their “dependent” status. See id.; cf. Oliphant v.
    Squamish Indian Tribe, 
    435 U.S. 191
    , 210 (1978).
    The court opines in the present case that “[o]nce the federal sovereign divests
    a tribe of a particular power, it is no longer an inherent power and it may only be
    restored by delegation of Congress’s power.” This holding draws on statements in
    Supreme Court opinions that a tribe’s inherent sovereignty consists of those aspects
    of sovereignty that the tribes “retained” despite the federal government’s overriding
    sovereignty. See, e.g., Duro, 
    495 U.S. at 685
    . The court’s apparent premise is that
    power cannot be a retained one once the Supreme Court holds that it no longer exists.
    This premise, however, fails both as a matter of history and of logic.
    Historically, it misapprehends the materials that the Supreme Court has used over the
    years to fashion the relationship between the United States and Indian tribes;
    logically, it improperly assumes that there is only one way that a power can be
    retained. In my view, the ICRA amendments did not create a new tribal power out
    of whole cloth, it merely relaxed a common-law restriction on a power previously
    possessed. Regardless of the fact that the ICRA amendments are a “but-for” cause
    of the Spirit Lake Nation’s ability to try Mr. Lara here (which of course they
    necessarily are), the origin of that power was not the ICRA amendments themselves
    but the full territorial sovereignty that the tribes possessed in the past. Cf. Prudential
    Ins. Co. v. Benjamin, 
    328 U.S. 408
    , 421-33, 437-38 (1946). Thus, the power at hand
    is a “retained” one, even if it had been rendered temporarily unavailable by decisions
    of the United States Supreme Court.
    A.
    Three cases from the early nineteenth century, all of which Chief Justice
    Marshall wrote, provided a foundation for federal Indian law: Johnson v. McIntosh,
    21 U.S. (8 Wheat) 543 (1823), Cherokee Nation v. Georgia, 30 U.S. (5 Peters)
    1 (1831), and Worcester v. Georgia, 31 U.S. (6 Peters) 515 (1832). An examination
    -10-
    of these cases shows that in forging the legal relationship between Indian tribes and
    the government of the United States, “the Supreme Court in the Marshall trilogy
    embraced pre-constitutional notions of the colonial process, rooted in the law of
    nations, involving both inherent tribal sovereignty and a colonial prerogative vested
    exclusively in the centralized government.” See Philip P. Frickey, Domesticating
    Federal Indian Law, 
    81 Minn. L. Rev. 31
    , 57 (1996). These principles, which the
    Supreme Court created from extra-constitutional sources, have “been consistently
    followed by the courts for more than a hundred years.” See Felix S. Cohen,
    Handbook of Federal Indian Law 123 (1988); cf. Frickey, supra, at 58-60.
    In McIntosh, 21 U.S. at 573, Chief Justice Marshall justified federal power over
    Indian tribes in terms of the right of discovery, a euphemism for the right of conquest,
    see Judith Resnik, Multiple Sovereignties: Indian Tribes, States, and the Federal
    Government, 79 Judicature 118, 119 (1995). That this right was universally
    recognized, he asserted, was “prove[d]” by “the history of America from its discovery
    to the present day.” McIntosh, 21 U.S. at 574. As Judge Canby has explained, “[t]he
    principles of discovery were, of course, European (and, by adoption, federal) law
    [and] in Marshall’s view that was the only kind of law that the Supreme Court could
    apply.” William C. Canby, Jr., Federal Indian Law 69 (3d ed. 1998).
    Eight years later in Cherokee Nation, 30 U.S. at 16-17, Chief Justice Marshall
    held that Indian tribes were foreign states, but ones with a special relationship to the
    United States, namely, that “of a ward to his guardian.” In making this determination,
    the Chief Justice looked not to the Constitution but, as in McIntosh, to the uniform
    custom of nations and the history of our country’s dealings with Indian tribes. See
    id. at 16-18. The next year in Worcester, 31 U.S. at 555, Chief Justice Marshall
    wrote that the relationship of the Cherokees to the United States “was that of a nation
    claiming and receiving the protection of one more powerful: not that of individuals
    abandoning their national character, and submitting as subjects to the laws of a
    -11-
    master.” He then held that under international law the Indian tribes retained the right
    to self-government, because
    [t]he very fact of repeated treaties with them recognizes it; and the settled
    doctrine of the law of nations is, that a weaker power does not surrender
    its independence--its right to self-government, by associating with a
    stronger, and taking its protection. A weak state, in order to provide for
    its own safety, may place itself under the protection of one more
    powerful, without stripping itself of the right of government, and ceasing
    to be a state.
    Id. at 560-61.
    At the end of the century, the Court reaffirmed these sentiments in United
    States v. Kagama, 
    118 U.S. 375
     (1886). A few years before that case, in Ex Parte
    Crow Dog, 
    109 U.S. 556
     (1883), the Court had held that the murder of an Indian by
    another Indian in Indian country was within the sole jurisdiction of the tribe, and so
    federal territorial courts had no power over such a crime. Congress reacted by
    passing the Indian Major Crimes Act, 
    18 U.S.C. § 1153
    , declaring murder and other
    serious crimes committed by an Indian in Indian country to be federal offenses triable
    in federal court. In Kagama, the Court upheld the constitutionality of the act, despite
    the fact that the Constitution “is almost silent in regard to the relations of the
    government which was established by it to the numerous tribes of Indians within its
    borders,” 
    118 U.S. at 378
    , and even though the Court was “not able to see in [any
    clause] of the constitution and its amendments any delegation of power to enact a
    code of criminal law for the punishment of [serious crimes],” 
    id. at 379
    . Rather, the
    Court concluded, the legitimacy of the act derived from extra-constitutional sources,
    such as its necessity for the Indians’ protection and the fact that the power to pass the
    act “must exist in th[e federal] government because it never has existed anywhere
    else; because the theater of its exercise is within the geographical limits of the United
    States; because it has never been denied; and because it alone can enforce its laws on
    all the tribes.” 
    Id. at 384-85
    .
    -12-
    Unlike Kagama, which addressed the question of whether a grant of federal
    criminal jurisdiction in Indian country was consistent with the federal government’s
    role as “guardian,” Oliphant, United States v. Wheeler, 
    435 U.S. 313
     (1978), and
    Duro, addressed the converse question, that is, whether the retention of certain
    criminal jurisdiction in Indian country was consistent with the Indian tribe’s role as
    “ward.” Despite this difference, all four cases reached their answers in the same way,
    namely, by reference to governmental custom and practice and to the general
    principles of the jus gentium. What is importantly missing from all of these cases is
    the slightest intimation that their outcome was dictated by some substantive
    constitutional principle.
    In Wheeler, 435 U.S. at 324-26, for instance, the Court analyzed various
    statutes establishing federal criminal jurisdiction over crimes involving Indians, and
    described how these statutes had left in place tribal criminal jurisdiction over
    members as part of the inherent sovereign power of Indian tribes. In discussing why
    none of these statutes had divested the Indians of this power, the Court restated the
    sentiments expressed in Worcester that the “ ‘settled doctrine of the law of nations is,
    that a weaker power does not surrender its independence--its right to self-government,
    by associating with a stronger, and taking its protection.’ “ See Wheeler, 
    435 U.S. at 326
     (quoting Worcester, 31 U.S. at 560-61). Wheeler thus quite clearly decided
    that tribes retained criminal jurisdiction over tribal matters as a matter of federal
    common law.
    Although neither Oliphant nor Duro ever explicitly stated that it was a
    common-law decision, or referred to the law of nations, these decisions too were
    founded on federal common law. See, e.g., Canby, supra, at 127; Philip P. Frickey,
    A Common Law for our Age of Colonialism: The Judicial Divestiture of Indian Tribal
    Authority over Nonmembers, 
    109 Yale L.J. 1
    , 65 (1999); L. Scott Gould, The
    Consent Paradigm: Tribal Sovereignty at the Millennium, 
    96 Colum. L. Rev. 809
    ,
    -13-
    853 (1996). In both cases, the Court analyzed history and governmental custom and
    devised from them the principle that, as a result of the dependent status of Indian
    tribes, tribal criminal enforcement power did not extend beyond internal relations
    among its members. See Duro, 
    495 U.S. at 685-92
    ; Oliphant, 
    435 U.S. at 196-210
    ;
    cf. United States v. Enas, 
    255 F.3d 662
    , 668-69 (9th Cir. 2001) (en banc), cert.
    denied, 
    534 U.S. 1115
     (2002).
    The Court in Duro did say that any power delegated to the tribes would be
    “subject to the constraints of the Constitution,” 
    495 U.S. at 686
    , and that there would
    be due process concerns in subjecting nonmember Indians to trial in tribal courts
    because those courts did not provide constitutional protections as a matter of right,
    see 
    id. at 693-94
    . But none of this can serve to convert Duro into a “constitutional”
    decision. A decision is “constitutional” only when it states, or necessarily implies,
    that the Constitution requires the result that it reaches.
    In Duro, as in all cases, the Court had the obligation and the power under
    Article III to decide the case before it and “to say what the law is.” Marbury v.
    Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 177 (1803). Without any statute stating whether
    Indian tribes had criminal jurisdiction over nonmember Indians, it acted as a
    common-law court, using whatever sources were relevant and readily at hand to
    ascertain the applicable legal principles and to answer the question before it. As with
    all federal common law, however, Congress has the legislative authority to revise the
    result in Duro in whatever way it desires.
    B.
    The court holds that Duro’s distinction between inherent and delegated powers
    is of “constitutional magnitude.” I take that to be a claim that Duro was based on the
    Constitution and, therefore, that the Court’s determination in Duro of what constitutes
    inherent tribal sovereignty is final and binding on Congress. The court, however,
    never says precisely where in the Constitution principles of Indian sovereignty might
    -14-
    actually reside. Cf. United States v. Weaselhead, 
    156 F.3d 818
    , 825 (8th Cir. 1998)
    (M.S. Arnold, J., dissenting).
    The court does provide two possibilities. First, it refers to “structural principles
    that are both implicit and explicit in the Constitution,” citing Duro and Seminole
    Tribe. The court, however, does not describe what these structural principles are, nor
    does it explain why they derived from the Constitution. In fact, “no court has [ever]
    found a constitutionally protectible interest in tribal sovereignty itself,” Canby, supra,
    at 85; and, “[t]o the extent that Indian tribes are discussed in the Constitution, they
    seem to be recognized as having a status outside its” perimeters, Judith Resnik,
    Dependent Sovereigns: Indian Tribes, States, and the Federal Courts, 
    56 U. Chi. L. Rev. 671
    , 691 (1989).
    Perhaps the proposition that the court is urging is that since certain attributes
    of state sovereignty derive from the structure of the Constitution, see, e.g., Alden v.
    Maine, 
    527 U.S. 706
    , 724 (1999), the perimeters of inherent tribal sovereignty must
    do so as well. That proposition, however, fails to recognize the fact that “[u]nlike
    states, which ceded some sovereignty with the passage of the Constitution, Indian
    tribes did not.” Resnik, Multiple Sovereignties, supra, at 119. The Indian tribes did
    not participate in the making of the Constitution, so its structure cannot tell us
    anything about the extent of their sovereignty. Cf. Worcester, 31 U.S. at 555, 559-60;
    Martha A. Field, Sources of Law: The Scope of Federal Common Law, 
    99 Harv. L. Rev. 881
    , 949 (1986). Thus, as Chief Justice Marshall noted in Worcester, Indian
    nations, such as the Cherokees in Worcester, remained “distinct, independent political
    communities” even after the adoption of the Constitution. Worcester, 31 U.S. at
    559-61. The status of Indian tribes in our constitutional order is thus more akin to
    that of foreign nations than to that of the states.
    Second, the court points out that in recent years references to “non-
    constitutional sources of [Congress’s plenary power] have largely been supplanted
    -15-
    by a reliance on the [Indian] commerce power.” But the fact that the scope of the
    Indian commerce power has expanded in recent years and is now often seen as the
    source of legislation that regulates the Indians as dependent communities, e.g., Alaska
    v. Native Vill. of Venetie Tribal Gov’t, 
    522 U.S. 520
    , 531 n.6 (1998), does not mean
    that the traditional view of the origins of the relationship between Indian tribes and
    the United States has somehow been submerged. When pressed for a source of
    Congress’s plenary authority, the Court tends increasingly to rely on the Indian
    commerce clause, I think, simply because in the particular context, it sees no need to
    look further.
    The source of Congress’s plenary power is in any case beside the point:
    Regardless of its source, it is well settled that Congress’s power is plenary. It is a
    non sequitur to intimate that because the source of the plenary power may have
    changed from a “non-constitutional” to a constitutional source, Congress’s ability to
    legislate is somehow circumscribed. If that were true, then Congress’s authority
    would no longer be plenary. Cf. Lone Wolf v. Hitchcock, 
    187 U.S. 553
    , 565 (1903).
    Even if the mere existence of the Indian commerce clause somehow restricted
    the powers that tribes inherently possess, moreover, inherent tribal sovereignty would
    still be a matter of federal common law. Consider, as an analogy, dormant commerce
    clause restrictions on state legislation that unduly burdens interstate commerce. A
    court can invalidate a state law on dormant commerce clause grounds, but Congress
    can reverse the court’s decision and authorize the state to re-enact the legislation:
    Dormant commerce clause prohibitions are thus considered federal common law.
    See, e.g., Adrian Vermeule, Three Commerce Clauses? No Problem, 
    55 Ark. L. Rev. 1175
    , 1175 (2003); cf. Frickey, A Common Law, supra, at 71-72. Thus, no matter
    how one views the matter, Congress retains legislative authority to determine
    prospectively what power tribes inherently possess.
    -16-
    C.
    The court also relies on South Dakota v. Bourland, 
    508 U.S. 679
     (1993), a case
    that it notes was decided “subsequent to the ICRA amendments.” The Supreme Court
    in that case did state that the exercise of tribal power beyond what is necessary to
    control internal relations is not inherent and therefore cannot survive without express
    congressional delegation, see 
    id.
     at 694-95 & n.15, and our subsequent case law is
    replete with similar statements. But, as always, language must be understood in
    context, and the context in which these statements were made was different in a way
    that makes the present case legally distinguishable.
    Although Bourland and some other cases that were decided after the ICRA
    amendments, e.g., Nevada v. Hicks, 
    533 U.S. 353
     (2001), have addressed inherent and
    delegated powers, they did not involve the amendments. The question raised here,
    namely, whether Congress could restore aspects of sovereignty to tribes, rather than
    delegate power to it, therefore did not arise in those cases and could not have been
    decided by them. It is only if Congress does not have the power to restore aspects of
    Indian sovereignty that delegation becomes the only option. In my opinion, the
    statements in cases such as Oliphant and Duro that the jurisdiction in question was
    not inherent and could only be delegated by Congress described what would be true
    absent the sort of legislation that we have before us. Cf. Hicks, 
    533 U.S. at
    377 n.2
    (Souter, J., concurring).
    II.
    In reaching its conclusion, the court rejects a contrary result by a unanimous
    eleven-judge court in Enas, 
    255 F.3d 662
    . Though the rationales in the two opinions
    in that case differed somewhat, all of the judges agreed that the inherent sovereignty
    of Indian tribes was a matter of federal common law, not constitutional law. For the
    reasons that I have tried to explain, that conclusion seems to me to be ineluctable.
    -17-
    The basic question in this case is whether providing tribes with the inherent
    power to try nonmember Indians for crimes falls within Congress’s plenary authority
    over Indian affairs (which the court agrees that Congress has). In light of the
    Supreme Court pronouncement that all “aspect[s] of tribal sovereignty ... [are] subject
    to plenary federal control and definition,” see Three Affiliated Tribes of Fort Berthold
    Reservation v. Wold Eng’g, 
    476 U.S. 877
    , 891 (1986), it seems to me that the only
    possible answer to that question is that Congress can do what it quite plainly sought
    to do here.
    I therefore respectfully dissent.
    A true copy.
    Attest:
    CLERK, U.S. COURT OF APPEALS, EIGHTH CIRCUIT.
    -18-