Duy Mai v. United States ( 2020 )


Menu:
  •                      FOR PUBLICATION
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT
    DUY T. MAI,                                       No. 18-36071
    Plaintiff-Appellant,
    D.C. No.
    v.                           2:17-cv-00561-
    RAJ
    UNITED STATES OF AMERICA;
    UNITED STATES DEPARTMENT OF
    JUSTICE; BUREAU OF ALCOHOL,                           ORDER
    TOBACCO, FIREARMS, AND
    EXPLOSIVES; FEDERAL BUREAU OF
    INVESTIGATION; WILLIAM P. BARR,
    Attorney General; CHRISTOPHER A.
    WRAY, as Director of the Federal
    Bureau of Investigation; REGINA
    LOMBARDO, as Acting Director of
    the Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco,
    Firearms, and Explosives,
    Defendants-Appellees.
    Filed September 10, 2020
    Before: Susan P. Graber and Ronald M. Gould, Circuit
    Judges, and David A. Ezra, * District Judge.
    *
    The Honorable David A. Ezra, United States District Judge for the
    District of Hawaii, sitting by designation.
    2                    MAI V. UNITED STATES
    Order;
    Dissent by Judge Collins;
    Dissent by Judge Bumatay;
    Dissent by Judge VanDyke
    SUMMARY **
    Second Amendment
    The panel denied a petition for panel rehearing and
    denied on behalf of the court a petition for rehearing en banc.
    In the underlying appeal, the panel affirmed the district
    court’s dismissal of a 42 U.S.C. § 1983 complaint containing
    an as-applied Second Amendment challenge to 18 U.S.C.
    § 922(g)(4), which prohibits plaintiff from possessing
    firearms due to his involuntary commitment in 1999 to a
    mental institution for more than nine months after a
    Washington state court found plaintiff to be both mentally ill
    and dangerous. The panel concluded that Section 922(g)(4)’s
    continued application to plaintiff did not violate the Second
    Amendment.
    Dissenting from the denial of rehearing en banc, Judge
    Collins stated that the panel’s application of intermediate
    scrutiny here was seriously flawed and created a direct split
    with the Sixth Circuit. That alone was enough to warrant en
    banc review, and Judge Collins therefore joined Part IV.B of
    Judge Bumatay’s dissent from the denial of rehearing en
    banc. Moreover, Judge Collins stated that he had substantial
    doubt that the framework of rules that the court uses to
    **
    This summary constitutes no part of the opinion of the court. It
    has been prepared by court staff for the convenience of the reader.
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                     3
    analyze Second Amendment claims properly construes the
    controlling principles set forth in District of Columbia v.
    Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    (2008).
    Dissenting from the denial of rehearing en banc, Judge
    Bumatay, joined by Judges VanDyke, and with whom judges
    Ikuta, Bade, and Hunsaker join as to Part IV, and with whom
    Judges Bennett, Collins, and Bress join as to Part IV.B,
    stated that the panel’s opinion justified the disturbing
    deprivation of a fundamental right by ignoring the history
    and tradition of the Second Amendment and applying ill-
    suited, foreign statistical studies that had no bearing on
    plaintiff’s circumstances. The proper inquiry would have
    recognized that the lifetime ban imposed by § 922(g)(4) on
    plaintiff is unequivocally a complete deprivation of his core
    right to home gun ownership, and therefore that the law was
    unconstitutional. Judge Bumatay stated that the panel
    incorrectly identified intermediate scrutiny as the proper
    standard of review and then flubbed its application. By
    failing to correct these errors, the Court undermined its
    Second Amendment jurisprudence and gave an unworthy
    judicial imprimatur to the false premise that once mentally
    ill, always mentally ill.
    Dissenting from the denial of rehearing en banc, Judge
    VanDyke, joined by Judge Bumatay, stated that he agreed
    with Judge Bumatay’s dissent from the denial of rehearing
    en banc and wrote separately because he believes that the
    panel should have reconsidered the panel’s circular logic
    about who lies at the core of the Second Amendment. Judge
    VanDyke stated that the panel’s bootstrapping, class-based
    approach to defining those at the “core” of the Second
    Amendment was unjust and antithetical to controlling case
    law. Judge VanDyke also stated that the court’s intermediate
    4                 MAI V. UNITED STATES
    scrutiny jurisprudence is broken, at least as to Second
    Amendment claims.
    COUNSEL
    Vitaliy Kertchen (argued), Tacoma, Washington, for
    Plaintiff-Appellant.
    Abby C. Wright (argued) and Michael S. Raab, Appellate
    Staff; Brian T. Moran, United States Attorney; Joseph H.
    Hunt, Assistant Attorney General; Civil Division, United
    States Department of Justice, Washington, D.C.; for
    Defendants-Appellees.
    ORDER
    The panel judges have voted to deny Appellant’s petition
    for rehearing. Judges Graber and Gould voted to deny the
    petition for rehearing en banc, and Judge Ezra recommended
    denying the petition for rehearing en banc.
    The full court has been advised of the petition for
    rehearing en banc. A judge of the court requested a vote on
    en banc rehearing. The matter failed to receive a majority of
    votes of non-recused active judges in favor of en banc
    consideration. Fed. R. App. P. 35.
    Appellant’s petition for rehearing and petition for
    rehearing en banc, filed Docket No. 37, are DENIED.
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                     5
    COLLINS, Circuit Judge, dissenting from the denial of
    rehearing en banc:
    As Judge Bumatay ably explains in Part IV(B) of his
    dissent, the panel’s application of intermediate scrutiny here
    is seriously flawed and creates a direct split with the Sixth
    Circuit. That alone is enough to warrant en banc review, and
    I therefore join that section of Judge Bumatay’s dissent.
    Moreover, I have substantial doubt that the framework of
    rules that this court uses to analyze Second Amendment
    claims properly construes the controlling principles set forth
    in District of Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    (2008), and
    granting en banc review in this case would have given us a
    welcome opportunity to reexamine that framework. I
    respectfully dissent from our failure to rehear this case en
    banc.
    BUMATAY, Circuit Judge, with whom VANDYKE,
    Circuit Judge, joins, with whom IKUTA, BADE, and
    HUNSAKER, Circuit Judges, join as to Part IV, and with
    whom BENNETT, COLLINS, and BRESS, Circuit Judges,
    join as to Part IV.B, dissenting from the denial of rehearing
    en banc:
    Today, our court advances an extraordinarily sweeping
    view of government power. Against the text, history, and
    tradition of the Second Amendment, we hold that the
    government may forever deprive a person of the individual
    right to bear arms—if that person spends even one day
    committed involuntarily, even as a juvenile, and no matter
    the person’s current mental health soundness. Of course, we
    only adopt this view for the Second Amendment. For other,
    more fashionable constitutional rights, we would not
    countenance such an abridgment.
    6                  MAI V. UNITED STATES
    When the Second Amendment was ratified, times were
    different. Firearms were ubiquitous and their regulation was
    sparse. Firearms were considered essential for defense of
    the home and hearth. District of Columbia v. Heller,
    
    554 U.S. 570
    , 635 (2008). While times have changed, the
    Constitution has not. The Second Amendment is not “a
    second-class right,” McDonald v. City of Chicago, Ill.,
    
    561 U.S. 742
    , 780 (2010), so we must continue to uphold the
    right it confers against government encroachment. But by
    aggrandizing the government’s power here, we improperly
    relegate the Second Amendment to “disfavored right” status
    yet again. Silvester v. Becerra, 
    138 S. Ct. 945
    (2018)
    (Thomas, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari).
    In doing so, we seemingly treat some people as second-
    class citizens—concluding that they don’t deserve the full
    complement of fundamental rights. We don’t make that
    decision based on any present-day impairments or past
    criminal convictions, but, in the case of Duy Mai, for an
    involuntary commitment to a mental-health facility more
    than 20 years ago when he was just 17 years old. Because
    of that brief commitment as a teen, our court lets the federal
    government ban Mai—for life—from possessing a firearm.
    This, despite a state court finding that Mai is no longer
    mentally ill or dangerous. We justify this disturbing
    deprivation of a fundamental right by ignoring the history
    and tradition of the Second Amendment and applying ill-
    suited, foreign statistical studies that have no bearing on
    Mai’s circumstances. By failing to correct our errors here,
    we undermine our Second Amendment jurisprudence and
    give an unworthy judicial imprimatur to the false premise
    that “once mentally ill, always mentally ill.”
    I respectfully dissent from the denial of rehearing en
    banc.
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                     7
    I.
    By all accounts, Duy Mai is an American success story.
    Mai was born in a Thai refugee camp to a Vietnamese family
    and moved to the United States at the age of two. As so
    many immigrants have, Mai has flourished in this country.
    Overcoming an early language barrier, Mai carved out a
    stellar academic and professional career. After starting at a
    community college, Mai graduated from the University of
    Washington with a 3.7 GPA and a degree in microbiology.
    While at the University of Washington, Mai’s studies were
    inspired by a desire to help people living with HIV and, in
    his spare time, Mai volunteered for environmental and
    humanitarian causes. Post-graduation, Mai enrolled at the
    University of Southern California, where he focused on
    cancer research and received a master’s in microbiology.
    After returning to Washington state, Mai started a job at the
    Benaroya Research Institute, concentrating on virology. As
    part of his job, he passed an FBI background check allowing
    him access to an irradiator. Today, Mai works as an immune
    monitoring specialist at the Seattle-based Fred Hutchinson
    Cancer Research Center.
    Mai is similarly enriched in his home life. While at USC,
    Mai met a woman and they now raise eight-year-old twins.
    He remains close to his sister and parents and often meets
    them for weekend family dinners. He also enjoys wilderness
    activities and volunteer work.
    Mai has been a productive member of society for nearly
    20 years. But like most people, Mai has faced his share of
    challenges. At the age of 17, he suffered from depression,
    for which he was involuntarily committed to a mental health
    hospital for a little over two months total after a Washington
    state court determined that he might be a harm to others. But
    8                  MAI V. UNITED STATES
    since Mai’s commitment order expired in August 2000, he
    has not been re-committed and his medical record shows no
    reoccurrence of serious mental illness. He has no criminal
    history or substance abuse issues.
    Under state and federal law, Mai was barred from
    possessing a firearm due to his involuntary commitment. In
    2014, Mai successfully petitioned the State of Washington
    to remove the state-law barrier. See Wash. Rev. Code
    § 9.41.047(3)(c)(iii). Mai submitted his medical history
    showing that he’s been free of depression since at least 2010
    and that, based on the opinions of multiple psychologists, he
    is not considered a significant risk of suicide or harm to
    others. Based on this evidence and declarations from his
    friends and family, the Washington court agreed that Mai
    doesn’t present a substantial danger to himself or to the
    public and that the symptoms that led to his commitment are
    not reasonably likely to reoccur. Thus, today, under state
    law, Mai’s right to possess a firearm has been fully restored.
    Mai’s final hurdle is federal law. It prohibits an
    individual who has been “committed to a mental institution”
    from possessing a firearm. 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(4). Mai
    brought an as-applied challenge to § 922(g)(4) and sought
    declaratory and injunctive relief declaring him eligible to
    possess a firearm under federal law and the Constitution.
    The district court granted the government’s motion to
    dismiss. Mai v. United States, No. C17-0561 RAJ, 
    2018 WL 784582
    , at *6 (W.D. Wash. Feb. 8, 2018). Applying
    intermediate scrutiny, the district court rejected Mai’s claim
    based on various studies linking mental illness to a
    heightened risk of gun violence.
    Id. On appeal, this
    court affirmed. Without bothering itself
    with the text, history, or tradition of the Second Amendment,
    the court decided that, due to Mai’s brief commitment, he
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                       9
    was not a “law-abiding, responsible” citizen and, therefore,
    not protected by the Second Amendment’s “core.” See Mai
    v. United States, 
    952 F.3d 1106
    , 1115 (9th Cir. 2020). In so
    ruling, the court compared Mai’s past commitment to a
    conviction for domestic violence.
    Id. The court also
    concluded that Washington’s adjudication of his mental
    soundness and subsequent restoration of his gun rights—and
    Mai’s present-day mental health status—were irrelevant to
    the constitutional analysis.
    Id. at 1115
    , 1120. 
    Finally, with
    the help of studies from Sweden, Australia, Italy, and other
    countries, the court ruled that the permanent deprivation of
    Mai’s fundamental right cleared intermediate scrutiny.
    Id. at 1118–20.
    We should’ve corrected the layers of errors in
    this decision through en banc review.
    II.
    The Second Amendment guarantees that, “[a] well
    regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free
    State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall
    not be infringed.” U.S. Const. amend. II. “[O]n the basis of
    both text and history,” the Second Amendment confers “an
    individual right to keep and bear arms.” 
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 595
    . This guarantee was considered “among those
    fundamental rights necessary to our system of ordered
    liberty.” 
    McDonald, 561 U.S. at 778
    .
    Of course, this right is not without its limits. It does not
    guarantee a right to keep and carry “any weapon whatsoever
    in any manner whatsoever and for whatever purpose.”
    
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 626
    . The Court noted, for example, that
    nothing in Heller should “be taken to cast doubt on
    longstanding prohibitions on the possession of firearms by
    felons and the mentally ill.”
    Id. But it recognized
    that there
    would be time to “expound upon the historical justifications
    for the exceptions . . . if and when those exceptions come
    10                 MAI V. UNITED STATES
    before” the Court.
    Id. at 635.
    Heller, in the meantime,
    observed that these “longstanding” prohibitions were
    “presumptively lawful regulatory measures.”
    Id. at 627
    n.26.
    Heller provided us the roadmap for Second Amendment
    claims. The Court looked to the Amendment’s words,
    Founding-era thinkers, and early court decisions to examine
    the scope of the Second Amendment right. Heller, thus,
    showed us exactly what to look at: the text, history, and
    tradition.
    Id. at 605, 625, 635.
    Importantly, the Court
    warned that the Second Amendment was not subject to a
    “freestanding ‘interest-balancing’ approach.”
    Id. at 634.
    The Court observed that the “very enumeration of the right
    takes out of the hands of government—even the Third
    Branch of Government—the power to decide on a case-by-
    case basis whether the right is really worth insisting upon.”
    Id. Accordingly, Heller squarely
    rejected the view that “the
    scope of the Second Amendment right should be determined
    by judicial interest balancing.” 
    McDonald, 561 U.S. at 785
    .
    Yet judicial interest balancing is exactly what our court
    does. Following Heller, our circuit, like many others,
    adopted a two-step test to adjudicate Second Amendment
    claims. First, we ask whether the statute at issue “burdens
    conduct protected by the Second Amendment[.]” United
    States v. Chovan, 
    735 F.3d 1127
    , 1136 (9th Cir. 2013). We
    decide this “based on a ‘historical understanding of the scope
    of the [Second Amendment] right[.]’” Jackson v. City &
    Cty. of San Francisco, 
    746 F.3d 953
    , 960 (9th Cir. 2014)
    (quoting 
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 625
    ). Second, having
    determined that the law burdens protected Second
    Amendment activity, we select the appropriate level of
    scrutiny based on our assessment of “(1) how close the law
    comes to the core of the Second Amendment right and
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                     11
    (2) the severity of the law’s burden on the right.” 
    Chovan, 735 F.3d at 1138
    (simplified).
    Judges across this country have questioned whether
    Chovan-type tests are consistent with Heller’s command to
    follow the text, history, and tradition in evaluating the scope
    of the Second Amendment. See, e.g., United States v.
    McGinnis, 
    956 F.3d 747
    , 762 (5th Cir. 2020) (Duncan, J.,
    concurring) (encouraging the replacement of the Fifth
    Circuit’s two-step test in favor of Heller’s text and history
    mandate); Ass’n of N.J. Rifle & Pistol Clubs, Inc. v. Attorney
    Gen. New Jersey, 
    910 F.3d 106
    , 127 (3d Cir. 2018) (Bibas,
    J., dissenting) (arguing that Heller did not set up tiers of
    scrutiny with respect to regulations affecting the Second
    Amendment); Mance v. Sessions, 
    896 F.3d 390
    , 398 (5th Cir.
    2018) (Ho, J., dissenting) (explaining that Heller instructs
    that fundamental constitutional rights are enshrined with the
    scope they were understood to have at the Founding); Tyler
    v. Hillsdale Cty. Sheriff’s Dep’t, 
    837 F.3d 678
    , 702 (6th Cir.
    2016) (Batchelder, J., concurring) (encouraging the
    replacement of the Sixth Circuit’s two-step test in favor of a
    test that, as required by Heller and McDonald, looks to
    history and tradition);
    id. at 710
    (Sutton, J., concurring)
    (arguing that history and tradition should inform the scope
    of the Second Amendment rather than tiers of scrutiny);
    Ezell v. City of Chicago, 
    651 F.3d 684
    , 701–02 (7th Cir.
    2011) (Sykes, J.) (explaining that the scope of the Second
    Amendment right requires a historical inquiry into original
    meaning and does not leave room for interest-balancing);
    Heller v. District of Columbia, 
    670 F.3d 1244
    , 1271 (D.C.
    Cir. 2011) (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting) (“Heller and
    McDonald leave little doubt that courts are to assess gun
    bans and regulations based on text, history, and tradition, not
    by a balancing test such as strict or intermediate scrutiny.”);
    see also N.Y. State Rifle & Pistol Ass’n, Inc. v. City of New
    12                 MAI V. UNITED STATES
    York, 
    140 S. Ct. 1525
    , 1544 (2020) (Alito, J., dissenting)
    (“We are told that the mode of review in this case is
    representative of the way Heller has been treated in the lower
    courts. If that is true, there is cause for concern.”).
    Indeed, when this court first adopted the two-step test,
    Judge Bea rightfully questioned whether applying tiers of
    scrutiny to a Second Amendment right was consistent with
    Heller. 
    Chovan, 735 F.3d at 1143
    (Bea, J., concurring). As
    Judge Bea noted, “[u]nitary tests such as strict scrutiny,
    intermediate scrutiny, undue burden, and the like don’t make
    sense . . . in the Second Amendment context because the
    language of Heller seems to foreclose scrutiny analysis.”
    Id. (quoting Eugene Volokh,
    Implementing the Right to Keep
    and Bear Arms for Self-Defense: An Analytical Framework
    and a Research Agenda, 56 UCLA L. Rev. 1443, 1443,
    1461–73 (2009)) (simplified). Nevertheless, since Chovan
    didn’t challenge the application of an interest-balancing test,
    Judge Bea considered the question waived.
    Id. I
    share these concerns. It is difficult to square the type
    of means-ends weighing of a government regulation inherent
    in the tiers-of-scrutiny analysis with Heller’s directive that a
    core constitutional protection should not be subjected to a
    “freestanding ‘interest-balancing’ approach.”           
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 634
    . In fact, such an analysis is difficult to
    square with the interpretation of most constitutional rights.
    As Justice Scalia wrote, “[a] constitutional guarantee subject
    to future judges’ assessments of its usefulness is no
    constitutional guarantee at all.”
    Id. After all, “[t]he
    People,
    through ratification, have already weighed the policy
    tradeoffs that constitutional rights entail.” Luis v. United
    States, 
    136 S. Ct. 1083
    , 1101 (2016) (Thomas, J.,
    concurring). Our duty as unelected and unaccountable
    judges is to defer to the view of the people who ratified the
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                     13
    Second Amendment, which is itself the “very product of an
    interest balancing by the people.” 
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 635
    .
    By ignoring the balance already struck by the people, and
    instead subjecting enumerated rights, like the Second
    Amendment, to our own judicial balancing, “we do violence
    to the [constitutional] design.” Crawford v. Washington,
    
    541 U.S. 36
    , 67–68 (2004). Perhaps, this is why “[t]he
    Constitution does not prescribe tiers of scrutiny.” Whole
    Woman’s Health v. Hellerstedt, 
    136 S. Ct. 2292
    , 2327 (2016)
    (Thomas, J., dissenting).
    If operating on a clean slate, I would hew to Heller’s and
    McDonald’s fidelity to the Second Amendment’s history,
    tradition, and text. The precise contours of such a review
    should be subject to further refinement; but we might, as
    Justice Scalia suggested in Heller itself, look to the original
    meaning of the First Amendment. See 
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 635
    (suggesting categorical exceptions to the First
    Amendment as recognized at the Founding, such as
    obscenity, libel, and disclosure of state secrets); see also
    
    Tyler, 837 F.3d at 712
    (Sutton, J., concurring) (opining that
    “Heller creates an on-off switch to the right to bear arms”).
    Under this view, a law may only constitutionally prohibit the
    core right to keep arms in the home for self-defense if the
    prohibition falls within an exception understood to be
    outside of the Amendment’s scope at the time of the
    Founding.
    As the following section shows, when viewed under the
    original understanding of the Second Amendment,
    § 922(g)(4)’s application to Mai cannot pass muster.
    III.
    In the Founding era, little regulation surrounded the core
    right of gun ownership for self-defense of the home. As
    14                 MAI V. UNITED STATES
    recognized by Heller, the Founders understood the “[t]he
    right of self defence” as “the first law of nature” and “the
    true palladium of liberty[.]” 
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 606
    (quoting
    1 St. George Tucker, Blackstone’s Commentaries 300
    (1803)). William Rawle, a constitutional scholar and George
    Washington’s pick for Attorney General, noted that “[n]o
    clause in the Constitution could by any rule of construction
    be conceived to give to congress a power to disarm the
    people. . . . But if in any blind pursuit of inordinate power,
    [congress] should attempt it, [the Second] amendment may
    be appealed to[.]” William Rawle, A View of the
    Constitution of the United States 125–26 (2d. ed 1829).
    When proposing a model constitution for Virginia in 1776,
    Jefferson included within the document the explicit
    guarantee that “[n]o free man shall be debarred the use of
    arms in his own lands.” The Jefferson Cyclopedia 51 (Foley
    ed., reissued 1967).
    Historical regulations of the right to bear arms focused
    more on how people used weapons—not who could own
    them. For example, in 1840, the Alabama Supreme Court
    upheld a ban on the secret carrying of guns and knives. State
    v. Reid, 
    1 Ala. 612
    , 614–15, 622 (1840); see also Aymette v.
    State, 
    21 Tenn. 154
    (1840) (upholding a statute making the
    carrying of a concealed weapon a crime); State v. Chandler,
    
    5 La. Ann. 489
    , 489–90 (1850) (same). In 1846, the
    Supreme Court of Georgia noted that at the time of the
    Founding there was a distinction between “a law prohibiting
    the exercise of the right [to bear arms], and a law merely
    regulating the manner of exercising that right.” Nunn v.
    State, 
    1 Ga. 243
    , 247 (1846). Consequently, a state
    legislature could ban the concealed-carry of a gun, so long
    as the ban did not infringe upon the “natural right of self-
    defence, or of [the] constitutional right to keep and bear
    arms.”
    Id. at 251.
                       MAI V. UNITED STATES                    15
    Indeed, the first decision addressing a firearms
    regulation based on the condition of a person (rather than the
    manner of carrying) did not arise until 1886. See C. Kevin
    Marshall, Why Can’t Martha Stewart Have A Gun?,
    32 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 695, 711 (2009) (citing State v.
    Shelby, 
    2 S.W. 468
    , 469 (Mo. 1886)) (hereinafter,
    “Martha”). In Shelby, the Supreme Court of Missouri
    upheld a restriction on the carrying of a deadly weapon while
    
    intoxicated. 2 S.W. at 469
    . Similarly, late 19th century laws
    in Michigan and the District of Columbia restricted weapons
    ownership for minors. See Martha at 712 n.93. But as a
    Texas state court explained, the state may have “the power
    by law to regulate the wearing of arms, with a view to
    prevent crime, but it has not the power to enact a law the
    violation of which will work a forfeiture of defendant’s
    arms.” Jennings v. State, 
    5 Tex. Ct. App. 298
    , 300 (1878)
    (striking down a law requiring forfeiture of guns used during
    a crime under the state constitution).
    It should come as no surprise, then, that scholars have
    “search[ed] in vain through eighteenth-century records to
    find any laws specifically excluding the mentally ill from
    firearms ownership.” Carlton F.W. Larson, Four Exceptions
    in Search of a Theory: District of Columbia v. Heller and
    Judicial Ipse Dixit, 
    60 Hastings L.J. 1371
    , 1376 (2009).
    Such laws would be highly unusual in a context where
    regulations focused on use rather than ownership. Not until
    1930 do we see laws specifically touching on gun ownership
    and mental health, after the ABA-approved Uniform
    Firearms Act prohibited delivery of a pistol to any person of
    “unsound” mind.
    Id. at 1376
    (quoting Handbook of the
    National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State
    Laws and Proceedings of the Fortieth Annual Conference
    563 (1930)). The Act, first drafted in 1926, sought to
    promote uniform state laws on firearms. Legislation, The
    16                   MAI V. UNITED STATES
    Uniform Firearms Act, 
    18 Va. L
    . Rev. 904, 904–05 (1932).
    It was adopted by Pennsylvania in 1931
    , id. at 905
    n.9, and
    other states passed similar laws in the following decades,
    see, e.g., 1965 N.Y. Laws 2343, 2472 (codified at N.Y. Penal
    Law §400.00.1 (McKinney 2008)). The statute at issue here,
    § 922(g)(4), was not enacted until 1968. Gun Control Act of
    1968, Pub. L. No. 90-618, 82 Stat. 1213, 1220.
    Given the paucity of Founding-era laws specifically
    prohibiting gun ownership by the mentally ill, we are better
    served by exploring the dominant thinking on mental illness
    in that period. On this, the evidence is clear: temporary
    mental illness didn’t lead to a permanent deprivation of
    rights.
    Influential philosophers of the day understood that rights
    attach with the attainment of “reason” and, correspondingly,
    the loss of rights persisted only through the loss of reason.
    See 
    Tyler, 837 F.3d at 705
    –06 (Batchelder, J., concurring)
    (citing 1 Jean-Jacques Burlamaqui, The Principles of
    Natural and Politic Law 82 (1747); John Locke, Two
    Treatises of Government (1691), reprinted in 4 John Locke,
    The Works of John Locke 207, 339, 342 (12th ed. 1824);
    1 Frederick Pollock & Frederic William Maitland, The
    History of English Law Before the Time of Edward I 507–08
    (1898)). This understanding accorded with a deeply rooted
    common law tradition recognizing that mental illness was
    not a permanent condition. See
    id. at 707–14
    (Sutton, J.,
    concurring) (citing 1 William Blackstone, Commentaries
    *304–05; Anthony Highmore, A Treatise on the Law of
    Idiocy and Lunacy 104 (1807)). 1 Thus, an “insane” person
    1
    For example, in 1689, a Virginia court ordered the confinement of
    John Stock, who kept “running about the neighborhood day and night in
    sad Distracted Condition to the great Disturbance of the people” to
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                         17
    was one who “by disease, grief, or other accident hath lost
    the use of his reason.” 1 William Blackstone, Commentaries
    *304. But “the law always imagines, that the[] accidental
    misfortunes [that caused the lunacy] may be removed” and
    at that point the person’s rights restored.
    Id. at *304–05;
    see
    1 Frederick Pollock & Frederic William Maitland, The
    History of English Law Before the Time of Edward I 507–08
    (1898); see also Anthony Highmore, A Treatise on the Law
    of Idiocy and Lunacy 73 (1807) (“[A] lunatic [was] never to
    be looked upon as irrecoverable.”).
    These views on the mentally ill were reflected in
    historical practices and laws. Even as Virginia sought to
    ratify its constitution with a limitation on the civil rights of
    “lunatics,” such limitation was only “during their state of
    insanity.”        1 St. George Tucker, Blackstone’s
    Commentaries: With Notes of Reference, to the Constitution
    and Laws, of the Federal Government of the United States;
    and of the Commonwealth of Virginia 145 (1803). Virginia
    recognized that “an[c]ient law” mandated that the insane
    should recover their rights when “they recovered their
    senses.”
    Id. For example, even
    if a former “lunatic[]” had
    his property taken, he was free to petition a tribunal to
    establish that “he was now restored to his Understanding” in
    order to re-claim the property. Charles Viner, A General
    Abridgment of Law and Equity 138 (1741). And while
    judicial officials were authorized to “lock up” “lunatics” or
    “other individuals with dangerous mental impairments”
    (thereby depriving them of all rights), they were “locked up
    only so long as such lunacy or disorder shall continue, and
    no longer.” Henry Care, English Liberties, or the Free- born
    prevent “his doeing any further Mischiefe.” Gerald N. Grob, Mad
    Among Us 16 (1994). But Stock was to be confined only “until hee bee
    in a better condition to Governe himself.”
    Id. 18
                   MAI V. UNITED STATES
    Subject’s Inheritance 329 (6th ed. 1774). Similarly, the
    statute of limitations affecting a claimed property right
    would not run against a mentally ill person until the
    “removal of his disability and knowledge of the existence
    of” such right. See Dicken v. Johnson, 
    7 Ga. 484
    , 494
    (1849).
    From this historical record a clear picture emerges:
    mental illness was considered a temporary ailment that only
    justified a temporary deprivation of rights. At the time of
    the Founding, the idea that the formerly mentally ill were
    permanently deprived of full standing in the community was
    nowhere to be found. Thus, § 922(g)(4)’s permanent
    prohibition on those “formerly committed to a mental
    institution” patently burdens the Second Amendment right
    of an individual, like Mai, who has been adjudicated to be
    no longer mentally ill and whose commitment was long ago.
    Heller’s observations about “presumptively lawful
    regulatory measures” does not change this analysis. See
    United States v. Torres, 
    911 F.3d 1253
    , 1262 (9th Cir. 2019).
    Heller’s reference to firearm prohibitions for the “mentally
    ill” as being “presumptively 
    lawful,” 554 U.S. at 626
    , 627
    n.26, apply to those who are presently mentally ill. “[A]
    good rule of thumb for reading [Court] decisions is that what
    they say and what they mean are one and the same.” Mathis
    v. United States, 
    136 S. Ct. 2243
    , 2254 (2016). As such, we
    view these categories as “well-defined and narrowly
    limited.” 
    Jackson, 746 F.3d at 960
    (quoting Brown v. Entm’t
    Merchants Ass’n, 
    564 U.S. 786
    , 791 (2011)). Accordingly,
    nothing in these categories contravenes the historical
    evidence that mental illness was considered a temporary
    status with no lifelong legal consequences. Because Mai is
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                          19
    not currently mentally ill, he doesn’t belong in that
    “presumptive” category. 2
    With no historical support for this type of permanent
    restriction, or even an analogous restriction, § 922(g)(4) as
    applied to Mai violates the Second Amendment’s command
    that “the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not
    be infringed.” U.S. Const. amend. II. Accordingly, we
    should have said as much and reversed the district court’s
    decision.
    IV.
    As I have shown, § 922(g)(4)’s application to Mai has no
    basis in the text, tradition, and history of the Second
    Amendment. But until our court agrees to apply such a test
    to Second Amendment claims under en banc review or the
    Court provides us with further guidance, we remain bound
    by the Chovan test. But even under that test, the court still
    got it wrong.        The court first incorrectly identified
    intermediate scrutiny as the proper standard of review and
    then flubbed its application. These errors were further
    reason to revisit this case.
    A.
    As discussed, Chovan calls for a two-step process. First,
    we determine if the law “burdens conduct protected by the
    Second Amendment,” 
    Chovan, 735 F.3d at 1136
    , “based on
    a historical understanding of the scope of the [Second
    2
    As the Sixth Circuit held, “Heller’s presumption of lawfulness
    should not be used to enshrine a permanent stigma on anyone who has
    ever been committed to a mental institution for whatever reason.” 
    Tyler, 837 F.3d at 688
    . To do so “would amount to a judicial endorsement of
    Congress’s power to declare, ‘Once mentally ill, always so.’”
    Id. 20
                    MAI V. UNITED STATES
    Amendment] right[.]” 
    Jackson, 746 F.3d at 960
    (9th Cir.
    2014) (simplified). Second, we decide what level of scrutiny
    applies based on our assessment of “(1) how close the law
    comes to the core of the Second Amendment right and
    (2) the severity of the law’s burden on the right.” 
    Chovan, 735 F.3d at 1138
    (simplified). Depending on the answers to
    these questions, we determine our review on a sliding scale
    ranging from intermediate scrutiny to per se
    unconstitutionality. See Silvester v. Harris, 
    843 F.3d 816
    ,
    821 (9th Cir. 2016). A law, like the complete handgun ban
    examined in Heller, that imposes “such a severe restriction”
    on the core Second Amendment right that “it amounts to a
    destruction of [that] right” is per se unconstitutional. See
    Bauer v. Becerra, 
    858 F.3d 1216
    , 1222 (9th Cir. 2017)
    (simplified). A “law that implicates the core of the Second
    Amendment right and severely burdens that right”—without
    totally destroying it, like a ban on large-capacity
    magazines—“warrants strict scrutiny.” Duncan v. Becerra,
    No. 19-55376, 
    2020 WL 4730668
    , at *22 (9th Cir. Aug. 14,
    2020) (quoting 
    Silvester, 843 F.3d at 821
    , 827). For all other
    laws that do not implicate the core Second Amendment right
    or do not substantially burden that right, like a short waiting
    period to purchase firearms, we apply intermediate scrutiny.
    
    Torres, 911 F.3d at 1262
    (citing 
    Jackson, 746 F.3d at 961
    );
    
    Silvester, 843 F.3d at 823
    .
    The court erred at both steps of the Chovan analysis. At
    step one, the court assumed, rather than decided, that
    § 922(g)(4) as applied to Mai burdens conduct protected by
    the Second Amendment right. 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1114
    . But
    by dodging the question of “which perspective better
    comports with the historical evidence,”
    id., the court sidesteps
    Heller’s command to review the text, history, and
    tradition of the Amendment. 
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 605
    , 625,
    635. But when we suspect that a question may implicate a
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                         21
    “core” constitutional concern, “we should do more before
    tossing it aside.” Fazaga v. FBI, 
    965 F.3d 1015
    , 1079 (9th
    Cir. 2020) (Bumatay, J., dissenting). Furthermore, when
    undertaking a constitutional analysis, “[w]e should resolve
    questions about the scope of [our] precedents in light of and
    in the direction of the constitutional text and constitutional
    history.” Edmo v. Corizon, Inc., 
    949 F.3d 489
    , 506 (9th Cir.
    2020) (Bumatay, J., dissenting) (quoting Free Enter. Fund
    v. Public Co. Accounting Oversight Bd., 
    537 F.3d 667
    , 698
    (D.C. Cir. 2008) (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting)).
    By punting the analysis of the historical scope of the
    Second Amendment and its impact on the formerly mentally
    ill, we let false assumptions cloud our judgment and distort
    our precedent even further from the original understanding
    of the Constitution. Had we done the requisite analysis, we
    would have recognized that this law not only burdens
    Second Amendment-protected conduct, but that it also
    strikes at the core right protected by its guarantee. Instead,
    our court skips this important step—an omission that infects
    the rest of the Chovan analysis.
    The court erred again at Chovan step two, by incorrectly
    identifying intermediate scrutiny as the proper standard. 3 As
    we have recently explained, step two of Chovan “is a simple
    inquiry: if a law regulating arms adversely affects a law-
    abiding citizen’s right of defense of hearth and home, that
    law strikes at the core Second Amendment right.” Duncan,
    
    2020 WL 4730668
    , at *12; 
    Jackson, 746 F.3d at 961
    3
    Without reference to our precedent, Mai apparently agreed that
    intermediate scrutiny should apply to his case. See 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1115
    . Nevertheless, “we are not bound to decide a matter of
    constitutional law based on a concession.” Colo. Republican Fed.
    Campaign Comm. v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 
    518 U.S. 604
    , 622 (1996).
    22                 MAI V. UNITED STATES
    (recognizing that laws which regulate only the “manner in
    which persons may exercise their Second Amendment
    rights” are less burdensome than those which “bar firearm
    possession completely”) (quoting 
    Chovan, 735 F.3d at 1138
    ); see also 
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 635
    (“[W]hatever else
    it leaves to future evaluation, [the Second Amendment]
    surely elevates above all other interests the right of law-
    abiding, responsible citizens to use arms in defense of hearth
    and home.”).
    Under this framework, the application of § 922(g)(4) to
    Mai strikes at the core Second Amendment right—and guts
    it. Indeed, § 922(g)(4) completely deprives Mai of the
    ability to possess a firearm, even within the home, where
    protections are “at their zenith.” Duncan, 
    2020 WL 4730668
    , at *12 (quoting Kachalsky v. Cty. of Westchester,
    
    701 F.3d 81
    , 89 (2d Cir. 2012)). In any other context, laws
    that burden the core of a fundamental right are invariably
    analyzed under heightened scrutiny—e.g., restrictions on the
    “content” of speech rarely survive strict scrutiny, e.g., Brown
    v. Entm’t Merchs. Ass’n, 
    564 U.S. 786
    , 799 (2011), nor do
    laws that restrict “core” political speech, see, e.g., McIntyre
    v. Ohio Elections Comm’n, 
    514 U.S. 334
    , 347 (1995);
    Buckley v. Am. Constitutional Law Found., Inc., 
    525 U.S. 182
    , 207 (1999) (Thomas, J., concurring). We should not
    treat the Second Amendment any different. Instead, we
    should have recognized that § 922(g)(4) effects a complete
    deprivation of Mai’s core Second Amendment right and held
    the law unconstitutional as applied to him.
    At a minimum, the law is a “substantial burden” on the
    core Second Amendment right, warranting the application of
    strict scrutiny. Duncan, 
    2020 WL 4730668
    , at *22. But the
    court evaded any form of strict scrutiny, despite admitting
    that § 922(g)(4)’s “lifetime ban” on Mai’s Second
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                             23
    Amendment right was “quite substantial,” by minimizing the
    law’s burden as falling on only a “narrow class” of
    individuals. 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1115
    . In doing so, the court
    seemingly pulls new doctrine out of its hat and magically
    transforms a fundamental right that belongs to an individual,
    
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 592
    , into one that is class-based. Rather
    than face the total and permanent deprivation of the core
    Second Amendment right for Mai (and the class of people
    like him), the court refocused the inquiry on the size of the
    class. And ta-da!, the court holds, intermediate scrutiny
    applies. Like most magicians, the court refused to explain
    its act. 4 Because the law deprives only a “narrow class” of
    individuals their Second Amendment right, ipse dixit, it is
    analyzed only under intermediate scrutiny. Such reasoning
    is even more perplexing given that heightened scrutiny was
    originally announced as a method to protect the rights of
    “discrete and insular minorities.” See United States v.
    Carolene Prods. Co., 
    304 U.S. 144
    , 152 n.4 (1938). Today,
    according to the court, the fact that Mai belongs to a “narrow
    class” is, paradoxically, the very reason to lower the level of
    scrutiny applied to him. We should have corrected this
    jurisprudential sleight of hand.
    Next, the court justified its decision to apply
    intermediate scrutiny by refusing to recognize Mai as a “law-
    abiding, responsible citizen.” But its refusal to do so is
    baffling. Besides a brief involuntary commitment as a
    youth, nothing in the record shows that Mai is anything but
    4
    The court cites to Tyler for its analysis, 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1115
    , but
    Tyler provides no reasoning for the class-based burden approach and
    only cites to a Tenth Circuit case for that proposition. 
    Tyler, 837 F.3d at 691
    (citing United States v. Reese, 
    627 F.3d 792
    , 802 (10th Cir.
    2010)). In turn, the Tenth Circuit case merely announces the proposition
    with no accompanying analysis. 
    Reese, 627 F.3d at 792
    . So the court
    falls into a rabbit hole within rabbit holes to justify its conclusion.
    24                    MAI V. UNITED STATES
    a “law-abiding, responsible citizen.” Instead, it shows that
    Mai is a person of advanced education and demonstrated
    professional achievement, with strong community and
    family support and no history of criminal activity or
    substance abuse.       Yes, he suffered from significant
    depression as a teen, but recent psychological evaluators and
    Washington state have concluded he is not currently
    mentally ill and presents no risk of violence to others or
    himself. Nor is that reasonably likely to change in the future.
    Washington, in turn, restored his right to possess firearms
    under state law.
    But this court decided it knows better, holding that,
    “[r]egardless of [Mai’s] present-day peaceableness,” Mai is
    not a “law-abiding, responsible citizen” because of his brief
    commitment 20 years ago. 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1115
    . The
    court, with no analysis, held that “[t]he same logic” used to
    prohibit a domestic-violence convict from possessing a
    firearm applied here—to a person like Mai.
    Id. (citing Chovan, 735
    F.3d at 1138). 5 But a criminal conviction is not
    the same as mental illness. Unless pardoned, expunged, or
    set aside, a conviction always remains a conviction under the
    law. See, e.g., 18 U.S.C. § 921(a)(20)(B), (33)(B)(ii). And,
    5
    In Chovan, we found § 922(g)(9)’s prohibition on firearm
    possession by domestic-violence misdemeanants didn’t implicate the
    “core” Second Amendment protection because the law’s burden fell only
    on “individuals with criminal convictions.” Chovan, F.3d at 1138. The
    court doesn’t justify why mental illness fits into the same category.
    Indeed, while civil commitment often results from threats of physical
    harm, some states allow civil commitment where no risk of physical
    harm is present at all. See, e.g., Haw. Rev. Stat. § 334-1 (“substantial”
    emotional injury on others); Iowa Code § 229.1(20) (“serious” emotional
    injury on others); Kan. Stat. Ann. § 59-2946(f)(1)–(3) (property
    damage); La. Stat. Ann. §§ 28:55(E)(1), 28:2(10) (substance abuse);
    N.H. Rev. Stat. Ann. §§ 135-C:34, 135-C:2(X) (noncontinuous alcohol
    abuse).
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                      25
    at least for felony convictions, there is historical support for
    a law resulting in forfeiture of property and rights. See
    2 William Blackstone, Commentaries *377 (describing the
    possible punishments of serious crime as including
    “confiscation, by forfeiture of lands, or moveables, or both,
    or of the profits of lands for life: others induce a disability,
    of holding offices or employments, being heirs, executors,
    and the like”); see also United States v. McCane, 
    573 F.3d 1037
    , 1049 (10th Cir. 2009) (Tymkovich, J., concurring)
    (“[T]he application of § 922(g) to a violent felon . . . would
    appear appropriate under any Second Amendment reading.
    After all, felons lose out on fundamental rights such as
    voting and serving on juries, and face discrimination that
    need only survive rational basis review.”). As we have said,
    “felons are categorically different from the individuals who
    have a fundamental right to bear arms.” United States v.
    Vongxay, 
    594 F.3d 1111
    , 1115 (9th Cir. 2010).
    So, while the law may hold that “once a convict, always
    a convict,” tradition, history, and elementary psychology
    teach us that “once mentally ill, not always mentally ill.”
    This is the distinction that the court ignores. Indeed, under
    the court’s extreme reading of the law, any person falls
    outside of the Constitution’s core protection if that person
    spends even one day in commitment—even as a youth!
    Nothing in the text, history, and tradition of Constitution
    supports this view. The proper inquiry would have
    recognized that the lifetime ban imposed by § 922(g)(4) on
    Mai is unequivocally a complete deprivation of his core right
    to home gun ownership.              As such, the law is
    unconstitutional.
    B.
    Even accepting the court’s error and analyzing Mai’s
    claim under intermediate scrutiny, we still got it wrong.
    26                    MAI V. UNITED STATES
    To satisfy intermediate scrutiny, the government’s
    statutory objective must be “significant, substantial, or
    important,” and there must be a “reasonable fit” between the
    challenged law and that objective. 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1115
    (quoting 
    Silvester, 843 F.3d at 821
    –22). 6 The burden of
    satisfying intermediate scrutiny is demanding and rests
    entirely on the government. United States v. Virginia,
    
    518 U.S. 515
    , 533 (1996). It doesn’t require the court to
    approve “shoddy data or reasoning.” See City of Los Angeles
    v. Alameda Books, Inc., 
    535 U.S. 425
    , 438 (2002). We
    demand “consistency and substantiality” in the evidence the
    government uses to establish a sufficient fit between its
    means and ends. Lalli v. Lalli, 
    439 U.S. 259
    , 274 (1978)
    (quoting Mathews v. Lucas, 
    427 U.S. 495
    , 515 (1976)). The
    proffer of “loose-fitting generalities” in the form of
    statistical data is insufficient to clear intermediate scrutiny.
    See Craig v. Boren, 
    429 U.S. 190
    , 191–92, 202–04, 209
    (1976) (rejecting to the use of “broad sociological
    propositions” to particularized applications under
    heightened scrutiny).
    Here, the court disclaims any adherence to the false
    assumption that “once mentally ill, always mentally ill.”
    The court also fully professes to believe in Mai’s current
    mental health. But, once we acknowledge that Mai has no
    present-day mental health impairment, what justifies the
    deprivation of his fundamental right? Apparently, according
    to the court, Swedish statistical studies.
    6
    As Judge VanDyke traces in his dissent, our court transplanted the
    “reasonable fit” standard from the First Amendment context, where it
    was used to evaluate neutral, incidental burdens on speech. VanDyke,
    J., dissenting at 46. I join Judge VanDyke in questioning whether this
    standard inappropriately waters down the exacting scrutiny required to
    review the complete deprivation of a fundamental right.
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                            27
    In justifying the “reasonable fit” between the
    government’s objective here, the court relies on several ill-
    suited studies, many compiling data from foreign countries.
    One of the primary studies relied on by the court analyzed
    suicide risk after release from involuntary commitment, but
    offered no information about suicide risk for someone like
    Mai—20 years past his commitment and free of mental
    health issues. 7 See also 
    Tyler, 837 F.3d at 696
    (finding this
    same study insufficient to “explain why a lifetime ban [on
    gun possession] is reasonably necessary”). The court admits
    the inapplicability of this study to someone like Mai. See
    
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1121
    . But undeterred, the court offers
    additional studies, perhaps even more inapplicable, such as
    a study focused on patients from Sweden, 8 “community
    care” patients from Italy and Australia, 9 an “[o]ut-patients”
    7
    Of the patients considered, 98% were considered for only a year
    following their commitment, and the remaining 2% were studied from
    2.5 to 8.5 years post-commitment. E. Clare Harris & Brian Barraclough,
    Suicide as an Outcome for Mental Disorders: A Meta-Analysis, 170 Brit.
    J. Psychiatry 205, 219 (1997) (hereinafter “Meta-Analysis”). The study
    doesn’t include any research into the suicide risk at 10, 15, and 20 years
    out from commitment—even while recognizing that “[s]uicide risk
    seems highest at the beginning of treatment and diminishes thereafter.”
    Meta-Analysis at 223.
    8
    In one study of “[p]reviously hospitalised patients,” 80% of the
    observations were from Sweden and involved all types of psychiatric
    diagnoses, not just depression. See 
    Mai, 953 F.3d at 1118
    (citing Meta-
    Analysis at 220–21); Allgulander C. et al., Risk of Suicide by Psychiatric
    Diagnosis in Stockholm County. A Longitudinal Study of 80,970
    Psychiatric Inpatients, 241 Eur. Archives Psychiatry Clinical
    Neuroscience 323, 324 (1992); Appendix, Figure 1.
    9
    In this study of “[c]ommunity care patients,” 86% of observations
    were patients from Italy and Australia (the United States represented a
    mere 4% or three total observations). 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1118
    (citing
    28                   MAI V. UNITED STATES
    study with a meager 34 observations, 10 and another study of
    predominately foreign patients (with some U.S. data from
    1969). 11
    The court offered no reasoned explanation of how a
    fundamental right can be contingent on off-point studies
    conducted overseas, see 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1117
    –18 (relying
    on Meta-Analysis), despite the Supreme Court counseling
    against relying on such inapposite data. See 
    Craig, 429 U.S. at 201
    .
    The court’s application of intermediate scrutiny here
    requires more of a rifle’s precision, not a shotgun’s spread.
    See Ass’n of N.J. Rifle & Pistol Clubs, 
    Inc., 910 F.3d at 133
    –
    34 (Bibas, J., dissenting) (“Intermediate scrutiny requires
    more concrete and specific proof before the government may
    restrict any constitutional right, period.”). The panel’s cited
    studies fail to meet this standard because none demonstrate
    a “continued risk presented by people who were
    involuntarily committed many years ago and who have no
    history of intervening mental illness, criminal activity, or
    substance abuse.” 
    Tyler, 837 F.3d at 699
    . If we are to accede
    to the permanent deprivation of Mai’s fundamental right, we
    should, at a minimum, demand evidence sufficiently tailored
    to his circumstances. See
    id. (remanding to the
    district court
    Meta-Analysis at 221); see Appendix, Figure 2. The court doesn’t even
    define “community care,” much less its relevance to Mai.
    10
    
    Mai, 252 F.3d at 1118
    (citing Meta-Analysis at 220–21); see
    Appendix, Figure 3.
    11
    
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1118
    (citing Meta-Analysis at 221); see
    Appendix, Figure 4.
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                     29
    to allow the government to present “additional evidence
    explaining the necessity of § 922(g)(4)’s lifetime ban”).
    V.
    Many years ago, judges took a turn as pseudo-
    psychologists and waded into whether a woman’s mental
    health may be balanced against her constitutional rights. See
    Buck v. Bell, 
    274 U.S. 200
    (1927). That case is generally not
    treated kindly today. I fear the court goes down the same
    path.
    Heller’s endorsement of text, history, and tradition as the
    proper lens for evaluating the scope of the Second
    Amendment was not accidental.             There, the Court
    emphatically disapproved of courts determining on an ad hoc
    basis whether certain individuals were undeserving of the
    full complement of fundamental rights. Duy Mai deserves
    better. Our Constitution deserves better. I respectfully
    dissent from the denial of rehearing en banc.
    30   MAI V. UNITED STATES
    APPENDIX
    Figure 1
    Figure 2
    MAI V. UNITED STATES   31
    Figure 3
    Figure 4
    32                 MAI V. UNITED STATES
    VANDYKE, Circuit Judge, with whom BUMATAY,
    Circuit Judge, joins, dissenting from denial of rehearing en
    banc:
    In the final paragraph of its opinion rejecting Mai’s
    Second Amendment claim, the panel emphasized that “[w]e
    emphatically do not subscribe to the notion that ‘once
    mentally ill, always so.’” Mai v. United States, 
    952 F.3d 1106
    , 1121 (9th Cir. 2020). I believe them. Yet just like the
    government’s position in this case, the panel’s decision
    inescapably effectuates exactly that ethic. How can this
    court purport to be applying “heightened” scrutiny, yet bless
    a legal position and practical outcome everyone insists isn’t
    true?
    The answer is a simple four-letter word: guns. It is hard
    to conceive of any other area of the law where, given the
    opportunity to apply heightened scrutiny, this court would
    countenance for a moment an outcome rooted in the
    scientifically indefensible, morally repugnant, and legally
    insufficient concept of “once mentally ill, always so.” Mr.
    Mai could understandably take personally this court’s
    labeling of him as a second-class citizen (more on that
    below). But he shouldn’t. Our court cannot really believe
    that, just because a currently healthy individual decades ago
    suffered from mental illness, they are permanently relegated
    to a disfavored status impervious to even heightened
    scrutiny. Mr. Mai is not a second-class citizen—not in this
    court’s eyes or anyone else’s. He’s just seeking to exercise
    a second-class right. He is another innocent casualty of this
    court’s demonstrated dislike of things that go bang. Perhaps
    Mr. Mai can take faint solace in the fact that, were he seeking
    to exercise any other right entitled to heightened scrutiny, he
    would no doubt get the judicial review he plainly merits.
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                       33
    Mai, and all others who have overcome mental illness,
    deserve better than to be permanently designated second-
    class citizens, particularly as it relates to their equal
    participation in a fundamental right. I therefore agree
    entirely with Judge Bumatay’s dissent and write separately
    to expound on two of the reasons this case deserved en banc
    attention.
    First, our en banc court should have reconsidered and
    corrected the panel’s circular logic about who lies at the
    “core” of the Second Amendment. By lumping individuals
    like Mai into overbroad groups that, as a whole, may pose
    heightened risks of violence, the panel has effectively given
    governments carte blanche to legislate the Second
    Amendment away. The panel’s classist approach labels
    many law-abiding, responsible citizens like Mai non-law-
    abiding, irresponsible citizens, outside the protections of the
    Second Amendment. No evidence suggests Mai is mentally
    ill, yet the panel’s rationale labels him so, for life. The panel
    then uses this grouping to lower the applicable level of
    scrutiny, which in turn relaxes (or eliminates) the
    requirement that a restriction should substantially fit the
    government objective. It’s circular. All this, when the
    “core” of the Second Amendment in Heller is about
    protected conduct—not people.
    Second, our intermediate scrutiny jurisprudence is
    broken, at least as to Second Amendment claims. We have
    appropriated a “reasonable fit” standard from the First
    Amendment context, where it was used to evaluate neutral,
    incidental burdens on speech. Not only have we pilfered a
    test ill-suited to direct burdens on a different fundamental
    right, we have further diminished that already too-anemic
    test. Our track record on the Second Amendment is quite
    34                MAI V. UNITED STATES
    poor, and the analytical maltreatment exhibited again in this
    case only adds to the rap sheet.
    I. ASSUMPTIONS, PRESUMPTIONS, AND THE
    “CORE” OF THE SECOND AMENDMENT RIGHT
    A. The Panel’s Awkward Assumption at Chovan Step 1
    The panel sidestepped the difficult task of determining
    whether 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(4) burdens Mai’s Second
    Amendment rights (Chovan Step 1) by simply assuming it
    did. 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1114
    –15. According to the panel, a
    restriction does not burden a Second Amendment right if it
    fits a presumptively lawful ban in Heller (felons or the
    mentally ill) or regulates conduct outside the scope of the
    Second Amendment.
    Id. at 1114
    (referencing Unites States
    v. Chovan, 
    735 F.3d 1127
    , 1136 (9th Cir. 2013)). Blanketly
    banning firearm possession clearly implicates the scope of
    the Second Amendment, so, if the panel had decided Mai’s
    case at Chovan Step 1, it could only uphold § 922(g)(4) as
    applied to Mai by concluding that he is properly included
    amongst “the mentally ill.” Faced with either holding that
    Mai’s past mental illness rendered him perpetually mentally
    ill (once mentally ill, always so) or admitting that Mai had
    the same Second Amendment right as any other law-abiding
    citizen, the panel punted.
    Id. at 1115
    . 
    This “well-trodden”
    analytical technique is generally fine, but here the panel
    buried the lede in Chovan Step 1 to avoid the awkwardness
    of expressly saying up front what it implicitly concluded in
    Chovan Step 2, Prong 1: that Mr. Mai’s long-ago mental
    illness forever excludes him from the community of “law-
    abiding, responsible citizens” under the Second Amendment
    (i.e., once mentally ill, always so). 
    Chovan, 735 F.3d at 1138
    .
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                    35
    B. After Assuming the Statute Burdens Mai’s Second
    Amendment Rights, the Panel Concluded Mai Is
    “Well Outside the Core of the Second Amendment.”
    Chovan Step 2 is a two-prong inquiry to determine the
    appropriate level of scrutiny: (1) how close the law comes to
    the core of the Second Amendment and (2) the severity of
    the law’s burden on that right. 
    Chovan, 735 F.3d at 1138
    .
    As to the second prong, the panel correctly recognized that
    § 922(g)(4) severely burdens Mai’s Second Amendment
    right and amounts to a lifetime ban on firearm ownership.
    
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1115
    .
    This put all the pressure on the panel’s Prong 2 “core”
    analysis. The panel first determined Mai was not a law-
    abiding, responsible citizen because of his former mental
    illness.
    Id. (likening Mai to
    domestic violence
    misdemeanants). From this, and despite § 922(g)(4)’s
    severe burden on Mai’s Second Amendment rights, the panel
    concluded that § 922(g)(4) “falls well outside the core of the
    Second Amendment right.”
    Id. The panel then
    deemed a
    lower level of scrutiny appropriate, because a “lifetime ban”
    on the formerly committed “burdens only a narrow class of
    individuals who are not at the core of the Second
    Amendment.”
    Id. The panel believes
    class-based categorical bans are
    permissible under intermediate scrutiny, so long as those
    bans target groups that pose a heightened risk of violence.
    Id. at 1116.
    Because some metrics indicate that individuals
    recently involuntarily committed are more violent than the
    general public, the panel surmises that the firearm ban, as
    applied to Mai (who was committed as a juvenile decades
    36                    MAI V. UNITED STATES
    ago), survives intermediate scrutiny. 1
    Id. at 1116–17.
    But
    this standard abandons any reasonable fit requirement.
    Presumably, the panel’s version of “intermediate scrutiny”
    would uphold firearm bans as applied to young men, the
    poor, or the entire 2008 Florida Gators football team. 2
    Ironically, the broader the class, the more likely it is to pass
    this standard. Suppose Congress instituted a firearm ban
    against anyone who has committed a crime—from
    jaywalkers to violent felons.          That “all criminals”
    classification would withstand scrutiny under the panel’s
    standard because, when lumped together into one group, that
    group—as a whole—poses a heightened risk of violence just
    because some members of that group do. Whether
    committing murder or activating the turn signal too late,
    under the panel’s rationale, “all criminals” are no longer law-
    abiding, responsible citizens entitled to basic Second
    Amendment rights.
    Of course, this is absurd and circular. Step 1: Congress
    bans firearm possession for a broad class of people including
    some sub-class therein that poses a heightened risk of
    violence. Step 2: Our court says the broad class is outside
    “core” of the Second Amendment. Step 3: We say the
    1
    For the reasons Judge Bumatay ably explains, those metrics’
    relevance to Mai’s circumstances is dubious at best, and clearly
    insufficient to meet any form of heightened scrutiny with real teeth.
    2
    As of 2013, 34% of the 2008 Florida Gators football team had been
    arrested. Many were charged with violent crimes, including at least one
    who was convicted of a notorious murder. See Greg Bishop, Hernandez
    Among Many Who Found Trouble at Florida in the Meyer
    Years, N.Y. TIMES (July 6, 2013), https://www.nytimes.com/2013/07/0
    7/sports/ncaafootball/hernandez-among-many-arrested-at-florida-in-the
    -meyer-years.html. But the team was also graced by model citizen Tim
    Tebow, who, I’m sure we can all agree, could be trusted to own a firearm
    (and probably raise our children).
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                     37
    individual in the broad class is also outside the core, even
    though no evidence says he belongs to a violent sub-class,
    and all the evidence suggests otherwise. Step 4: We lower
    the level of scrutiny and relax the “fit” requirement so that a
    wildly overbroad prohibition can be deemed “reasonable.”
    This bootstrapping approach is an ingenious but insidious
    way to render the Second Amendment a paper tiger. See
    
    Chovan, 735 F.3d at 1148
    (Bea, J., concurring) (“If … the
    terms ‘law-abiding’ and ‘responsible’ are not tied to ‘felons’
    and ‘mentally ill,’ how are the lower courts to recognize the
    limits of the ‘law-abiding, responsible citizen’ standard?”).
    C. The “Core” of the Second Amendment Right has
    Nothing to Do with Classes of People.
    The panel references Chovan (which quotes from Heller)
    for the principle that “[t]he core of the Second Amendment
    is ‘the right of law-abiding, responsible citizens to use arms
    in defense of hearth and home.’”
    Id. at 1115
    (quoting
    
    Chovan, 735 F.3d at 1138
    ). According to the panel, this
    supported its decision to subject different classes of people
    to different tiers of scrutiny.
    Id. But this “core”
    standard
    finds no support in and misrepresents Heller.
    Although the panel concludes that certain privileged
    classes of people constitute the “core of the Second
    Amendment” (while, by extension, other classes like the one
    it lumped Mai into don’t), the Heller Court never applied this
    test to the right’s holders, but only to its substance. The
    word “core” appears only twice in Heller and both times
    describes the activity protected by the Second Amendment.
    District of Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 630 (2008)
    (“the core lawful purpose of self-defense”) (emphasis
    added);
    id. at 634
    (reasoning that handgun ownership is the
    “core protection” of the Second Amendment) (emphasis
    added).
    38                 MAI V. UNITED STATES
    Heller never used “core,” or its like, to discuss the
    Second Amendment’s application to individuals. But the
    panel nonetheless splices language—separated by fifty-four
    pages from Heller’s actual individual rights analysis—to
    support its claim that the formerly mentally ill lie outside the
    core of the Second Amendment. See 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1115
    ;
    compare 
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 581
    (“We move now from the
    holder of the right—‘the people’—to the substance of the
    right ….”) with
    id. at 635
    (“And whatever else it leaves to
    future evaluation, it surely elevates above all other interests
    the right of law-abiding, responsible citizens to use arms in
    defense of hearth and home.”).
    Heller actually cuts against the panel’s supposition. The
    Heller Court noted that the six other constitutional
    provisions that guarantee rights to “the people” refer
    unambiguously to the same class of individuals: namely, “all
    members of the political community.”
    Id. at 580
    (First,
    Second, Fourth, Ninth, Tenth, and Seventeenth
    Amendments). Heller then concluded that “the Second
    Amendment right is [likewise] exercised individually and
    belongs to all Americans.”
    Id. at 581
    (emphasis added).
    Does the panel’s contrary logic mean groups or individuals
    may also be placed outside the “core” of other constitutional
    rights?
    I’m certain this court would say no. The Supreme Court
    has repeatedly declined to do so. Instead, it takes an all-or-
    nothing approach to delineate the scope of individuals
    included in a constitutional protection and then applies an
    appropriate level of scrutiny to the regulatory burden on the
    substance of that right, if necessary. See, e.g., Boumediene
    v. Bush, 
    553 U.S. 723
    , 771 (2008) (holding that enemy
    combatants are entitled to the privilege of habeas corpus);
    Demore v. Kim, 
    538 U.S. 510
    , 531 (2003) (aliens not entitled
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                       39
    to bail hearings during removal proceedings under Due
    Process Clause); Jones v. Helms, 
    452 U.S. 412
    , 419–20
    (1981) (convicted felons have no fundamental right to
    travel); Richardson v. Ramirez, 
    418 U.S. 24
    , 54–56 (1974)
    (states can prevent convicted felons from voting). Just this
    year, the Supreme Court reaffirmed this approach. See
    Agency for Int’l Dev. v. All. for Open Soc’y. Intl., Inc., 
    140 S. Ct. 2082
    , 2086 (2020). There, the Court held that “foreign
    organizations operating abroad … possess no rights under
    the First Amendment.”
    Id. at 2087.
        The foreign
    organizations’ status didn’t dictate the Court’s selected tier
    of scrutiny—indeed, scrutiny appears nowhere in the
    decision.
    Id. at 2085–89.
    On the contrary, the Court’s
    decision was categorical: the plaintiffs don’t have First
    Amendment rights.
    Id. at 2087.
    Our court, too, has generally refused to apply a Mai-
    style, second-class citizen “core” analysis to rights
    guaranteed to “the People.” See, e.g., Rodriguez v. Swartz,
    
    899 F.3d 719
    , 730 (9th Cir. 2018) (extending the full
    protection of the Fourth Amendment to a Mexican citizen
    shot on Mexican soil by American officer on American soil),
    cert. granted, judgment vacated, 
    140 S. Ct. 1258
    (2020);
    Deorle v. Rutherford, 
    272 F.3d 1272
    , 1285 (9th Cir. 2001)
    (ruling that mentally disturbed individuals are protected by
    the Fourth Amendment right against excessive force); Maag
    v. Wessler, 
    960 F.2d 773
    , 775 (9th Cir. 1991) (per curiam)
    (holding that mentally ill individuals are fully protected by
    the Fourth Amendment), as amended on denial of reh’g
    (Apr. 1, 1992).
    In this case, the panel invents a class scrutiny standard in
    order to quietly lump Mai into a class (“the mentally ill”) to
    which it wouldn’t explicitly consign him at Chovan Step 1.
    It then leverages intermediate scrutiny to allow it to ignore
    40                 MAI V. UNITED STATES
    the group’s obvious overbreadth, thereby allowing anyone
    who has ever suffered from mental illness to be deprived of
    their Second Amendment rights for life, regardless of their
    present condition. Once mentally ill, always so. But see
    
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 634
    –35 (“Constitutional rights are
    enshrined with the scope they were understood to have when
    the people adopted them, whether or not … future judges
    think that scope too broad.”). Consistently applied, this
    class-based recharacterization about the “core” of the
    Second Amendment would bode ill for our foregoing
    scrutiny of laws burdening other fundamental rights. But we
    would never allow such subtle and slippery reasoning to so
    grievously burden the rights of “the People” protected
    elsewhere by the Constitution. This disparate treatment is
    unacceptable, even as applied to one of this circuit’s least-
    favored constitutional provisions.       By refusing to
    acknowledge that it is giving second-class treatment to the
    Second Amendment, the panel tragically relegates folks like
    Mai to permanent second-class status.
    II. LOWERING HEIGHTENED SCRUTINY
    Of course, any concerns about the panel’s circular class-
    based rationale bankrupting other constitutional rights is
    probably misplaced. This appears to be a “one-show-only”
    phenomenon specially reserved for the Second Amendment.
    Particularly in that context, we have watered down the
    “reasonable fit” prong of intermediate scrutiny to little more
    than rational basis review.
    The panel cited circuit precedent when articulating the
    reasonable fit standard: “‘the statute simply needs to
    promote a substantial government interest that would be
    achieved less effectively absent the regulation.’” 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1116
    (quoting United States v. Torres, 
    911 F.3d 1253
    , 1263 (2019)). Whatever kind of fit that requires, it
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                    41
    certainly isn’t reasonable. A grossly overbroad regulation
    with just a miniscule bit more effectiveness meets that
    standard. A law that banned firearm ownership for “young
    men” or “anyone who has committed any crime” would meet
    that standard. Such a standard is an incomplete and incorrect
    tool for measuring regulations that facially burden a
    fundamental right.
    The panel not only applies this inappropriate standard
    (see Section I, above), it applies it inappropriately. The
    “reasonable fit” language the panel relied upon was crafted
    for use in a specific, and very different, context: facially
    neutral regulations that incidentally burden freedom of
    speech in a way that is no greater than is essential. It’s
    worth exploring how this standard stumbled its way from the
    First to the Second Amendment and arrived here.
    A. The “Reasonable Fit” Standard Is Born and
    Promptly Diluted.
    The trail begins at the well-known United States v.
    O’Brien, where the Court dealt with a war protester who
    burned his draft card. 
    391 U.S. 367
    , 369 (1968). O’Brien
    argued the prohibition on burning draft cards violated his
    freedom of speech
    , id. at 370,
    while the government claimed
    it needed to ensure the ready accessibility of issued draft
    cards.
    Id. at 378.
    The Court reasoned:
    [W]e think it clear that a government
    regulation is sufficiently justified … if it
    furthers an important or substantial
    governmental interest; if the governmental
    interest is unrelated to the suppression of free
    expression; and if the incidental restriction
    on alleged First Amendment freedoms is no
    42                    MAI V. UNITED STATES
    greater than is essential to the furtherance of
    that interest.
    Id. at 377
    (emphasis added). The restriction in O’Brien was
    (a) incidental and (b) no greater than was essential to further
    an important or substantial government interest. Both
    qualifications are critical to the O’Brien test, but subsequent
    cases purporting to apply it neglected these qualifications.
    In United States v. Albertini, the defendant argued his
    First Amendment rights were violated because he was
    banned from entering a military base and thereby prevented
    from peacefully protesting during an open house on Armed
    Forces Day that was generally open to the public. 
    472 U.S. 675
    , 677–78 (1985) (the defendant had previously
    improperly entered military bases and destroyed government
    documents). The Court disagreed: “an incidental burden on
    speech is no greater than is essential, and therefore is
    permissible under O’Brien, so long as the neutral regulation
    promotes a substantial government interest that would be
    achieved less effectively absent the regulation.”
    Id. at 689
    (emphasis added). 3
    In Ward v. Rock Against Racism, musicians argued the
    denial of a permit to perform in a public space due to
    repeated past noise violations burdened their First
    Amendment rights. 
    491 U.S. 781
    , 785 (1989). Quoting
    from Albertini, the Court affirmed that a speech regulation
    must be:
    3
    Albertini’s recitation of the O’Brien standard is confusing and
    probably oxymoronic. But even Albertini’s word jumble is a poor fit in
    Mai’s case, where the regulation is neither incidental, nor neutral, nor
    “no greater than is essential.”
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                     43
    narrowly tailored to serve the government’s
    legitimate, content-neutral interests but that it
    need not be the least restrictive or least
    intrusive means of doing so. Rather, the
    requirement of narrow tailoring is satisfied so
    long as the ... regulation promotes a
    substantial government interest that would be
    achieved less effectively absent the
    regulation.
    Id. at 798–99
    (internal quotation marks omitted). Ward
    further clarified that the speech regulation may not “burden
    substantially more speech than is necessary to further the
    government’s legitimate interests.”
    Id. at 799
    (emphasis
    added) (“Government may not regulate expression in such a
    manner that a substantial portion of the burden on speech
    does not serve to advance its goals.”). Yet while Ward
    explicitly described the regulation as a content-neutral,
    incidental burden on speech
    , id. at 791–92,
    it curiously
    omitted the word “neutral” from its Albertini quotation.
    Compare
    id. at 799
    (“so long as the … regulation”) with
    
    Albertini, 472 U.S. at 689
    (“so long as the neutral
    regulation”). As a result, later cases citing Ward likewise
    fail to note that the test was crafted to analyze neutral,
    incidental burdens on speech.
    We cited the Ward language in Colacurcio v. City of
    Kent to uphold a content-neutral, narrowly tailored
    regulation of nude dancing performances. 
    163 F.3d 545
    , 553
    (9th Cir. 1998) (upholding ordinance requiring nude dancers
    to perform at least ten feet away from patrons for health and
    safety reasons). Colacurcio notably reaffirmed that a
    regulation evaluated under this test may not burden
    substantially more speech than necessary to further the
    government’s interests.
    Id. 44
                      MAI V. UNITED STATES
    B. The Ninth Circuit Leans into the Watered-Down
    Standard.
    But things went sideways when we jumped from the
    First to the Second Amendment. In Fyock v. Sunnyvale, 
    779 F.3d 991
    (9th Cir. 2015), for the first time, we applied a sub-
    Albertini standard (lacking explicit neutrality, incidental
    burden, and not substantially more burdensome than
    necessary language) to a regulation that squarely and
    severely burdened the fundamental right to keep and bear
    arms.
    Id. at 1000
    . 
    The Fyock plaintiffs challenged a
    regulation restricting possession of higher-capacity
    magazines under the Second Amendment.
    Id. at 994–95.
    The court upheld the restriction, holding that “[the
    government] was required to show only that [the regulation]
    promotes a ‘substantial government interest that would be
    achieved less effectively absent the regulation.’”
    Id. at 1000
    (quoting 
    Colacurcio, 163 F.3d at 553
    )) (emphasis added).
    And there it is. Quietly and fatally, we watered down a First
    Amendment “reasonable fit” requirement (of dubious value
    to the Second) to a Second Amendment test the government
    could drive a truck through.
    Our cases have subsequently cited and applied Fyock’s
    (un)reasonable fit requirement. 4 But this isn’t heightened
    scrutiny at all. Originally developed to analyze neutral
    regulations that incidentally burdened First Amendment
    4
    See, e.g., 
    Torres, 911 F.3d at 1263
    ; United States v. Singh, 
    924 F.3d 1030
    , 1057–58 (9th Cir. 2019), cert. granted, judgment vacated sub
    nom. Azano Matsura v. United States, 
    140 S. Ct. 991
    (2020), and cert.
    denied, 
    140 S. Ct. 1265
    (2020); Pena v. Lindley, 
    898 F.3d 969
    , 979 (9th
    Cir. 2018); Mahoney v. Sessions, 
    871 F.3d 873
    , 882–83 (9th Cir. 2017);
    Bauer v. Becerra, 
    858 F.3d 1216
    , 1226–27 (9th Cir. 2017); Silvester v.
    Harris, 
    843 F.3d 816
    , 829 (9th Cir. 2016).
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                    45
    rights in a way that was no greater than was essential, this
    test would have been a poor fit for direct restrictions on
    Second Amendment rights (i.e., 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(4)) even
    if we hadn’t plied it with diazepam.
    C. The Panel Doubles Down on “Relaxed” Heightened
    Scrutiny.
    Mai quotes Torres, which quoted Fyock, and that’s how
    we arrived at our present predicament. 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1116
    (quoting 
    Torres, 911 F.3d at 1263
    (upholding
    prohibition on illegal aliens possessing firearms)). In our
    Second Amendment cases, therefore, a reasonable fit under
    intermediate scrutiny demands only that the regulation
    “simply needs to ‘promote[] a substantial government
    interest that would be achieved less effectively absent the
    regulation.’” 
    Torres, 911 F.3d at 1263
    (quoting 
    Fyock, 779 F.3d at 1000
    ) (quotation marks omitted); 
    Mai, 952 F.3d at 1116
    . The result? The end of any regulatory tailoring and
    the advent of limitless regulatory overbreadth.
    There was a glimmer of good sense in Young v. Hawaii,
    where a panel of our court held that the Second Amendment
    “encompasses the right of a responsible law-abiding citizen
    to carry a firearm openly for self-defense outside of the
    home.” 
    896 F.3d 1044
    , 1048 (9th Cir. 2018), reh’g en banc
    granted, 
    915 F.3d 681
    (9th Cir. 2019). That panel astutely
    recognized and avoided the same problem we see in Mai—
    that the reasonable fit standard was significantly weaker than
    it ought to be:
    According to the dissent, the only question a
    court must answer under intermediate
    scrutiny is whether the government action
    promotes a substantial government interest
    that would be achieved less effectively absent
    46                 MAI V. UNITED STATES
    the regulation. That is incomplete, because a
    court must also determine whether the
    government action burdens substantially
    more protected conduct than is necessary to
    further that interest.         Thus, while
    intermediate scrutiny surely does not require
    the government to pursue the least restrictive
    means of achieving an important interest, the
    substantial overbreadth or impreciseness of a
    government action must be considered.
    Id. 1072–73
    (cleaned up; internal citations omitted) (quoting
    Turner Broad. Sys., Inc. v. F.C.C., 
    520 U.S. 180
    , 213–14,
    (1997)). Refreshing indeed—an insistence that overbreadth
    be a salient consideration in the reasonable fit analysis! But
    our en banc court reasserted our errant orthodoxy and
    vacated Young. Young v. Hawaii, 
    915 F.3d 681
    , 682 (9th
    Cir. 2019).
    In Mai’s as-applied challenge, § 922(g)(4) clearly
    burdens substantially more protected conduct than is
    necessary to advance Congress’s interests (disarming “the
    mentally ill”). The statute’s permanent, total burden on
    Mai’s Second Amendment right is far more restrictive than
    necessary to further the government’s interest in preventing
    gun violence. Yet the panel and the precedent it cites simply
    omit that additional prong of the test.
    Instead, the panel applied our court’s adulterated and
    incomplete version of the “reasonable fit” standard—a
    standard that in its current form (with our downward
    modifications) is unfit to size up even neutral regulations
    that incidentally burden free speech rights. But basic logic
    (constitutional and otherwise) tells us that we should demand
    a closer regulatory fit for a law that directly burdens a
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                          47
    fundamental right than that which imposes neutral,
    incidental burdens on a fundamental right. If the panel had
    undertaken real heightened scrutiny, or even just faithfully
    applied the test as articulated in O’Brien, Albertini, Ward, or
    Colacurcio, § 922(g)(4) could not have withstood Mai’s
    challenge.
    It’s time to face reality: the requirement we applied in
    Fyock, Torres, and Mai is no requirement at all.
    Government burdens on the Second Amendment may not
    always need to fit into skinny jeans, but they should never
    come dressed in clown pants. The current “reasonable fit”
    standard makes it embarrassingly easy for the government to
    sustain its regulations. Heightened scrutiny should have
    some, well, height. Our en banc court spurned a golden
    opportunity to reaffirm that intermediate scrutiny is, indeed,
    a form of heightened scrutiny.
    D. This Circuit Treats the Second Amendment Like a
    Second-Class Constitutional Right. 5
    To the rational observer, it is apparent that our court just
    doesn’t like the Second Amendment very much. We always
    uphold restrictions on the Second Amendment right to keep
    and bear arms. 6 Show me a burden—any burden—on
    5
    See Peruta v. Cty. of San Diego, 
    824 F.3d 919
    , 945 (9th Cir. 2016)
    (en banc) (Callahan, J., dissenting) (“The Second Amendment is not a
    ‘second-class’ constitutional guarantee.” (citing McDonald v. City of
    Chicago, 
    561 U.S. 742
    , 780 (2010))).
    6
    See, e.g., 
    Torres, 911 F.3d at 1264
    –65 (upholding ban on illegal
    aliens possessing firearms); 
    Pena, 898 F.3d at 973
    (upholding ban on
    purchasing particular firearms); 
    Mahoney, 871 F.3d at 883
    (upholding
    limitations on police officers using department-issued firearms); 
    Bauer, 858 F.3d at 1227
    (upholding use of firearm sales fees to fund
    48                    MAI V. UNITED STATES
    Second Amendment rights, and this court will find a way to
    uphold it. Even when our panels have struck down laws that
    violate the Second Amendment, our court rushes in en banc
    to reverse course. See, e.g., Teixeira v. County of Alameda,
    
    873 F.3d 670
    , 690 (9th Cir. 2017) (en banc) (reversing
    panel’s invalidation of a regulation prohibiting the right to
    purchase and sell firearms); Peruta v. County of San Diego,
    
    824 F.3d 919
    , 942 (9th Cir. 2016) (en banc) (reversing
    panel’s invalidation of city law requiring showing of special
    self-defense need to obtain conceal carry permit where open
    carry was also prohibited); Young v. Hawaii, 
    896 F.3d 1044
    ,
    1074 (9th Cir. 2018) (discussed above), reh’g en banc
    granted, 
    915 F.3d 681
    (9th Cir. 2019). 7 Other rights don’t
    enforcement efforts against illegal firearm purchasers); 
    Silvester, 843 F.3d at 829
    (upholding 10-day waiting period for purchasers who have
    already cleared a background check in less than 10 days); 
    Fyock, 779 F.3d at 1001
    (upholding city’s ban on high-capacity magazines); Jackson
    v. City & County of San Francisco, 
    746 F.3d 953
    , 970 (9th Cir. 2014)
    (upholding city’s firearm and ammunition regulations); 
    Chovan, 735 F.3d at 1142
    (upholding ban on domestic violence misdemeanants
    owning firearms despite not committing domestic violence for 15 years);
    United States v. Vongxay, 
    594 F.3d 1111
    , 1118 (9th Cir. 2010)
    (upholding ban on felons possessing firearms).
    7
    Very recently, a panel of our court struck down another California
    regulation as violating the Second Amendment. See Duncan v. Becerra,
    No. 19-55376, 
    2020 WL 4730668
    , at *2 (9th Cir. Aug. 14, 2020). Given
    our court’s history recounted above, court observers are of course
    already forecasting an inevitable en banc reversal. See, e.g., Don
    Thompson, 9th Circuit ends California ban on high-capacity magazines,
    WASH. POST (Aug. 14, 2020) (“We expect an en banc panel will rehear
    the case and correct this … out-of-step decision.”) (source omitted),
    https://www.washingtonpost.com/national/9th-circuit-ends-california-
    ban-on-high-capacity-magazines/2020/08/14/f77751cc-de52-11ea-b4f1-
    25b762cdbbf4_story.html.
    MAI V. UNITED STATES                           49
    receive such harsh treatment. 8 There exists on our court a
    clear bias—a real prejudice—against the Second
    Amendment and those appealing to it. That’s wrong. Equal
    justice should mean equal justice.
    III. CONCLUSION
    The panel’s bootstrapping, class-based approach to
    defining those at the “core” of the Second Amendment is
    unjust and antithetical to controlling case law. Here, our
    court’s unacknowledged antipathy toward the Second
    Amendment forced the panel into the unenviable position of
    condoning the perverse result of “once mentally ill, always
    so,” notwithstanding its authentic disapproval of that
    obviously immoral canard.
    Our toothless “heightened” scrutiny of Second
    Amendment restrictions is broken, and not accidentally so.
    8
    See e.g., Nat’l Inst. of Family & Life Advocs. v. Harris, 
    839 F.3d 823
    , 845 (9th Cir. 2016) (holding law requiring anti-abortion pregnancy
    centers to provide notice of publicly funded family-planning services,
    including abortions, did not violate First Amendment), rev’d and
    remanded sub nom. Nat’l Inst. of Family & Life Advocs. v. Becerra, 
    138 S. Ct. 2361
    (2018); Italian Colors Rest. v. Becerra, 
    878 F.3d 1165
    , 1179
    (9th Cir. 2018) (holding California statute prohibiting retailers from
    imposing surcharge on payments by credit card violated First
    Amendment); Latta v. Otter, 
    771 F.3d 456
    , 476 (9th Cir. 2014) (holding
    states’ anti-gay marriage laws violated Equal Protection Clause and due
    process); deLaurier v. San Diego Unified Sch. Dist., 
    588 F.2d 674
    , 684
    (9th Cir. 1978) (holding school district’s mandatory maternity leave
    policy did not violate Equal Protection Clause); Valley Broad. Co. v.
    United States, 
    107 F.3d 1328
    , 1336 (9th Cir. 1997) (holding federal ban
    prohibiting broadcast advertisements of casino gambling violated First
    Amendment); Monterey Mech. Co. v. Wilson, 
    125 F.3d 702
    , 715 (9th
    Cir. 1997) (holding “state program setting goals for ethnic and sex
    characteristics of construction subcontractors” violated Equal Protection
    Clause).
    50                  MAI V. UNITED STATES
    But Second Amendment rights are fundamental, and
    litigants attempting to vindicate theirs deserve better than
    what we’re currently offering, for “[t]he very enumeration
    of the right takes out of the hands of government—even the
    Third Branch of Government—the power to decide on a
    case-by-case basis whether the right is really worth insisting
    upon.” 
    Heller, 554 U.S. at 634
    .
    I respectfully dissent.