Randolph Wolfson v. Colleen Concannon , 750 F.3d 1145 ( 2014 )


Menu:
  •                  FOR PUBLICATION
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT
    RANDOLPH WOLFSON,                       No. 11-17634
    Plaintiff-Appellant,
    D.C. No.
    v.                     3:08-cv-08064-
    FJM
    COLLEEN CONCANNON, in her
    official capacity as member of the
    Arizona Commission on Judicial            OPINION
    Conduct; LOUIS FRANK DOMINGUEZ,
    in his official capacity as member of
    the Arizona Commission on Judicial
    Conduct; PETER J. ECKERSTROM, in
    his official capacity as member of
    the Arizona Commission on Judicial
    Conduct; GEORGE H. FOSTER, in his
    official capacity as member of the
    Arizona Commission on Judicial
    Conduct; SHERRY L. GEISLER, in her
    official capacity as member of the
    Arizona Commission on Judicial
    Conduct; MICHAEL O. MILLER, in
    his official capacity as member of
    the Arizona Commission on Judicial
    Conduct; ANGELA H. SIFUENTES, in
    her official capacity as secretary of
    the Arizona Commission on Judicial
    Conduct; CATHERINE M. STEWART,
    in her official capacity as member of
    the Arizona Commission on Judicial
    2               WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    Conduct; J. TYRELL TABER, in his
    official capacity as member of the
    Arizona Commission on Judicial
    Conduct; LAWRENCE F. WINTHROP,
    in his official capacity as member of
    the Arizona Commission on Judicial
    Conduct; MARET VESSELLA, Chief
    Bar Counsel of the State Bar of
    Arizona,
    Defendants-Appellees.
    Appeal from the United States District Court
    for the District of Arizona
    Frederick J. Martone, District Judge, Presiding
    Argued and Submitted
    July 11, 2013—San Francisco, California
    Filed May 9, 2014
    Before: Richard A. Paez, Marsha S. Berzon,
    and Richard C. Tallman, Circuit Judges.
    Opinion by Judge Paez;
    Concurrence by Judge Berzon;
    Dissent by Judge Tallman
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                              3
    SUMMARY*
    Civil Rights
    The panel reversed the district court’s grant of summary
    judgment in favor of Arizona state officials and remanded an
    action brought by an unsuccessful candidate for judicial
    office in Mohave County, Arizona, who alleged that several
    provisions of the Arizona Code of Judicial Conduct,
    restricting judicial candidate speech, violated the First
    Amendment.
    The panel emphasized that its analysis of the challenged
    provisions was based on plaintiff’s status as a non-judge
    candidate. Applying strict scrutiny, the panel held that
    the Code’s solicitation clause, Rule 4.1(A)(6), was
    unconstitutional as applied to non-judge judicial candidates
    because it restricted speech that presented little to no risk of
    corruption or bias towards future litigants and was not
    narrowly tailored to serve those state interests. The panel
    held that the political activities clauses of the Code, Rules
    4.1(A)(2)–(5), were not sufficiently narrowly tailored to serve
    the state’s interest in an impartial judiciary, and were thus
    unconstitutional restrictions on the political speech of non-
    judge candidates.
    Concurring, Judge Berzon stated that the panel’s opinion
    addressed the constitutionality of certain provisions of the
    Arizona Code of Judicial Conduct only as they apply to
    *
    This summary constitutes no part of the opinion of the court. It has
    been prepared by court staff for the convenience of the reader.
    4                WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    judicial candidates who, like plaintiff, had not yet ascended
    to the bench.
    Dissenting in part, Judge Tallman stated that Rules
    4.1(a)(2) (giving speeches on behalf of others), (3) (endorsing
    others), and (4) (soliciting money for others), were
    constitutional because they were narrowly tailored to serve
    the state’s compelling interest in maintaining judicial
    impartiality and its appearance.
    COUNSEL
    Anita Y. Woudenberg (argued), The Bopp Law Firm, Terre
    Haute, Indiana, for Plaintiff-Appellant.
    Charles A. Grube (argued), Assistant Attorney General,
    Arizona Attorney General’s Office, Phoenix, Arizona, for
    Defendants-Appellees Colleen Concannon, Louis Frank
    Dominguez, Peter J. Eckerstrom, George H. Foster, Sherry L.
    Geisler, Michael O. Miller, Angela H. Sifuentes, Catherine
    M. Stewart, Tyrell Taber, and Lawrence F. Winthrop in their
    official capacities as members of the Arizona Commission on
    Judicial Conduct; Kimberly A. Demarchi (argued), Lewis
    Roca Rothgerber LLP, Phoenix, Arizona, for Defendant-
    Appellee Maret Vessella, Chief Bar Counsel of the State Bar
    of Arizona.
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                         5
    OPINION
    PAEZ, Circuit Judge:
    A state sets itself on a collision course with the First
    Amendment when it chooses to popularly elect its judges but
    restricts a candidate’s campaign speech. The conflict arises
    from the fundamental tension between the ideal of apolitical
    judicial independence and the critical nature of unfettered
    speech in the electoral political process. Here we must decide
    whether several provisions in the Arizona Code of Judicial
    Conduct restricting judicial candidate speech run afoul of
    First Amendment protections. Because we are concerned
    with content-based restrictions on electioneering-related
    speech, those protections are at their apex. Arizona, like
    every other state, has a compelling interest in the reality and
    appearance of an impartial judiciary, but speech restrictions
    must be narrowly tailored to serve that interest. We hold that
    several provisions of the Arizona Code of Judicial Conduct
    unconstitutionally restrict the speech of non-judge candidates
    because the restrictions are not sufficiently narrowly tailored
    to survive strict scrutiny. Accordingly, we reverse the district
    court’s grant of summary judgment in favor of Defendants.
    I.
    Arizona counties with fewer than 250,000 people
    popularly elect local judicial officers. See Ariz. Const. art.
    6                    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    VI, §§ 12, 40.1 The Arizona Code of Judicial Conduct2 (the
    “Code”) regulates the conduct of judges campaigning for
    retention and judicial candidates campaigning for office. The
    Code provides for discipline if a candidate is elected as a
    judge, but lawyers who are unsuccessful in their candidacy
    may also be subject to discipline under the Arizona Rules of
    Professional Conduct.3 See Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 17A, Sup.
    Ct. Rules, Rule 42, Rules of Prof. Conduct, ER 8.2 (2003).
    Plaintiff Randolph Wolfson was an unsuccessful
    candidate for judicial office in Mohave County, Arizona in
    2006 and 2008. Wolfson 
    I, 616 F.3d at 1052
    –53. He intends
    to run in a future election. 
    Id. at 1054–55.
    As a candidate,
    Wolfson wished to conduct a number of activities he believed
    to be prohibited by the Code, but refrained from doing so,
    fearing professional discipline.4 He brought this action
    1
    Arizona Supreme Court and appellate court judges and judicial officers
    in counties with a population greater than 250,000 (and smaller counties
    that vote to do so) use a system of merit selection with retention elections.
    Ariz. Const. art. VI, §§ 37, 38, 40.
    2
    Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 17A, Sup. Ct. Rules, Rule 81, Code of Jud.
    Conduct (2009). After Wolfson filed his complaint, the Code was revised,
    effective September 1, 2009. The revision to the Code recodified and
    renumbered the Rules, but did not alter the substance of the challenged
    Rules at issue in this appeal. See Wolfson v. Brammer, 
    616 F.3d 1045
    ,
    1053 (9th Cir. 2010) (Wolfson I).
    3
    “An unsuccessful judicial candidate who is a lawyer and violates this
    code may be subject to discipline under applicable court rules governing
    lawyers.” Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 17A, Sup. Ct. Rules, Rule 81, Code of
    Jud. Conduct, Canon 4, cmt. 2 (2009).
    4
    Wolfson alleges that he wanted personally to solicit campaign
    contributions at live appearances and speaking engagements, and by
    making phone calls and signing his name to letters seeking donations.
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                               7
    challenging the facial and as-applied constitutionality of
    certain provisions of the Code, seeking declaratory and
    injunctive relief. Defending this appeal are the members of
    the Arizona Commission on Judicial Conduct (the
    “Commission”) and Arizona Chief Bar Counsel (“State Bar
    Counsel”), collectively the “Arizona defendants.”5
    Wolfson challenges five clauses of Rule 4.1 of the Code
    (the “Rules”):
    (A) A judge or judicial candidate shall not do
    any of the following:
    ....
    (2) make speeches on behalf of a political
    organization or another candidate for public
    office;
    (3) publicly endorse or oppose another
    candidate for any public office;
    (4) solicit funds for or pay an assessment
    to a political organization or candidate, make
    contributions to any candidate or political
    organization in excess of the amounts
    permitted by law, or make total contributions
    Wolfson 
    I, 616 F.3d at 1052
    . He also alleges that he wanted to endorse
    other candidates for office and support their election campaigns. 
    Id. 5 Wolfson
    voluntarily dismissed all claims against a third defendant, the
    Arizona Supreme Court Disciplinary Commission. Wolfson v. Brammer,
    
    822 F. Supp. 2d 925
    , 926–27 (D. Ariz. 2011) (Wolfson II).
    8                  WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    in excess of fifty percent of the cumulative
    total permitted by law . . . .
    (5) actively take part in any political
    campaign other than his or her own campaign
    for election, reelection or retention in office;
    (6) personally solicit or accept campaign
    contributions other than through a campaign
    committee authorized by Rule 4.4 . . . .6
    Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 17A, Sup. Ct. Rules, Rule 81, Code of
    Jud. Conduct (2009).
    This is the second time that this case is before us. We
    previously held in Wolfson I that Wolfson’s challenges to
    these clauses (hereinafter the “solicitation” clause (6) and
    “political activities” clauses, (2)–(5)) were justiciable and
    remanded them to the district court to consider them on the
    merits. Wolfson 
    I, 616 F.3d at 1054
    –62, 1066–67. With
    respect to his challenge to a now-defunct “pledges and
    promises” clause, we held that Wolfson lacked standing to
    challenge it insofar as it applied to the speech of judges. 
    Id. at 1064.
    “Wolfson cannot assert the constitutional rights of
    judges when he is not, and may never be, a member of that
    group.” 
    Id. On remand,
    ruling on cross-motions for summary
    judgment, the district court applied a balancing test
    articulated by the Seventh Circuit in Siefert v. Alexander,
    
    608 F.3d 974
    (7th Cir. 2010), and Bauer v. Shepard, 
    620 F.3d 6
       Arizona’s Code closely tracks the American Bar Association’s Model
    Code of Judicial Conduct, Rule 4.1 (2011).
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                          9
    704 (7th Cir. 2010), and upheld the constitutionality of the
    five challenged Code provisions. Wolfson 
    II, 822 F. Supp. 2d at 929
    –30. The balancing test from Siefert/Bauer “derives
    from the line of Supreme Court cases upholding the limited
    power of governments to restrict their employees’ political
    speech in order to promote the efficiency and integrity of
    government services.” 
    Id. at 929.
    The district court held that
    this standard “strikes an appropriate balance between the
    weaker First Amendment rights at stake and the stronger
    State interests in regulating the way it chooses its judges,”
    apparently because the speech at issue was not “core speech”
    deserving of strict scrutiny but “behavior short of true
    speech.” 
    Id. at 929–30.
    The district court proceeded to balance the interests of the
    state against the interests of a judicial candidate. With
    respect to the political activities restrictions (the campaigning
    and endorsement clauses), the district court held that
    “[e]ndorsements, making speeches, and soliciting funds on
    behalf of other candidates is not . . . core political speech.”
    
    Id. at 931.
    The district court distinguished between
    announcing one’s own political views or qualifications—
    speech protected by Republican Party of Minn. v. White, 
    536 U.S. 765
    , 788 (2002) (White I )—and the type of speech
    prohibited by the Rules, which only “advance[s] other
    candidates’ political aspirations, or . . . garner[s] votes by way
    of political coattails.” Wolfson 
    II, 822 F. Supp. 2d at 931
    –32.
    Moreover, although the district court recognized that its
    review was “limited to the constitutionality of the Rules as
    applied to judicial candidates who are not also sitting judges,”
    
    id. at 928,
    it nonetheless
    reject[ed] the suggestion that judicial
    candidates ought to enjoy greater freedom to
    10                WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    engage in partisan politics than sitting judges.
    An asymmetrical electoral process for judges
    is unworkable. Fundamental fairness requires
    a level playing field among judicial
    contenders. Candidates for judicial office
    must abide by the same rules imposed on the
    judges they hope to become.
    
    Id. at 932.
    The district court assumed the constitutional
    validity of the Rules restricting political activities as applied
    to sitting judges, holding that “the Pickering line of cases
    [upholding the government’s power to restrict employees’
    political speech to promote efficiency and integrity of
    government services] remains relevant to restrictions on the
    speech of sitting judges.” 
    Id. The court
    concluded that Rules
    4.1(A)(2)–(5) appropriately balanced the state’s interest in
    “protecting the due process rights of litigants and ensuring the
    real and perceived impartiality of the judiciary” against a
    candidate’s interest in “participating in the political
    campaigns of other candidates” and upheld the political
    activities clauses as constitutional. 
    Id. As for
    the solicitation clause (Rule 4.1(A)(6)) prohibiting
    a judicial candidate from “personally solicit[ing] or
    accept[ing] campaign contributions other than through a
    campaign committee,” the district court held that it was
    constitutional as applied to non-judge candidates because it
    struck “a constitutional balance” between the state’s interest
    in the appearance and actuality of an impartial judiciary and
    a candidate’s need for funds. 
    Id. at 931.
    The district court
    found that all forms of personal solicitation, whether in-
    person or via signed mass mailings, created “the same risk of
    coercion and bias.” 
    Id. Wolfson timely
    appealed.
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                             11
    II.
    A.
    We review de novo an order granting summary judgment
    on the constitutionality of a statute. See Nunez by Nunez v.
    City of San Diego, 
    114 F.3d 935
    , 940 (9th Cir. 1997).
    B.
    Wolfson seeks to invalidate the challenged Rules on their
    face, including as to sitting judges campaigning for retention
    or reelection. In Wolfson I, however, we held that “Wolfson
    cannot assert the constitutional rights of judges when he is
    not, and may never be, a member of that 
    group.” 616 F.3d at 1064
    .     Nonetheless, although we reject the Arizona
    defendants’ argument, which the district court adopted, that
    the balancing test applicable to government employee speech
    cases also applies to sitting judges and thus fairly extends to
    non-judge candidates campaigning for office, we must
    establish the scope of our review of the challenged Rules.
    We decline to adopt the district court’s approach because
    such reasoning requires a series of unnecessary constitutional
    decisions.7 Rather, our analysis of the challenged Rules is
    7
    We find no Supreme Court authority extending the limited First
    Amendment protection for public employee speech to judicial candidate
    speech, and we decline to answer the hypothetical question of whether
    sitting judges are sufficiently similar to rank-and-file government
    employees to warrant such application. See, e.g., White I, 536 U.S at 796
    (Kennedy, J., concurring). We also find no Supreme Court authority
    extending the limited First Amendment protection for employee speech to
    a private citizen who is not currently a government employee but merely
    seeks to become one. 
    Id. (“Petitioner Gregory
    Wersal was not a sitting
    12                  WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    based on Wolfson’s status as a non-judge candidate. While
    the Rules apply to judges whether or not a judge is actively
    campaigning for retention or reelection, they only apply to
    non-judge candidates during an election campaign for judicial
    office.8 There is a meaningful distinction in how the Rules
    actually apply to judges versus non-judge candidates that may
    warrant distinct levels of scrutiny. Regulated non-judge
    speech only takes place during a campaign. As noted above,
    political speech is subject to the highest degree of First
    Amendment protection. Because Wolfson’s desired speech
    would only take place in the context of a political campaign
    for judicial office, we do not decide whether the restrictions
    as applied to judges—whether campaigning or not—fit into
    the “narrow class of speech restrictions” that may be
    constitutionally permissible if “based on an interest in
    allowing governmental entities to perform their functions.”
    Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 
    558 U.S. 310
    , 341
    (2010).
    We are not persuaded that “fundamental fairness,” see
    Wolfson 
    II, 822 F. Supp. 2d at 929
    , warrants making an
    advisory decision about the constitutional speech rights of
    judges who are not presently before us and whose rights
    judge but a challenger; he had not voluntarily entered into an employment
    relationship with the State or surrendered any First Amendment rights. His
    speech may not be controlled or abridged in this manner.”). Nor do we
    take a position on a question explicitly unresolved by the Supreme Court
    in White I: whether the First Amendment “requires campaigns for judicial
    office to sound the same as those for legislative office.” 
    Id. at 783
    (majority opinion).
    8
    “When a person becomes a judicial candidate, this canon becomes
    applicable to his or her conduct.” Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 17A, Sup. Ct.
    Rules, Rule 81, Code of Jud. Conduct, Canon 4, cmt. 2 (2009).
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                       13
    Wolfson cannot assert, Wolfson 
    I, 616 F.3d at 1064
    . Under
    strict scrutiny, see Part III.A, the proponents of a speech
    regulation must establish a compelling state interest served by
    the regulation. Neither the Commission nor the State Bar
    Counsel has argued that Arizona has a compelling state
    interest in applying the same election regulations to
    incumbent sitting judges as to candidates who are not sitting
    judges—only that such an equal application is principled,
    logical, and fair.
    Our decision to limit our review to non-judge candidates
    is ultimately based on judicial restraint. We need not decide
    today what restrictions on judges’ speech are constitutionally
    justified by the interest in allowing the judiciary to function
    optimally, nor are we squarely presented with that question.
    We neither “‘anticipate a question of constitutional law in
    advance of the necessity of deciding it’ nor ‘formulate a rule
    of constitutional law broader than is required by the precise
    facts to which it is to be applied.’” Wash. State Grange v.
    Wash. State Republican Party, 
    552 U.S. 442
    , 450 (2008)
    (quoting Ashwander v. TVA, 
    297 U.S. 288
    , 347 (1936)
    (Brandeis, J., concurring)). The only constitutional question
    we address is whether the challenged Rules violate the First
    Amendment rights of non-judge candidates.
    III.
    A.
    Strict scrutiny applies to this First Amendment challenge.
    The regulations in question are content- and speaker-based
    restrictions on political speech, which receives the most
    stringent First Amendment protection. Republican Party of
    Minn. v. White, 
    416 F.3d 738
    , 748–49 (8th Cir. 2005) (White
    14               WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    II); see also Eu v. San Francisco Cnty. Democratic Cent.
    Comm., 
    489 U.S. 214
    , 223 (1989) (“[T]he First Amendment
    has its fullest and most urgent application to speech uttered
    during a campaign for political office.” (internal quotation
    marks omitted)). We recently applied strict scrutiny to
    another state statute regulating judicial elections because it
    was, “on its face, a content-based restriction on political
    speech and association [which] thereby threaten[ed] to
    abridge a fundamental right.” Sanders Cnty. Republican
    Cent. Comm. v. Bullock, 
    698 F.3d 741
    , 746 (9th Cir. 2012)
    (holding unconstitutional a ban on political party
    endorsement of judicial candidates).
    Content-based restrictions on speech receive strict
    scrutiny. See United States v. Playboy Entm’t Grp., Inc.,
    
    529 U.S. 803
    , 813 (2000). Here, the Rules at issue
    censor speech based on content in the most
    basic of ways: They prevent candidates from
    speaking about some subjects [who they
    endorse or on whose behalf they can speak if
    that person is running for office or if the entity
    is a political party] . . . ; and they prevent
    candidates from asking for support in some
    ways (campaign funds) but not in others (a
    vote, yard signs).
    Carey v. Wolnitzek, 
    614 F.3d 189
    , 198–99 (6th Cir. 2010).
    The canons do not address any of the “categorical carve-outs”
    of proscribable speech. See 
    id. at 199.
    Nor are they the types
    of regulations to which the Supreme Court has applied a less
    rigorous standard of review, such as time, place and manner
    restrictions, commercial speech, or expressive conduct. 
    Id. WOLFSON V.
    CONCANNON                                 15
    Every sister circuit except the Seventh that has considered
    similar regulations since White I has applied strict scrutiny as
    the standard of review. See Wersal v. Sexton, 
    674 F.3d 1010
    ,
    1019 (8th Cir. 2012) (en banc), cert. denied, 
    133 S. Ct. 209
    (2012); 
    Carey, 614 F.3d at 198
    –99; White 
    II, 416 F.3d at 749
    ,
    764–65; Weaver v. Bonner, 
    309 F.3d 1312
    , 1319 (11th Cir.
    2002). We are not persuaded by the Seventh Circuit’s
    approach, which the Arizona defendants urge us to adopt by
    asking us to affirm the district court.
    The Seventh Circuit treated the solicitation ban in Siefert
    as a “campaign finance regulation” and applied the “closely
    drawn scrutiny” framework of Buckley v. 
    Valeo, 608 F.3d at 988
    (citing 
    424 U.S. 1
    (1976) (per curiam)). The court
    treated the solicitation ban like a restriction on a campaign
    contribution—though by default, because the solicitation ban
    was not an expenditure restriction. 
    Id. Contrary to
    the
    Arizona defendants’ argument, the solicitation clause at issue
    here is not a restriction on a campaign contribution within the
    meaning of 
    Buckley, 424 U.S. at 26
    –27. Arizona’s
    solicitation ban does nothing at all to limit contributions to a
    judicial candidate’s campaign—either in amount or from
    certain persons or groups. Contribution restrictions, like
    those at issue in Buckley, restrict the speech of potential
    
    contributors. 424 U.S. at 21
    –22. The Rule at issue here
    restricts only the solicitation for the contributions—the
    speech of the candidate.9 Indeed, Buckley says nothing at all
    9
    See also 
    Carey, 614 F.3d at 200
    (“[T]his argument [that the solicitation
    clause is akin to a restriction on political donation subject to less rigorous
    scrutiny] gives analogy a bad name. The solicitation clause does not set
    a contribution limit, as in McConnell and similar cases. It flatly prohibits
    speech, not donations, based on the topic (solicitation of a contribution)
    and speaker (a judge or judicial candidate)—precisely the kind of content-
    16                    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    about solicitation, other than to note that candidates will ask
    for contributions. Buckley’s framework is inapposite here.10
    Considering a rule prohibiting a judge or judicial
    candidate from making endorsements or speaking on behalf
    of a partisan candidate or platform, the Seventh Circuit
    applied “a balancing approach” derived from a line of cases
    determining the speech rights of government employees.
    
    Siefert, 608 F.3d at 983
    –87. As noted in Part II.B, here we
    consider only the speech rights of Wolfson as a private citizen
    and judicial candidate—not yet, and perhaps never, a
    government employee. “[Wolfson] [i]s not a sitting judge but
    a challenger; he ha[s] not voluntarily entered into an
    employment relationship with the State or surrendered any
    First Amendment rights. His speech may not be controlled or
    abridged in this manner.” See White I, 536 U.S at 796
    (Kennedy, J., concurring). For the reasons discussed above,
    we decline to extend the rationale from the employee-speech
    based regulations that traditionally warrant strict scrutiny.” (internal
    citation omitted) (emphasis in original)).
    10
    Nor are we persuaded by the Commission defendants’ argument that
    the rules prohibiting solicitation “do not involve core political speech,”
    and that “[w]hen a candidate says ‘give me money,’ he adds nothing to the
    full and fair expression of ideas that the First Amendment protects.” This
    is a content-based distinction of pure speech that is not excepted from full
    First Amendment protection. See, e.g., Int'l Soc. for Krishna
    Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 
    505 U.S. 672
    , 677 (1992) (“It is uncontested
    that the solicitation at issue in this case is a form of speech protected under
    the First Amendment.”); Vill. of Schaumburg v. Citizens for a Better Env't,
    
    444 U.S. 620
    , 629 (1980) (“[S]oliciting funds involves interests protected
    by the First Amendment's guarantee of freedom of speech.”); Bates v.
    State Bar of Ariz., 
    433 U.S. 350
    , 363 (1977) (observing that the First
    Amendment protects speech “in the form of a solicitation to pay or
    contribute money”). This argument is wholly without merit.
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                             17
    cases to apply a lower level of scrutiny to the restrictions on
    Wolfson’s First Amendment rights during a judicial
    campaign.
    The Seventh Circuit also reasoned that a balancing
    approach was appropriate because endorsements are “a
    different form of speech” outside of “core” political speech
    thus having “limited communicative value,” and when judges
    make endorsements they are “speaking as judges, and trading
    on the prestige of their office to advance other political ends.”
    
    Siefert, 608 F.3d at 983
    , 984, 986.11 We do not hold the same
    view of endorsements by non-judge candidates. In Sanders
    County, we held that endorsements of judicial candidates are
    no different from other types of political speech: “Thus,
    political speech—including the endorsement of candidates for
    office—is at the core of speech protected by the First
    
    Amendment.” 698 F.3d at 745
    . Similarly, endorsements by
    candidates for office is also political speech protected by the
    First Amendment. Moreover, endorsements made by a non-
    judge candidate cannot trade on the prestige of an office that
    candidate does not yet hold.
    We share the Seventh Circuit’s concerns about protecting
    litigants’ due process rights, which we recognize as a
    compelling state interest. That court reasoned that because
    “restrictions on judicial speech may, in some circumstances,
    be required by the Due Process Clause,” states could regulate
    even political speech by judges if the regulations served the
    state’s interest in protecting litigants’ constitutional right to
    due process. 
    Siefert, 608 F.3d at 984
    . We agree that due
    11
    In this vein, the Commission defendants argue that endorsements have
    “limited communicative value” other than the desire to be a political
    powerbroker.
    18                  WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    process concerns are paramount, but this concern does not
    justify a categorically lower level of constitutional scrutiny
    for political speech by judicial candidates. Applying strict
    scrutiny, we can adequately assess whether regulations on a
    judicial candidate’s political speech are narrowly tailored to
    serve the state’s compelling interest in protecting litigants’
    due process rights. Narrow tailoring is most appropriate.
    Although we could scarcely imagine a more compelling state
    interest, we also recognize that “due process” concerns arise
    not in the ether, but “only . . . in the context of judicial
    proceedings.” See Michelle T. Friedland, Disqualification or
    Suppression: Due Process and the Response to Judicial
    Campaign Speech, 104 Colum. L. Rev. 563, 613 (2004).12
    We are mindful of the fact that we should endeavor to protect
    litigants from even the “potential for due process violations”
    or the “probability of unfairness.” See White 
    I, 536 U.S. at 815
    –16 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting) (emphasis added) (internal
    quotation marks omitted). The potential for and probability
    of a problem that in actuality arises only in real cases does
    not, however, translate into a generalized concern about the
    appearance or reality of an impartial judiciary warranting a
    lower level of scrutiny. Indeed, the Eighth Circuit identified
    the flaw in this argument.
    It is the general practice of electing judges,
    not the specific practice of judicial
    campaigning, that gives rise to impartiality
    concerns because the practice of electing
    judges creates motivations for sitting judges
    12
    “Even if a judicial candidate campaigned solely on the basis of his
    hatred and vindictiveness toward Joe Smith and the candidate were
    elected, no due process problem would be presented if Joe Smith were
    never involved in litigation or other proceedings before that judge.” 
    Id. WOLFSON V.
    CONCANNON                                 19
    and prospective judges in election years and
    non-election years to say and do things that
    will enhance their chances of being elected.
    
    Weaver, 309 F.3d at 1320
    ; accord White 
    I, 536 U.S. at 792
    (O’Connor, J., concurring) (“If the State has a problem with
    judicial impartiality, it is largely one the State brought upon
    itself by continuing the practice of popularly electing
    judges.”).13 Moreover, there is an equally compelling state
    interest in the free flow of information during a political
    campaign. “Deciding the relevance of candidate speech is the
    right of the voters, not the State.” White 
    I, 536 U.S. at 794
    (Kennedy, J., concurring). Whether and to what extent a
    judicial candidate chooses to engage in activities such as
    endorsing and making speeches on behalf of other candidates,
    fundraising for or taking part in other political campaigns, or
    asking for contributions is information that the electorate can
    use to decide whether he or she is qualified to hold judicial
    office. “The vast majority of states have judicial elections
    because of a belief that judges as government officials should
    be accountable to their constituents. By making this choice,
    the states, by definition, are turning judges into politicians.”
    Erwin Chemerinsky, Restrictions on the Speech of Judicial
    Candidates Are Unconstitutional, 
    35 Ind. L
    . Rev. 735, 736
    13
    See also Geary v. Renne, 
    911 F.2d 280
    , 294 (9th Cir. 1990) (en banc)
    (Reinhardt, J., concurring), vacated on other grounds, 
    501 U.S. 312
    (1991) (“The State of California cannot have it both ways. If it wants to
    elect its judges, it cannot deprive its citizens of a full and robust election
    debate. . . . Whether a judicial candidate wishes to make his views known
    on those issues during the electoral process is another matter. So is the
    question whether it is proper for him to do so. But those are all problems
    inherent in California’s decision to conduct judicial elections. If
    California wishes to elect its judges, it must allow free speech to prevail
    in the election process.”).
    20                   WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    (2002). Along with knowing a candidate’s views on legal or
    political issues, voters have a right to know how political their
    potential judge might be.14 To the extent states wish to avoid
    a politicized judiciary, they can choose to do so by not
    electing judges.
    B.
    Under strict scrutiny, the Arizona defendants have the
    burden to prove that the challenged Rules further a
    compelling interest and are narrowly tailored to achieve that
    interest. Citizens 
    United, 558 U.S. at 340
    . First we consider
    Arizona’s state interests. Then, we analyze whether the
    solicitation clause (Rule 4.1(A)(6)) and the political activities
    clauses (Rules 4.1(A)(2)–(5)) are narrowly tailored to serve
    those interests.
    1.
    Every court to consider the issue has affirmed that states
    have a compelling interest in the appearance and actuality of
    an impartial judiciary. See, e.g., White 
    I, 536 U.S. at 775
    –76.
    The meaning of “impartiality” is lack of bias for or against
    either party to a case. 
    Id. at 775.
    This definition accords with
    the idea that due process violations arise only in case-specific
    14
    See, e.g., Michael R. Dimino, Pay No Attention To That Man Behind
    The Robe: Elections, The First Amendment, and Judges As Politicians,
    21 Yale L. & Pol’y Rev. 301, 356 (2003) (“[S]tates that have rejected the
    federal model of judicial independence have necessarily accepted (if not
    celebrated) that some level of electoral accountability will play a part in
    their judges’ decisions. Accordingly, because there is nothing ‘corrupt’
    about the functioning of democracy, limiting speech so as to conceal the
    part that electoral politics does play in judicial decisions cannot be
    constitutionally justified.”).
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                            21
    contexts. The Supreme Court has also recognized that states
    have a compelling interest in preventing corruption or the
    appearance of corruption through campaign finance
    regulations. 
    Buckley, 424 U.S. at 26
    –27; see also Citizens
    
    United, 558 U.S. at 357
    . Thus, we recognize that Arizona has
    a compelling interest in an uncorrupt judiciary that appears to
    be and is impartial to the parties who appear before its judges.
    The Arizona defendants also argue for two other
    compelling interests that we do not find persuasive. First, the
    Commission defendants argue that “the State has a
    compelling interest in preventing candidates (who will after
    all be the next judges if and when elected) from trampling on
    the interests of impartiality and public confidence.” This
    argument is, essentially, that states have a compelling interest
    in regulating candidates’ speech; we do not find an interest in
    regulating speech per se to be compelling. We do agree,
    however, that states have a compelling interest in maintaining
    public confidence in the judiciary. In a similar vein, State
    Bar Counsel argues that Arizona has a compelling interest in
    avoiding “judicial campaign abuses that threaten to imperil
    public confidence in the fairness and integrity of the nation’s
    elected judges.” But, as explained above, any imperilment of
    public confidence has its roots in the very nature of judicial
    elections, and not in the speech of candidates who must
    participate in those elections to become judges. See White 
    I, 536 U.S. at 792
    (O’Connor, J., concurring).15 If a judicial
    candidate wishes to engage in politicking to achieve a seat on
    15
    The reality is that the Rules do not “change the circumstances or
    pressures that cause the candidates to want to make [prohibited]
    statements,” and that “[j]udicial campaign speech codes are therefore
    much more about maintaining appearances by hiding reality than about
    changing reality.” Friedland, 104 Colum. L. Rev. at 612.
    22                   WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    the bench, keeping the public ignorant of that fact may
    conceal valuable information about how well that candidate
    may uphold the office of an ideally impartial, apolitical
    adjudicator.
    Second, the Commission defendants argue that Arizona
    has a compelling interest in “preventing judges and judicial
    candidates from using the prestige of their office or potential
    office for purposes not related to their judicial duties.” We
    are not persuaded by this argument as applied to non-judge
    candidates, who cannot abuse the prestige of an office they do
    not yet and may never hold.
    2.
    The solicitation clause prohibits a judicial candidate from
    “personally solicit[ing] or accept[ing] campaign contributions
    other than through a campaign committee authorized by Rule
    4.4.” Rule 4.1(A)(6).16 The Code defines “personally solicit”
    as “a direct request made by a judge or a judicial candidate
    for financial support or in-kind services, whether made by
    letter, telephone, or any other means of communication.”
    Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 17A, Sup. Ct. Rules, Rule 81, Code of
    Jud. Conduct, “Terminology” (2009). We hold that Rule
    16
    Wolfson argues that Rule 4.1(A)(4) is also a restriction on solicitation,
    because he wishes to solicit contributions to his own campaign committee,
    which he considers to be a “political organization.” But the Code
    explicitly carves out a judicial candidate’s campaign committee from the
    definition of “political organization.” See Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 17A,
    Sup. Ct. Rules, Rule 81, Code of Jud. Conduct, “Terminology” (2009).
    Therefore, we analyze Rule 4.1(A)(4) alongside (A)(2)–(3) and (5),
    because it prohibits a judicial candidate from soliciting funds on behalf of
    or donating to a specific political organization or candidate—classic
    political campaigning activities.
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                        23
    4.1(A)(6) is unconstitutional as applied to non-judge judicial
    candidates because it restricts speech that presents little to no
    risk of corruption or bias towards future litigants and is not
    narrowly tailored to serve those state interests.
    Arizona’s sweeping definition of “personally solicit”
    encompasses methods not likely to impinge on even the
    appearance of impartiality. The Sixth Circuit recently
    invalidated a similar clause in Kentucky that also extended
    beyond one-on-one, in-person solicitations to group
    solicitations, telephone calls, and letters. 
    Carey, 614 F.3d at 204
    . We agree with our sister court’s cogent analysis of this
    issue. “[I]ndirect methods of solicitation [such as speeches to
    large groups and signed mass mailings] present little or no
    risk of undue pressure or the appearance of a quid pro quo.”
    
    Id. at 205.
    The clauses are also underinclusive: a personal
    solicitation by a campaign committee member who may be
    the candidate’s best friend or close professional associate
    (such as a law practice partner) is likely to have a greater risk
    for “coercion and undue appearance” than a signed mass
    mailing or request during a speech to a large group. 
    Id. Moreover, the
    Code does not prohibit a candidate’s campaign
    committee from disclosing to the candidate the names of
    contributors and solicited non-contributors.
    That omission suggests that the only interest
    at play is the impolitic interpersonal dynamics
    of the candidate’s request for money, not the
    more corrosive reality of who gives and how
    much. If the purported risk addressed by the
    clause is that the judge or candidate will treat
    donors and non-donors differently, it is
    knowing who contributed and who balked that
    24                   WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    makes the difference, not who asked for the
    contribution.
    Id.17 The lack of narrow tailoring is obvious here: if
    impartiality or absence of corruption is the concern, what is
    the point of prohibiting judges from personally asking for
    solicitations or signing letters, if they are free to know who
    contributes and who balks at their committee’s request?
    Wersal teaches that the in-person “‘ask’ is precisely the
    speech [a state] must regulate to maintain its interest in
    impartiality and the appearance of impartiality” because of
    the greater risk of a quid pro 
    quo. 674 F.3d at 1029
    –31.
    Indeed, we agree with State Bar Counsel’s argument that “the
    very act of asking for money, personally, creates the
    impression that judge (and justice) may be for sale.” But the
    clause here sweeps more broadly. It is not necessary “to
    decide today whether a State could enact a narrowly tailored
    solicitation clause—say, one focused on one-on-one
    solicitations or solicitations from individuals with cases
    pending before the court—only that this clause does not do so
    narrowly.” 
    Carey, 614 F.3d at 206
    (emphasis in original).18
    17
    The lack of a non-disclosure-to-the-candidate requirement in
    Arizona’s Code presents the opposite situation of that in White II, where
    appellants challenged the fact that they could not solicit from large groups
    or via signed appeal letters. The Eighth Circuit found that the prohibition
    on disclosing to a candidate who contributed and who rebuffed meant the
    clause was “barely tailored at all to serve [the end of impartiality as to
    parties in a particular case]” or an interest in 
    “open-mindedness.” 416 F.3d at 765
    –66.
    18
    Indeed, the Eighth Circuit upheld the Minnesota solicitation clause
    even under strict scrutiny precisely because the challenged clause only
    prohibited direct, in-person solicitation, while the rest of Minnesota’s
    Code of Judicial Conduct permitted solicitation of groups and of a judge’s
    intimates. 
    Wersal, 674 F.3d at 1028
    –29. That court distinguished the
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                                 25
    The solicitation clause is invalid as applied to non-judge
    candidates.
    3.
    We analyze Rules 4.1(A)(2)–(5) as the “political
    activities” clauses. Judicial candidates are prohibited from
    speechifying for another candidate or organization, endorsing
    or opposing another candidate, fundraising for another
    candidate or organization, or actively taking part in any
    political campaign other than his or her own. These clauses
    are also not sufficiently narrowly tailored to serve the state’s
    interest in an impartial judiciary, and are thus unconstitutional
    restrictions on political speech of non-judge candidates for
    judicial office.
    Rules 4.1(A)(2)–(4)—prohibiting speechifying,
    endorsements, and fundraising—present the closest question.
    There is an argument that these rules are sufficiently narrowly
    tailored to be constitutional because they curtail speech that
    evidences bias towards a particular (potential) party within
    the scope of White I: the candidate or political organization
    endorsed or spoken of favorably by the judicial candidate. A
    plurality of the Eighth Circuit, sitting en banc, upheld a nearly
    identical Minnesota prohibition on a judge or judicial
    candidate endorsing “another candidate for public office”
    because such an endorsement “creates a risk of partiality
    outcome from that in White II, where an earlier version of the state’s Code
    of Judicial Conduct prohibited group solicitation and banned judges and
    candidates from signing fund appeal letters. 
    Id. at 1029.
    Direct personal
    solicitation “gives rise to a greater risk of quid pro quo,” 
    id., but the
    scope
    of Arizona’s solicitation clause is broader than Minnesota’s and we must
    consider all of the affected speech.
    26                   WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    towards the endorsed party and his or her supporters.”
    
    Wersal, 674 F.3d at 1024
    , 1025. The plurality concluded that
    the clause was narrowly tailored to serve the state’s
    compelling interest in the appearance and reality of an
    impartial judiciary. 
    Id. at 1028.19
    Nonetheless, we hold that these regulations are
    underinclusive because they only address speech that occurs
    beginning the day after a non-judge candidate has filed his
    intention to run for judicial office.20 The day before a private
    citizen becomes a judicial candidate, he or she could have
    been a major fundraiser or campaign manager for another
    19
    Judge Loken, joined by Judge Wollman, concurred in the result but
    agreed with the plurality’s judgment on the separate ground that the
    endorsement clause served the distinct compelling state interest in
    “protecting the political independence of its judiciary.” 
    Id. at 1033
    (“An
    endorsement links the judicial candidate’s political fortunes to a particular
    person, who may then come to hold office in a coordinate branch of
    government. This is antithetical to any well considered notion of judicial
    independence—that we are a ‘government of laws, not of men.’”) (Loken,
    J., concurring.).
    20
    The Wersal plurality concluded that the Minnesota endorsement
    clause was not underinclusive but only by reference to what it restricted:
    “endorsements for other candidate[s] for public office.” 
    Id. at 1027
    (internal quotation marks omitted) (emphasis added). That plurality noted
    that a separate clause in Minnesota’s Code of Judicial Conduct prevented
    a judge or judicial candidate from making any statement that would
    “reasonably be expected to affect the outcome or impair the fairness of a
    matter pending or impending in any court,” and reasoned that the two
    clauses read together meant that a judicial candidate was prevented from
    making any biased statement about a party or potential party, whether or
    not the target of the speech had become a candidate for public office at the
    time of the statement. 
    Id. We are
    concerned about the temporal
    dimension of a non-judge candidate’s speech, rather than the candidate
    status of its target.
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                      27
    elected official, or may have donated large sums of money to
    another’s political campaign, or may have himself been an
    elected politician. The Supreme Court confronted a similar
    underinclusive issue in White I. There, in explaining why the
    “announce clause” was underinclusive, the Court said
    In Minnesota, a candidate for judicial office
    may not say “I think it is constitutional for the
    legislature to prohibit same-sex marriages.”
    He may say the very same thing, however, up
    until the very day before he declares himself
    a candidate, and may say it repeatedly (until
    litigation is pending) after he is elected. As a
    means of pursuing the objective of
    open-mindedness that respondents now
    articulate, the announce clause is so woefully
    underinclusive as to render belief in that
    purpose a challenge to the credulous.
    White 
    I, 536 U.S. at 779
    –80. Here too, Rules 4.1(A)(2)–(4)
    are “woefully underinclusive” because they only address
    speech made after a candidate has filed his intention to enter
    the race. 
    Id. at 780.
    Contrary to the dissent, we fail to see
    why this same concern does not apply here.
    Moreover, the Arizona defendants have failed to show
    why the less restrictive remedy of recusal of a successful
    candidate from any case in which he or she was involved in
    a party’s political campaign or gave an endorsement is an
    unworkable alternative. “[B]ecause restricting speech should
    be the government’s tool of last resort, the availability of
    obvious less-restrictive alternatives renders a speech
    restriction overinclusive.” Valle Del Sol Inc. v. Whiting,
    
    709 F.3d 808
    , 826 (9th Cir. 2013). Here, it seems that if a
    28                  WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    candidate indeed becomes a judge, a less restrictive means of
    addressing the state’s concerns would be to require recusal in
    cases where the new judge’s bias against or in favor of a party
    is clear.21 Unlike the dissent and the plurality of the Eighth
    Circuit in Wersal, we decline to address hypothetical
    situations involving potential frequent litigants and single-
    judge counties. See Dissent at 46; 
    Wersal, 674 F.3d at 1027
    –28 (posing the hypothetical that “candidates and judges
    would be free to endorse individuals who would become
    frequent litigants in future cases, such as county sheriffs and
    prosecutors”). The Arizona defendants have not offered any
    evidence nor argued that these concerns exist, cf. 
    Siefert, 608 F.3d at 987
    , though they bear the burden of
    demonstrating that the Rules survive strict scrutiny. We
    decline to speculate on whether such a problem would exist
    in the Arizona judicial elections affected by these Rules.
    We hold Rule 4.1(A)(5), which prohibits a judicial
    candidate from “actively tak[ing] part in any political
    campaign other than his or her own campaign for election,
    reelection, or retention in office” to be unconstitutional
    because it is overbroad. By its terms, it is not limited to
    restrictions on participation in political campaigns on behalf
    of persons who may become parties to a suit, but may also
    include political campaigns on ballot propositions and other
    issues, including political campaigns for ballot propositions
    that present no risk of impartiality towards future parties.
    21
    See, e.g., Friedland, 104 Colum. L. Rev. at 614 (“[T]he proper
    response to judicial campaign speech that could threaten Fourteenth
    Amendment due process rights may be to allow the speech and then, if a
    case arises in which the judge’s former campaign speech poses a problem,
    to assign that case to another judge.”).
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                        29
    Thus, Rule 4.1(A)(5) unconstitutionally prohibits protected
    speech about legal issues. White 
    I, 536 U.S. at 776
    –78.
    IV.
    For these reasons, we reverse the district court’s grant of
    summary judgment to the Arizona defendants. We hold that
    strict scrutiny applies and that the challenged portions of the
    Arizona Code of Judicial conduct unconstitutionally restrict
    the speech of non-judge judicial candidates. We remand the
    case for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
    REVERSED and REMANDED.
    BERZON, Circuit Judge, concurring:
    Sitting for judicial election while judging cases, Justice
    Otto Kaus famously quipped, is like “brushing your teeth in
    the bathroom and trying not to notice the crocodile in the
    bathtub.” Joseph R. Grodin, In Pursuit of Justice: Reflections
    of a State Supreme Court Justice 177 (1989) (quoting Kaus).
    Kaus would know. He sat on the California Supreme Court
    from 1981 to 1985, Gerald T. McLaughlin, Memorial
    Dedication to Otto Kaus, 30 Loy. L.A. L. Rev. 923, 923
    (1997), having narrowly won a retention election in 1982 and
    retiring from the court soon before the 1986 vote that would
    unseat three of his former colleagues, Stephen R. Barnett,
    30                   WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    Otto and the Court, 30 Loy. L.A. L. Rev. 943, 947 & n.19
    (1997).1
    Kaus’ point about the psychology of judging applies
    outside the context of judicial elections, for the temptation to
    engage in overt political behavior affects judges generally.
    And so I write separately to identify, and hopefully to tame,
    the “crocodile” stalking today’s majority opinion: the
    prospect that the principles we apply now will be used in
    future litigation to challenge the constitutionality of
    restrictions on the political behavior of sitting judges. The
    opinion studiously — and designedly — does not address that
    issue. But it is worth explaining why, in my view, the
    considerations pertinent to evaluating the complex of
    constitutional issues raised by such restrictions are quite
    different than those the majority opinion applies today.
    I.
    Today’s opinion addresses the constitutionality of certain
    provisions of the Arizona Code of Judicial Conduct (“Code”)
    only as they apply to judicial candidates who, like Wolfson,
    have not yet ascended to the bench. It does not decide those
    provisions’ constitutionality as they apply to elected judges
    1
    Justices of the California Supreme Court and Judges of the California
    Court of Appeal are nominated by the Governor, confirmed by the
    Commission on Judicial Appointments, and then subject to voter approval
    in a retention election at the time of the next gubernatorial election and,
    thereafter, at the end of each 12-year term. See Cal. Const. art. 6, § 16(d);
    Cal. Elec. Code § 9083. Judges of the California Superior Court usually
    sit for general election every six years, Cal. Const. art. 6, § 16(b), unless
    an incumbent is not unopposed, Cal. Elec. Code § 8203, or a county
    adopts by majority popular vote the retention-election system applicable
    to appellate judges, Cal. Elec. Code § 8220.
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                            31
    who, like Kaus, have already taken their oaths of office. Still
    less does it decide the constitutionality of restrictions on the
    political activity of judges who, like us on the federal bench,
    “hold their Offices during good Behaviour,” U.S. Const. art.
    III, § 1, and never sit for election. In the name of prudence
    and constitutional avoidance, the majority’s opinion rightly
    reserves judgment on the constitutionality of restricting the
    speech of sitting judges, an issue neither properly before us
    nor necessary to the resolution of this case.
    I emphasize the limited scope of today’s decision for fear
    that future litigants might otherwise seek to obscure it,
    despite the repeated admonishments in the opinion. Of the
    five Code provisions we strike today, only one — the
    solicitation ban — directly relates to a judicial candidate’s
    own campaign for office.2 The remainder prohibit a would-be
    judge’s efforts to advance the political fortunes of other
    candidates or causes, through speeches, endorsements,
    fundraising, financial support, or other campaign assistance.3
    2
    The full text of the provision is as follows:
    (A) A judge or judicial candidate shall not . . . .
    (6) personally solicit or accept campaign contributions
    other than through a campaign committee authorized by
    Rule 4.4 . . . .
    Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 17A, Sup. Ct. Rules, Rule 81, Code of Jud.
    Conduct (2009), Rule 4.1(A)(6).
    3
    The full text of the provision is as follows:
    (A) A judge or judicial candidate shall not do any of the
    following:
    32                 WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    As these proscriptions bear little direct relation to judicial
    candidates’ personal political fortunes, a casual reader might
    be forgiven for assuming that they are just as constitutionally
    offensive as applied outside the election context, to sitting
    judges, whether or not they reached the bench via election.
    In my view, that is not so, for at least two reasons: The
    analytic framework applicable to political restrictions on
    sitting judges may well differ from the one we apply today.
    And the compelling state interest that could well justify such
    restrictions differs from the one emphasized in the majority
    opinion. I address each difference in turn.
    ....
    (2) make speeches on behalf of a political organization
    or another candidate for public office;
    (3) publicly endorse or oppose another candidate for
    any public office;
    (4) solicit funds for or pay an assessment to a political
    organization or candidate, make contributions to any
    candidate or political organization in excess of the
    amounts permitted by law, or make total contributions
    in excess of fifty percent of the cumulative total
    permitted by law . . . .
    (5) actively take part in any political campaign other
    than his or her own campaign for election, reelection or
    retention in office . . . .
    Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 17A, Sup. Ct. Rules, Rule 81, Code of Jud.
    Conduct (2009), Rule 4.1(A)(2)–(5).
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                        33
    II.
    In applying strict scrutiny to a judicial candidate who is
    not now a judge, today’s majority opinion rightly rejects the
    Seventh Circuit’s approach, which applies to political
    restrictions on elected sitting judges a balancing test derived
    from the Supreme Court’s cases on public employee speech.
    Bauer v. Shepard, 
    620 F.3d 704
    (7th Cir. 2010); Siefert v.
    Alexander, 
    608 F.3d 974
    (7th Cir. 2010). Although such a
    tempered standard has no application to a candidate who has
    not yet taken his oath of judicial office, whether it would be
    appropriately applied to political restrictions governing sitting
    judges is quite a different manner.
    The Constitution permits the government to prohibit its
    employees from speaking about matters of public concern
    where the government’s interest “in promoting the efficiency
    of the public services it performs through its employees”
    outweighs the First Amendment interest in speech. Pickering
    v. Bd. of Educ. of Twp. High Sch. Dist. 205, Will Cnty., Ill.,
    
    391 U.S. 563
    , 568 (1968). The Pickering balancing test seeks
    “both to promote the individual and societal interests that are
    served when employees speak as citizens on matters of public
    concern and to respect the needs of government employers
    attempting to perform their important public functions.”
    Garcetti v. Ceballos, 
    547 U.S. 410
    , 420 (2006). And that test
    recognizes that “there are certain governmental functions that
    cannot operate without some restrictions on particular kinds
    of speech.” Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n,
    
    558 U.S. 310
    , 341 (2010).
    Republican Party of Minnesota v. White, 
    536 U.S. 765
    (2002), did not decide whether the public employee speech
    cases would justify restrictions on judges’ active support for
    34               WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    political causes or the candidacies of others. Justice
    Kennedy, who was a member of the five-justice majority,
    wrote a separate concurrence, explaining this limitation:
    “Whether the rationale of Pickering[, 
    391 U.S. 563
    ], and
    Connick v. Myers, 
    461 U.S. 138
    (1983), could be extended to
    allow a general speech restriction on sitting judges —
    regardless of whether they are campaigning — in order to
    promote the efficient administration of justice, is not an issue
    raised here.” 
    White, 536 U.S. at 796
    (Kennedy, J.,
    concurring).
    In 
    Siefert, 608 F.3d at 985
    , the Seventh Circuit extended
    the public employee speech cases to a provision of the
    Wisconsin Code of Judicial Conduct prohibiting an elected
    sitting judge from “[p]ublicly endors[ing] or speak[ing] on
    behalf of [a political party’s] candidates or platforms,” 
    id. at 978–79.
    It reasoned that the government’s authority as an
    employer, “its duty to promote the efficiency of the public
    services it performs,” and the imperative that “the work of the
    judiciary conform[] with the due process requirements of the
    Constitution” justified a less rigorous balancing test for
    restrictions on elected sitting judges’ participation in the
    political campaigns or candidacies of others. 
    Id. at 985.
    In
    a subsequent decision, the Seventh Circuit extended this
    balancing test to provisions of the Indiana Code of Judicial
    Conduct prohibiting elected judges from leading or holding
    office in political organizations or making speeches on behalf
    of such organizations. 
    Bauer, 620 F.3d at 710
    –11.
    The core rationale of the public employee speech cases,
    on which Siefert and Bauer relied, does not apply to the case
    presently before us. Wolfson has never been an employee of
    Arizona, let alone a judge. Indeed, he may never become
    one. While the public employee speech cases do not rest
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                        35
    solely on the now-antiquated principle that the government
    can condition employment on the waiver of First Amendment
    rights, see 
    Myers, 461 U.S. at 143
    –44, the nature of
    government employment is a necessary component of their
    reasoning. Pickering recognized as much, commenting that
    “it cannot be gainsaid that the State has interests as an
    employer in regulating the speech of its employees that differ
    significantly from those it possesses in connection with
    regulation of the speech of the citizenry in 
    general.” 391 U.S. at 568
    . The public employee speech cases thus recognize the
    “crucial difference, with respect to constitutional analysis,
    between the government exercising ‘the power to regulate or
    license, as lawmaker,’ and the government acting ‘as
    proprietor, to manage [its] internal operation.’” Engquist v.
    Or. Dep’t of Agric., 
    553 U.S. 591
    , 598 (alteration in original)
    (quoting Cafeteria & Rest. Workers v. McElroy, 
    367 U.S. 886
    , 896 (1961)). Critically, the balancing test the Pickering
    line of cases articulates does not apply to governmental
    restrictions on the speech of those, like judicial candidates,
    not employed by the government. We could not abandon that
    determinative distinction without dangerously expanding the
    scope of constitutionally permissible regulation of speech.
    But our refusal to apply to a judicial candidate not yet a
    state employee a balancing test derived from the public
    employee speech cases says nothing whatever about the
    applicability of such a test to individuals who have already
    taken their oaths of judicial office and already receive wages
    from the state.        That question remains unanswered.
    Resolving the First Amendment challenge of a sitting judge
    to similar restrictions on his speech will require answering it.
    And, without prejudging whether we should adopt the Siefert
    analysis for restrictions on political activity by sitting judges
    on behalf of political causes or the candidacies of others, I
    36                WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    suggest that the analogy to the Pickering line of cases has
    much to commend it.
    III.
    Even if we determined that restrictions on the political
    activity of sitting judges were subject to strict scrutiny, the
    state interest supporting such a restriction would be far
    stronger than the one we hold inadequate to justify the
    restrictions on judicial candidate Wolfson’s speech today.
    The Supreme Court has recognized as a “vital state
    interest” the interest in maintaining those “safeguard[s]
    against judicial campaign abuses that threaten to imperil
    public confidence in the fairness and integrity of the nation’s
    elected judges.” Caperton v. A.T. Massey Coal Co., 
    556 U.S. 868
    , 889 (2009) (emphasis added) (internal quotation marks
    and citation omitted). Preserving public confidence includes
    maintaining the perception of judicial propriety. In other
    words, “‘justice must satisfy the appearance of justice.’” In
    re Murchison, 
    349 U.S. 133
    , 136 (1955) (quoting Offutt v.
    United States, 
    348 U.S. 11
    , 14 (1954)). “[T]he appearance of
    evenhanded justice . . . is at the core of due process.”
    Mayberry v. Pennsylvania, 
    400 U.S. 455
    , 469 (1971) (Harlan,
    J., concurring).
    The majority opinion, taking its cue from Supreme Court
    cases on judicial elections, focuses its strict scrutiny analysis
    on the interest in preserving the actuality and appearance of
    judicial impartiality. The case law’s emphasis on impartiality
    derives from the obligations imposed by the due process
    clause, particularly “the proposition that an impartial judge is
    essential to due process.” 
    White, 536 U.S. at 776
    . This
    compelling interest in preserving the appearance of
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                        37
    impartiality is both weighty and narrow: weighty, because it
    rises to the level of a constitutional obligation, requiring a
    judge to recuse himself from a particular case in the name of
    due process, 
    Caperton, 556 U.S. at 886
    –87; and narrow,
    because it refers only to “lack of bias for or against either
    party to the proceeding,” 
    White, 536 U.S. at 775
    –76
    (emphasis in original). Given this narrow focus on the parties
    appearing before a judge in an actual proceeding, the less-
    restrictive remedy of mandatory recusal is available to a state
    seeking to protect, as it must, the due process rights of
    litigants appearing in its courts.
    But I would define the state’s interest in preserving public
    confidence in its judiciary more broadly, as reaching beyond
    the process due specific litigants in particular cases.
    Maintaining public trust in the judiciary as an institution
    driven by legal principles rather than political concerns is a
    structural imperative. The rule of law depends upon it.
    The fundamental importance of this structural imperative
    has been recognized from the founding of the nation. As
    Alexander Hamilton emphasized in The Federalist No. 78,
    the courts possess “neither FORCE nor WILL, but merely
    judgment . . . .” 
    Id. at 433
    (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961).
    Deprived of those alternative sources of power, the authority
    of the judiciary instead “lies . . . in its legitimacy, a product
    of substance and perception that shows itself in the people’s
    acceptance of the Judiciary as fit to determine what the . . .
    law means and to declare what it demands.” Planned
    Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
    , 865 (1992);
    see also 
    White, 536 U.S. at 793
    (Kennedy, J., concurring)
    (“The power and the prerogative of a court . . . rest, in the
    end, upon the respect accorded to its judgments.”). It is the
    courts’ perceived legitimacy as institutions grounded in
    38                   WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    established legal principles, not partisanship, “that leads
    decisions to be obeyed and averts vigilantism and civil
    strife.” 
    Bauer, 620 F.3d at 712
    . Loss of judicial legitimacy
    thus corrodes the rule of law, “sap[ping] the foundations of
    public and private confidence, and . . . introduc[ing] in its
    stead universal distrust and distress.” The Federalist No. 78,
    at 438. In this sense, “[t]he rule of law, which is a foundation
    of freedom, presupposes a functioning judiciary respected for
    its independence, its professional attainments, and the
    absolute probity of its judges.” NY State Bd. of Elections v.
    Lopez Torres, 
    552 U.S. 196
    , 212 (2008) (Kennedy, J.,
    concurring).
    This nation’s political history demonstrates the disastrous
    effects of the perceived politicization of the courts. Charges
    that King George “ha[d] obstructed the Administration of
    Justice” and “ha[d] made judges dependent on his Will alone
    . . . .” were among the founding generation’s justifications for
    the 1776 revolution. The Declaration of Independence para.
    11 (U.S. 1776). Similar concerns apply outside the context
    of a monarchy: Where the judiciary is drawn into the political
    intrigues of its coordinate branches, the public might well
    “fear that the pestilential breath of faction may poison the
    fountains of justice. The habit of being continually marshaled
    on opposite sides will be too apt to stifle the voice both of law
    and of equity.” The Federalist No. 81, at 452 (Alexander
    Hamilton) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961).4 And where the
    4
    This quotation appears in an explanation of why the Supreme Court is
    “composed of a distinct body of magistrates, instead of being one of the
    branches of the legislature, as in the government of Great Britain . . . .”
    
    Id. at 451.
    But the dangers of perceived partisanship apply at least as
    much to judges independently chosen but participating publicly in the
    selection of legislative or executive policies and decisionmakers.
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                              39
    politicization of the judiciary brings it into alliance with the
    politicians who staff the other two branches of government,
    the public may no longer consider “the courts of justice . . . as
    the bulwark of a limited Constitution against legislative
    encroachments,” The Federalist No. 78, at 437, or executive
    excesses. In short, when sitting judges support the campaigns
    of nonjudicial candidates — via endorsements, speeches,
    money, or other means — the public may begin to see them
    not as neutral arbiters of a limited system of governance, but
    as participants in the larger game of politics.5
    The defendants here express precisely this concern — that
    if sitting judges may support the campaigns of others, the
    public will perceive them as masters of the political game,
    powerbrokers “trading on the prestige of their office to
    advance other political ends . . . .” 
    Siefert, 608 F.3d at 984
    ;
    see also Model Code of Judicial Conduct R. 4.1, cmt.4 (2011)
    (justifying prohibitions on endorsements and speeches on
    behalf of other candidates as “prevent[ing sitting judges]
    from abusing the prestige of judicial office to advance the
    interests of others”). The opposite fear is equally justified:
    Today’s powerbroker is tomorrow’s pawn, as the political
    winds shift and the next election cycle approaches. The
    endorsing judge entwines his fate with whomever he endorses
    and earns the enmity of his favored politician’s opponents.
    5
    I leave aside whether sitting judges may endorse or support other
    candidates for judicial office. Such support does not implicate the
    powerful state interest in the appearance of judicial independence from the
    political branches I discuss in the text. Moreover, a sitting judge’s
    endorsement of a judicial candidate is a singularly effective mode of voter
    education. Few observers are as qualified as sitting judges to evaluate the
    competencies of those who would join their ranks. The concerns and
    analyses in this concurring opinion are therefore limited to judicial
    participation in issue, legislative, and executive elections.
    40                WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    “This kind of personal affiliation between a member of the
    judiciary and a member of the political branches raises the
    specter — readily perceived by the general public — that the
    judge’s future rulings will be influenced by this political
    dependency.” Wersal v. Sexton, 
    674 F.3d 1010
    , 1034 (8th
    Cir. 2012) (Loken, J., concurring in the judgment) (emphasis
    in original).
    In his concurrence in Wersal, Judge Loken concluded that
    there is a “compelling state interest . . . in protecting the
    political independence of its judiciary.” 
    Id. at 1033
    . I have
    no reason at this juncture to come to rest on that question.
    Instead, I emphasize that, at the very least, there is a powerful
    state interest in preventing sitting judges from playing the
    part of political powerbroker and creating the publicly visible
    interdependence that corrodes confidence in judicial
    autonomy. Assessing whether that interest qualifies as
    “compelling,” in the lexicon of First Amendment doctrine,
    awaits a properly presented case — particularly as the issue
    will never arise if we first determine that the Pickering
    balancing test, rather than strict scrutiny, applies to speech
    restrictions on sitting judges.
    Almost certainly, a state does not forfeit this powerful
    interest in judicial autonomy by selecting its judges via
    popular election. It was in the context of a state prohibition
    against judicial candidates expressing their personal views on
    disputed legal and political issues during their own campaigns
    that the Supreme Court has explained that “‘the greater power
    to dispense with elections altogether does not include the
    lesser power to conduct elections under conditions of state-
    imposed voter ignorance. If the State chooses to tap the
    energy and the legitimizing power of the democratic process,
    it must accord the participants in that process . . . the First
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                               41
    Amendment rights that attach to their roles.’” 
    White, 536 U.S. at 788
    (alteration in original) (quoting Renne v.
    Geary, 
    501 U.S. 312
    , 349 (1991) (Marshall, J., dissenting)).
    But that observation does not seem to extend to prohibitions
    on campaigning on behalf of issue elections or for nonjudicial
    candidates. The Supreme Court’s case law on the political
    behavior of government employees has “carefully
    distinguishe[d] between [proscribable] partisan political
    activities and mere expressions of views,” which are
    constitutionally protected. Biller v. U.S. Merit Sys. Prot. Bd.,
    
    863 F.2d 1079
    , 1089 (2d Cir. 1988) (citing U.S. Civil Serv.
    Comm’n v. Nat’l Ass’n of Letter Carriers, AFL-CIO, 
    413 U.S. 548
    , 554–56 (1973), and United Pub. Workers of Am. v.
    Mitchell, 
    330 U.S. 75
    , 98–99 (1947)); 
    Siefert, 608 F.3d at 984
    ; see also Citizens 
    United, 558 U.S. at 341
    (citing Letter
    Carriers in support of the proposition that the Supreme Court
    has often “upheld a narrow class of speech restrictions that
    operate to the disadvantage of certain persons, . . . based on
    an interest in allowing governmental entities to perform their
    functions”).6      Indeed, prohibitions on supporting the
    campaigns of others complement, rather than contradict, the
    decision to select judges via popular election: By adopting
    such restrictions alongside judicial elections, states harness
    the “legitimizing power of the democratic process” while
    avoiding worrisome interdependence between judges and
    politicians from the remaining two branches.
    6
    It is true that an elected judge’s support of another candidate or cause
    signals something about his views, which might be marginally useful to
    voters assessing their options at the polls. See 
    Siefert, 608 F.3d at 994
    –95
    (Rovner, J., dissenting) (“We are, after all, often judged by the company
    we keep.”). But so long as an elected judge may articulate his personal
    views of legal and political issues in support of his own campaign,
    attentive voters have a far more direct means with which to form an
    opinion about competing judicial candidates.
    42                    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    Nor should we forget that our own federal scheme
    supplements its structural protections for judicial autonomy
    with direct prohibitions on politicking. Structurally, our
    Constitution endows judges with life tenure and prohibits the
    diminution of their salaries. U.S. Const. art. III, § 1. Such
    protections seek to encourage “that independent spirit in the
    judges which must be essential to the faithful performance of
    so arduous a duty,” The Federalist No. 78, at 437, and help
    “preserve[] the independence of the Federal Judiciary,”
    
    White, 536 U.S. at 795
    (Kennedy, J., concurring). In addition
    to those structural safeguards the federal judiciary has
    adopted a code of ethics that regulates directly the behavior
    of federal judges, including restrictions on supporting the
    political causes and candidacies of others.7 Our ethical code
    7
    The full text of the relevant canon provides:
    (A) A judge should not:
    (1) act as a leader or hold any office in a political
    organization;
    (2) make speeches for a political organization or
    candidate, or publicly endorse a candidate for public
    office; or
    (3) solicit funds for, pay an assessment to, or make a
    contribution to a political organization or candidate, or
    attend or purchase a ticket for a dinner or other event
    sponsored by a political organization or candidate.
    (B) A judge should resign the judicial office if a judge
    becomes a candidate in a primary or general election
    for any office.
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                              43
    is independent of the structural safeguards that insulate us
    from the political branches, and it performs a slightly
    different function. I see no reason why a state cannot adopt
    the one without the other, except with regard to a judicial
    candidate’s personal campaign for judicial office in states
    where judicial elections are held.
    Critically, the state interest in preserving an autonomous
    judiciary is powerful only insofar as it applies to sitting
    judges; it has no application to judicial candidates who, like
    Wolfson, have not yet reached the bench. The spectacle of
    sitting judges aiding partisan allies in their political struggles
    corrodes the public repute of the judiciary in a way that the
    participation of a mere candidate never can. Indeed, the
    interest in an independent judiciary does not come into
    existence until a judge assumes office; the politicking of lay
    people cannot damage the reputation of a body whose ranks
    they have not yet joined. Individuals who run for judicial
    office may themselves be officers of political parties or
    holders of nonjudicial political office when they decide to run
    for a judgeship. That politicians can become judges is no
    secret. But that is different from allowing judges to remain
    or become politicians while still on the bench. Moreover, as
    the majority opinion explains, a layman who has not yet
    assumed office has no prestige derived from the office he has
    not yet attained to lend his political brethren. Essentially,
    (C) A judge should not engage in any other political
    activity. This provision does not prevent a judge from
    engaging in activities described in Canon 4.
    Administrative Office of U.S. Courts, Code of Judicial Conduct for United
    States Judges, Canon 5 (2011).
    44                WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    ascending to the bench is like taking the veil, and that veil
    does not descend until the oath of office is sworn.
    Meanwhile, to the extent White sought to preserve voters’
    access to “relevant information” and to prevent “state-
    imposed voter ignorance” about the candidates sitting for
    
    election, 536 U.S. at 782
    , 788 (internal quotation marks
    omitted), such concerns are weaker for already seated judges.
    Such judges already possess a record of decisions that
    interested voters can analyze to inform themselves about the
    desirability of competing judicial candidates; under White,
    they are free to campaign for their own reelection by drawing
    attention to their records on the bench. By contrast, lay
    people, like Wolfson, who have not yet sat on the bench lack
    any such judicial record, making their campaign speech —
    including endorsements — relatively more valuable for what
    it reveals about how they might perform in office.
    *   *    *
    In sum, the principles applicable to the constitutionality
    of political restrictions on sitting judges diverge dramatically
    from those we apply to today’s challenge to restrictions on a
    judicial candidate not now a judge. The standard of review
    may well differ. And the powerful interests supporting such
    restrictions differ, too. I need not address, as the issue is not
    before us, whether the particular restrictions we review today
    would be constitutional as applied to sitting judges. But I am
    quite sure that the analysis required to resolve that question
    will receive scant support from our decision in this case.
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                        45
    TALLMAN, Circuit Judge, dissenting in part:
    I agree with the majority that strict scrutiny—not
    Seifert—is the appropriate standard. I agree that we should
    limit our decision to non-incumbent judicial candidates. And
    I agree that Rules 4.1(a)(5) (campaigning for others) and
    4.1(a)(6) (personal solicitation) are unconstitutional as
    applied to those candidates. I concur in the majority opinion
    only on those points. I part company with my colleagues as
    to Rules 4.1(a)(2) (giving speeches on behalf of others),
    (3) (endorsing others), and (4) (soliciting money for others).
    These three rules are constitutional because they are narrowly
    tailored to serve the state’s compelling interest in maintaining
    judicial impartiality and its appearance—the hallmark of
    government’s third branch.
    My colleagues acknowledge that these three rules
    “present the closest question,” and that the Eighth Circuit
    upheld similar ones. 
    Wersal, 674 F.3d at 1024
    –25.
    Nonetheless, the majority concludes that they are not
    narrowly tailored for two reasons: timing and recusal. The
    timing argument is that the rules are underinclusive because
    “they only address speech that occurs beginning the day after
    a non-judge candidate has filed his intention to run for
    judicial office.” The recusal argument is that the rules are
    more restrictive than recusal, i.e., requiring judges who have
    campaigned for others to recuse themselves when those
    others show up as litigants. I dissent because I do not find
    these reasons persuasive.
    The majority’s timing argument is clever but impractical.
    Its breadth alone suggests this. The argument would cut
    down any restriction (a) that is subject to strict scrutiny and
    (b) that starts to apply to people only after some triggering
    46                WOLFSON V. CONCANNON
    event. If the restriction’s enactment counts as a triggering
    event, and I don’t see why it wouldn’t, then strict scrutiny
    would always be fatal. That cannot be the law.
    Moreover, the argument doesn’t actually answer the
    question, which is whether there are less restrictive ways to
    preserve judicial impartiality and its appearance. Having no
    rules is, of course, less restrictive. But it isn’t an alternative
    means of furthering the interest at stake here. Any actual
    alternative will suffer from the timing problem the majority
    identifies. So the timing argument tells us nothing about
    which alternative is the least restrictive; it only identifies a
    problem that all conceivable alternatives share.
    The majority’s recusal argument, like the timing
    argument, is too impractical in my view. In Arizona, only
    very small counties elect judges. And some small counties
    may well have only one superior court judge. If that one
    judge campaigns for someone who is then elected sheriff or
    district attorney, an outside judge would be necessary in
    every criminal case and in all civil cases involving the county
    where the district attorney is its lawyer. Constant recusal is
    no solution.
    That’s what the Eighth Circuit held in Wersal, after it
    considered this obvious 
    problem. 674 F.3d at 1027
    –28. The
    majority, on the other hand, recognizes the problem, but then
    sidesteps it, claiming that the state failed to raise it and that
    dealing with it would require us to speculate. I disagree.
    There’s no need to speculate about something so self-evident.
    And it’s hard to fault the state for failing to dwell on the
    obvious.
    WOLFSON V. CONCANNON                       47
    In sum, I don’t buy the timing or recusal arguments. And
    without them, there’s nothing that prevents us from declaring
    that these three rules are the least restrictive means at
    Arizona’s disposal for furthering their compelling interest in
    maintaining judicial impartiality and its appearance. Simply
    affixing the label of strict scrutiny and then declaring that
    unspecified less restrictive means are required gives no
    guidance as to what rules pass constitutional muster. And it
    encourages an elective free-for-all that undermines respect for
    the third branch of government. Because my colleagues
    disagree, I respectfully dissent.
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 11-17634

Citation Numbers: 750 F.3d 1145, 2014 WL 1856390, 2014 U.S. App. LEXIS 8761

Judges: Paez, Berzon, Tallman

Filed Date: 5/9/2014

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 11/5/2024

Authorities (25)

Ashwander v. Tennessee Valley Authority , 56 S. Ct. 466 ( 1936 )

Garcetti v. Ceballos , 126 S. Ct. 1951 ( 2006 )

Cafeteria & Restaurant Workers Union, Local 473 v. McElroy , 81 S. Ct. 1743 ( 1961 )

Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey , 112 S. Ct. 2791 ( 1992 )

Republican Party of Minnesota v. White , 122 S. Ct. 2528 ( 2002 )

Caperton v. A. T. Massey Coal Co., Inc. , 129 S. Ct. 2252 ( 2009 )

George M. Weaver v. Jerry B. Blackstock , 309 F.3d 1312 ( 2002 )

Morris Biller and Vincent R. Sombrotto v. United States ... , 863 F.2d 1079 ( 1988 )

Wersal v. Sexton , 674 F.3d 1010 ( 2012 )

bob-geary-robert-silvestri-dennis-mark-melissa-gundrun-wayne-johnson-david , 911 F.2d 280 ( 1990 )

Washington State Grange v. Washington State Republican Party , 128 S. Ct. 1184 ( 2008 )

Village of Schaumburg v. Citizens for a Better Environment , 100 S. Ct. 826 ( 1980 )

International Society for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee , 112 S. Ct. 2701 ( 1992 )

Wolfson v. Brammer , 822 F. Supp. 2d 925 ( 2011 )

Carey v. Wolnitzek , 614 F.3d 189 ( 2010 )

Bauer v. Shepard , 620 F.3d 704 ( 2010 )

gabriel-nunez-a-minor-by-rene-nunez-his-guardian-ad-litem-jennifer , 114 F.3d 935 ( 1997 )

Bates v. State Bar of Arizona , 97 S. Ct. 2691 ( 1977 )

In Re Murchison. , 75 S. Ct. 623 ( 1955 )

Renne v. Geary , 111 S. Ct. 2331 ( 1991 )

View All Authorities »