Kevin Jones, Jr. v. K. Harrington ( 2016 )


Menu:
  •                   FOR PUBLICATION
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT
    KEVIN JONES, JR.,                    No. 13-56360
    Petitioner-Appellant,
    D.C. No.
    v.                 2:10-cv-05071-GW-PLA
    K. HARRINGTON,
    Respondent-Appellee.               OPINION
    Appeal from the United States District Court
    for the Central District of California
    George H. Wu, District Judge, Presiding
    Argued and Submitted August 31, 2015
    Pasadena, California
    Filed July 22, 2016
    Before: Alex Kozinski, Diarmuid F. O’Scannlain,
    and Jay S. Bybee, Circuit Judges.
    Opinion by Judge Bybee;
    Dissent by Judge O’Scannlain
    2                     JONES V. HARRINGTON
    SUMMARY*
    Habeas Corpus
    The panel reversed the district court’s judgment denying
    California state prisoner Kevin Jones’s habeas corpus petition
    challenging his murder conviction, and remanded with
    instructions to grant the writ, in a case in which Jones, after
    hours of police questioning with little progress, told the
    officers “I don’t want to talk no more.”
    The panel held that any reasonable jurist would have to
    conclude that when Jones said he did not want to talk “no
    more,” he meant it, and that by continuing to interrogate
    Jones after his invocation of his right to remain silent, the
    officers squarely violated Miranda v. Arizona. The panel
    wrote that the government cannot use against Jones anything
    he said after his invocation, and held that allowing the state
    to use his post-invocation statements against him, even to
    argue that his initial invocation was ambiguous, is contrary to
    clearly established Supreme Court case law.
    Dissenting, Judge O’Scannlain wrote that whether one
    believes that the California courts’ determination that Jones’s
    statement was not unambiguous when considered in full
    context to be correct or not, that determination rests on a
    reasonable application of clearly established Supreme Court
    law to the facts of the case and must therefore stand under the
    deferential standard of review.
    *
    This summary constitutes no part of the opinion of the court. It has
    been prepared by court staff for the convenience of the reader.
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                    3
    COUNSEL
    Kathryn A. Young (argued), Deputy Federal Public Defender;
    Hilary Potashner, Federal Public Defender; Office of the
    Federal Public Defender, Los Angeles, California; for
    Petitioner-Appellant.
    David Glassman (argued), Stephanie A. Miyoshi, and Ana R.
    Duarte, Deputy Attorneys General; Lance E. Winters, Senior
    Assistant Attorney General; Gerald A. Engler, Chief
    Assistant Attorney General; Kamala D. Harris, Attorney
    General of California; Office of the Attorney General, Los
    Angeles, California; for Respondent-Appellee.
    4                   JONES V. HARRINGTON
    OPINION
    BYBEE, Circuit Judge:
    The Los Angeles Police Department suspected that
    defendant Kevin Jones was involved in a gang shooting that
    left one person dead and two injured. Detectives picked
    Jones up and began interrogating him. After hours of
    questioning, and little progress, Jones finally told the officers
    “I don’t want to talk no more.” Undeterred, the officers
    continued questioning Jones, and eventually, he made a
    number of incriminating statements. Jones’s statements were
    the lynchpin of the state’s prosecution against him—and
    Jones was convicted and sentenced to seventy-five years to
    life.
    On direct appeal, Jones contended that officers were
    wrong to continue to interrogate him after he invoked his
    right to remain silent, and that his incriminating statements
    should not have been used against him. The California Court
    of Appeal held that Jones did not unambiguously invoke his
    right to remain silent, so no suppression was warranted. It
    reasoned that after officers continued to interrogate Jones
    with only a single follow-up question, he continued to talk
    and made statements that cast some doubt on whether he had
    actually invoked his right to remain silent.
    But the Supreme Court has been clear on this point: When
    a suspect invokes his right to silence, the officers’
    interrogation must cease. Period. See Miranda v. Arizona,
    
    384 U.S. 436
    , 444 (1966). By continuing to interrogate Jones
    after his invocation, the officers squarely violated Miranda.
    That means the government cannot use against Jones
    anything he said after his invocation. And that includes using
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                         5
    Jones’s subsequent statements to “cast retrospective doubt on
    the clarity of [his] initial request itself.” Smith v. Illinois,
    
    469 U.S. 91
    , 98–99 (1984) (per curiam); see Davis v. United
    States, 
    512 U.S. 452
    , 458 (1994); Miranda, 
    384 U.S. at 444
    .
    Allowing the state to use Jones’s post-invocation statements
    against him, even to argue that his initial invocation was
    ambiguous, is thus contrary to clearly established Supreme
    Court case law. Once Jones said he wished to remain silent,
    even one question was one question too many.
    We hold that any reasonable jurist would have to
    conclude that when Jones said he did not want to talk “no
    more,” he meant it. The Court of Appeal’s decision is both
    contrary to and an unreasonable application of clearly
    established Supreme Court law, and it is based on an
    unreasonable determination of the facts. Further, given the
    pivotal role Jones’s statements played at trial, the trial court’s
    error was not harmless. We reverse the judgment of the
    district court and remand with instructions to grant the writ.
    I
    A. The Shooting
    In August of 2003, three teenagers—members of the
    Eight Treys Gangster Crips—were stopped at a gas station
    that bordered the territory of neighboring rival gang Westside
    Rolling 90s Crips. A black Ford pulled up to the teens. An
    African-American male wearing a Cleveland Indians cap
    leaned out the passenger window and shouted, “F— [Eight
    Treys]. This is Westside Rolling Crips.” The Ford then
    drove off.
    6                  JONES V. HARRINGTON
    The three teenagers finished pumping their gas, and
    pulled out of the gas station into the intersection. Moments
    later, the black car reappeared on their right side. The driver
    of the black car, a “[l]ight skinned” African-American, made
    a Rolling 90s gang sign, and then turned and said something
    to his passenger. The passenger lifted himself onto the
    window frame of his door. He leveled a semi-automatic
    weapon at the teens, and opened fire. Two of the teens were
    struck, along with a third person who was driving nearby.
    One of the teens died from his wounds later that night.
    On August 15, 2003, police officers stopped Jones, who
    was driving his black two-door Ford Escort. The officers had
    previously received a tip from an informant that Jones was a
    member of the Rolling 90s who drove a car like the one
    identified in the shootings. The police found a Cleveland
    Indians cap in Jones’s car, and after impounding the car,
    matched fingerprints on the outside door to a person who
    belonged to a gang affiliated with the Rolling 90s. Police
    brought Jones in for questioning that night.
    B. The Interrogation
    Jones was brought to the police station some time
    between 9:00 and 9:40 p.m. He was read his Miranda rights
    and interviewed later that night, beginning at 12:33 a.m., by
    Detectives Kevin Jolivette and Bill Fallon. Jones was
    nineteen years old, had graduated from technical school, and
    worked full-time for UPS. The interview lasted between two
    and three hours.
    At the outset of the interview, Jones told the detectives
    that he owned his black Ford Escort, and that no one else
    drove it. He initially insisted that he had no knowledge of the
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                        7
    shooting, and that on the day in question he had driven
    straight home after finishing work.
    The detectives lied to Jones, telling him they had
    incriminating evidence which did not actually exist. The
    detectives told Jones that witnesses had identified his car as
    the one used in the shooting and that the car appeared on
    surveillance video from the gas station. The detectives held
    consistently to the ruse, insisting to Jones that they already
    knew he and his car were involved with the shooting, and
    implored him to come clean about his role. The police told
    Jones that he would receive more lenient punishment if he
    admitted to being only the driver rather than the shooter or
    the person whose idea the shooting was.
    Over the course of the interview, Jones’s story changed
    several times. First, he told the police that he had no personal
    knowledge of the shooting, and gave a somewhat inconsistent
    story about how he learned of the shooting from a barber on
    the street while driving home a few days after the shooting.
    Jones stated that, on the day of the shooting, he came straight
    home from work, parked his car at his house around 5:00 p.m.
    or 5:30 p.m., and then walked to the gym. He stated that
    around 6:45 he noticed his car was missing, but assumed it
    would be returned, and went to the gym anyway. His
    explanations for why he assumed the car would be returned
    changed somewhat, but he said that by the time he got home
    from the gym, the car was back. As detectives continued to
    press Jones about his implausible story, the following
    exchange occurred:
    Jolivette: Kevin, do you think – why don’t
    you stop this man.
    8                  JONES V. HARRINGTON
    Jones: All right.
    Jolivette: Stop this. The thing is you drove a
    car, it shows that on the tape and that’s all I’m
    going to put down, as far as what you were
    doing. You drove the car. You just didn’t
    know it was going to happen like that. Kevin,
    sit up, man.
    Jones: I don’t want to talk no more, man.
    Jolivette: I understand that, but the bottom
    line is –
    Jones: You don’t want to hear what I’m
    telling you.
    Jolivette: I’m so sorry. I can’t – you’re
    mumbling, you got to speak up. I got bad
    hearing.
    Jones: I’m telling you all.
    From there, questioning continued as normal, and eventually
    Jones made incriminating statements. Most importantly, he
    admitted to driving the car during the shooting. He claimed
    that a stranger with a gun jumped into his car, ordered him to
    drive to the gas station, yelled at the teenagers, and then
    hopped out of his car at the intersection and began shooting.
    Officers arrested Jones a few days later and interviewed
    him again. The detectives pressed him on the implausibility
    of his earlier statements about driving a stranger to the
    shooting, but Jones again stated that was what happened.
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                      9
    C. The Trial
    The case against Jones revolved around the statements he
    made during the police interrogations. In her closing
    argument, the prosecutor explained there were no witnesses:
    “From the beginning, I had told you that there have been no
    identifications of Mr. Jones. None of the surviving victims
    were able to pick him out of the photographic lineup. None
    of them came into court and ID'd Mr. Jones.” No physical
    evidence connected Jones to the shooting. Indeed, witness
    testimony cut in favor of Jones’s case: Witnesses stated that
    the car involved in the shooting was different than Jones’s
    car, and Jones’s baseball cap was different from the one
    witnesses described.
    Instead, the government relied on Jones’s statements.
    During her opening statement, the prosecutor told the jury
    that “you’re going to hear Jones’ own words which convict
    him . . . of being the driver in this case.” The prosecutor
    concluded “Through all of these lies, you will have his
    admission that he drove in the shooting.” During closing
    arguments the prosecutor again relied heavily on Jones’s
    statements:
    So what do you have? You have Mr. Jones by
    his own words identifying himself as the
    driver in this shooting . . . [H]e tells you he
    was the driver in the shooting. And that’s it.
    That’s all you need. That’s evidence beyond
    a reasonable doubt that he is the driver in the
    shooting . . . Once you review those tapes, if
    you believe those tapes, that’s the end of the
    inquiry for Mr. Jones. . . . So when you look
    through Jone[’s] taped statements, his words
    10                 JONES V. HARRINGTON
    convicting himself as the driver in the
    shooting is all that you need. That is proof
    beyond a reasonable doubt.
    The jury convicted Jones of first degree murder, two
    counts of attempted murder, two counts of shooting at an
    occupied motor vehicle, and assault with a firearm. The trial
    court sentenced Jones to five years, plus 75 years to life.
    D. Post-Trial Review
    Jones appealed to the California Court of Appeal. The
    court affirmed his conviction in an unpublished decision. It
    ruled on Jones’s Miranda argument in a single paragraph,
    reasoning that Jones’s statement that he did not “want to talk
    no more” was ambiguous in light of the statements he made
    after:
    At a single point, midway through the first
    interview, appellant said, “I don't want to talk
    no more, man.’ His next sentence, however,
    was, ‘You don't want to hear what I'm telling
    you.” Taken in context, considering [Jones’s]
    willingness to talk with the detectives before
    and after that point in the interview, [Jones]
    was expressing frustration with the detectives’
    refusal to believe him, rather than
    unambiguously invoking his right to remain
    silent.
    The court thus relied on the fact that Jones’s next sentence
    after saying he did not want to talk—made in response to
    officers continuing to question him—made his initial
    invocation ambiguous. Jones filed a petition for review with
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                       11
    the California Supreme Court, which was denied without
    comment.
    Jones then filed a federal habeas petition. The magistrate
    judge filed a Final Report and Recommendation—a report
    summarily adopted by the district judge—recommending
    denial of Jones’s petition. Because the district judge adopted
    the magistrate judge’s report, we look to this report as the
    decision. But curiously, in granting the certificate of
    appealability, the district judge’s analysis suggested that the
    State violated Miranda here. The district judge observed that
    Jones’s statement was a “seemingly unambiguous” invocation
    of his right to remain silent. “Petitioner said, ‘I don’t want to
    talk no more, man.’ Aside from mentioning Miranda by
    name, what could be clearer?”
    Like the California Court of Appeal, the magistrate
    judge’s report held Jones’s request was ambiguous in light of
    the statements he made after invoking his right to silence.
    The court also relied on the fact that Jones did not ask to
    remain silent again after his initial invocation.
    II
    We review the district court’s denial of a habeas petition
    de novo. Hebner v. McGrath, 
    543 F.3d 1133
    , 1136 (9th Cir.
    2008). The Anti-Terrorism and Effective Death Penalty Act
    of 1996 (AEDPA) governs Jones’s petition. See Woodford v.
    Garceau, 
    538 U.S. 202
    , 210 (2003). We may grant the
    petition only if the state court’s adjudication of Jones’s claim
    “resulted in a decision that was contrary to, or involved an
    unreasonable application of, clearly established Federal law,
    as determined by the Supreme Court of the United States” or
    “resulted in a decision that was based on an unreasonable
    12                 JONES V. HARRINGTON
    determination of the facts in light of the evidence presented
    in the State court proceeding.” 
    28 U.S.C. § 2254
    (d)(1)–(2).
    A decision is “contrary to” Supreme Court precedent
    where “the state court arrives at a conclusion opposite to that
    reached by [the Supreme] Court on a question of law or if the
    state court decides a case differently than [the Supreme]
    Court has on a set of materially indistinguishable facts.”
    Williams v. Taylor, 
    529 U.S. 362
    , 413 (2000). We may not
    grant habeas relief unless the state court's determination “was
    so lacking in justification that there was an error well
    understood and comprehended in existing law beyond any
    possibility for fairminded disagreement.” Harrington v.
    Richter, 
    562 U.S. 86
    , 103 (2011). “[A]n unreasonable
    application of federal law is different from an incorrect
    application of federal law.” Williams, 
    529 U.S. at 410
    (emphasis removed). “A state court’s determination that a
    claim lacks merit precludes federal habeas relief so long as
    fair-minded jurists could disagree on the correctness of the
    state court’s decision.” Richter, 
    562 U.S. at 101
     (internal
    quotation marks omitted). The standard is meant to be
    “difficult to meet.” 
    Id. at 102
    .
    Similarly, the standard for finding that a state court made
    an unreasonable determination of the facts is “daunting,” and
    “will be satisfied in relatively few cases.” Taylor v. Maddox,
    
    366 F.3d 992
    , 1000 (9th Cir. 2004). But we can “conclude
    the decision was unreasonable or that the factual premise was
    incorrect by clear and convincing evidence.” Maxwell v. Roe,
    
    628 F.3d 486
    , 503 (9th Cir. 2010). And where the state court
    makes factual findings “under a misapprehension as to the
    correct legal standard,” “the resulting factual determination
    will be unreasonable and no presumption of correctness can
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                       13
    attach to it.” Taylor, 
    366 F.3d at 1001
    ; see also Miller-El v.
    Cockrell, 
    537 U.S. 322
    , 340 (2003).
    In this case, the California Supreme Court summarily
    denied review. Looking through to the last reasoned state
    court decision, the California Court of Appeal’s decision will
    serve as the focus of our analysis. See Cannedy v. Adams,
    
    706 F.3d 1148
    , 1158 (9th Cir. 2013) amended on denial of
    reh’g, 
    733 F.3d 794
     (9th Cir. 2013).
    III
    The California Court of Appeal determined that Jones’s
    statement that he “don’t want to talk no more” was made
    ambiguous by statements he made later in the interrogation.
    As we demonstrate in Part A, this determination was contrary
    to and an unreasonable application of clearly established
    Supreme Court law. 
    28 U.S.C. § 2254
    (d)(1). By continuing
    to interrogate Jones after he had invoked his right to remain
    silent, officers violated Miranda—which means the
    government cannot use against Jones anything he said after
    his invocation. This includes using Jones’s subsequent
    statements to police to “cast retrospective doubt on the clarity
    of the initial request itself.” Smith. 
    469 U.S. at 100
    . “To
    permit the continuation of custodial interrogation” after
    Jones’s invocation “would clearly frustrate the purposes of
    Miranda.” Michigan v. Mosley, 
    423 U.S. 96
    , 102 (1975). To
    the extent the California Court of Appeal read ambiguity into
    Jones’s invocation—based on statements he made later—that
    finding was “an unreasonable determination of the facts.”
    
    28 U.S.C. § 2254
    (d)(2). Because we also conclude in Part B
    14                    JONES V. HARRINGTON
    that the admission of this evidence at trial was prejudicial, we
    reverse the district court’s decision denying the writ.1
    A. Violation of clearly established law
    1. Officers violated Miranda by continuing to
    interrogate Jones after he invoked his right to remain
    silent
    The Supreme Court has made clear that once a person
    being questioned “indicates in any manner that he does not
    wish to be interrogated, the police may not question him.”
    Miranda, 
    384 U.S. at 445
    . “The mere fact that he may have
    answered some questions or volunteered some statements on
    his own does not deprive him of the right to refrain from
    answering any further inquiries.” 
    Id.
     To make sure that we
    understood this procedure, the Court repeated it: “If the
    individual indicates in any manner, at any time prior to or
    during questioning, that he wishes to remain silent, the
    interrogation must cease.” 
    Id.
     at 473–74. “[A]ny statement
    taken after the person invokes his privilege cannot be other
    than the product of compulsion, subtle or otherwise.” 
    Id. at 474
    . Once a person has “exercise[d] . . . his option to
    terminate questioning[,] he can control the time at which
    questioning occurs, the subjects discussed, and the duration
    of the interrogation. . . . [T]he admissibility of statements
    obtained after the person in custody has decided to remain
    silent depends under Miranda on whether his right to cut off
    questioning was scrupulously honored.” Mosley, 
    423 U.S. at
    103–04 (internal quotation marks omitted).
    1
    Because we reverse on Miranda grounds, we need not reach Jones’s
    alternative argument that his statements to police were involuntary. See
    Dickerson v. United States, 
    530 U.S. 428
    , 433–34 (2000).
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                        15
    The Supreme Court has left us with no doubt that this
    prohibition on continued questioning is a “bright-line” rule,
    “a prophylactic safeguard whose application does not turn on
    whether coercion in fact was employed.” Id. at 98, 99 n.8.
    “[C]onjecture and hair-splitting” is what “the Supreme Court
    wanted to avoid when it fashioned the bright-line rule in
    Miranda.” Anderson, 516 F.3d at 790; cf. Davis, 
    512 U.S. at 461
     (noting that the benefit of a bright-line rule is the “clarity
    and ease of application” that “can be applied by officers in
    the real world . . . without unduly hampering the gathering of
    information” by forcing them “to make difficult judgment
    calls” with a “threat of suppression if they guess wrong”).
    Here, there is no doubt officers violated Miranda.
    Certainly, Jones saying he “did not want to talk no more”
    qualifies as “indicat[ing] in any manner that he does not wish
    to be interrogated.” Miranda, 
    384 U.S. at 445
     (emphasis
    added). And there is no real dispute that officers continued
    interrogating Jones. Officers knew well that he was invoking
    his right, but continued to push him for more answers: “I
    understand that but—.” No fairminded jurist could
    reasonably interpret this statement to be “ceasing” the
    interrogation. Id.
    2. Jones’s invocation was not ambiguous under Berghuis
    v. Thompkins
    The Supreme Court recently added another layer to the
    Miranda inquiry: Whether the suspect invoked his right to
    remain silent unambiguously. Berghuis v. Thompkins,
    
    560 U.S. 370
    , 381 (2010). Up until Thompkins, the right to
    remain silent could be invoked in “any manner.” Miranda,
    
    384 U.S. at 445
    . On the other hand, the right to counsel could
    be invoked only “unambiguously.” Thompkins, 
    560 U.S. at
    16                 JONES V. HARRINGTON
    381. In Thompkins, the Court clarified that the requirement
    that the right to counsel be invoked “unambiguously” would
    now be applied with respect to requests to remain silent. 
    Id.
    Because we must now apply the rules from right to counsel
    cases to right to silence cases like Jones’s, we first walk
    through the right to counsel caselaw.
    In Miranda, the Court held that the right to remain silent
    could be invoked “in any manner” and that the interrogation
    must then “cease.” Miranda, 
    384 U.S. at 445
    . By contrast,
    with respect to the right to counsel, Miranda announced a
    slightly different rule: “If the individual states that he wants
    an attorney, the interrogation must cease until an attorney is
    present.” 
    384 U.S. at 474
     (emphasis added). The scope of
    the two rights was thus not coextensive—the Court in
    Miranda was unequivocal on what officers must do when an
    accused invoked his right to silence; it was not as clear what
    they had to do when the right to counsel was invoked.
    From there the caselaw diverged into two lines: One
    addressing invocations of the right to silence, the other
    addressing invocations of the right to counsel. In Michigan
    v. Mosley, 
    423 U.S. 96
     (1976), with respect to the right to
    silence, the Court clarified that Miranda did not mean that
    “once a person has indicated a desire to remain silent,
    questioning may be resumed only when counsel is present,”
    
    id.
     at 104 n.10, but repeated what Miranda had said: the
    suspect’s “right to cut off questioning” must be “fully
    respected,” 
    id. at 104
    .
    In Edwards v. Arizona, 
    451 U.S. 477
     (1981), the Court
    continued to develop the requirements for invocations of the
    right to counsel. It held that “when an accused has invoked
    his right to have counsel present during custodial
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                      17
    interrogation, a valid waiver of that right cannot be
    established by showing only that he responded to further
    police-initiated custodial interrogation even if he has been
    advised of his rights.” 
    Id. at 484
     (footnote omitted). This
    was a change—a strengthening of the accused’s rights—in
    the right to counsel: “Edwards established a new test for
    when . . . waiver would be acceptable once the suspect had
    invoked his right to counsel: the suspect had to initiate
    subsequent communication.” Solem v. Stumes, 
    465 U.S. 638
    ,
    646 (1984). See 
    id. at 648
    . This was different than the test
    for the right to silence, which allowed police to continue
    questioning after some delay. Mosley, 
    423 U.S. at 118
    .
    Right to counsel cases then addressed the requirement at
    issue in this case: How we determine that “the suspect [has]
    unambiguously request[ed] counsel.” Davis v. United States,
    
    512 U.S. 452
    , 459 (1994). This development in the right to
    counsel context makes sense. Suspects can invoke their right
    to remain silent in many ways. They may invoke their right
    by simply remaining silent, or they may indicate in other
    ways—including by words—that they do not want to talk
    with police. By contrast, invoking the right to counsel cannot
    be accomplished by silence or pantomime, but requires the
    suspect to articulate specifically that she wants counsel. This
    line of cases explained that an “ambiguous or equivocal”
    request for counsel does not require police questioning to end
    and places no limits on how the interrogation can be used
    later. 
    Id.
    But the Court also held that the standard for invoking the
    right to counsel unambiguously was not a demanding one. A
    suspect need only invoke his rights “sufficiently clearly that
    a reasonable police officer in the circumstances would
    understand the statement to be [such] a request.” 
    Id. at 459
    .
    18                    JONES V. HARRINGTON
    He need not specifically reference his constitutional rights,
    nor need he use any specific terminology. 
    Id.
    The Court clarified that in determining whether an
    invocation of the right to counsel is ambiguous, “[u]nder
    Miranda and Edwards, . . . an accused’s post request
    responses to further interrogation may not be used to cast
    doubt on the clarity of his initial request for counsel.” Smith,
    
    469 U.S. at 92
    . Allowing the government to use these post-
    request statements to “cast retrospective doubt” on prior
    unambiguous invocations would give officers an incentive to
    ignore invocations in the hopes that a suspect may be
    persuaded to talk anyway. 
    Id. at 100
    . “No authority, and no
    logic, permits the interrogator to proceed . . . on his own
    terms and as if the defendant had requested nothing, in the
    hope that the defendant might be induced to say something
    casting retrospective doubt on his initial statement . . . .” 
    Id. at 99
    . Construing a person’s unambiguous invocation of his
    Fifth Amendment rights by “looking to [his] subsequent
    responses to continued police questioning” and whether
    “considered in total, [his] statements were equivocal” is
    “unprecedented and untenable.” 
    Id. at 97
     (emphasis
    removed). Accordingly, “under the clear logical force of
    settled precedent, an accused’s postrequest responses to
    further interrogation may not be used to cast retrospective
    doubt on the clarity of the initial request itself. Such
    subsequent statements are relevant only to the distinct
    question of waiver.” 
    Id. at 100
    .2
    2
    The dissent argues that we have unfairly attributed “sweeping
    propositions” to Smith. But we and the dissent seem to agree on Smith’s
    propositions. The dissent characterizes Smith’s holding as: “[O]nce a
    suspect clearly invokes his right to counsel, officers may not continue to
    question him.” Dissenting Op. at 36. Indeed, this is the same holding we
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                               19
    Finally, in Thompkins, the Court noted it had “not yet
    stated” whether the rules about ambiguity it had developed in
    the context of invocations of the right to counsel should also
    apply in the context of invocations of the right to silence.
    Thompkins, 
    560 U.S. at 381
    . The Court held “there is no
    principled reason to adopt different standards for determining
    when an accused has invoked the Miranda right to remain
    silent and the Miranda right to counsel as issue in Davis.” 
    Id.
    Thus, the Court held that the same “standards” about
    rely on from Miranda: Once an “individual indicates in any manner, at
    any time prior to or during questioning, that he wishes to remain silent, the
    interrogation must cease.” Miranda, 
    384 U.S. at
    473–74. Both cases
    stand for the simple proposition that officers must stop questioning a
    suspect once he unambiguously invokes his right to silence—and if they
    do not—the suspect’s statements can no longer be used against him.
    But the dissent appears to suggest something quite different. The
    dissent argues for a standard that would permit officers to ask some
    threshold number of questions before we find that officers have indeed not
    “ceased” “interrogating.” The dissent makes much out of the fact that
    “Detective Jolivette did not even get out a complete sentence.” Dissenting
    Op. at 37. The dissent says that this is nothing like Smith where the
    officers interrogated the suspect “at length” after his invocation. But the
    dissent is suggesting we create a gray area about how much interrogation
    is interrogation enough. And that is exactly what the Supreme Court told
    us not to do when it made Miranda a “bright-line” rule. Smith, 
    469 U.S. at
    99 n.8. There can be no serious dispute that officers did not “cease”
    their interrogation of Jones once he had unambiguously told them he
    wanted to remain silent. And there the Miranda analysis must end.
    The dissent also says our decision “would have sweeping
    consequences for police officers.” Dissenting Op. at 38. But this parade
    of horribles is baseless. The rule governing interrogations is the same
    after this case as it was before—it comes straight from Miranda: If a
    suspect unambiguously states he wants to remain silent, the officers must
    stop interrogating. Full stop.
    20                 JONES V. HARRINGTON
    ambiguity it had developed in Davis and its progeny should
    now apply to invocations of the right to silence. 
    Id.
    The government and the dissent urge us to require that
    Jones’s statements be “unambiguous” in light of Thompkins,
    despite that this case came out long after the California
    Supreme Court’s decision. Dissenting Op. at 26, 31.
    Thompkins’s holding is nominally a new holding, see 
    id.
     at
    10–11, but in this context it is a holding in the government’s
    favor because it clarified that invocations of the right to
    remain silent must also be unambiguous. Under the
    circumstances, we will apply Thompkins’s directive that the
    same standards for finding ambiguity in the right to counsel
    context should also apply to finding ambiguity in the right to
    silence context.
    But Thompkins does not change much: No fairminded
    jurist could determine that Jones’s invocation was ambiguous.
    First, Jones’s initial request to remain silent was
    unambiguous on its face, and nothing about the prior context
    of the statement made it ambiguous or equivocal. Jones
    stated: “I don’t want to talk no more”; in other words, he did
    not want to talk anymore. See Garcia v. Long, 
    808 F.3d 771
    ,
    773–74 (9th Cir. 2015) (holding that a suspect answering
    “no” to the question “[d]o you wish to talk to me?” was an
    unambiguous request to remain silent under Miranda). Jones
    did not equivocate by using words such as “maybe” or
    “might” or “I think.” See Anderson, 516 F.3d at 788; cf.
    Smith, 
    469 U.S. at
    96–97 (holding that nothing in the
    statement “Uh, yeah. I’d like to do that” suggested
    equivocation). Nor did anything Jones did or said leading up
    to this statement make it ambiguous.              During the
    interrogation leading up to this point, Jones spoke little. Most
    of the interrogation consisted of detectives repeatedly asking
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                             21
    Jones questions, and Jones giving short, often one-word
    answers. In any event, the fact that Jones spoke to officers
    for a while before invoking his right to remain silent makes
    no difference. The California Court of Appeal’s decision is
    simply “contrary to” and “an unreasonable application” of
    Miranda. 
    28 U.S.C. § 2254
    (d)(1); Miranda, 
    384 U.S. at
    473–74 (holding that the right to remain silent can be invoked
    “any time prior to or during questioning”).
    The only statements that could cast any ambiguity on
    Jones’s initial invocation were statements he made after the
    fact. Indeed, the California Court of Appeal relied largely on
    Jones’s statement made after officers continued interrogating
    him, reasoning that because Jones made a follow-up
    statement after only a single clarifying comment from
    officers, his initial invocation was ambiguous. But it was
    clearly established, when determining whether the invocation
    of a constitutional right is ambiguous, that the California
    courts could not look to post-invocation statements to “cast
    retrospective doubt on the clarity of [Jones’s] initial request
    itself.” Smith, 
    469 U.S. at
    98–99.3 Officers continued to
    3
    The dissent argues that Smith v. Illinois, 
    469 U.S. 91
     (1984), cannot
    serve as “clearly established Federal law, as determined by the Supreme
    Court of the United States,” 
    28 U.S.C. § 2254
     (d)(1), because Smith rested
    on Miranda’s invocation of the right to counsel, not on Miranda’s
    invocation of the right to silence. Dissenting Op. at 33–35. See Smith,
    
    469 U.S. at 98-99
     (discussing “the request for counsel”). The dissent
    contends that only recently, in Thompkins, did the Supreme Court declare
    the right to silence should be treated the same as the right to counsel.
    According to the dissent, since Thompkins post-dates the California
    decisions in this case, it cannot serve as the “clearly established Federal
    law” required by AEDPA. Dissenting Op. at 34.
    With respect, we think the dissent is wrong. The dissenting opinion
    begins by quoting Thompkins. Dissenting Op. at 26; see also id. at 31.
    22                    JONES V. HARRINGTON
    interrogate Jones after he had unambiguously asked to remain
    silent. When Jones said “I don’t want to talk no more,” the
    officer responded: “I understand that but—.” That means the
    government cannot rely on Jones’s later statements to
    establish that his earlier statement was ambiguous.
    And the California court’s allusion to the fact that officers
    only interrogated Jones briefly after his invocation is of no
    matter. Even one question was one question too many.
    When an “individual indicates in any manner, at any time
    prior to or during questioning, that he wishes to remain silent,
    the interrogation must cease.” Miranda, 
    384 U.S. at
    473–74
    (emphasis added).
    Nor does it matter, as the California court and federal
    district court seemed to suggest, that Jones did not repeat his
    request to remain silent later in the interrogation: “Under
    Miranda, the onus [is] not on [the suspect] to be persistent in
    [his] demand to remain silent. Rather, the responsibility
    f[alls] to the law enforcement officers to scrupulously respect
    The dissent insists that we apply Thompkins to ensure that Jones invoked
    his right to remain silent “unambiguously,” but the dissent doesn’t want
    us to consider the Supreme Court’s earlier cases describing what
    constitutes an ambiguous or unambiguous invocation. The dissent can’t
    have it both ways. Either we apply Thompkins—and with it prior cases
    such as Davis, Smith, Solem, Edwards, and Miranda on which it
    builds—or we must ignore it. What we cannot do is say we are going to
    apply Thompkins and then ignore the standard Thompkins tells us to apply
    (the standards created in its right to counsel cases). If we ignore cases
    such as Davis and Smith, what standards for ambiguity are we to apply?
    Some new standard? That is exactly what Thompkins told us the Court
    would not do: “there is no principled reason to adopt different standards
    for determining when an accused has invoked the Miranda right to remain
    silent and the Miranda right to counsel at issue in Davis.” Thompkins,
    
    560 U.S. at 381
    .
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                       23
    [his] demand.” United States v. Lafferty, 
    503 F.3d 293
    , 304
    (3d Cir. 2007). Relying on the fact that “[i]t was the
    defendant, not the interrogators, who continued the
    discussion,” “ignores the bedrock principle that the
    interrogators should have stopped all questioning. A
    statement taken after the suspect invoked his right to remain
    silent ‘cannot be other than the product of compulsion, subtle
    or otherwise.’” Anderson, 516 F.3d at 789–90 (quoting
    Miranda, 
    384 U.S. at 474
    ).
    Although we give considerable deference to the state
    courts, “AEDPA deference is not a rubber stamp.” 
    Id.
     at 786
    (citing Miller-El v. Dretke, 
    545 U.S. 231
    , 240, 265 (2005)).
    The California Court of Appeal’s determination that Jones’s
    statement “I don’t want to talk no more” was ambiguous
    based on his responses to further questioning, was either “an
    unreasonable determination of the facts,” 
    28 U.S.C. § 2254
    (d)(2), or an “unreasonable application” of Miranda,
    
    id.
     § 2254(d)(1). By continuing to ask questions, the officers
    failed to “scrupulously honor” Jones’s simple request. We
    accordingly hold that 
    28 U.S.C. § 2254
    (d) does not bar
    habeas review of Jones’s Miranda claim, and we conclude,
    on de novo review, that Jones’s constitutional rights were
    violated when his interrogation was used at trial.
    B. Harmlessness
    Miranda error does not entitle Jones to habeas relief if the
    error was harmless. In AEDPA proceedings, we apply the
    actual-prejudice standard set forth in Brecht v. Abrahamson,
    
    507 U.S. 619
     (1993). Under Brecht, habeas relief is only
    available if the constitutional error had a “substantial and
    injurious effect or influence” on the jury verdict or trial court
    decision. 
    Id. at 623
     (quoting Kotteakos v. United States,
    24                 JONES V. HARRINGTON
    
    328 U.S. 750
    , 776 (1946)). This standard is satisfied if the
    record raises “grave doubts” about whether the error
    influenced the jury’s decision. Davis v. Ayala, 
    135 S. Ct. 2187
    , 2203 (2015) (brackets omitted) (quoting O’Neal v.
    McAninch, 
    513 U.S. 432
    , 436 (1995)).
    Under AEDPA, we accord deference to a state court’s
    harmlessness determination. Nevertheless, because the
    Brecht standard that we apply on collateral review is “less
    onerous” for the state than the “harmless beyond a reasonable
    doubt” standard that state courts apply on direct review,
    Brecht, 
    507 U.S. at
    622–23, the Supreme Court has explained
    that “it certainly makes no sense to require formal application
    of both tests (AEDPA/Chapman and Brecht) when the latter
    obviously subsumes the former,” Fry v. Pliler, 
    551 U.S. 112
    ,
    120 (2007). We therefore apply the Brecht test, but we do so
    with due consideration of the state court’s reasons for
    concluding that the error was harmless beyond a reasonable
    doubt. Davis, 
    135 S. Ct. at 2198
    .
    In Brecht, the Supreme Court determined that the state’s
    improper use of the petitioner’s post-Miranda silence for
    impeachment purposes was harmless. 
    507 U.S. at
    638–39.
    The state’s physical evidence against the defendant was
    “weighty,” and the state’s references to the post-Miranda
    evidence were “infrequent.” 
    Id. at 639
    .
    The same cannot be said here. Jones’s own incriminating
    statements—made after he had invoked his right to
    silence—formed the backbone of the government’s case.
    Indeed, there was little other evidence before the jury. No
    witnesses identified Jones in relation to the shooting.
    Witnesses reported that a four-door vehicle with no body
    damage had been driven in the drive-by; Jones drove a two-
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                        25
    door vehicle with extensive body damage. The only evidence
    linking Jones to the shooting consisted of an informant who
    told detectives that Jones was involved with a rival gang, and
    that Jones drove a vehicle the same color (black) as the one
    used in the shooting. It is true that, prior to invoking his right
    to silence, Jones made some confusing comments about his
    whereabouts during the shooting, but that was weak tea
    compared with Jones’s other words admitting to the crime.
    Jones likely could not have been convicted without his
    confession.
    Importantly, the prosecutor repeatedly referred to Jones’s
    incriminating statements, telling the jury that they could
    convict beyond a reasonable doubt based only on his own
    statements. The prejudice from a defendant’s confession
    “cannot be soft pedaled.” Anderson, 516 F.3d at 792. “A
    confession is like no other evidence”; it may be “the most . . .
    damaging evidence that can be admitted” against a defendant.
    Arizona v. Fulminante, 
    499 U.S. 279
    , 296 (1991) (internal
    quotation marks omitted).
    Exercising “extreme caution,” as we must, “before
    determining that the admission of [a] confession at trial was
    harmless,” 
    id. at 296
    , we conclude that the admission of
    Jones’s interrogation had a substantial and injurious effect on
    the jury’s decision. Brecht, 
    507 U.S. at
    637–38. In light of
    our decision, we do not reach Jones’s remaining claims.
    IV. CONCLUSION
    The Supreme Court has repeatedly made clear that when
    a suspect simply and unambiguously says he wants to remain
    silent, police questioning must end. Under any reasonable
    interpretation of the facts, Jones simply and unambiguously
    26                 JONES V. HARRINGTON
    invoked that right. Clearly established Supreme Court law
    required the suppression of Jones’s interrogation. The State
    shall either release Jones or grant him a new trial.
    REVERSED and REMANDED.
    O’SCANNLAIN, Circuit Judge, dissenting:
    A suspect who wishes to invoke his Fifth Amendment
    right to silence must do so “unambiguously.” Berghuis v.
    Thompkins, 
    560 U.S. 370
    , 381–82 (2010). Well into his
    interrogation, the suspect in this case made a single statement
    that, standing alone, might be characterized as an
    unambiguous invocation of such right. The California courts
    determined, however, that the suspect’s statement was not
    unambiguous when considered in full context. Whether one
    believes that determination to be correct or not, it
    unquestionably rests on a reasonable application of clearly
    established Supreme Court law to the facts of the case before
    us—and it must therefore stand under our deferential standard
    of review. See 
    28 U.S.C. § 2254
    (d); Cullen v. Pinholster,
    
    563 U.S. 170
    , 181 (2011).
    In reaching its conclusion to the contrary, the majority
    faults the state court for failing to apply Supreme Court
    precedent that post-dates the state court’s decision, attempts
    to extend readily distinguishable Supreme Court precedent to
    circumstances the Court has never considered, and ultimately
    grants relief to Jones because the state court’s decision failed
    to conform to the majority’s preferred view of the law—all of
    which we are forbidden from doing under § 2254.
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                      27
    I respectfully dissent.
    I
    A
    Let’s begin by restating the relevant facts.
    After he was identified as the potential driver in a gang-
    related shooting that injured two teenagers and killed a third,
    Kevin Jones, Jr. was brought in for questioning by the Los
    Angeles Police Department. LAPD Detectives Kevin
    Jolivette and Bill Fallon proceeded to interview Jones for a
    period of a few hours, beginning shortly after midnight on
    August 16, 2003. After being informed of his constitutional
    rights, Jones spoke willingly with the detectives. Throughout
    the interview, the detectives employed a ruse against Jones,
    telling him that both eye witnesses and security-camera
    footage identified his car as having been involved in the
    drive-by shooting. The officers pressed Jones on both his and
    his car’s whereabouts the night of the shooting, and they
    urged him to admit his involvement in the crime.
    Jones spoke at length with the detectives, and as the
    majority recounts, his story changed considerably throughout
    the course of the interview. After extensive interrogation,
    Jones clung to the assertion that on the evening of the crime,
    his car had gone missing for several hours, even though he
    admitted that no one other than him used the car. Jones
    insisted that he had noticed his car missing from its parking
    space that evening, but for various reasons, he thought little
    of it and simply assumed that the car would be returned to
    him. Rather than investigate where his car had been taken,
    Jones stated that he went to a nearby gym for a couple hours
    28                 JONES V. HARRINGTON
    and—as luck would have it—when he returned home, his car
    was back.
    The detectives pressed Jones on the implausibility of this
    story, leading eventually to the following exchange:
    JOLIVETTE: Kevin, do you think – why
    don’t you stop this man.
    JONES: All right.
    JOLIVETTE: Stop this. The thing is you
    drove a car, it shows that on the tape, and
    that’s all I’m going to put down, as far as
    what you were doing. You drove the car. You
    just didn’t know it was going to happen like
    that. Kevin, sit up, man.
    JONES: I don’t want to talk no more, man.
    JOLIVETTE: I understand that, but the
    bottom line is –
    JONES You don’t want to hear what I’m
    telling you.
    JOLIVETTE: I’m so sorry. I can’t – you’re
    mumbling, you got to speak up. I got bad
    hearing.
    JONES: I’m telling you all.
    At that point, the questioning proceeded as it had for hours,
    and in short order Jones admitted to driving the car during the
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                       29
    shooting. He professed innocence, however, insisting that a
    stranger had jumped into his car, ordered him to drive to the
    scene of the shooting, and then jumped out of the car, firing
    a gun at the victims. A few days later, police interviewed
    Jones again, and he again insisted on this latest version of his
    story.
    B
    Jones was prosecuted largely on the strength of his
    incriminating statements and was found guilty by a jury of
    first degree murder, two counts of attempted murder, and
    other lesser crimes. Jones was sentenced to 75 years to life.
    Jones appealed to the California Court of Appeal, arguing,
    among other things, that his incriminating statements should
    not have been introduced at trial, because they were obtained
    in violation of his Fifth Amendment right to silence. The
    California Court of Appeal disagreed, concluding that Jones’s
    statement that he did not “want to talk no more” was
    ambiguous in context and it thus did not require police to end
    his interrogation. Jones filed a petition for review
    challenging this conclusion with the California Supreme
    Court, which the court denied without comment.
    Jones then filed a federal habeas petition under 
    28 U.S.C. § 2254
    , which was denied by the district court. Jones timely
    appealed.
    II
    Under the Antiterrorism and Effective Death Penalty Act
    of 1996 (AEDPA), we may grant relief only if the California
    30                    JONES V. HARRINGTON
    Court of Appeal’s1 rejection of Jones’s right-to-silence claim
    “was contrary to, or involved an unreasonable application of,
    clearly established Federal law, as determined by the
    Supreme Court of the United States” or “resulted in a
    decision that was based on an unreasonable determination of
    the facts in light of the evidence presented in the State court
    proceeding.” 
    28 U.S.C. §§ 2254
    (d)(1)–(2). Time and again,
    the Supreme Court has reminded federal courts—and ours in
    particular—that this standard is “difficult to meet” and
    “highly deferential,” which “demands that state-court
    decisions be given the benefit of the doubt.” Pinholster,
    
    563 U.S. at 181
     (quoting Harrington v. Richter, 
    562 U.S. 86
    ,
    102 (2011); Woodford v. Visciotti, 
    537 U.S. 19
    , 24 (2002)
    (per curiam)).
    A decision is “contrary to” clearly established law where
    the state court “applies a rule that contradicts the governing
    law set forth in [Supreme Court] cases” or where it “confronts
    a set of facts that are materially indistinguishable from a
    decision of [the Supreme] Court and nevertheless arrives at
    a result different from” the Court. Mitchell v. Esparza,
    
    540 U.S. 12
    , 15–16 (2003) (per curiam) (quoting Williams v.
    Taylor, 
    529 U.S. 362
    , 405–06 (2000)). A state court
    unreasonably applies clearly established federal law only if
    its determination “was so lacking in justification that there
    was an error well understood and comprehended in existing
    law beyond any possibility for fairminded disagreement.”
    Richter, 
    562 U.S. at 103
    . “[A]n unreasonable application of
    1
    Because the California Supreme Court summarily denied review, we
    look through that denial to the reasoning given by the California Court of
    Appeal when it denied Jones’s claim. See Cannedy v. Adams, 
    706 F.3d 1148
    , 1158 (9th Cir. 2013), amended on denial of reh’g, 
    733 F.3d 794
     (9th
    Cir. 2013).
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                      31
    federal law is different from an incorrect application of
    federal law.” 
    Id. at 101
     (quoting Williams, 
    529 U.S. at 410
    ).
    “A state court’s determination that a claim lacks merit
    precludes federal habeas relief so long as fairminded jurists
    could disagree on the correctness of the state court’s
    decision.” 
    Id.
     (internal quotation marks omitted).
    A state-court decision “will not be overturned on factual
    grounds unless objectively unreasonable in light of the
    evidence presented in the state-court proceeding.” Miller-El
    v. Cockrell, 
    537 U.S. 322
    , 340 (2003) (emphasis added).
    “While not impossible to meet, that is a daunting
    standard—one that will be satisfied in relatively few cases,
    especially because we must be particularly deferential to our
    state-court colleagues.” Hernandez v. Holland, 
    750 F.3d 843
    ,
    857 (9th Cir. 2014) (internal quotation marks omitted). Thus,
    a “state-court factual determination is not unreasonable
    merely because the federal habeas court would have reached
    a different conclusion in the first instance.” Wood v. Allen,
    
    558 U.S. 290
    , 301 (2010).
    III
    All parties agree on the foundational principle underlying
    this case: a suspect who seeks to invoke his Fifth Amendment
    right to silence must do so unambiguously. See Thompkins,
    
    560 U.S. at
    381–82. Once he does, the suspect’s right to cut
    off questioning must be “scrupulously honored,” Michigan v.
    Mosley, 
    423 U.S. 96
    , 103–04 (1975) (internal quotation
    marks omitted), and the “interrogation must cease,” Miranda
    v. Arizona, 
    384 U.S. 436
    , 473–74 (1966). But interrogating
    officers have no duty to heed a request that—either on its face
    or in context—is “ambiguous or equivocal.” Thompkins,
    
    560 U.S. at
    381–82.
    32                 JONES V. HARRINGTON
    The California Court of Appeal correctly acknowledged
    this rule, and determined that, in context, Jones did not
    unambiguously invoke his right to silence. The court
    explained that immediately after Jones said he did not “want
    to talk no more,” he continued, “You don’t want to hear what
    I’m telling you.” The court opined that, “in context,
    considering his willingness to talk with the detectives before
    and after that point in the interview,” Jones was not
    “unambiguously invoking his right to remain silent,” but
    instead was “expressing frustration with the detectives’
    refusal to believe him.”
    There is little doubt that this factual conclusion—that, in
    the full context of Jones’s interrogation, any invocation of his
    right to silence was ambiguous—is reasonable on the record
    before us. When strung together, Jones’s statements quite
    reasonably read as the state court portrayed them: not as a
    request for silence but as an expression of frustration by a
    person who wished the police would believe his story. In the
    pivotal exchange, Jones’s thoughts appear scattered and he
    seems upset, cutting off Detective Jolivette mid-sentence.
    Further, neither before nor after this exchange did Jones even
    obliquely mention a desire for silence. Indeed, for all but one
    isolated statement, Jones seemed perfectly willing to engage
    the detectives. In context, it is not unreasonable to interpret
    that singular, stand-out statement as something other than a
    clear invocation of the right to remain silent. Under AEDPA,
    that factual conclusion therefore must stand, unless it was
    based on an unreasonable misapprehension of clearly
    established law. See Wood, 
    558 U.S. at
    301–04; Miller-El,
    
    537 U.S. at 340
    .
    The majority does not seriously contest this conclusion,
    but instead asserts that clearly established law prohibited the
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                      33
    state court from considering this full factual context when
    evaluating the clarity of Jones’s statement. Specifically, the
    majority holds that the state court could not find Jones’s
    statement ambiguous based on anything Jones said after the
    precise moment he uttered, “I don’t want to talk no more,
    man.” See Maj. Op. at 4–5, 13–14. But the majority has
    failed to identify any case—alone or in combination with
    other cases—that clearly establishes anything of the sort.
    A
    The majority’s assertion that ambiguity can never be
    provided by words a suspect says after he supposedly invokes
    his right to silence stems, at bottom, from a single Supreme
    Court case: Smith v. Illinois, 
    469 U.S. 91
     (1984) (per curiam).
    But the Court’s opinion in Smith has no bearing on the case
    before us and, in any event, does not stand for the remarkable
    proposition the majority attributes to it.
    1
    First, and most simply, at the time the state court issued
    its decision, Smith—a case examining the right to
    counsel—could not provide clearly established law for
    Jones’s right-to-silence claim. In Miranda v. Arizona, the
    Supreme Court held that, during an interrogation, police must
    inform a suspect of both rights—his right to remain silent and
    his right to have an attorney present—and that they must
    cease all questioning upon the suspect’s invocation of either
    right. 
    384 U.S. at
    471–74. But, until last December, we had
    refused to treat cases defining the standards for invoking one
    right (e.g., the right to counsel) as clearly established law
    governing the standards for invoking the other right (e.g., the
    right to silence). See Garcia v. Long, 
    808 F.3d 771
    , 777 n.1
    34                 JONES V. HARRINGTON
    (9th Cir. 2015); Anderson v. Terhune, 
    516 F.3d 781
    , 787 n.3
    (9th Cir. 2008) (en banc); see also Bui v. DiPaolo, 
    170 F.3d 232
    , 239 (1st Cir. 1999) (right-to-counsel precedent did not
    “authoritatively answer” question in a right-to-silence case,
    even though the Supreme Court “likely would” apply the
    same standard to both rights (internal quotation marks
    omitted)).
    We recently changed our interpretation only because of
    intervening Supreme Court precedent. In 2010, the Supreme
    Court considered whether past decisions that required an
    invocation of the right to counsel to be unambiguous applied
    equally to a suspect who sought to invoke his right to silence.
    In Berghuis v. Thompkins, the Court held that the same
    standards indeed do apply, explaining that it saw “no
    principled reason to adopt different standards for determining
    when” either right had been invoked. 
    560 U.S. at 381
    .
    Accordingly, we recently held that, after Thompkins, right-to-
    counsel precedent now may indeed provide clearly
    established law in right-to-silence cases—despite our past
    practice to the contrary. Garcia, 808 F.3d at 777 n.1.
    But, critically, this development in the law occurred after
    both the California Court of Appeal and the California
    Supreme Court issued their decisions on Jones’s claim (in
    2008). Under AEDPA, we may grant relief only if the state
    court’s decision is irreconcilable with the law as clearly
    established by the Supreme Court at the time the state court
    acted. Greene v. Fisher, 
    132 S. Ct. 38
    , 44–45 (2011);
    Pinholster, 
    563 U.S. at 182
    . Before Thompkins, it was
    anything but clear that right-to-counsel cases governed right-
    to-silence claims. That very question was at the heart of the
    Supreme Court’s grant of certiorari in Thompkins. See
    Thompkins, 
    560 U.S. at 381
    . Even if one agrees with the
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                      35
    Court’s affirmative answer to that question, the point is that
    the answer had never been given until Thompkins. See id.;
    see also Anderson, 
    516 F.3d at 799
     (Tallman, J., dissenting)
    (“The United States Supreme Court has never declared its
    right to counsel principles applicable to invoking the right to
    silence, and under AEDPA that precedent was not ‘clearly
    established’ when the California Court of Appeal rendered its
    decision.”). Acting before Thompkins, the state court cannot
    possibly have failed reasonably to apply Smith’s right-to-
    counsel holding to Jones’s right-to-silence claim. Indeed,
    before Thompkins, not even our court would have evaluated
    Jones’s claim under Smith. See Garcia, 808 F.3d at 777 n.1.
    Accordingly, any supposed error related to Smith cannot be
    a basis for upsetting the decision of the California Court of
    Appeal.
    2
    Second, even if Smith did govern Jones’s right-to-silence
    claim, that case does not remotely stand for the sweeping
    propositions the majority attributes to it. Jones’s case is
    nothing at all like Smith, and the state court’s refusal to
    extend Smith to Jones’s situation is patently reasonable. In
    short, even on its merits, Smith provides no basis on which to
    grant relief in this case.
    a
    In Smith, at the outset of police questioning, the suspect
    (Smith) stated that an unidentified woman told him to get an
    attorney. 
    469 U.S. at 92
    . Shortly thereafter, when asked
    whether he understood his right to have an attorney present,
    Smith responded, “Uh, yeah. I’d like to do that.” 
    Id. at 93
    .
    Rather than stop so that Smith could contact an attorney, the
    36                 JONES V. HARRINGTON
    officers continued to read his rights, and “then pressed him
    again to answer their questions.” 
    Id.
     After a somewhat
    confused back-and-forth about his right to an attorney, Smith
    ultimately agreed to speak without a lawyer present. 
    Id.
     On
    review before the Supreme Court, Smith argued that all
    questioning should have ceased the moment he requested an
    attorney the first time. The State countered that it was
    unclear to the officers whether Smith actually wanted an
    attorney given that he agreed to proceed without one after
    further questioning.
    The Supreme Court rejected the State’s argument, and
    explained that once an unambiguous request for counsel has
    been made, “an accused’s postrequest responses to further
    interrogation may not be used to cast retrospective doubt on
    the clarity of the initial request itself.” 
    Id. at 100
     (emphasis
    omitted). This rule was needed to prevent officers from
    “badgering or overreaching” to “wear down the accused and
    persuade him to incriminate himself not withstanding his
    earlier request for counsel’s assistance.” 
    Id. at 98
     (internal
    quotation marks and alterations omitted). But questioning
    need not end where the accused’s request “may be
    characterized as ambiguous or equivocal as a result of events
    preceding the request or of nuances inherent in the request
    itself.” 
    Id.
     at 99–100.
    The rule of Smith is thus: once a suspect clearly invokes
    his right to counsel, officers may not continue to question him
    and use his answers to those questions to cast retrospective
    doubt on the clarity of his initial invocation. That is,
    ambiguity cannot be retroactively manufactured through the
    suspect’s “postrequest responses to further interrogation.”
    
    Id. at 100
     (emphasis added).             But Jones’s critical
    statement—the utterance that the state court reasonably
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                      37
    determined cast doubt on what Jones meant by “I don’t want
    to talk no more”—was not a response to further
    interrogation. Despite the majority’s many assertions to the
    contrary, Maj. Op. at 4, 15, 21–23, the police did not ask
    Jones a single question between his two statements. They did
    not continue “interrogating” him at all. Indeed, Detective
    Jolivette did not even get out a complete sentence—it is
    anyone’s guess what that sentence was going to be—before
    Jones cut him off to say, “You don’t want to hear what I’m
    telling you.” Jolivette’s next comment was just to ask Jones
    to speak louder because he was having trouble hearing him.
    Jones then said, “I’m telling you all.” Only then—at which
    point an officer quite reasonably may have been confused as
    to whether Jones was seeking to remain silent—did
    questioning continue. Jones never again hinted at a desire for
    silence.
    This is nothing at all like the situation in Smith, where
    officers spoke to and questioned the suspect at length after he
    requested an attorney. In Smith, the State contended that the
    suspect’s earlier request was unclear based only on his
    “responses to continued police questioning.” 
    469 U.S. at 97
    (emphasis added). By contrast, the officers here asked Jones
    nothing, they did not continue interrogating him, and they
    certainly did not manufacture ambiguity by badgering Jones
    or wearing him down. See 
    id. at 98
    . Instead, Jones’s
    statement was ambiguous immediately, as confirmed by
    comments he made directly afterward. While those
    comments came later in time (barely), they were not the
    product of any “further interrogation” whatsoever. This
    situation is patently—and certainly reasonably—
    distinguishable from that in Smith.
    38                  JONES V. HARRINGTON
    If the limitations of Smith were not already obvious on the
    face of the Court’s analysis, the Court took additional care to
    emphasize that its “decision [was] a narrow one.” 
    Id. at 99
    .
    That narrow decision did “not decide the circumstances in
    which an accused’s request for counsel may be characterized
    as ambiguous or equivocal as a result of events preceding the
    request or of nuances inherent in the request itself.” 
    Id.
     at
    99–100. And Smith certainly does not preclude the California
    courts from determining that Jones’s situation presents just
    such a circumstance where the suspect’s “request itself” was
    ambiguous. Even if on de novo review the majority would
    reach a different result, the majority’s preferred interpretation
    is certainly not “beyond any possibility for fairminded
    disagreement.” Richter, 
    562 U.S. at 103
    .
    b
    The majority holds to the contrary only by misattributing
    to Smith a sweeping rule that case in no way embraced. The
    majority suggests that Smith’s prohibition against creating
    ambiguity on the basis of “postrequest responses to further
    interrogation” actually means that the police must disregard
    anything the suspect happens to say at a moment in time after
    he has arguably invoked his right to silence. See Maj. Op. at
    4–5, 13–14. That is, even though context may render an
    otherwise apparently clear statement ambiguous, the majority
    concludes that such context can never be supplied by
    something the suspect says after his supposed request for
    silence.
    The majority’s reading not only stretches Smith to its
    breaking point, but it creates a rule that defies the basic logic
    of human interaction and which would have sweeping
    consequences for police officers. Consider, for example, a
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                       39
    situation in which there is no interruption by a police officer
    at all. Suppose that during an interrogation a suspect said,
    “Man, I don’t even want to talk about this anymore.” Then,
    after an uninterrupted pause, he continued, “This is so
    frustrating. I’m answering all your questions, but you won’t
    believe what I’m saying.” Must an officer plug his ears and
    ignore the latter two sentences, merely because they came
    after the first sentence? Of course not. Smith does not
    compel such a result, and anyone who has ever held a
    conversation would naturally reject it. Indeed, albeit in an
    unpublished disposition, another panel of our court recently
    held that Smith allows officers to take into account the totality
    of just such a sequence. In United States v. Winsor, a suspect
    stated, “I think I’d like an attorney,” which after a “couple
    moments of silence,” he followed with, “Shouldn’t I have an
    attorney here?” 549 F. App’x 630, 633 (9th Cir. 2013)
    (mem.) (internal quotation marks omitted). Our court held
    that the suspect’s two sentences—which the police did not
    attempt to “engineer”—should be read together as a single
    statement that, as a whole, was not an unambiguous request
    for counsel. 
    Id.
     Precedential or not, that decision certainly
    reflects a reasonable interpretation of Smith, which, again, is
    the low bar the State must clear.
    And if Smith would allow an officer to consider two
    separate but uninterrupted sentences together as a single
    statement, we are left with a simple question: does Smith
    mandate a different result merely because an officer manages
    to eke out half a thought between the suspect’s two
    sentences? As explained above, plainly not. Smith spoke of
    “responses to further interrogation” and was concerned with
    ambiguity manufactured through repeated questioning and
    badgering. It says nothing for where, as here, an officer
    40                  JONES V. HARRINGTON
    merely says something—but does not interrogate, question,
    or badger—before the suspect continues talking.
    The majority complains that such an interpretation of
    Smith somehow obscures the “bright-line” prohibition against
    continuing to interrogate a suspect after he has clearly
    invoked his right to silence. See Maj. Op. at 19 n.2. The
    majority claims that this interpretation would “create a gray
    area about how much [continued] interrogation is
    interrogation enough,” and would allow officers to continue
    asking a suspect “some threshold number of questions.” 
    Id.
    Not so. I must emphasize once again: the police asked no
    questions between Jones’s critical statements. The only
    “threshold number of questions” needed to distinguish this
    case from Smith is the simplest threshold of all: zero. If Jones
    had been forced to respond to even a single question—that is,
    if the police had continued to interrogate him at all—perhaps
    that would raise more difficult considerations regarding the
    precise limits of the rule set in Smith. Fortunately, in this
    case we need to recognize only that what Smith prohibits is
    “continued police questioning,” 
    469 U.S. at 97
    , and “further
    interrogation,” 
    id.
     at 100—neither of which happened here.
    At best, the majority’s expansive rule represents an
    extension of Smith to a situation not contemplated by the
    Court in that case. Regardless how much the majority might
    prefer such an extension, that is not cause for relief under
    AEDPA. See White v. Woodall, 
    134 S. Ct. 1697
    , 1706 (2014)
    (“[I]f a habeas court must extend a rationale before it can
    apply to the facts at hand, then by definition the rationale was
    not clearly established at the time of the state-court decision.”
    (internal quotation marks omitted)). Fundamentally, the
    question before us is not whether the majority’s expansive
    reading of Smith is correct or incorrect; the only question we
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                              41
    may consider is whether the state court could reasonably
    interpret Smith more narrowly so as to distinguish it from the
    situation before us. Quite obviously it could.2
    B
    Despite superficial attempts to do so, the majority cites no
    case that bridges the analytical gaps left unfilled by Smith.
    The majority asserts that Miranda v. Arizona itself clearly
    established that the police could not take into account
    anything Jones uttered after he said that he did not “want to
    talk no more.” See Maj. Op. at 4, 14–15. Cherry-picking
    quotations from Miranda, the majority argues that because
    Jones indicated “in any manner” that he wished for silence,
    the police were required to stop speaking to him. See Maj.
    Op. at 14–15, 23 (quoting Miranda, 
    384 U.S. at
    473–74).
    2
    Further, given the limitations of the record before us, I fail to see how
    we could possibly conclude that it is unreasonable to characterize Jones’s
    comments as one continuous statement. We do not have the benefit of an
    audio recording, and thus we are left to guess just how rapid the exchange
    between Jones and Jolivette was. As the author of today’s opinion
    suggested at oral argument, one quite reasonable interpretation of our
    limited record is that Jones and Jolivette spoke so quickly that they were
    “stepping on each other’s lines.” That is, perhaps the exchange was so
    rapid that Jones’s two statements came out “as almost one sentence that
    has a little interruption in there.”
    Of course, the transcript could be read in a way to make this a more
    difficult case for the government—for example if we infer a dramatic
    pause between when Jones and Jolivette spoke. But, once again, under
    AEDPA we are not asked to determine what the best reading of the record
    is (and certainly not what reading is most favorable to Jones). We are
    tasked only with determining whether the state court’s view of the
    exchange was reasonable. It was.
    42                     JONES V. HARRINGTON
    But, despite the majority’s selective quotations, it is
    decidedly not the law that police must cease speaking—or
    even questioning—once a suspect indicates that he wishes for
    silence “in any manner.” Rather, the manner in which the
    suspect requests silence must be unambiguous; an
    “ambiguous or equivocal” request will not do. Thompkins,
    
    560 U.S. at
    381–82. Thus, at least as subsequently clarified
    by the Supreme Court, Miranda would better be described to
    hold that questioning must stop whenever a suspect requests
    silence “in any [unambiguous] manner.” Despite its best
    efforts not to,3 the majority concedes as much. See Maj. Op.
    3
    The majority at times seems to suggest that our analysis should ignore
    the Supreme Court’s holding in Thompkins that a suspect’s request for
    silence must be unambiguous. See Maj. Op. at 20–21, 21–22 n.3. The
    majority argues that, if AEDPA prevents Jones from basing his claim on
    anything the Court wrote in Thompkins, see supra Part III.A.1, then the
    government must likewise ignore any aspect of Thompkins that confirms
    the correctness of the state court’s decision. See Maj. Op. at 21–22 n.3.
    But we have every reason to treat the parties differently in this respect,
    and the majority’s argument to the contrary would turn AEDPA on its
    head.
    AEDPA prohibits us from granting relief unless the state court
    unreasonably applied federal law as clearly established at the time the
    state court acted. See Greene, 
    132 S. Ct. at
    44–45. Thus, Jones cannot
    receive relief based on anything in Thompkins, because Thompkins came
    after the state court’s decision in this case. See supra Part III.A.1. The
    government, on the other hand, is asked only to show that the state court’s
    decision was reasonable. To do that, the government has no need to rely
    on Thompkins at all. Before Thompkins, we had held that it was at least
    reasonable for a court to conclude that a request for silence must be
    unambiguous, even if the Supreme Court had not clearly established as
    much. See DeWeaver v. Runnels, 
    556 F.3d 995
    , 1001–02 (9th Cir. 2009).
    Thus, in many ways, Thompkins is beside the point for the government in
    this case.
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                              43
    at 19 n.2 (“[Miranda and Smith] stand for the simple
    proposition that officers must stop questioning a suspect once
    he unambiguously invokes his right to silence . . . .”
    (emphasis added)). But that simply returns us to the same
    question we started with: what does it mean for a statement
    to be unambiguous, and what sort of factual context may an
    officer consider when interpreting the clarity of a statement?
    On these questions, Miranda provides no guidance at all.
    Completely beside the point, the majority makes much of
    the Supreme Court’s commands in Miranda and in Michigan
    v. Mosley that a valid request for silence must be
    But, even if reference to Thompkins is not necessary to conclude that
    the state court’s decision was reasonable, we may of course cite
    Thompkins to underscore that conclusion. It would be the very antithesis
    of deference for us to ignore the fact that state court’s conclusion about
    ambiguity was later held by the Supreme Court to be correct. Given the
    standard of review erected by AEDPA, there is no contradiction in
    allowing the government to rely on a case even when Jones may not. Cf.
    Lockhart v. Fretwell, 
    506 U.S. 364
    , 372–73 (1993) (state may take benefit
    of new rules on collateral review even though petitioner may not).
    Finally, I must observe that the majority and I have referenced
    Thompkins for two very different reasons. I cite Thompkins merely to
    confirm that the state court was right to conclude that Jones’s request for
    silence needed to be unambiguous. The majority, however, seeks to use
    Thompkins to sustain its otherwise unsupportable assertion that the state
    court was compelled to follow all of the Supreme Court’s prior cases
    discussing ambiguity in the right-to-counsel context. See Maj. Op. at
    21–22 n.3. Again, before Thompkins, the Supreme Court had never held
    that right-to-silence invocations are governed by the same standards as
    right-to-counsel invocations. Even if the state court determined that both
    invocations need to be “unambiguous,” it was by no means compelled also
    to conclude that the standards governing ambiguity must be the same in
    both contexts. As the majority itself points out, Maj. Op. at 16–17, there
    could reasonably be different standards that govern each right (even if that
    argument is now foreclosed by Thompkins).
    44                    JONES V. HARRINGTON
    “scrupulously honored.” See Maj. Op. at 15, 23. It is true
    that Miranda and Mosley state unequivocally that police
    questioning must cease once the right to silence is invoked.
    But that command simply instructs officers how to behave
    once the right to silence has been unambiguously invoked.
    This case is about whether the right was ever unambiguously
    invoked, or more accurately, whether the state court
    reasonably determined that any invocation was ambiguous in
    context. Neither Miranda nor Mosley speak to that question.4
    Finally, the majority reverts to what is becoming an old
    habit of our court: citing federal circuit court cases to help
    bolster an attempt to extend Supreme Court precedent under
    federal habeas review. See Maj. Op. at 15, 20, 22–23, 25
    (citing Garcia, 808 F.3d at 771; Anderson, 
    516 F.3d at 781
    ;
    United States v. Lafferty, 
    503 F.3d 293
     (3d Cir. 2007)). This
    we plainly cannot do. See Glebe v. Frost, 
    135 S. Ct. 429
    , 431
    (2014) (per curiam); Lopez v. Smith, 
    135 S. Ct. 1
    , 4 (2014)
    (per curiam); Marshall v. Rodgers, 
    133 S. Ct. 1446
    , 1450–51
    (2013) (per curiam). And even more, just like the majority’s
    chosen Supreme Court cases, none of the Court of Appeals
    cases cited by the majority actually holds that a court can
    never infer ambiguity on the basis of statements made after a
    4
    In the same vein, the majority discusses standards for evaluating a
    claim of waiver after the right to counsel has been invoked, as developed
    by the Supreme Court in cases such as Edwards v. Arizona, 
    451 U.S. 477
    (1981). See Maj. Op. at 16–17. Again, the case before us is strictly about
    whether Jones ever invoked his right to silence unambiguously; it has
    nothing to do with how we determine waiver after such an invocation has
    occurred.
    JONES V. HARRINGTON                             45
    supposedly clear request for silence.5 Even if these cases
    were relevant under AEDPA review, they would not get the
    majority to its preferred destination.
    In sum, the majority’s rejection of the factual context
    provided by Jones’s complete statements stems from an
    overly broad reading of Smith that is unsupported by
    reference to Miranda, Mosley, or any other case cited in the
    majority’s opinion. Under AEDPA, the State court cannot be
    faulted for failing to anticipate the majority’s de novo
    extension of the law.
    IV
    In this case, the California Court of Appeal: (1) identified
    the correct legal rule applicable to Jones’s right-to-silence
    claim, (2) reasonably interpreted the facts underlying Jones’s
    claim, and (3) reasonably applied that legal rule to those facts
    in rejecting the claim. The majority does not identify a single
    case—let alone a relevant Supreme Court case—that holds
    to the contrary or that even contemplates the situation in
    which Jones’s claim arose. Instead, the majority essentially
    concludes that Supreme Court precedent ought to extend
    farther than it currently does, and—as has unfortunately
    5
    Of the Court of Appeals cases, the majority relies most heavily on our
    en banc decision in Anderson v. Terhune, a case inapposite on its facts.
    There, officers ignored a suspect’s “clear and repeated invocations of his
    right to remain silent” by feigning not to understand what he meant. See
    
    516 F.3d at
    785–86. Under AEDPA, we held that Miranda does not allow
    officers to “manufacture[] [ambiguity] by straining to raise a question
    regarding the intended scope of a facially unambiguous invocation of the
    right to silence.” 
    Id. at 787
    . This case says nothing for how a court must
    interpret a one-time statement rendered ambiguous nearly immediately
    afterward—and before police officers can even complete another sentence.
    46                JONES V. HARRINGTON
    become routine for our court—chastises the state court for
    failing to predict and to adhere to the majority’s preferred
    view of the law.
    Because AEDPA prohibits federal courts from doing
    exactly that, I respectfully dissent.