Animal Legal Defense Fund v. Kimberly Reynolds ( 2021 )


Menu:
  •                  United States Court of Appeals
    For the Eighth Circuit
    ___________________________
    No. 19-1364
    ___________________________
    Animal Legal Defense Fund; Iowa Citizens for Community Improvement; Bailing
    Out Benji; People for The Ethical Treatment of Animals, Inc.; Center for Food Safety,
    lllllllllllllllllllllPlaintiffs - Appellees,
    v.
    Kimberly Reynolds; Tom Miller, Attorney General of Iowa; Drew B. Swanson,
    Montgomery County Attorney,
    lllllllllllllllllllllDefendants - Appellants.
    ------------------------------
    Brooke Kroeger; Ted Conover; Iowa Federation of Labor, AFL-CIO; Scholars of
    First Amendment and Information Law; Iowa Freedom of Information Council;
    United Farm Workers of America; Erwin Chemerinsky; 23 Media Organizations
    and Associations,
    lllllllllllllllllllllAmici on Behalf of Appellee(s).
    ____________
    Appeal from United States District Court
    for the Southern District of Iowa - Des Moines
    ____________
    Submitted: September 22, 2020
    Filed: August 10, 2021
    ____________
    Before COLLOTON, GRUENDER, and GRASZ, Circuit Judges.
    ____________
    COLLOTON, Circuit Judge.
    In this appeal, we consider whether an Iowa statute prohibiting accessing
    agricultural production facilities by false pretenses and making false statements as
    part of an employment application to an agricultural production facility violates the
    First Amendment. The district court ruled that both provisions are unconstitutional
    and enjoined their enforcement. We affirm in part and reverse in part.
    I.
    In 2012, the Iowa General Assembly passed a bill entitled “Agricultural
    Production Facility Fraud.” The statute states, in relevant part:
    A person is guilty of agricultural production facility fraud
    if the person willfully does any of the following:
    a. Obtains access to an agricultural production facility by
    false pretenses.
    b. Makes a false statement or representation as part of an
    application or agreement to be employed at an agricultural
    production facility, if the person knows the statement to be
    false, and makes the statement with an intent to commit an
    act not authorized by the owner of the agricultural
    production facility, knowing that the act is not authorized.
    Iowa Code § 717A.3A(1)(a)-(b) (2012). A first conviction under the statute
    constitutes a serious misdemeanor, and any subsequent conviction constitutes an
    aggravated misdemeanor. Id. § 717A.3A(2)(a)-(b).
    -2-
    Several organizations sued three Iowa officials in their official capacities:
    Governor Kimberly Reynolds, Attorney General Tom Miller, and Montgomery
    County Attorney Drew Swanson. The plaintiffs asserted, among other things, that the
    statute abridged their freedom of speech in violation of the First and Fourteenth
    Amendments. Specifically, they alleged that but for the statute, they and their
    investigators would assume “false pretenses” and make “false statements” in the
    course of obtaining access to, or employment with, agricultural production facilities
    for the purpose of publicizing the treatment of animals at these facilities.
    The district court granted summary judgment for the plaintiffs after concluding
    that both Iowa Code § 717A.3A(1)(a) (the “Access Provision”) and § 717A.3A(1)(b)
    (the “Employment Provision”) violate the First Amendment. The court entered an
    injunction against enforcement of the entire statute, § 717A.3A, including its
    punishment provisions in § 717A.3A(2)-(3). The State appeals, arguing that both
    disputed provisions are constitutional.
    II.
    The First Amendment, incorporated against the States through the Fourteenth
    Amendment, provides that “Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom
    of speech.” As a general matter, this “means that government has no power to restrict
    expression because of its message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its content.” Nev.
    Comm’n on Ethics v. Carrigan, 
    564 U.S. 117
    , 121 (2011) (internal quotation
    omitted). “Content-based laws” are “those that target speech based on its
    communicative content.” Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 
    576 U.S. 155
    , 163 (2015). In
    general, content-based laws “are subject to strict scrutiny” and “are presumptively
    unconstitutional.” 
    Id. at 163-64
    .
    Both the Access Provision and the Employment Provision constitute direct
    regulations of speech. The Access Provision targets false “pretenses,” Iowa Code
    -3-
    § 717A.3A(1)(a), and the Employment Provision targets false “statement[s],” id.
    § 717A.3A(1)(b). Pretenses may consist of nonverbal conduct, but that conduct
    constitutes “pretenses” only because it expresses information. “A law directed at the
    communicative nature of conduct” is treated like “a law directed at speech itself.”
    Texas v. Johnson, 
    491 U.S. 397
    , 406 (1989) (emphasis and internal quotation
    omitted). Thus, the Access Provision’s regulation of “pretenses,” like the regulation
    of “statements,” constitutes a direct regulation of speech. Both provisions also target
    expression for restriction on the basis of its content. Each prohibits expression that
    is “false,” and an observer must examine the content of the speech to determine
    whether it is prohibited. See Reed, 576 U.S. at 163-64; FCC v. League of Women
    Voters of Cal., 
    468 U.S. 364
    , 383 (1984).
    In debating the constitutionality of the statute, the parties focus on United
    States v. Alvarez, 
    567 U.S. 709
     (2012). Alvarez analyzed whether the Stolen Valor
    Act of 2005 violated the First Amendment by making it a crime for a person to
    “falsely represent[] himself or herself, verbally or in writing, to have been awarded
    any decoration or medal authorized by Congress for the Armed Forces.” 
    Id. at 715-16
    (plurality opinion); see Pub. L. No. 109-437, § 3, 120 Stat. 3266, 3266 (2006)
    (current version at 18 U.S.C. § 704(b)-(c) (2018)). The Supreme Court declared the
    Act unconstitutional, but there is no opinion of the Court that sets forth a guiding
    rationale.
    A plurality concluded that false speech is not in a general category that is
    presumptively unprotected. The plurality explained that where false claims are made
    knowingly or recklessly “to effect a fraud or secure moneys or other valuable
    considerations, say, offers of employment,” then it is well established that the
    government may restrict speech without violating the First Amendment. Alvarez, 
    567 U.S. at 723
    . Citing prior decisions, the plurality also acknowledged that false speech
    is not protected in certain cases involving “defamation, fraud, or some other legally
    cognizable harm associated with a false statement, such as an invasion of privacy or
    -4-
    the costs of vexatious litigation.” 
    Id. at 719
    . But the plurality concluded that the
    Stolen Valor Act targeted “falsity and nothing more,” and that it was subject to
    “exacting scrutiny” as a content-based restriction on speech. 
    Id. at 715, 719
    .
    Applying what has also been described as “strict scrutiny,” see Williams-Yulee v. Fla.
    Bar, 
    575 U.S. 433
    , 442-43 (2015), the plurality determined that the government failed
    to show that the Act’s restriction on false speech was “actually necessary” to achieve
    a compelling interest, or that the restriction was the “least restrictive means among
    available, effective alternatives.” Alvarez, 
    567 U.S. at 726, 729
     (internal quotation
    omitted). Accordingly, the Stolen Valor Act “infringe[d] upon speech protected by
    the First Amendment.” 
    Id. at 730
    .
    An opinion concurring in the judgment concluded that the Stolen Valor Act
    violated the First Amendment for a different reason. Applying “intermediate
    scrutiny” to a law that proscribed false statements about “easily verifiable facts,” the
    concurrence determined that the breadth of the prohibition created a significant risk
    of First Amendment harm, and that it was possible substantially to achieve the
    government’s objectives in less burdensome ways. 
    Id. at 732, 736-38
     (Breyer, J.,
    concurring in the judgment). Because the government did not convincingly explain
    why a more finely tailored statute would not work, the Act violated the First
    Amendment. 
    Id. at 739
    .
    When the Supreme Court is splintered, we attempt to apply the rule of Marks
    v. United States, 
    430 U.S. 188
     (1977), to determine the controlling rule. But where
    a concurring opinion is not a logical subset of the plurality’s rationale, or vice-versa,
    it is not possible to discern a holding in the case. United States v. Bailey, 
    571 F.3d 791
    , 798 (8th Cir. 2009); King v. Palmer, 
    950 F.2d 771
    , 781-82 (D.C. Cir. 1991) (en
    banc). That is the situation here. The Alvarez concurrence is arguably narrower than
    the plurality opinion because it applied intermediate scrutiny rather than exacting
    scrutiny. Yet the concurrence suggested more broadly that all false factual statements
    receive some protection under the First Amendment, while the plurality indicated that
    -5-
    certain false speech is outside the First Amendment. Without a single rationale from
    Alvarez that can be identified as a holding in the case, the only binding aspect of the
    decision is its specific result. See Anker Energy Corp. v. Consolidation Coal Co., 
    177 F.3d 161
    , 170 (3d Cir. 1999). Nevertheless, we bear in mind the reasoning of the
    various opinions as we seek to resolve this new dispute about restrictions on false
    statements.
    III.
    We consider first the Access Provision, which provides that a person is guilty
    of agricultural production facility fraud if he “obtains access to an agricultural
    production facility by false pretenses.” Iowa Code § 717A.3A(1)(a). The State
    argues that this provision is consistent with the First Amendment because it prohibits
    exclusively lies associated with a legally cognizable harm—namely, trespass to
    private property. We agree with this conclusion.
    The Alvarez plurality, in surveying prior statements of the Court declaring that
    false statements have no value or constitutional protection, explained that they all
    “derive from cases discussing defamation, fraud, or some other legally cognizable
    harm associated with a false statement, such as an invasion of privacy or the costs of
    vexatious litigation.” 
    567 U.S. at 719
    . Although none of the cited examples is
    precisely on point, trespass to private property is a comparable “legally cognizable
    harm,” such that knowingly false speech designed to cause that harm should lead to
    a similar conclusion.
    Trespass is an ancient cause of action that is long recognized in this country.
    See United States v. Jones, 
    565 U.S. 400
    , 404-05 (2012); 3 William Blackstone,
    Commentaries *209. Trespass by misrepresentation has a similar pedigree, see De
    May v. Roberts, 
    9 N.W. 146
    , 149 (Mich. 1881), and harm flowing from trespass is
    legally cognizable. “From every unlawful entry, or every direct invasion of the
    -6-
    person or property of another, the law infers some damage.” Nichols v. City of
    Evansdale, 
    687 N.W.2d 562
    , 573 (Iowa 2004) (quoting 75 Am. Jur. 2d Trespass
    § 117). Although falsity alone may not suffice to bring speech outside the First
    Amendment, there is no dispute that the term “false” in the Access Provision requires
    that false pretenses be assumed intentionally. Cf. State v. Hoyman, 
    863 N.W.2d 1
    , 16
    (Iowa 2015). The better rule in light of Alvarez is that intentionally false speech
    undertaken to accomplish a legally cognizable harm may be proscribed without
    violating the First Amendment.
    The district court concluded, however, that trespass onto private property does
    not result in a legally cognizable harm, because a property owner who suffers a
    trespass may be entitled to recover only nominal damages. The court reasoned that
    “nominal damage is just that—damage in name only.” But the court’s own citation
    to Black’s Law Dictionary acknowledged that nominal damages are “awarded when
    a legal injury is suffered but there is no substantial loss or injury to be compensated.”
    Damages, Black’s Law Dictionary (10th ed. 2014) (emphasis added). Nominal
    damages are not “purely symbolic, a mere judicial token that provides no actual
    benefit to the plaintiff.” Uzuegbunam v. Preczewski, 
    141 S. Ct. 792
    , 800-01 (2021).
    They are, rather, damages paid to a plaintiff that provide redress for an injury. 
    Id. at 801
    . Even without physical damage to property arising from a trespass, these
    damages may compensate a property owner for a diminution of privacy and a
    violation of the right to exclude—legally cognizable harms. See ALDF v. Wasden,
    
    878 F.3d 1184
    , 1205-06 (9th Cir. 2018) (Bea, J., dissenting in part and concurring in
    part); see also Cedar Point Nursery v. Hassid, No. 20-107, 
    2021 WL 2557070
     (U.S.
    June 23, 2021) (“The right to exclude is one of the most treasured rights of property
    ownership.”) (internal quotation omitted). We therefore conclude that the Access
    Provision’s prohibition on assuming false pretenses to obtain access to an agricultural
    production facility is consistent with the First Amendment.
    -7-
    IV.
    The plaintiffs also challenge the Employment Provision. This subsection
    provides that a person commits an offense if he “[m]akes a false statement or
    representation as part of an application or agreement to be employed at an agricultural
    production facility,” if he “knows the statement to be false, and makes the statement
    with an intent to commit an act not authorized by the owner of the agricultural
    production facility, knowing that the act is not authorized.” Iowa Code
    § 717A.3A(1)(b). The district court ruled this provision unconstitutional on its face
    under the First Amendment on the ground that it restricts protected speech and cannot
    satisfy either strict scrutiny or intermediate scrutiny.
    The State argues on appeal that the provision does not proscribe protected
    speech because the Alvarez plurality concluded that “[w]here false claims are made
    to effect a fraud or secure moneys or other valuable considerations, say, offers of
    employment, it is well established that the Government may restrict speech without
    affronting the First Amendment.” 
    567 U.S. at 723
     (plurality opinion) (emphasis
    added). The State maintains that the Employment Provision simply prevents making
    false statements to secure an offer of employment, so it is constitutional.
    We may assume for the sake of analysis that a narrowly tailored statute aimed
    at preventing false claims to secure offers of employment would pass constitutional
    muster. As the district court observed, however, the Iowa statute sweeps more
    broadly. The proscription of the Employment Provision does not require that false
    statements made as part of an employment application be material to the employment
    decision. As such, the statute is not limited to false claims that are made “to effect”
    an offer of employment; it allows for prosecution of those who make false statements
    that are not capable of influencing an offer of employment. Plausible scenarios
    abound: the applicant falsely professes to maintain a wardrobe like the interviewer’s,
    exaggerates her exercise routine, or inflates his past attendance at the hometown
    -8-
    football stadium. See generally Rachel Feintzeig, The Lies We Tell During Job
    Interviews, Wall St. J., Jan. 11, 2021, at A11; Nicolas Roulin, The Psychology of Job
    Interviews 86-104 (2017). The plaintiffs assert that their investigators would make
    misrepresentations that include omitting their affiliation with the Animal Legal
    Defense Fund, omitting their status as licensed private investigators, downplaying
    their educational backgrounds, and “telling innocuous white lies to ingratiate
    themselves to their interviewers, such as ‘I like your tie (or local sports team or
    company philosophy).’” R. Doc. 55-1, at 4 ¶ 13.
    Given the breadth of the Employment Provision, it proscribes speech that is
    protected by the First Amendment and does not satisfy strict scrutiny. Insofar as the
    State has a compelling interest in preventing false statements made to effect offers of
    employment, a prohibition on immaterial falsehoods is not actually necessary to
    achieve the interest. There is a less restrictive means available: proscribe only false
    statements that are material to a hiring decision. See Wasden, 878 F.3d at 1201-02.
    If intermediate scrutiny were the standard, the absence of a materiality requirement
    distinguishes the Iowa statute from permissible prohibitions on fraud, perjury, and
    lying to government officials. Alvarez, 
    567 U.S. at 734-36
     (Breyer, J., concurring in
    the judgment). While it is true that § 717A.3A(1)(b) requires proof of other elements,
    including intent to commit an unauthorized act in the agricultural facility, the fact
    remains that some persons may be prosecuted only because they make an immaterial
    false statement. Under either approach in the Alvarez majority, the scope of the
    Employment Provision is too broad to satisfy the First Amendment. See also
    McCullen v. Coakley, 
    573 U.S. 464
    , 496 & n.9 (2014); Brown v. Ent. Merchs. Ass’n,
    
    564 U.S. 786
    , 804 (2011).
    The State’s principal response on materiality is that the phrase “false pretenses”
    requires proof of a material misrepresentation under Iowa law. See Wilson v. Vanden
    Berg, 
    687 N.W.2d 575
    , 584 (Iowa 2004). That reply is no help with respect to the
    Employment Provision, which proscribes making a “false statement” without such a
    -9-
    limitation. See Iowa Code § 717A.3A(1)(b). A narrowing construction of the
    Employment Provision to require proof of a material misrepresentation is not possible
    because the statute is not “readily susceptible” to the limitation. Virginia v. Am.
    Booksellers Ass’n, Inc., 
    484 U.S. 383
    , 397 (1988). This federal court cannot rewrite
    the Iowa Code to impute a limitation that the legislature declined to include.
    *      *       *
    For these reasons, we affirm the district court’s grant of summary judgment for
    the plaintiffs on Iowa Code § 717A.3A(1)(b), reverse the judgment declaring
    unconstitutional § 717A.3A(1)(a), vacate the injunction against enforcement of
    § 717A.3A(1)(a), (2), and (3), and remand for further proceedings.
    GRASZ, Circuit Judge, concurring.
    This case tests the outer boundaries of protection of speech under the First
    Amendment. It concerns the concept of “truth” and the constitutionality of the
    government punishing, through criminal sanctions, the use of false speech in order
    to obtain access to, or employment at, certain private facilities.
    This nation was founded on the concept of objective truth (“We hold these
    truths to be self-evident . . . .”). And some of our nation's oldest institutions were
    founded as instrumentalities of the search for truth (Veritas). The quest for truth has
    not, of course, ended; nor has the clash between the free flow of ideas and the desire
    to punish untruthful speech that is perceived as harmful. The law has long provided
    for legal consequences for false speech constituting fraud, perjury, and defamation.
    The present case, however, presents a new category of deceit which the State of Iowa
    seeks to penalize. Some see it as investigative journalism. Others see it as lying to
    further an agenda at the expense of private property rights. In either sense, its
    punishment presents a legal dilemma between protecting property and protecting
    -10-
    speech. While some have always questioned whether truth can be known (“What is
    truth?”), our task is not to answer that question but simply to determine whether the
    constitution allows the government to criminally punish falsity in the specific context
    of the statute before us.
    I join the court's opinion in full because I believe it is consistent with current
    law, as best we can determine it from limited and sometimes hazy precedent. Still,
    I do so hesitantly as to the Access Provision. The court's opinion today represents the
    first time any circuit court has upheld such a provision. At a time in history when a
    cloud of censorship appears to be descending, along with palpable public fear of
    being “cancelled” for holding “incorrect” views, it concerns me to see a new category
    of speech which the government can punish through criminal prosecution.
    Ultimately, the Supreme Court will have to determine whether such laws can be
    sustained, or whether they infringe on the “breathing room” necessary to effectuate
    the promise of the First Amendment.
    Going forward, a key question will be whether access-by-deceit statutes will
    be applied to punish speech that has instrumental value or which is tied to political
    or ideological messages. The Alvarez decision, for the reasons noted in the court's
    opinion, is of limited guidance here. However, I find it significant that even the
    dissent in that case, while finding no value in the false speech there (lying about
    receiving high military honors), nonetheless recognized the principle that false speech
    which does have intrinsic or instrumental value may fall within the ambit of the Free
    Speech Clause. See United States v. Alvarez, 
    567 U.S. 709
    , 752 (2012) (Alito, J.,
    dissenting). Most notably, the dissenting opinion states, “The false statements
    proscribed by the [Stolen Valor] Act are highly unlikely to be tied to any particular
    political or ideological message.” 
    Id. at 740
    –41. Whether that conclusion also holds
    true in the application of this or future access-by-deceit provisions remains to be seen.
    -11-
    GRUENDER, Circuit Judge, concurring in part and dissenting in part.
    I join in Section III of the court’s opinion holding that the Access Provision
    does not violate the First Amendment. However, I disagree with the court’s Marks
    analysis and with its holding that the Employment Provision violates the First
    Amendment. I write separately to explain these disagreements and to offer additional
    support for the conclusion that the Access Provision is constitutional.
    I.
    I begin by addressing the Marks analysis. As the court notes, ante, at 4-5, the
    Supreme Court held in United States v. Alvarez that the Stolen Valor Act was
    unconstitutional, but no majority of justices agreed on the rationale. See 
    567 U.S. 709
    , 714-16 (2012) (plurality opinion); 
    id. at 730
     (Breyer, J., concurring in the
    judgment). Under Marks v. United States, “[w]hen a fragmented Court decides a case
    and no single rationale explaining the result enjoys the assent of five Justices,” “the
    holding of the Court may be viewed as that position taken by those Members who
    concurred in the judgments on the narrowest grounds.” 
    430 U.S. 188
    , 193 (1977).
    Where two opinions reach the same conclusion on different legal grounds, one
    is narrower than the other for Marks purposes if the former is a logical subset of the
    latter; that is, if the legal rule of decision in the latter entails the legal rule of decision
    in the former. See United States v. Bailey, 
    571 F.3d 791
    , 798 (8th Cir. 2009).
    However, the Marks rule “becomes problematic when one opinion supporting the
    judgment does not fit entirely within a broader circle drawn by the others.” 
    Id.
    (internal quotation marks omitted); see also King v. Palmer, 
    950 F.2d 771
    , 781 (D.C.
    Cir. 1991) (en banc) (“Marks is workable—one opinion can be meaningfully regarded
    as ‘narrower’ than another—only when one opinion is a logical subset of [the
    other].”).
    -12-
    I agree with the court that, in Alvarez, neither the plurality nor the concurrence
    is a logical subset of the other. See ante, at 5. But unlike the court, I would not hold
    that this means that it is impossible to discern which is narrower and conclude that
    “the only binding aspect of the decision is its specific result.” See ante, at 5-6. This
    approach may have support in the law of other circuits, see, e.g., Lair v. Bullock, 
    697 F.3d 1200
    , 1205 (9th Cir. 2012); United States v. Alcan Aluminum Corp., 
    315 F.3d 179
    , 189 (2d Cir. 2003); Anker Energy Corp. v. Consol. Coal Co., 
    177 F.3d 161
    , 170
    (3d Cir. 1999), but it is not the approach of our circuit. The court cites Bailey, ante,
    at 5, but Bailey stated that it is “difficult”—not impossible—“to determine which
    holding is the narrowest” when neither opinion is a logical subset of the other, 
    571 F.3d at 798
    . Historically, we have employed at least one other method for
    determining the narrowest opinion when the logical-subset test yields none. When
    a fractured Supreme Court sustains a constitutional challenge, we have followed the
    opinion that “would hold the fewest statutes unconstitutional.” Coe v. Melahn, 
    958 F.2d 223
    , 225 (8th Cir. 1992). And even when we have determined that there is no
    narrowest opinion, we have not concluded that the only binding aspect of the decision
    is the judgment. Rather, looking to the reasoning in the various opinions, we have
    attempted to resolve the issue before us in the way that would have commanded the
    votes of any five justices of the Court, including any dissenters. See Bailey, 
    571 F.3d at 799
     (citing United States v. Johnson, 
    467 F.3d 56
    , 66 (1st Cir. 2006)) (determining
    that there was jurisdiction under Rapanos v. United States, 
    547 U.S. 715
     (2006),
    because the one-justice concurrence in the judgment and the four-justice dissent
    would both find jurisdiction).1
    Here, it is not clear which of the two Alvarez opinions would hold the least
    number of statutes unconstitutional. One could argue that the plurality’s approach
    1
    Also, in Hopkins v. Jegley, we both identified a “controlling” opinion even
    though no opinion was a logical subset of another and noted that five justices,
    including four in the dissent, would have applied the controlling opinion’s rule to the
    case before us. See 
    968 F.3d 912
    , 915 (8th Cir. 2020) (per curiam).
    -13-
    would hold fewer statutes unconstitutional because it would not subject statutes that
    prohibit lies associated with a “legally cognizable harm” or told for the “purpose of
    material gain” to First Amendment scrutiny at all. See Alvarez, 
    567 U.S. at 719, 723
    (plurality opinion). The concurrence would subject these statutes to at least
    intermediate scrutiny. See 
    id. at 730-31, 734-36
     (Breyer, J., concurring in the
    judgment) (highlighting the “limiting features” of regulations of fraud, perjury, false
    claims, impersonation, and trademark infringement that enable them to hold up better
    under intermediate scrutiny than the Stolen Valor Act). However, one also could
    argue that the plurality would hold more statutes unconstitutional because it would
    apply strict scrutiny to laws, like the Stolen Valor Act, to which the concurrence
    would apply only intermediate scrutiny.
    Given that neither the logical-subset test nor the test from Coe determines a
    narrowest opinion, I believe that our Marks jurisprudence leaves open two ways of
    proceeding. The first is to look to other circuits for additional methods of
    determining a narrowest opinion for Marks purposes. For instance, the Sixth Circuit
    has characterized the “narrowest opinion” as the “opinion that offers the least change
    to the law.” United States v. Cundiff, 
    555 F.3d 200
    , 209 (6th Cir. 2009) (internal
    quotation marks omitted); cf. Marks, 
    430 U.S. at 193-94
     (treating as controlling the
    opinion that proposed the least change to the government’s ability to regulate
    obscenity under the First Amendment). The second is to resort to Bailey’s fallback
    approach that we use when Marks is inconclusive—resolving this case in the way that
    would have commanded the votes of five justices on the Alvarez Court. Here, both
    approaches lead to the same outcome.
    Consider first the approach of following the “opinion that offers the least
    change to the law.” See 
    id.
     (internal quotation marks omitted). In Alvarez, that
    opinion is the plurality. The concurrence deviated from longstanding Supreme Court
    precedent by subjecting the content-based Stolen Valor Act to intermediate rather
    than strict scrutiny. Compare Alvarez, 
    567 U.S. at 731-32
     (Breyer, J., concurring in
    -14-
    the judgment) (applying intermediate scrutiny to a content-based law), with Brown
    v. Entm’t Merchs. Ass’n, 
    564 U.S. 786
    , 799 (2011) (applying strict scrutiny to a
    content-based law); United States v. Playboy Entm’t Grp., 
    529 U.S. 803
    , 813 (2000)
    (same); Burson v. Freeman, 
    504 U.S. 191
    , 198-99 (1992) (same). The fact that the
    Supreme Court has continued, since Alvarez, to apply strict scrutiny to content-based
    regulations of speech and to decline invitations to relax this practice confirms how
    firmly entrenched this practice is in its caselaw. See, e.g., Barr v. Am. Ass’n of Pol.
    Consultants, Inc., 591 U.S. ---, 
    140 S. Ct. 2335
    , 2358 (2020) (Breyer, J., concurring
    in the judgment in part and dissenting in part) (criticizing the Court for “reflexively
    appl[ying] strict scrutiny to all content-based speech distinctions”); Reed v. Town of
    Gilbert, 
    576 U.S. 155
    , 176 (2015) (Breyer, J., concurring in the judgment) (parting
    ways with the majority on the basis that “the category ‘content discrimination’ is
    better considered . . . as a rule of thumb, rather than as an automatic ‘strict scrutiny’
    trigger”). Therefore, the Alvarez concurrence proposed a more radical change to the
    law than the Alvarez plurality. And, for the reasons I explain in Sections II-III, the
    Alvarez plurality’s reasoning requires upholding both the Access Provision and the
    Employment Provision. Thus, if we were to follow the “opinion that offers the least
    change to the law,” Cundiff, 
    555 F.3d at 209,
     then we would be required to uphold
    both the Access Provision and the Employment Provision.
    Now, consider the fallback approach of resolving this case in the way that
    would have commanded the votes of five justices on the Alvarez Court. According
    to the Alvarez dissent, a statute that criminalizes “only knowingly false statements
    about hard facts directly within a speaker’s personal knowledge” “presents no threat
    to the freedom of speech.” 
    567 U.S. at 739
     (Alito, J., dissenting). Both the Access
    Provision and the Employment Provision criminalize “only knowingly false
    statements about hard facts directly within [the] speaker’s personal knowledge.” See
    id.; Iowa Code § 717A.3A(1)(a)-(b). Presumably, then, the three dissenters in
    Alvarez would have voted to uphold both the Access Provision and the Employment
    Provision in this case. And, again, for the reasons I explain in Sections II-III, the
    -15-
    Alvarez plurality’s reasoning requires upholding both the Access Provision and the
    Employment Provision. So presumably the four justices in the plurality would also
    have voted to uphold both the Access Provision and the Employment Provision in this
    case. Thus, to resolve the case in the way that would have commanded the votes of
    five justices on the Alvarez Court, we would be required to uphold both the Access
    Provision and the Employment Provision.
    In sum, our jurisprudence leaves open two approaches to resolving the difficult
    Marks problem that this case presents. But if I am right about how the Alvarez
    plurality’s reasoning applies in this case, then the two approaches converge on the
    same result: we must uphold both the Access Provision and the Employment
    Provision. I devote the remainder of my opinion to explaining my view that the
    Alvarez plurality’s reasoning implies that both the Access Provision and the
    Employment Provision are constitutional.
    II.
    I begin with the Access Provision. The court concludes that the Access
    Provision does not violate the First Amendment under the Alvarez plurality’s
    reasoning because trespass is a “legally cognizable harm.” See ante, at 6-7; Alvarez,
    
    567 U.S. at 719
     (plurality opinion) (indicating that lies associated with a legally
    cognizable harm fall outside First Amendment protection). I agree. I write separately
    here to provide additional support for this conclusion.
    A “legally cognizable harm,” as the Supreme Court uses the phrase, is simply
    an injury that supports standing to pursue a cause of action. See, e.g., Lujan v.
    Defenders of Wildlife, 
    504 U.S. 555
    , 578 (1992) (using the phrase “legally cognizable
    injury” to refer to an injury that supports standing); Ariz. Christian Sch. Tuition Org.
    v. Winn, 
    563 U.S. 125
    , 162 (2011) (Kagan, J., dissenting) (using the phrase “legally
    cognizable harm” to refer to an injury that supports standing). An injury that supports
    -16-
    standing under the law of one sovereign may not support standing under the law of
    another sovereign. See Zicherman v. Korean Air Lines Co., 
    516 U.S. 217
    , 222-23
    (1996) (noting differences between France and other nations regarding “what
    constitutes legally cognizable harm”). In addition, an injury that supports standing
    under the law of one sovereign at one time may not support standing under the law
    of that same sovereign at a different time. See Spokeo, Inc. v. Robins, 578 U.S. ---,
    
    136 S. Ct. 1540
    , 1549 (2016) (explaining that “Congress may elevate to the status of
    legally cognizable injuries . . . injuries that were previously inadequate in [U.S.] law”
    (internal quotation marks and alterations omitted)). Therefore, the question what
    constitutes a legally cognizable harm cannot be answered except with respect to a
    particular legal sovereign at a particular time.
    I would interpret the Alvarez plurality’s use of “legally cognizable harm” as a
    reference to the kind of injury that supported standing under U.S. law when the First
    Amendment was ratified in 1791.2 This interpretation is consistent with the Court’s
    statement in Nevada Commission on Ethics v. Carrigan that “[l]aws punishing libel
    and obscenity are not thought to violate ‘the freedom of speech’ to which the First
    Amendment refers because such laws existed in 1791 and have been in place ever
    since.” 
    564 U.S. 117
    , 122 (2011); see also Alvarez, 
    567 U.S. at 717
     (plurality
    opinion) (limiting categories of unprotected speech to those “long familiar to the
    bar”); Roth v. United States, 
    354 U.S. 476
    , 482-83 (1957) (explaining the exclusion
    2
    I recognize that “standing” was not a term of art in 1791. See Cass R.
    Sunstein, Standing After Lujan? Of Citizen Suits, “Injuries,” and Article III, 91
    Mich. L. Rev. 163, 169 (1992) (tracing the use of the term “standing” in the Article
    III context to a 1944 case). Nonetheless, evidence exists that “there was an active law
    of [what we would today call] standing in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.”
    Ann Woolhandler & Caleb Nelson, Does History Defeat Standing Doctrine?, 102
    Mich. L. Rev. 689, 691 (2004). Here, it is irrelevant to what extent this “law of
    standing,” 
    id.,
     went beyond the requirement of a cause of action. What matters is that
    trespass constituted an actionable injury at common law before 1791. See, e.g., 3
    William Blackstone, Commentaries *209 (recognizing trespass as a cause of action).
    -17-
    of obscenity and libel from First Amendment protection by reference to laws in place
    “[a]t the time of the adoption of the First Amendment”).
    Interpreting “legally cognizable harm” to refer to an injury that supported
    standing under U.S. law in 1791 is also consistent with the four examples that the
    Alvarez plurality offered of legally cognizable harms: defamation, fraud, invasion of
    privacy, and costs of vexatious litigation. 
    567 U.S. at 719
    . Although not dispositive,
    what was recognized as supporting standing to pursue a cause of action in law or
    equity in England prior to the American Revolution is probative of what would have
    been recognized as supporting standing to pursue a cause of action in U.S. federal
    court in 1791. See Van Ness v. Pacard, 27 U.S. (2 Pet.) 137, 144 (1829) (explaining
    that the colonists “brought with them [the] general principles” of English common
    law, even if they did not adopt every detail). And there is evidence that defamation,
    fraud, certain kinds of invasions of privacy, and vexatious litigation were all
    actionable in law or equity in England prior to the American Revolution. See King
    v. Lake (1670), 145 Eng. Rep. 552, 552-53; Hardres 470, 470 (treating libel as
    actionable); Chandelor v. Lopus (1603), 79 Eng. Rep. 3, 3-4; Cro. Jac. 4, 4 (clarifying
    the circumstances under which a plaintiff has a cause of action for “deceit”); Pope v.
    Curl (1741), 26 Eng. Rep. 608, 608; 2 Atk. 342, 342-43 (granting an injunction
    against the publication of private letters); Waterer v. Freeman (1640), 80 Eng. Rep.
    412, 413; Hobart 266, 267 (“[I]f a man sue me in a proper Court, yet if his suit be
    utterly without ground of truth, and that certainly known to himself, I may have an
    action of the case against him for the undue vexation and damage that he putteth me
    unto by his ill practice.”).
    Finally, interpreting “legally cognizable harm” to refer to an injury that
    supported standing under U.S. law in 1791 makes the most sense out of the Alvarez
    plurality’s willingness to place false speech associated with a legally cognizable harm
    outside First Amendment protection. It would make little sense for the Court to
    condition the scope of First Amendment rights on what confers standing in the courts
    -18-
    of the state whose government took the challenged action (in this case, Iowa) rather
    than on what confers standing under federal law. That would imply that two states
    could enact identical laws, one of which violates the First Amendment and the other
    of which does not. I doubt that the Court meant to allow this possibility. See
    Virginia v. Moore, 
    553 U.S. 164
    , 176 (2008) (rejecting the proposal to “link[] Fourth
    Amendment protections to state law” because it “would cause them to vary from
    place to place” (internal quotation marks omitted)). It would also make little sense
    for the Court to condition the scope of First Amendment rights on what
    contemporaneously supports standing under U.S. law rather than on what supported
    standing under U.S. law in 1791. That would imply that the scope of First
    Amendment protection contracts over time as Congress “elevate[s]” new harms to the
    status of legally cognizable harms for the purposes of federal law. See Spokeo, 
    136 S. Ct. at 1549
    . Worse, it would allow Congress to bootstrap laws into compliance
    with the First Amendment by elevating harms associated with the false speech that
    the laws regulate to the status of legally cognizable harms. Again, I doubt that the
    Court meant to allow this possibility. See City of Boerne v. Flores, 
    521 U.S. 507
    , 545
    (1997) (O’Connor, J., dissenting) (“Congress lacks the ability independently to define
    or expand the scope of constitutional rights by statute.”). The interpretation that
    makes the most sense out of the Alvarez plurality’s use of the phrase “legally
    cognizable harm,” then, is an interpretation that treats the phrase as a reference to an
    injury that supported standing under U.S. law when the First Amendment was ratified
    in 1791.
    -19-
    Here, there is no question that the speech the Access Provision prohibits is
    associated with an injury that supported standing under U.S. law in 1791. The Access
    Provision is a trespass law. See Restatement (Second) of Torts §§ 173, § 892B (Am.
    Law Inst. 1965). As a common-law cause of action, trespass existed before the
    ratification of the First Amendment. See, e.g., United States v. Jones, 
    565 U.S. 400
    ,
    404-05 (2012) (citing Entick v. Carrington, 95 Eng. Rep. 807 (C.P. 1765) for the
    proposition that “[o]ur law holds the property of every man so sacred, that no man can
    set his foot upon his neighbour’s close without his leave; if he does he is a trespasser,
    though he does no damage at all”); 3 William Blackstone, Commentaries *209
    (“[T]he law of England . . . has treated every entry upon another’s lands (unless by
    the owner’s leave . . . ), as an injury or wrong, for satisfaction of which an action of
    trespass will lie . . . .”). The First Amendment was ratified against the backdrop of
    “[a] universal and long-established tradition of prohibiting” trespass, which “creates
    a strong presumption that the [Access Provision] is constitutional.” See Carrigan,
    
    564 U.S. at 122
     (making this point about libel and obscenity). Thus, the false speech
    that the Access Provision criminalizes is associated with the kind of legally
    cognizable harm that, according to the Alvarez plurality, places it outside First
    Amendment protection. See Alvarez, 
    567 U.S. at 719
    .
    III.
    I turn now to the Employment Provision. According to the Alvarez plurality,
    “[w]here false claims are made to effect a fraud or secure moneys or other valuable
    considerations, say offers of employment, it is well established that the Government
    may restrict speech without affronting the First Amendment.” 
    567 U.S. at 723
    .
    Therefore, according to the plurality, if a person lies for the purpose of securing an
    offer of employment, then the lie is not protected by the First Amendment—even if
    the lie is unsuccessful because the employer does not hire the person or immaterial
    because the employer would have hired him anyway.
    -20-
    Here, the Employment Provision prohibits “willfully . . . mak[ing] a false
    statement or representation as part of an application or agreement to be employed at
    an agricultural production facility,” if the speaker “knows the statement to be false”
    and “makes the statement with an intent to commit an act not authorized by the owner
    of the agricultural production facility, knowing that the act is not authorized.” Iowa
    Code § 717A.3A(1)(b). The plain language of the Alvarez plurality opinion implies
    that the Employment Provision does not violate the First Amendment. See Animal
    Legal Defense Fund v. Wasden, 
    878 F.3d 1184
    , 1201-02 (9th Cir. 2018) (holding that
    a similar provision did not violate the free-speech clause of the First Amendment
    under the Alvarez plurality’s rationale).
    IV.
    In sum, the Alvarez plurality’s reasoning implies that both the Access Provision
    and the Employment Provision are constitutional. Consequently, although our
    jurisprudence leaves open two ways of resolving the Marks question in this case, both
    ways converge on the same result: we must uphold both provisions.3 Accordingly,
    3
    The concurrence expresses concern about permitting the criminalization of
    false speech at a time “when a cloud of censorship appears to be descending, along
    with palpable public fear of being ‘cancelled’ for holding ‘incorrect’ views.” Ante,
    at 11. But even under the Alvarez plurality’s rule placing lies associated with a
    legally cognizable harm or made for material gain outside First Amendment
    protection, a statute criminalizing the expression of “incorrect” opinions on politically
    charged topics would be constitutionally problematic. By targeting politically
    incorrect views on a particular topic, the statute would draw a content-based
    distinction in addition to the distinction between truth and falsity. And this would
    trigger strict scrutiny (if not render the statute unconstitutional per se) even assuming
    the government could target a broader category of false speech without triggering any
    First Amendment scrutiny at all. See R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, 
    505 U.S. 377
    , 388
    (1992) (“A State might choose to prohibit only that obscenity which is the most
    patently offensive in its prurience—i.e., that which involves the most lascivious
    displays of sexual activity. But it may not prohibit, for example, only that obscenity
    which includes offensive political messages.”); cf. Alvarez, 
    567 U.S. at 723
     (making
    -21-
    I would reverse the district court’s judgment in favor of the plaintiffs with respect to
    both the Access Provision and the Employment Provision.
    ______________________________
    clear that the government may not “compile a list of subjects about which false
    statements are punishable” (emphasis added)). Here, neither the Access Provision nor
    the Employment Provision draws a further content-based distinction in addition to the
    distinction between truth and falsity. True, they target false speech used to obtain
    access to or employment at an agricultural production facility. But the fact that
    speech was used to obtain access to or employment at an agricultural production
    facility does not, by itself, entail anything about the content of the speech. Therefore,
    however legitimate the concurrence’s concerns may be, I do not believe that they are
    implicated in this case.
    -22-