Sontos Diaz-Reynoso v. William Barr ( 2020 )


Menu:
  •                      FOR PUBLICATION
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT
    SONTOS MAUDILIA DIAZ-REYNOSO,                      No. 18-72833
    AKA Sontos Maurilla Diaz-
    Reynoso,                                            Agency No.
    Petitioner,                 A205-256-857
    v.
    OPINION
    WILLIAM P. BARR, Attorney
    General,
    Respondent.
    On Petition for Review of an Order of the
    Board of Immigration Appeals
    Submitted March 24, 2020*
    San Francisco, California
    Filed August 7, 2020
    Before: Ronald M. Gould, Morgan Christen,
    and Daniel A. Bress, Circuit Judges.
    Opinion by Judge Christen;
    Partial Concurrence and Partial Dissent by Judge Bress
    *
    The panel unanimously concludes this case is suitable for decision
    without oral argument. See Fed. R. App. P. 34(a)(2).
    2                     DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    SUMMARY**
    Immigration
    Granting Sontos Diaz-Reynoso’s petition for review of
    the Board of Immigration Appeals’ decision affirming the
    denial of her application for withholding of removal and
    protection under the Convention Against Torture, and
    remanding, the panel held that the Board misapplied Matter
    of A-B-, 
    27 I. & N. Dec. 316
     (A.G. 2018), as well as Board
    and circuit precedent, in concluding that Diaz-Reynoso’s
    proposed social group comprised of “indigenous women in
    Guatemala who are unable to leave their relationship” was
    not cognizable, and that she failed to establish that the
    government of Guatemala would acquiesce in any possible
    torture.
    The panel rejected Diaz-Reynoso’s contention that Matter
    of A-B- was arbitrary and capricious and therefore not entitled
    to Chevron deference. The panel concluded that, despite the
    general and descriptive observations set forth in the opinion,
    Matter of A-B- did not announce a new categorical exception
    to withholding of removal for victims of domestic violence or
    other private criminal activity, but rather it reaffirmed the
    Board’s existing framework for analyzing the cognizability
    of particular social groups, requiring that such determinations
    be individualized and conducted on a case-by-case basis.
    The panel observed that the Board rejected Diaz-
    Reynoso’s proposed social group, with almost no analysis,
    **
    This summary constitutes no part of the opinion of the court. It has
    been prepared by court staff for the convenience of the reader.
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                       3
    because it “suffered from the same circularity problem
    articulated by the Attorney General in Matter of A-B-.” The
    panel explained that in doing so, the Board appeared to
    misapprehend the scope of Matter of A-B- as forbidding any
    mention of feared harm within the delineation of a proposed
    social group. The panel concluded that this was error,
    explaining that Matter of A-B- did not announce a new rule
    concerning circularity, but instead merely reiterated the well-
    established principle that a particular social group must exist
    independently of the harm asserted. The panel recognized
    that a proposed social group may be deemed impermissibly
    circular if, after conducting the proper case-by-case analysis,
    the Board determines that the group is defined exclusively by
    the fact that its members have been subjected to harm. The
    panel explained, however, that a proposed social group is not
    impermissibly circular merely because the proposed group
    mentions harm.
    The panel concluded that the Board also erred in
    assuming that domestic violence was the only reason Diaz-
    Reynoso was unable to leave her relationship, and in failing
    to conduct the rigorous case-by-case analysis required by
    Matter of A-B-. The panel therefore remanded Diaz-
    Reynoso’s withholding of removal claim for the Board to
    undertake the required analysis applying the correct
    framework.
    Because the Board failed to discuss evidence that Diaz-
    Reynoso reported her husband’s abuse to authority figures in
    her village community, and the government conceded remand
    was warranted, the panel also remanded Diaz-Reynoso’s
    CAT claim for further consideration.
    4                 DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    Concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in part,
    Judge Bress agreed with remand of the CAT claim in light of
    the government’s concession, but disagreed with the
    majority’s conclusion that the Board misread Matter of A-B-
    in rejecting Diaz-Reynoso’s proposed social group. In Judge
    Bress’s view, Matter of A-B- held that a proposed group that
    incorporates harm within its definition is not a group that
    exists independently of the harm asserted in an application for
    asylum or statutory withholding of removal. Judge Bress
    wrote that substantial evidence supported the Board’s
    assessment that Diaz-Reynoso’s social group was defined
    exclusively by the harm suffered, and that the Board correctly
    applied Matter of A-B-, and the circularity rule, in rejecting
    Diaz-Reynoso’s proposed social group.
    COUNSEL
    Gary A. Watt, Stephen Tollafield, and Tiffany J. Gates,
    Supervising Counsel; Shandyn H. Pierce and Hilda Kajbaf,
    Certified Law Students; Hastings Appellate Project, San
    Francisco, California; for Petitioner.
    Joseph H. Hunt, Assistant Attorney General; John S. Hogan
    and Linda S. Wernery, Assistant Directors; Susan Bennett
    Green, Senior Litigation Counsel; Ashley Martin, Trial
    Attorney; Office of Immigration Litigation, Civil Division,
    United States Department of Justice, Washington, D.C.; for
    Respondent.
    Blaine Bookey, Karen Musalo, Neela Chakravartula, and
    Anne Peterson, Center for Gender & Refugee Studies, U.S.
    Hastings College of Law, San Francisco, California, for
    Amicus Curiae Center for Gender & Refugee Studies.
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                   5
    Richard W. Mark, Amer S. Ahmed, Grace E. Hart, and
    Cassarah M. Chu, Gibson Dunn & Crutcher LLP, New York
    New York, for Amici Curiae Thirty-Nine Former
    Immigration Judges and Members of the Board of
    Immigration Appeals.
    Sabrineh Ardalan, Nancy Kelly, John Willshire Carrera,
    Deborah Anker, and Zachary A. Albun, Attorneys; Rosa
    Baum, Caya Simonsen, and Ana Sewell, Supervised Law
    Students; Harvard Immigration and Refugee Clinical
    Program, Cambridge, Massachusetts; for Amicus Curiae
    Harvard Immigration and Refugee Clinical Program.
    Ana C. Reyes and Alexander J. Kasner, Williams & Connolly
    LLP, Washington, D.C.; Alice Farmer, United Nations High
    Commissioner for Refugees, Washington, D.C.; for Amicus
    Curiae United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees.
    6                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    OPINION
    CHRISTEN, Circuit Judge:
    Sontos Maudilia Diaz-Reynoso, a native and citizen of
    Guatemala, petitions for review of the Board of Immigration
    Appeals’ (BIA) order dismissing her appeal of an
    Immigration Judge’s (IJ) order denying her application for
    withholding of removal and relief under the Convention
    Against Torture (CAT). Diaz-Reynoso seeks withholding of
    removal based on her fear that she would be persecuted in
    Guatemala on account of her membership in the particular
    social group of “indigenous women in Guatemala who are
    unable to leave their relationship.” Diaz-Reynoso argues she
    is entitled to relief under CAT because, if returned to
    Guatemala, the Guatemalan government would acquiesce in
    torture she would suffer at the hands of her husband.
    On her withholding claim, the BIA concluded that Diaz-
    Reynoso’s proposed particular social group was not
    cognizable, relying on the Attorney General’s decision in
    Matter of A-B-, 
    27 I. & N. Dec. 316
     (A.G. 2018). With
    respect to Diaz-Reynoso’s CAT claim, the BIA concluded
    that Diaz-Reynoso failed to establish that the government of
    Guatemala would acquiesce in any torture she might suffer.
    Because the BIA’s decision on both bases for relief departs
    from its own precedent and is contrary to this court’s case
    law, we grant the petition for review and remand for further
    proceedings.
    I
    Diaz-Reynoso was born in 1989 in the small, rural town
    of Yamoj, in the Guatemalan highlands. She is a member of
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                              7
    the indigenous group known as Mam. In 2008, Diaz-Reynoso
    moved in with a man named Arnoldo Vasquez-Juarez, who
    is also Mam. Although they did not legally marry, Diaz-
    Reynoso and Vasquez-Juarez had a common-law marriage
    and Diaz-Reynoso refers to Vasquez-Juarez as her husband.
    Vasquez-Juarez subjected Diaz-Reynoso to physical and
    sexual abuse. Among other things, he forced Diaz-Reynoso
    to work in the coffee fields without pay, and to have sex with
    him. When Diaz-Reynoso did not comply with his demands,
    Vasquez-Juarez attacked her, hitting her on her head and all
    over her body, sometimes with a belt. Diaz-Reynoso testified
    that she was attacked weekly, and that the resulting bruises
    sometimes lasted for eight to ten days.
    In 2012, after four years of living with Vasquez-Juarez,
    Diaz-Reynoso fled and entered the United States without
    documentation. She was apprehended, and after roughly a
    month in detention, returned to Guatemala. Diaz-Reynoso
    moved back in with her family in Yamoj.
    As soon as Diaz-Reynoso returned, Vasquez-Juarez came
    to find her. Vasquez-Juarez told Diaz-Reynoso that if she did
    not return to live with him, he would kill her, kill her
    daughter,1 or harm her mother. Diaz-Reynoso returned to live
    with Vasquez-Juarez for about a year. The abuse got worse
    during that time. Diaz-Reynoso then escaped and went to
    live with a friend in another town for roughly a year. She was
    in hiding during this period and did not leave her friend’s
    house. After that, Diaz-Reynoso returned to her family home
    1
    Diaz-Reynoso had a daughter with a previous partner named Angel
    Tomas Vasquez. Although Vasquez also subjected Diaz-Reynoso to
    physical and sexual abuse, she has not heard from him since she left him.
    8                 DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    in the hope that Vasquez-Juarez had forgotten about her, but
    Vasquez-Juarez found Diaz-Reynoso and ordered her to come
    back with him. At the urging of her mother, Diaz-Reynoso
    again fled to the United States.
    Diaz-Reynoso was apprehended near Topawa, Arizona on
    October 29, 2014, and her prior removal order was reinstated
    pursuant to 
    8 U.S.C. § 1231
    (a)(5). She pled guilty to illegal
    entry in violation of 
    8 U.S.C. § 1325
    (a)(1), and was sentenced
    to thirty days imprisonment.
    While Diaz-Reynoso was in detention, an asylum officer
    interviewed her and she expressed fear of returning to
    Guatemala. The asylum officer concluded that she had
    established a credible fear of persecution and referred her to
    removal proceedings before an immigration judge. Diaz-
    Reynoso filed an application for withholding of removal and
    protection under CAT. In her counseled brief, Diaz-Reynoso
    defined her particular social group as “Guatemalan
    indigenous women who are unable to leave their
    relationship,” and advanced evidence of a number of factors
    that prevented her from leaving.
    The IJ issued a written decision denying Diaz-Reynoso’s
    application for withholding of removal and relief under CAT.
    The IJ found Diaz-Reynoso credible, but concluded that
    because much of her account was inconsistent with her own
    testimony and other record evidence, “significant portions of
    her testimony [were] entitled to little weight.” On the
    withholding claim, the IJ did not rule on whether Diaz-
    Reynoso established the existence of a cognizable particular
    social group, but concluded that she did not establish
    membership in her proffered particular social group, did not
    show that she would more likely than not suffer persecution,
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                              9
    and did not demonstrate that the Guatemalan government
    would be unable or unwilling to protect her. On her CAT
    claim, the IJ concluded that Diaz-Reynoso failed to establish
    she would more likely than not be tortured if removed to
    Guatemala, and that she did not demonstrate that her past
    abuse or feared future abuse would occur in the context of
    government control, authority, or acquiescence. The IJ
    further concluded that Diaz-Reynoso failed to seek protection
    from law enforcement, and found she could safely and
    reasonably avoid abusive conduct by relocating within
    Guatemala. Diaz-Reynoso timely appealed to the BIA.
    The BIA dismissed Diaz-Reynoso’s appeal.              On
    withholding, the BIA did not rely on the IJ’s rationale.
    Instead, the BIA concluded that Diaz-Reynoso’s proposed
    particular social group was not cognizable in light of Matter
    of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 316.2 On CAT, the BIA concluded
    that Diaz-Reynoso had failed to establish that any
    Guatemalan public official would more likely than not
    consent to or acquiesce in any torture she may suffer.
    II
    We have jurisdiction to review final orders of removal
    pursuant to 
    8 U.S.C. § 1252
    (a)(5). “Our review is limited to
    those grounds explicitly relied upon by the [BIA].” Budiono
    v. Lynch, 
    837 F.3d 1042
    , 1046 (9th Cir. 2016). Where the
    BIA writes its own decision, as it did here, we review the
    BIA’s decision, except to the extent it expressly adopts the
    IJ’s decision. Rodriguez v. Holder, 
    683 F.3d 1164
    , 1169 (9th
    Cir. 2012).
    2
    The Attorney General decided Matter of A-B- after the IJ issued its
    decision, but before the BIA ruled on Diaz-Reynoso’s appeal.
    10               DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    We review de novo the BIA’s determinations on
    questions of law. Pirir-Boc v. Holder, 
    750 F.3d 1077
    , 1081
    (9th Cir. 2014). We review for substantial evidence the
    BIA’s factual findings, which “should be upheld ‘unless the
    evidence compels a contrary result.’” Budiono, 837 F.3d
    at 1046 (quoting Hernandez-Mancilla v. Holder, 
    633 F.3d 1182
    , 1184 (9th Cir. 2011)). Whether Diaz-Reynoso’s
    particular social group is cognizable is a question of law.
    Conde Quevedo v. Barr, 
    947 F.3d 1238
    , 1242 (9th Cir. 2020);
    see also Barbosa v. Barr, 
    926 F.3d 1053
    , 1059 (9th Cir.
    2019).
    III
    To qualify for withholding of removal, a petitioner must
    demonstrate that, if removed to her home country, her life
    would be threatened on account of any one of five
    enumerated grounds: race, religion, nationality, membership
    in a particular social group, or political opinion. Mendoza-
    Alvarez v. Holder, 
    714 F.3d 1161
    , 1163–64 (9th Cir. 2013)
    (per curiam). At issue here is “membership in a particular
    social group”—specifically, the cognizability of Diaz-
    Reynoso’s proffered social group. 
    8 U.S.C. § 1231
    (b)(3)(A);
    see also Reyes v. Lynch, 
    842 F.3d 1125
    , 1132 n.3 (9th Cir.
    2016) (noting that establishing the “existence” of a
    cognizable social group is a separate requirement from
    establishing “membership” in the group).
    The Attorney General’s and the BIA’s constructions of
    ambiguous statutory terms are entitled to deference under
    Chevron, U.S.A., Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Council,
    Inc., 
    467 U.S. 837
     (1984). Pirir-Boc, 750 F.3d at 1081; Jiang
    v. Holder, 
    611 F.3d 1086
    , 1091–92 (9th Cir. 2010). Because
    we have already concluded that the phrase “particular social
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                        11
    group” is ambiguous, Henriquez-Rivas v. Holder, 
    707 F.3d 1081
    , 1083 (9th Cir. 2013) (en banc), we must adhere to an
    agency interpretation of that term, so long as it is reasonable,
    id. at 1087. An interpretation fails this step if it is “arbitrary
    or capricious in substance.” Judulang v. Holder, 
    565 U.S. 42
    ,
    52 n.7 (2011) (quoting Mayo Found. for Med. Educ. &
    Research v. United States, 
    562 U.S. 44
    , 53 (2011)); see also
    Gomez-Sanchez v. Sessions, 
    892 F.3d 985
    , 993 (9th Cir.
    2018).
    A
    The BIA first construed the phrase “particular social
    group” in Matter of Acosta, 
    19 I. & N. Dec. 211
     (BIA 1985),
    overruled in part on other grounds as stated in Matter of
    Mogharrabi, 
    19 I. & N. Dec. 439
    , 441 (BIA 1987). There,
    the BIA explained that members of a particular social group
    must share a “common, immutable characteristic.” Id. at 233.
    An immutable characteristic is one that is either: (1) “beyond
    the power of an individual to change,” or (2) “so fundamental
    to [individual] identity or conscience that it ought not be
    required to be changed.” Id. at 233–34.
    Over time, “Acosta’s immutable characteristic test ‘led to
    confusion and a lack of consistency as adjudicators struggled
    with various possible social groups, some of which appeared
    to be created exclusively for asylum purposes.’” Reyes,
    842 F.3d at 1134 (quoting Matter of M-E-V-G-, 
    26 I. & N. Dec. 227
    , 231 (BIA 2014)). Thus, beginning with Matter of
    C-A-, 
    23 I. & N. Dec. 951
    , 957–59 (BIA 2006), the BIA
    refined the Acosta standard by stating that an applicant must
    also demonstrate that his or her proposed particular social
    group has “social visibility” and “particularity.” See
    12                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    Henriquez-Rivas, 707 F.3d at 1084; see also Matter of A-M-
    E- & J-G-U-, 
    24 I. & N. Dec. 69
    , 74–76 (BIA 2007).
    The BIA later reaffirmed that these concepts—
    particularity and social visibility—are distinct requirements
    for establishing membership in a cognizable social group.
    Matter of S-E-G-, 
    24 I. & N. Dec. 579
    , 582 (BIA 2008);
    Matter of E-A-G-, 
    24 I. & N. Dec. 591
    , 594 (BIA 2008). In
    2014, the BIA continued to refine these concepts with its
    decisions in Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 227, and
    Matter of W-G-R-, 
    26 I. & N. Dec. 208
     (BIA 2014). See
    Reyes, 842 F.3d at 1135–37. The BIA explained that the
    particularity inquiry recognizes that the social group must be
    defined by characteristics that provide a clear benchmark for
    determining who falls within the group, such that the group
    possesses “discrete and . . . definable boundaries.” Matter of
    M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 239. Social visibility, later
    renamed “social distinction,” considers whether those with a
    common immutable characteristic are “set apart, or distinct,
    from other persons within the society in some significant
    way.” Id. at 238. As a result of this precedent, it is now well-
    established that an applicant seeking relief based on
    membership in a particular social group must establish that
    the group is: “(1) composed of members who share a
    common immutable characteristic, (2) defined with
    particularity, and (3) socially distinct within the society in
    question.” Id. at 237.
    In 2014, the BIA also decided Matter of A-R-C-G-, 
    26 I. & N. Dec. 388
     (BIA 2014). There, the BIA recognized as
    cognizable the proposed social group of “married women in
    Guatemala who are unable to leave their relationship.” 
    Id. at 389
    . Critically, in Matter of A-R-C-G-, the Government
    conceded the petitioner had “established that she suffered past
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                      13
    harm rising to the level of persecution and that the
    persecution was on account of” her particular social group.
    
    Id. at 390
    . Although the BIA cited as controlling its recent
    decisions in Matter of M-E-V-G- and Matter of W-G-R-, it
    relied in large part on the Government’s concession that the
    group was cognizable. 
    Id.
     at 392–95.
    B
    This appeal concerns the Attorney General’s recent
    interpretation of “particular social group” in Matter of A-B-,
    27 I. & N. Dec. at 317. There, the Attorney General reviewed
    a BIA decision that concluded the applicant’s social
    group—“El Salvadoran women who are unable to leave their
    domestic relationships where they have children in
    common”—was cognizable. Id. at 317, 321; see also
    
    8 C.F.R. § 1003.1
    (h)(1). In its review of A-B-’s appeal, the
    BIA had relied heavily on its earlier precedential decision in
    Matter of A-R-C-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 388, so it was
    necessary for the Attorney General to review that decision as
    well. Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 321. Ultimately, the
    Attorney General overruled Matter of A-R-C-G-, concluding
    that it impermissibly deviated from the BIA’s prior precedent.
    Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 317, 333, 340; see also
    
    8 C.F.R. § 1003.1
    (d)(7), (g)(1).
    The Attorney General found Matter of A-R-C-G-’s
    reasoning to be lacking because the BIA failed to engage in
    the rigorous analysis required to properly analyze a particular
    social group. Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 331. The
    Attorney General concluded that Matter of A-R-C-G-
    “recognized a new particular social group without correctly
    applying the[] standards” for asylum, id. at 317, and “[t]o the
    extent that the Board examined the legal questions,” rather
    14                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    than relying on the Government’s concessions, “its analysis
    lacked rigor and broke with the Board’s own precedents,” id.
    at 333.
    The Attorney General identified several specific errors in
    the BIA’s analysis of the particular social group at issue in
    Matter of A-R-C-G-. First, “[t]o be cognizable, a particular
    social group must ‘exist independently’ of the harm asserted.”
    Id. at 334 (quoting Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec.
    at 236 n.11). In the Attorney General’s view, the BIA had
    “avoided considering whether [the petitioner] could establish
    the existence of a cognizable particular social group without
    defining the group by the fact of persecution.” Id. In
    particular, the Attorney General opined that the BIA never
    considered that the group “was effectively defined to consist
    of women in Guatemala who are victims of domestic abuse
    because the inability ‘to leave’ was created by harm or
    threatened harm.” Id. at 335.
    Second, the Attorney General reiterated the precedent
    establishing that not every immutable characteristic is
    sufficiently precise to define a particular social group. Id.
    The Attorney General questioned the viability of “[s]ocial
    groups defined by their vulnerability to private criminal
    activity” because those groups “likely lack” particularity
    “given that broad swaths of society may be susceptible to
    victimization.” Id. The Attorney General observed that the
    BIA did not engage with this analysis in Matter of A-R-C-G-;
    it merely concluded that the terms used to describe the group
    had “commonly accepted definitions within Guatemalan
    society.” Id.
    Third, the BIA “provided no explanation for why it
    believed that [the] evidence established that Guatemalan
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                      15
    society” perceived the proposed social group to be distinct,
    and erred by accepting the Government’s concession as to
    distinction. Id. at 336. The Attorney General found the
    record lacking on this point and concluded there was
    significant room for doubt that Guatemalan society viewed
    the women comprising the social group “as members of a
    distinct group in society, rather than each as a victim of a
    particular abuser in highly individualized circumstances.” Id.
    After overruling Matter of A-R-C-G-, the Attorney
    General described the BIA’s reasoning in Matter of A-B- as
    similarly cursory because it consisted of general citations to
    Matter of A-R-C-G- and country condition reports. Id. at 340.
    The Attorney General vacated the BIA’s decision in Matter
    of A-B- and remanded the case to the BIA for further analysis
    “under the standards articulated in [the Matter of A-B-]
    opinion and in past Board decisions.” Id. at 340–41, 346.
    Separate from its holding, Matter of A-B- included several
    broad observations about asylum claims brought by “victims
    of private criminal activity.” Id. at 317. For example, the
    Attorney General acknowledged that “there may be
    exceptional circumstances when victims of private criminal
    activity could meet” the requirements for asylum, id., but also
    suggested that, “[g]enerally, claims by aliens pertaining to
    domestic violence or gang violence perpetrated by non-
    governmental actors will not qualify for asylum,” id. at 320.
    In the end, Matter of A-B- reaffirmed existing standards
    for establishing membership in a particular social group, and
    overruled Matter of A-R-C-G- because of its failure to comply
    with the BIA’s precedents regarding those requirements.
    Indeed, the Attorney General has since described Matter of
    A-B- in precisely this manner. Matter of L-E-A-, 27 I. & N.
    16                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    Dec. 581, 588–89 (A.G. 2019) (recognizing that in Matter of
    A-B-, the Attorney General “reaffirmed” and “reiterated” the
    established framework for analyzing the cognizability of
    particular social groups, and “emphasized the importance of
    a rigorous application of that legal standard”).
    IV
    On Diaz-Reynoso’s withholding claim, the BIA ruled that
    her proposed social group was not cognizable in light of the
    Attorney General’s decision in Matter of A-B-. On appeal,
    Diaz-Reynoso contends that the Attorney General’s decision
    in Matter of A-B- is not entitled to Chevron deference because
    it is arbitrary and capricious. Diaz-Reynoso raises two
    principal arguments: (1) Matter of A-B- runs counter to the
    Immigration and Nationality Act’s (INA) scheme for bars to
    withholding; and (2) in Matter of A-B-, the Attorney General
    eliminated the requirement that particular social groups be
    evaluated on a case-by-case basis. Neither argument is
    persuasive.
    A
    Diaz-Reynoso first argues that Matter of A-B- is arbitrary
    and capricious because it announced a new rule that amounts
    to a categorical ban on withholding of removal for victims of
    domestic violence, and therefore runs counter to the INA’s
    scheme, which provides for only narrow and expressly
    enumerated exceptions to withholding. Diaz-Reynoso’s
    argument is that the Attorney General essentially added a new
    exception to withholding of removal claims.
    Diaz-Reynoso is correct that withholding of removal is
    generally mandatory “if an alien ‘establish[es] that it is more
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                       17
    likely than not that [she] would be subject to persecution on
    one of the specified grounds.’” INS v. Aguirre-Aguirre,
    
    526 U.S. 415
    , 419 (1999) (first alteration in original) (quoting
    INS v. Stevic, 
    467 U.S. 407
    , 429–30 (1984)); see also
    
    8 U.S.C. § 1231
    (b)(3)(A). And the statute has specific
    exceptions embodied in 
    8 U.S.C. § 1231
    (b)(3)(B). See
    Aguirre-Aguirre, 
    526 U.S. at 419
    . For example, an applicant
    is barred from obtaining withholding relief when he or she
    has been convicted of a particularly serious crime, 
    8 U.S.C. § 1231
    (b)(3)(B)(ii), or when there are serious reasons to
    believe that he or she committed a serious nonpolitical crime
    before arriving in the United States, 
    id.
     § 1231(b)(3)(B)(iii).
    See also Gomez-Sanchez, 892 F.3d at 990; Go v. Holder,
    
    640 F.3d 1047
    , 1052 (9th Cir. 2011).
    We recognize that the Attorney General began the opinion
    in Matter of A-B- by offering some general impressions about
    asylum and withholding claims based on domestic violence
    and other private criminal activity. See 27 I. & N. Dec.
    at 320. For example, the Attorney General observed that
    “[g]enerally, claims by aliens pertaining to domestic violence
    . . . perpetrated by non-governmental actors will not qualify
    for asylum,” and “in practice such claims are unlikely to
    satisfy the statutory grounds for proving group persecution
    that the government is unable or unwilling to address.” Id.
    (emphasis added). But the holding of Matter of A-B- plainly
    does not endorse any sort of categorical exception based on
    these remarks and observations. In fact, the Attorney General
    explicitly stated: “I do not decide that violence inflicted by
    non-governmental actors may never serve as the basis for an
    asylum or withholding application based on membership in
    a particular social group.” Id. Far from endorsing a
    categorical bar, the Attorney General emphasized that the
    18                    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    BIA must conduct the “rigorous analysis” set forth in the
    BIA’s precedents. Id. at 340.3
    Despite the general and descriptive observations set forth
    in the opinion, the Attorney General’s prescriptive instruction
    is clear: the BIA must conduct the proper particular social
    group analysis on a case-by-case basis. Indeed, had the
    Attorney General announced a categorical rule, there would
    have been no reason to remand Matter of A-B- to the BIA for
    analysis “under the standards articulated in this opinion and
    in past Board decisions.” Id. In Matter of A-B-, the Attorney
    General did not announce a new categorical exception for
    victims of domestic violence or other private criminal
    activity.
    B
    Diaz-Reynoso next argues that the Attorney General’s
    opinion in Matter of A-B- is arbitrary and capricious because
    it marks a dramatic and unexplained departure from the
    BIA’s longstanding recognition that particular social group
    determinations must be individualized and conducted on a
    3
    Like Diaz-Reynoso, the dissent focuses on the Attorney General’s
    observation that claims based on domestic violence “are unlikely to satisfy
    the statutory grounds for proving group persecution that the government
    is unable or unwilling to address.” Id. at 320. But the Attorney General
    explicitly declined to decide that violence “inflicted by non-governmental
    actors may never serve as the basis” for asylum or withholding relief. Id.
    Indeed, though such applicants face numerous hurdles—e.g., establishing
    the existence of a particular social group, membership in that group,
    persecution on account of that membership, and persecution that a
    government is unwilling or unable to control—the Attorney General
    recognized that “there may be exceptional circumstances when victims of
    private criminal activity could meet these requirements.” Id. at 317.
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                     19
    case-by-case basis. This argument is based on a misreading
    of Matter of A-B-.
    In Matter of A-B-, the Attorney General reaffirmed the
    BIA’s existing framework for analyzing the cognizability of
    particular social groups, and faulted the BIA for failing to
    apply it. See 27 I. & N. Dec. at 331. Under the BIA’s
    established standards, social groups must “be determined on
    a case-by-case basis.” Matter of Acosta, 19 I. & N. Dec.
    at 233; see also, e.g., Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec.
    at 251. On this point, the Attorney General was not subtle.
    Matter of A-B- reminded the BIA to “perform[] the detailed
    analysis required” by the BIA’s precedents, emphasizing that
    “[s]uch claims must be carefully analyzed under the standards
    articulated in [Matter of A-B-] and in past Board decisions.”
    27 I. & N. Dec. at 332, 340. “Neither immigration judges nor
    the Board may avoid the rigorous analysis required in
    determining asylum claims . . . .” Id. at 340. Matter of A-B-
    did not announce a bright-line rule concerning applications
    based on domestic violence; in fact, it underscored the need
    for an intensive case-by-case analysis. Accordingly, we
    decline to hold that the Attorney General’s decision in Matter
    of A-B- was arbitrary or capricious.
    V
    A
    Diaz-Reynoso next argues that, even if Matter of A-B- did
    not establish a categorical rule barring relief for victims of
    domestic violence and other private criminal activity, the BIA
    misapprehended the scope of the Attorney General’s holding
    in Matter of A-B-. On this point, we agree with Diaz-
    Reynoso. The BIA seems to have erroneously understood
    20                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    Matter of A-B- to forbid any mention of feared harm within
    a proposed social group.
    With almost no analysis, the BIA rejected Diaz-
    Reynoso’s proposed particular social group because it
    “suffer[ed] from the same circularity problem articulated by
    the Attorney General in Matter of A-B-.” But Matter of A-B-
    did not announce a new rule concerning circularity, or
    identify a categorical “circularity problem.” It merely
    reiterated the well-established principle that a particular
    social group must exist independently of the harm asserted,
    and that the BIA must consider whether a petitioner’s social
    group is cognizable if it is defined without reference to the
    fact of persecution. Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec.
    at 334–35. If a group is otherwise cognizable, Matter of A-B-
    does not demand that it be devoid of any reference to an
    applicant’s claimed persecution. To the contrary, Matter of
    A-B- reiterated the longstanding rule that persecution may be
    relevant to a group’s social distinction. The BIA’s
    precedents, as well as our own, make this clear.
    Matter of A-B- restated the rule that “a particular social
    group must ‘exist independently’ of the harm asserted in an
    application for asylum or statutory withholding of removal,”
    27 I. & N. Dec. at 334 (quoting Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. &
    N. Dec. at 236 n.11), and “individuals in the group must share
    a narrowing characteristic other than their risk of being
    persecuted,” id. at 335 (quoting Rreshpja v. Gonzales,
    
    420 F.3d 551
    , 556 (6th Cir. 2005)). This principle finds its
    genesis in the BIA’s 2006 decision in Matter of C-A-, 23 I. &
    N. Dec. at 957–61.
    Matter of C-A- discussed the importance of social
    distinction (then called social visibility) to the particular
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                             21
    social group analysis. Id. at 959–60. The BIA cited the
    guidelines adopted by the United Nations High
    Commissioner for Refugees (UNHCR) for establishing
    membership in a particular social group, and observed that
    the guidelines “confirm that ‘visibility’ is an important
    element in identifying the existence of a particular social
    group.” Id. at 960 (citing UNHCR Guidelines ¶¶ 2, 14).4 The
    BIA explained that “a social group cannot be defined
    exclusively by the fact that it is targeted for persecution,” but
    said nothing to suggest that the mention of feared harm
    somehow disqualifies an otherwise cognizable group. Id.
    (quoting UNHCR Guidelines ¶ 2). In fact, the BIA explained
    that “persecutory action toward a group may be a relevant
    factor in determining the visibility of a group in a particular
    society.” Id. (quoting UNHCR Guidelines ¶ 14).
    Subsequent BIA decisions in 2007 and 2008 repeated this
    refrain. See, e.g., Matter of S-E-G-, 24 I. & N. Dec. at 584
    (observing that although a particular social group cannot be
    “defined exclusively by the fact that its members have been
    subjected to harm in the past . . . [,] this may be a relevant
    factor in considering the group’s visibility in society” (citing
    Matter of C-A-, 23 I. & N. Dec. at 960)); Matter of A-M-E- &
    J-G-U-, 24 I. & N. Dec. at 74 (“Although a social group
    cannot be defined exclusively by the fact that its members
    have been subjected to harm, . . . this may be a relevant factor
    in considering the group’s visibility in society.” (citing
    Matter of C-A-, 23 I. & N. Dec. at 960)). In 2014, the BIA in
    4
    “UNHCR Guidelines” refers to UNHCR, Guidelines on
    International Protection: “Membership of a particular social group” within
    the context of Article 1A(2) of the 1951 Convention and/or its 1967
    Protocol relating to the Status of Refugees, U.N. Doc. HCR/GIP/02/02
    (May 7, 2002), available at https://www.unhcr.org/3d58de2da.pdf.
    22                    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    Matter of M-E-V-G- reaffirmed that the requirement that “the
    social group must exist independently of the fact of
    persecution” was “well established in [its] prior precedents
    and is already a part of the social group analysis.” 26 I. &. N.
    Dec. at 236 n.11 (citing Matter of A-M-E- & J-G-U-, 24 I. &
    N. Dec. at 74); see also Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec.
    at 215 (“Persecutory conduct aimed at a social group cannot
    alone define the group, which must exist independently of the
    persecution.” (citing Matter of A-M-E- & J-G-U-, 24 I. & N.
    Dec. at 74)).5
    The Attorney General’s opinion in Matter of A-B-
    reaffirmed this line of authority for assessing the
    cognizability of particular social groups, citing the BIA’s
    prior articulations of the rule in cases like Matter of M-E-V-
    G-, 26 I. &. N. Dec. at 236 n.11, and Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I.
    & N. Dec. at 215, and the Sixth Circuit’s decision in
    5
    Our sister circuits’ published opinions have widely acknowledged
    the rule that persecution alone cannot define the social group. See, e.g.,
    Perez-Rabanales v. Sessions, 
    881 F.3d 61
    , 67 (1st Cir. 2018) (“[W]here
    a proposed group is defined only by the characteristic that it is persecuted,
    it does not qualify as a ‘social group.’” (emphasis added) (citation
    omitted)); Paloka v. Holder, 
    762 F.3d 191
    , 198 (2d Cir. 2014) (“[A]
    particular social group is not cognizable merely because members have
    been subjected to harm . . . .” (emphasis added) (quotation marks and
    citations omitted)); Orellana-Monson v. Holder, 
    685 F.3d 511
    , 518–19
    (5th Cir. 2012) (“[T]he risk of persecution alone does not create a
    particular social group . . . .” (emphasis added) (citation omitted));
    Rivera-Barrientos v. Holder, 
    666 F.3d 641
    , 650 (10th Cir. 2012) (“[A]
    social group cannot be defined exclusively by the fact that its members
    have been subjected to harm . . . .” (emphasis added) (citation omitted));
    Jonaitiene v. Holder, 
    660 F.3d 267
    , 271 (7th Cir. 2011) (“The social group
    . . . cannot be defined merely by the fact of persecution.” (emphasis
    added)); Castillo-Arias v. U.S. Att’y Gen., 
    446 F.3d 1190
    , 1198 (11th Cir.
    2006) (“The risk of persecution alone does not create a particular social
    group . . . .” (emphasis added)).
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                        23
    Rreshpja, which explained that the “individuals in the group
    must share a narrowing characteristic other than their risk of
    being persecuted.” Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 334–35
    (quoting Rreshpja, 
    420 F.3d at 556
    ); see also Matter of L-E-
    A-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 595 (observing that a proposed social
    group must have an “‘existence independent of’ the alleged
    persecutors,” and that “the risk of persecution alone can never
    create a particular social group” (citation omitted)). In
    Rreshpja, the court further observed that persecution may not
    be “the touchstone defining the group.” 
    420 F.3d at 556
    (citation omitted). The group at issue in Rreshpja—young,
    attractive Albanian women who were forced into
    prostitution—lacked a “narrowing characteristic” because, if
    viewed without reference to being forced into prostitution, the
    proposed group would allow “virtually any young Albanian
    woman who possesse[d] the subjective criterion of being
    ‘attractive’” to obtain asylum. Id.; see also Matter of A-B-,
    27 I. & N. Dec. at 335.
    B
    Despite this solid and consistent line of precedent, on
    appeal the Government and dissent defend the BIA’s
    summary rejection of Diaz-Reynoso’s particular social group
    on the grounds that it “suffers from the same circularity
    problem articulated by the Attorney General in Matter of
    A-B-.” They concede that the fact of persecution may be
    relevant to social distinction in a particular society, but insist
    that a proposed particular social group may not include
    mention of feared persecution. In the Government’s and
    dissent’s view, in order to exist independently from the
    petitioner’s feared harm, a proposed group may not refer to
    that harm at all. We disagree. The idea that the inclusion of
    persecution is a sort of poison pill that dooms any group does
    24                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    not withstand scrutiny. See Matter of C-A-, 23 I. & N. Dec.
    at 960 (confirming that “‘visibility’ is an important element
    in identifying the existence of a particular social group,” and
    that “persecutory action toward a group may be a relevant
    factor in determining the visibility of a group in a particular
    society” (citation omitted)).
    The BIA has taken pains to state that “the shared trait of
    persecution does not disqualify an otherwise valid social
    group.” Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 243 (citing
    Cece v. Holder, 
    733 F.3d 662
    , 671 (7th Cir. 2013) (en banc));
    see also Paloka, 762 F.3d at 198. Though “persecutory
    conduct alone cannot define the group,” Matter of M-E-V-G-,
    26 I. & N. Dec. at 242 (emphasis added); see also id. at 243
    (a particular social group “cannot be defined merely by the
    fact of persecution” (quoting Cece, 733 F.3d at 671)),
    persecution itself “may be the catalyst that causes” a society
    to distinguish a group in a meaningful way and consider it
    distinct, id. at 243; see also supra Part V.A.
    Because BIA precedent dictates that a particular social
    group cannot be defined “exclusively” by harm, the
    Government and dissent insist that BIA precedent does not
    permit a group to include any mention of harm. To reach this
    conclusion, they ignore the word “exclusively”—along with
    similar limiting language in the BIA’s decisions and those
    from our sister circuits, supra Part V.A—and argue that in
    order for a group to “exist independently” from harm, its
    description must not refer to harm at all. But as we have
    explained, BIA precedent confirms that a group that exists
    independent of persecution is simply a group that shares an
    immutable characteristic other than the persecution it
    suffers—i.e., a group that shares a “narrowing characteristic.”
    Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 335 (quoting Rreshpja,
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                            25
    
    420 F.3d at 556
    ); Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 215;
    see also Matter of L-E-A-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 595.
    The BIA articulated an example in Matter of M-E-V-G-
    that leaves no room for doubt on this score.6 There, the BIA
    posited that a proposed social group composed of former
    employees of a country’s attorney general may not be valid
    for asylum purposes, even though the group is discrete and
    the members’ shared past experience is immutable, because
    “the society may not consider these employees to be
    meaningfully distinct within society in general.” Id. at 242.
    However, the BIA explained, if the government began
    persecuting those people, it is possible that society would
    then discern that this group of individuals is distinct in some
    significant way. Id. at 243. In this example, the act of
    persecution by the government causes the society to
    recognize the former employees as distinct, “but the
    immutable characteristic of their shared past experience exists
    independent of the persecution.” Id.
    The UNHCR Guidelines provide a similar example
    concerning left-handed people.7 Left-handed people possess
    an immutable characteristic that is defined with particularity,
    but the group lacks social distinction—that is, the relevant
    society may not consider the characteristic to set apart the
    group in a meaningful way. See UNHCR Guidelines ¶ 14. If,
    however, left-handed people were subjected to persecution
    6
    This example is drawn from the Seventh Circuit’s decision in
    Sepulveda v. Gonzales, 
    464 F.3d 770
    , 771 (7th Cir. 2006).
    7
    The BIA has recognized that although the views of the UNHCR are
    not binding, they “are a useful interpretative aid.” Matter of M-E-V-G-,
    26 I. & N. Dec. at 248.
    26                   DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    because they were left-handed, their immutable characteristic
    could become recognizable and distinct within their society.
    Id. In this example, it is the attribute of being left-handed—
    and not the persecutory acts—that would identify members of
    this particular social group. Id. Thus, the group possesses an
    underlying immutable characteristic, the fact of persecution
    establishes the group’s distinction within the relevant society,
    and because the group’s members can be identified by means
    other than the feared persecution, it shares a narrowing
    characteristic and is cognizable. 8
    If we were to follow the reasoning suggested by the
    Government and dissent, neither the BIA’s group of former
    employees of a country’s attorney general, nor the UN High
    Commissioner’s group of left-handed people, would be
    cognizable if members of those groups included mention of
    their feared persecution in their proposed social groups. The
    particular formulation of the groups—e.g., “former
    employees of the attorney general” versus “former employees
    of the attorney general, who are being hunted down and
    killed,” or “left-handed people” versus “left-handed people
    who have been persecuted”—makes all the difference to the
    group’s cognizability for the Government and dissent
    because, in their view, groups that include mention of feared
    harm cannot exist independently of that harm.
    Though it cannot be contested that persecution may be
    relevant to a group’s social distinction, the dissent argues that
    the “group itself” cannot “be defined in some way by that
    persecution,” and the Government echoes this view.
    8
    This example is borrowed from a “widely cited” decision. UNHCR
    Guidelines ¶ 14 (citing Applicant A v. Minister for Immigration and Ethnic
    Affairs (1997) 
    190 CLR 225
    , 264 (Austl.)).
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                       27
    In advancing this argument, the Government and dissent
    confuse the definition of a “particular social group” with one
    of its components—i.e., the group’s shared immutable
    characteristic—and thereby treat every element of a proposed
    social group as necessary to the group’s immutable
    characteristic. This is contrary to BIA precedent, which
    unequivocally establishes that a group’s persecution may be
    relevant to a different component: social distinction. See
    Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 242–43. Further, it
    is important to recognize that the question is not whether
    feared persecution can serve as an immutable characteristic;
    the question is whether mention of feared persecution
    disqualifies an otherwise cognizable social group.
    The Government and dissent argue that by failing to treat
    harm as integral to a social group’s definition—i.e., by failing
    to treat it as part of the group’s shared immutable
    characteristic—we advocate a rule that allows courts to
    impermissibly rewrite proposed social groups. See Matter of
    W-Y-C- & H-O-B-, 
    27 I. & N. Dec. 189
    , 191–92 (BIA 2018)
    (noting that a petitioner must delineate his or her proposed
    social group before the IJ, and may not reframe the group on
    appeal). We agree that courts cannot rewrite proposed social
    groups, but nothing requires us to analyze them as
    mechanistically as the dissent and Government urge.
    As we have explained, the BIA’s precedent establishes
    that we may consider the entirety of a proffered social group
    to determine whether the petitioner has established all the
    requirements for a cognizable group: an immutable
    characteristic, particularity, and social distinction. Matter of
    M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 227. We do not rewrite the
    petitioner’s proposed social group by recognizing that the
    mention of harm in a proposed social group may be relevant
    28                 DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    to the group’s social distinction, nor does this prevent us from
    examining whether the petitioner’s proffered group shares an
    immutable characteristic other than harm. To be sure, it is
    the applicant’s burden to demonstrate the existence of a
    cognizable particular social group. Reyes, 842 F.3d at 1132
    n.3; see also Matter of W-Y-C- & H-O-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at
    191 (noting that “it is an applicant’s burden to specifically
    delineate her proposed social group”); Matter of A-T-, 
    25 I. & N. Dec. 4
    , 10 (BIA 2009). And it is the applicant’s burden to
    establish membership in that group. Reyes, 842 F.3d at 1132
    n.3. But nothing in the precedential framework constrains the
    petitioner to specifying a proposed group that mentions only
    the proffered immutable characteristic, and no more.
    The purpose of asylum and withholding is to provide
    relief to people who have been persecuted in foreign lands
    because of their race, religion, nationality, membership in a
    particular social group, or political opinion. 
    8 U.S.C. §§ 1158
    (b)(1)(B)(i), 1231(b)(3)(A); see also INS v. Cardoza-
    Fonseca, 
    480 U.S. 421
    , 423–24, 427–29 (1987). The
    Government and dissent do not explain why a person seeking
    relief on the basis of membership in a particular social group
    should be required to omit any mention of threatened
    persecution. Notably, the rule they propose is not limited to
    victims of domestic violence. Under the interpretation urged
    by the Government and dissent, a Tutsi fleeing Rwanda
    during the Rwandan Civil War would be denied relief if he or
    she included in the description of the Tutsi social group that
    Tutsis had been targeted in a campaign of genocide. See
    Donchev v. Mukasey, 
    553 F.3d 1206
    , 1220 (9th Cir. 2009)
    (“When the Hutus in Rwanda murdered as many Tutsis
    as they could, the persecution was not on account of
    ‘race, religion, nationality, . . . , or political opinion,’” but
    “being Tutsi . . . fits well into the ‘particular social group’
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                      29
    category.” (first alteration in original) (quoting 
    8 U.S.C. § 1101
    (a)(42)(A))). Tellingly, the dissent’s only response to
    this hypothetical is that such person fleeing genocide would
    not need to mention that harm because he or she could rely on
    Tutsi ethnicity to establish group membership. Of course
    they could, and that is precisely the point; the mere mention
    of harm does not categorically disqualify an otherwise
    cognizable social group.
    The dissent asserts that no court has endorsed the view
    that a proposed social group is not disqualified if it includes
    mention of feared persecution. But the most recent decision
    doing so is Grace v. Barr, — F.3d —, 
    2020 WL 4032652
    (D.C. Cir. 2020). There, the Government argued that a group
    “must be separate from the harm, not consisting of the harm,
    even in part,” and the D.C. Circuit rejected this argument as
    “flatly inconsistent” with Matter of A-B-. Id. at *16 (internal
    quotation marks omitted); see also id. (noting the
    Government’s concession at oral argument that the group
    “Guatemalan women unable to leave their relationships”
    would not be “categorically barred,” and that “its validity
    would turn on the specific factual circumstances of an
    applicant’s claim”).
    The case-by-case approach we describe is the very one
    articulated by Matter of A-B-. There, the Attorney General
    faulted the BIA’s decision in Matter of A-R-C-G- because it
    “avoided considering whether [the petitioner] could establish
    the existence of a cognizable particular social group without
    defining the group by the fact of persecution.” Matter of
    A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 334. The Attorney General
    explained that members of a cognizable group “must share a
    narrowing characteristic other than their risk of being
    persecuted.” Id. at 335 (emphasis added) (quoting Rreshpja,
    30                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    
    420 F.3d at 556
    ); see also, e.g., Sarhan v. Holder, 
    658 F.3d 649
    , 655 (7th Cir. 2011) (concluding that proposed social
    group of “women in Jordan who have (allegedly) flouted
    repressive moral norms, and thus who face a high risk of
    honor killing” was cognizable because it was not defined
    solely by its risk of persecution); Rodriguez v. U.S. Att’y
    Gen., 
    735 F.3d 1302
    , 1310 (11th Cir. 2013) (concluding that
    proposed social group of “members of a family targeted by a
    drug-trafficking organization because a family member
    sought criminal justice against a member of the drug-
    trafficking organization” was not cognizable because its
    “defining attribute” was its persecution, and the “risk of
    persecution alone does not create a particular social group”
    (citation omitted)); Matter of S-E-G-, 24 I. & N. Dec. at 584,
    588 (concluding that proposed social group of “young
    Salvadorans who have been subject to recruitment efforts by
    criminal gangs” was not cognizable because aside from being
    “subjected to harm in the past (i.e., forced gang recruitment
    and any violence associated with that recruitment),” the
    proposed group lacked a common immutable characteristic).
    If the petitioners’ mere reference to harm defeated these
    proposed social groups, any further analysis of the groups
    would have been unnecessary. As the D.C. Circuit
    recognized in Grace, Matter of A-B- requires a “careful[]”
    examination of a group to “ascertain whether it contains any
    attributes that ‘exist independently of the harm asserted.’”
    
    2020 WL 4032652
    , at *14–15. This is because a group
    “exists independently of the harm suffered” so long as
    persecution is not “what defines the contours of the group.”
    See id. at *2 (citation omitted).
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                       31
    We recognize that, consistent with Matter of A-B-,
    numerous courts have deemed proposed social groups that
    referred to feared harm to be impermissibly circular. In some
    circumstances, this will be the correct result. Nothing in our
    analysis negates the precedent establishing that a group may
    be deemed impermissibly “circular” if, after conducting the
    proper case-by-case analysis, the BIA determines that the
    group is “defined exclusively by the fact that its members
    have been subjected to harm.” Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. &
    N. Dec. at 242 (quoting Matter of A-M-E- & J-G-U-, 24 I. &
    N. Dec. at 74). Courts have frequently held, after proper
    analysis, that groups lacking a common characteristic aside
    from persecution are not cognizable. See, e.g., Amezcua-
    Preciado v. U.S. Att’y Gen., 
    943 F.3d 1337
    , 1345 (11th Cir.
    2019) (concluding that proposed group lacked a “‘narrowing
    characteristic’ other than the[] risk of being persecuted”);
    Melnik v. Sessions, 
    891 F.3d 278
    , 286 (7th Cir. 2018)
    (concluding that, other than persecution, “the only common
    characteristic of members of the proffered class [was] their
    status as small business owners”); Rreshpja, 
    420 F.3d at 556
    (concluding that, aside from the fact of persecution, the group
    included all “young, attractive Albanian women”). These
    groups may also suffer from other deficiencies, such as a lack
    of particularity or social distinction, but this appeal does not
    require that we consider those aspects of the particular social
    group analysis. Here, we clarify that the conclusion that a
    proposed social group is impermissibly circular may not be
    reached summarily merely because the proposed group
    mentions harm.
    32                    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    The dissent cites to a plethora of unpublished decisions
    that rejected groups similar to the one advanced here, arguing
    that our decision is inconsistent with them.9 The dissent’s
    reliance on these decisions reflects its mistaken premise that
    the rejection of a social group in one case suggests that a
    similar group may be rejected summarily in another. This
    accounts for the dissent’s approval of the BIA’s one-sentence
    analysis in this case. But it also contravenes binding
    authority establishing that whether a particular social group
    is cognizable “requires a fact-specific inquiry based on the
    evidence in a particular case.” Matter of L-E-A-, 27 I. & N.
    Dec. at 591.
    The dissent also conflates the requirement to show nexus
    with the requirements for establishing a particular social
    group, and argues that if petitioners were allowed to include
    mention of their claimed persecution, they would somehow
    be relieved of the burden to establish a nexus between the
    persecution and their membership in the group. What the
    dissent overlooks is that this is only a concern if social groups
    are “defined exclusively” by the harm the petitioners identify.
    Matter of C-A-, 23 I. & N. Dec. at 960 (quoting UNHCR
    Guidelines ¶ 14). If the only immutable characteristic is a
    feared harm, the group becomes an impermissible “‘catch all’
    applicable to all persons fearing persecution.” Id. (citing
    UNHCR Guidelines ¶ 2); see also Castillo-Arias, 
    446 F.3d at 1198
    . That problem does not exist if a narrowing
    9
    Unpublished decisions are not precedent precisely because they are
    “not written in a way that will be fully intelligible to those unfamiliar with
    the case, and the rule of law is not announced in a way that makes it
    suitable for governing future cases.” Hart v. Massanari, 
    266 F.3d 1155
    ,
    1178 (9th Cir. 2001). Thus, contrary to the dissent’s urging, we cannot
    discern the reasoning of those decisions simply from their outcome.
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                      33
    characteristic allows the group to be defined without
    reference to feared persecution. Matter of A-B- is clear on
    this point. 27 I. & N. Dec. at 335 (noting that a group defined
    by its persecution “moots the need to establish actual
    persecution,” and it is “[f]or this reason” that the group
    members must share a “narrowing characteristic” (emphasis
    added) (citation omitted)).
    C
    The BIA ruled that Diaz-Reynoso’s proposed social group
    was not cognizable because it assumed her inability to leave
    her relationship was attributable to domestic violence, and
    because it understood Matter of A-B- to say that the mention
    of domestic violence disqualifies a particular social group.
    The BIA’s decision consisted of a citation to Matter of A-B-
    and an assertion that Diaz-Reynoso’s group suffered from the
    same “circularity problem” identified in that case. Without
    more, this was plainly contrary to the Attorney General’s
    requirement that claims must be carefully analyzed under the
    framework established by the BIA’s precedents. Matter of
    A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 331–32, 339–40; see also Pirir-Boc,
    750 F.3d at 1084. There are no shortcuts.
    There are at least two problems with the BIA’s reasoning
    in Diaz-Reynoso’s appeal. First, as explained, the BIA
    misunderstood Matter of A-B-’s holding. Second, it is not
    clear that the reason Diaz-Reynoso was “unable to leave” her
    relationship was limited to domestic violence. Rather, the
    BIA assumed that domestic violence was the only reason
    34                    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    Diaz-Reynoso was unable to leave her relationship. The
    dissent makes the same assumption.10
    Diaz-Reynoso described her particular social group as
    “indigenous women in Guatemala who are unable to leave
    their relationship.” The persecution Diaz-Reynoso fears is
    undoubtedly the abuse perpetrated by her husband, but before
    the immigration judge, she advanced evidence of economic,
    societal, and cultural factors that also may have prevented her
    from leaving her relationship. These included her financial
    dependence on her husband, limited education, rural location,
    and an ingrained Mayan cultural view that a relationship does
    not end until the man so agrees.11 Contrary to the dissent’s
    assertion, Diaz-Reynoso identified these factors in her brief
    to the BIA.
    The IJ made no findings about the cognizability of Diaz-
    Reynoso’s particular social group. Instead, the IJ ruled that
    Diaz-Reynoso failed to establish her membership in her
    10
    The dissent states that the IJ “made clear that the entire basis for
    petitioner’s proposed social group was her fear of domestic violence.”
    This is incorrect. The IJ made no findings about the basis for Diaz-
    Reynoso’s proposed social group, and instead relied on her inability to
    show membership in the group she advanced. The dissent also attributes
    a finding to the BIA that it did not make—that Diaz-Reynoso’s inability
    to leave “was created by harm or threatened harm.” The BIA did not
    make this ruling, and we cannot supply our own reasoning in lieu of that
    actually offered by the BIA. See, e.g., Recinos De Leon v. Gonzales,
    
    400 F.3d 1185
    , 1189 (9th Cir. 2005).
    11
    There are many reasons a petitioner might be unable to leave a
    relationship, including a variety of “cultural, societal, religious, economic,
    or other factors.” De Pena-Paniagua v. Barr, 
    957 F.3d 88
    , 94 (1st Cir.
    2020); see also Grace, 
    2020 WL 4032652
    , at *14–15; Amezcua-Preciado,
    943 F.3d at 1345.
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                      35
    proposed social group because she did not establish she was
    unable to leave her relationship. On appeal, the BIA relied on
    entirely different grounds. It plucked one fact identified by
    Diaz-Reynoso—that her husband physically abused her—and
    ruled that her proposed social group, which it presumed to be
    premised solely on domestic violence, suffered from the same
    “circularity problem” identified in Matter of A-B-. By
    reaching this conclusion without engaging in the analysis
    underscored by the Attorney General, the BIA committed the
    very same error it made in Matter of A-B-. See Matter of
    A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 331, 340; see also Grace, 
    2020 WL 4032652
    , at *15 (noting that “whether a given group is
    circular depends on the facts of the particular case”).
    Even if Diaz-Reynoso’s social group necessarily
    incorporated her husband’s physical abuse, the best indication
    that this does not categorically disqualify her social group is
    that the Attorney General remanded Matter of A-B- for the
    BIA to conduct a proper analysis. 27 I. & N. Dec. at 340.
    The group at issue in Matter of A-B- was “El Salvadoran
    women who are unable to leave their domestic relationships
    where they have children in common.” Id. at 321. Rather
    than simply invalidating that group, the Attorney General
    remanded so the group could be “carefully analyzed under the
    standards articulated in this opinion and in past Board
    decisions, such as M-E-V-G- and W-G-R-.” Id. at 340.
    The dissent brushes aside the Attorney General’s remand
    in Matter of A-B-, arguing the remand in that case was
    nothing more than “standard remand language,” and urging
    that Matter of A-B- reiterated a rule that any mention of harm
    disqualifies a social group as impermissibly circular without
    further analysis. Accepting this interpretation would require
    us to ignore the Attorney General’s clear language about the
    36                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    mistakes made in Matter of A-B-, including that we cannot
    “avoid the rigorous analysis required” by the BIA’s
    precedents, id. at 340, as well as the Attorney General’s
    acknowledgment that “there may be exceptional
    circumstances when victims of private criminal activity could
    meet” the requirements for relief, id. at 317. See also id.
    at 339 (observing that “any claim regarding the existence of
    a particular social group” must be evaluated “in the context
    of the evidence presented regarding the particular
    circumstances in the country in question” (citation omitted)).
    Because the BIA avoided the case-specific inquiry demanded
    by Matter of A-B- and the BIA’s precedents, we grant Diaz-
    Reynoso’s petition and remand her withholding claim.
    D
    Diaz-Reynoso argues that the panel should analyze her
    proposed particular social group under the proper framework
    in the first instance. We decline to do so.
    A panel may only affirm on the grounds set forth in the
    BIA’s decision. Recinos De Leon, 
    400 F.3d at 1189
    . When
    the BIA’s decision “cannot be sustained upon its reasoning,
    [the court] must remand to allow the agency to decide any
    issues remaining in the case.” Andia v. Ashcroft, 
    359 F.3d 1181
    , 1184 (9th Cir. 2004) (per curiam); see also INS v.
    Ventura, 
    537 U.S. 12
    , 16 (2002); Azanor v. Ashcroft,
    
    364 F.3d 1013
    , 1021 (9th Cir. 2004).
    VI
    Diaz-Reynoso also sought relief pursuant to the
    Convention Against Torture.       CAT’s implementing
    regulations require the agency to consider “all evidence
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                        37
    relevant to the possibility of future torture,” and we have
    reversed where the agency has failed to do so. Parada v.
    Sessions, 
    902 F.3d 901
    , 914–15 (9th Cir. 2018) (quoting
    
    8 C.F.R. § 1208.16
    (c)(3)); see also Cole v. Holder, 
    659 F.3d 762
    , 771–72 (9th Cir. 2011); Kamalthas v. INS, 
    251 F.3d 1279
    , 1284 (9th Cir. 2001). Here, we conclude that the BIA
    failed to consider all relevant evidence, so we remand Diaz-
    Reynoso’s CAT claim for further consideration.
    To qualify for relief under CAT, an alien must establish
    it is more likely than not that he or she would be tortured if
    returned to the proposed country of removal. Garcia-Milian
    v. Holder, 
    755 F.3d 1026
    , 1033 (9th Cir. 2014) (citing
    
    8 C.F.R. § 208.16
    (c)(2)). Torture is any act by which severe
    pain or suffering is intentionally inflicted for such purposes
    as obtaining information or a confession, punishing an act
    committed or one suspected of having been committed,
    intimidating or coercing, or for any reason based on
    discrimination of any kind. Singh v. Whitaker, 
    914 F.3d 654
    ,
    663 (9th Cir. 2019) (citing 
    8 C.F.R. § 1208.18
    (a)(1)).
    Torture must be inflicted by, at the instigation of, or with
    the consent or acquiescence of, a public official or other
    person acting in an official capacity. Zheng v. Ashcroft, 
    332 F.3d 1186
    , 1188 (9th Cir. 2003) (citing 
    8 C.F.R. § 208.18
    (a)(1)). “Public officials acquiesce in torture if they:
    ‘(1) have awareness of the activity (or consciously close their
    eyes to the fact it is going on); and (2) breach their legal
    responsibility to intervene to prevent the activity because they
    are unable or unwilling to oppose it.” Barajas-Romero v.
    Lynch, 
    846 F.3d 351
    , 363 (9th Cir. 2017) (quoting Garcia-
    Milian, 755 F.3d at 1034). The public official need not have
    actual knowledge of the specific incident of torture; instead,
    it is sufficient that the public official is aware that torture of
    38                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    the sort feared by the applicant occurs and remains willfully
    blind to it. Madrigal v. Holder, 
    716 F.3d 499
    , 509 (9th Cir.
    2013); see also Ornelas-Chavez v. Gonzales, 
    458 F.3d 1052
    ,
    1059–60 (9th Cir. 2006).
    Diaz-Reynoso, who was deemed generally credible,
    testified that she told a man in her community named
    Sebastian about Vasquez-Juarez abusing her. Sebastian was
    “like an assistant mayor” in Yamoj, and according to Diaz-
    Reynoso, he had the power to arrest Vasquez-Juarez but did
    not do so. Instead, Sebastian told her that the abuse she
    suffered was a personal problem. Diaz-Reynoso further
    testified that she witnessed her husband bribing Sebastian.
    Diaz-Reynoso also reported her abuse to a man named
    Avelino, who she described as a mayor figure in her village.
    Avelino told Vasquez-Juarez that what he was doing was not
    right, but Vasquez-Juarez responded that Avelino could not
    tell him what to do because Vasquez-Juarez “kn[e]w the
    law[].” Diaz-Reynoso did not attempt to report the abuse to
    anyone else, as she lacked the resources to do so. Her
    mountain village was quite remote, with the nearest police
    station two hours away by car.
    The BIA did not discuss the evidence that Diaz-Reynoso
    reported her abuse to two different authority figures in her
    remote, rural community and that neither of them helped her.
    The BIA’s statement that it “consider[ed] all of the evidence,”
    does not suffice in this context. See Cole, 
    659 F.3d at 772
    .
    Indeed, after briefing in this appeal was completed, the
    Government conceded that the BIA failed to discuss
    potentially dispositive evidence regarding the issue of
    governmental acquiescence, specifically acknowledging that
    the BIA failed to consider whether Sebastian and Avelino
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                           39
    qualified as public officials within the meaning of 
    8 C.F.R. § 208.18
    (a)(1). The Government agreed that, remand is
    required under these circumstances. Accordingly, we remand
    for reconsideration of Diaz-Reynoso’s CAT claim.
    VII
    Contrary to the dissent’s concern, there is no confusion
    about the next steps for this case. On the CAT claim, the
    Government now stipulates that the failure to consider the
    reports Diaz-Reynoso made to people in her village requires
    remand. On the withholding claim, the BIA may consider in
    the first instance Diaz-Reynoso’s proffered social group
    under the required framework. See Matter of W-Y-C- & H-O-
    B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 191; see also Matter of L-E-A-, 27 I. &
    N. Dec. at 591.12 In addition or in the alternative, the BIA
    may choose to rule on the other issues Diaz-Reynoso
    appealed and briefed to the BIA—membership in her claimed
    social group, a clear probability of persecution, and
    persecution the Guatemalan government is unable or
    unwilling to control.
    Our decision today confirms a rule that has already been
    firmly established in the BIA’s decisions. Beginning with its
    2006 decision in Matter of C-A-, the BIA’s precedent has
    been premised on the rule that persecutory action taken
    toward a group can be relevant to that group’s social visibility
    (now social distinction). It is equally clear that the mere
    mention of persecutory action does not defeat an otherwise
    12
    Because the BIA cannot engage in fact-finding, 
    8 C.F.R. § 1003.1
    (d)(3), the BIA may find it necessary to remand for the IJ to
    decide any underlying factual issues. Matter of W-Y-C- & H-O-B-, 27 I.
    & N. Dec. at 191.
    40                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    cognizable social group. Matter of A-B- did not hold
    otherwise, and in fact expressly reaffirmed the BIA’s
    longstanding precedent.
    We remand Diaz-Reynoso’s claims to the BIA for further
    consideration.
    PETITION           FOR       REVIEW          GRANTED;
    REMANDED.
    BRESS, Circuit Judge, concurring in the judgment in part and
    dissenting in part:
    In Matter of A-B-, 
    27 I. & N. Dec. 316
     (A.G. 2018), the
    Attorney General revisited a recurring problem in the area of
    immigration law: the circumstances under which victims of
    domestic violence may seek asylum or withholding of
    removal. The Attorney General recognized that domestic
    abuse is “vile” but determined that under our immigration
    laws, claims of persecution based on domestic violence will
    generally “not qualify” for relief. 
    Id. at 320, 346
    . The court
    today purports to uphold Matter of A-B- but in fact largely
    disregards it, creating an uncertain legal landscape and widely
    opening the door to the types of claims Matter of A-B- said
    were largely unavailable.
    Under the Immigration and Nationality Act (INA), “the
    Attorney General may not remove an alien to a country if the
    Attorney General decides that the alien’s life or freedom
    would be threatened in that country because of the alien’s
    race, religion, nationality, membership in a particular social
    group, or political opinion.” 
    8 U.S.C. § 1231
    (b)(3)(A)
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                       41
    (emphasis added). In Matter of A-B-, the Attorney General
    reiterated the government’s longstanding approach to the
    ambiguous term “particular social group”: “[t]o be
    cognizable, a particular social group must exist independently
    of the harm asserted in an application for asylum or statutory
    withholding of removal.” 27 I. & N. Dec. at 334 (emphasis
    in original) (quotations omitted). Because an applicant must
    show persecution “because of” (or, for asylum, “on account
    of”) membership in a “particular social group,” embedding
    the harm in the definition of the group itself would be
    impermissibly circular. Id. at 335, 338.
    In Matter of A-B-, the Attorney General determined that
    the Board of Immigration Appeals (BIA) erred in recognizing
    the proposed social group “married women in Guatemala who
    are unable to leave their relationship.” Id. at 319, 334. The
    reason was that such a proposed group was impermissibly
    circular, “effectively defined to consist of women in
    Guatemala who are victims of domestic abuse because the
    inability ‘to leave’ was created by harm or threatened harm.”
    Id. at 335. The Attorney General in Matter of A-B- was
    unequivocal: when these issues are “properly analyzed,” it is
    “clear that the particular social group [is] not cognizable.” Id.
    at 334.
    Citing domestic violence at the hands of her common-law
    husband, the petitioner in this case sought withholding of
    removal based on the proposed social group “indigenous
    women in Guatemala who are unable to leave their
    relationship.” Recognizing that Matter of A-B- presented an
    obvious obstacle to her claim, petitioner’s primary argument
    on appeal is that the Attorney General’s decision was
    arbitrary and capricious and unentitled to deference under
    Chevron U.S.A. Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Council,
    42                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    Inc., 
    467 U.S. 837
     (1984). The court today rejects that
    challenge. But the majority nevertheless concludes that the
    BIA in this case misinterpreted Matter of A-B- in rejecting a
    proposed social group that is in all relevant respects identical
    to the proposed social group that the Attorney General
    squarely rejected in Matter of A-B-.
    This is error, with far-reaching consequences. The BIA
    in this case did not misread Matter of A-B-; it just applied it.
    So what did the BIA do wrong, not only in this case but
    presumably in many cases in which substantially identical
    proposed social groups have been rejected under the clear
    reasoning of Matter of A-B-? The majority’s opinion
    provides no clear answer to that question. The court’s
    varying and inconsistent rationales share the common theme
    that they reflect an unfortunate misunderstanding of the
    INA’s requirements and the longstanding BIA precedent
    interpreting them. Today’s opinion thus upholds Matter of
    A-B- in name only, improperly overstepping the Attorney
    General while departing from decisions of other circuits,
    inviting confusion in this important area of law.
    There is no doubt that domestic violence is a problem in
    countries around the world and that the conduct of
    petitioner’s husband is deplorable. But our court and the BIA
    have long recognized that not every person who has
    experienced suffering in a foreign country is entitled to
    asylum or withholding of removal. In this case, the BIA
    simply applied an Attorney General opinion in Matter of A-B-
    that the majority otherwise holds is a valid interpretation of
    the INA. That should have been the beginning and end of
    this case.
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                            43
    I thus respectfully dissent from the majority’s
    determination to grant the petition for review as to the
    withholding of removal claim.1
    I
    To appreciate the errors in the majority opinion, it is
    necessary to understand the statutory backdrop for the
    Attorney General’s decision in Matter of A-B- and the
    reasoning that supported that opinion.
    A
    An applicant is entitled to withholding of removal “if the
    Attorney General decides that the alien’s life or freedom
    would be threatened in that country because of the alien’s
    race, religion, nationality, membership in a particular social
    group, or political opinion.” 
    8 U.S.C. § 1231
    (b)(3)(A). The
    undefined phrase “particular social group,” which also
    appears in the similarly worded asylum statute, 
    id.
    §§ 1101(a)(42)(A), 1158(b)(1), has proven to be a source of
    considerable difficulty. Reyes v. Lynch, 
    842 F.3d 1125
    , 1134
    (9th Cir. 2016); Fatin v. INS, 
    12 F.3d 1233
    , 1238 (3d Cir.
    1993). We have therefore recognized that “particular social
    group” is an ambiguous term and that the agency is entitled
    to Chevron deference when interpreting it. Henriquez-Rivas
    1
    The majority also remands to the BIA for consideration of
    petitioner’s claim under the Convention Against Torture (CAT). I concur
    in this portion of the judgment because the government requested a
    remand to the BIA on petitioner’s CAT claim. I do not, however, join in
    the majority’s discussion of the merits of this claim because I find the
    discussion unnecessary given the government’s remand request.
    44                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    v. Holder, 
    707 F.3d 1081
    , 1083, 1087 (9th Cir. 2013) (en
    banc).
    Over time, the BIA has expounded on what “particular
    social group” means. In Matter of Acosta, 
    19 I. & N. Dec. 211
     (BIA 1985), and relying on the neighboring statutory
    references to “race,” “religion,” “nationality,” and “political
    opinion,” the BIA concluded that “particular social group”
    means “a group of persons all of whom share a common,
    immutable characteristic.” Id. at 233. In the BIA’s
    considered view, “whatever the common characteristic that
    defines the group, it must be one that the members of the
    group either cannot change, or should not be required to
    change because it is fundamental to their individual identities
    or consciences.” Id.
    Due to persisting uncertainty, and after a series of
    intervening decisions, the BIA in Matter of M-E-V-G-, 
    26 I. & N. Dec. 227
    , 237 (BIA 2014), and Matter of W-G-R-, 
    26 I. & N. Dec. 208
    , 212–18 (BIA 2014), refined two other
    requirements for a “particular social group.” In addition to
    sharing an “immutable characteristic,” the group must also be
    “defined with particularity” and “socially distinct within the
    society in question.” Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec.
    at 237. “Particularity” means that the group “must be defined
    by characteristics that provide a clear benchmark for
    determining who falls within the group,” must be “discrete
    and have definable boundaries,” and “must not be amorphous,
    overbroad, diffuse, or subjective.” Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I. &
    N. Dec. at 214. To be “socially distinct,” a group “must be
    perceived as a group by society.” Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I.
    & N. Dec. at 240. In Reyes, we held that the BIA’s
    construction of the “particularity” and “social distinction”
    requirements merited Chevron deference. 842 F.3d at 1133.
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                     45
    In Matter of M-E-V-G-, and particularly relevant here, the
    BIA explained that a proposed social group must still meet
    another separate requirement: “the social group must exist
    independently of the fact of persecution,” a “criterion [that]
    is well established in our prior precedents.” 26 I. & N. Dec.
    at 236 n.11; see also Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec.
    at 215. The rationale for this requirement centers on the fact
    that an applicant must not only prove membership in a
    cognizable group, but a risk of persecution “on account of”
    (or “because of”) “membership in the particular social
    group.”      Reyes, 842 F.3d at 1132 n.3; 
    8 U.S.C. §§ 1101
    (a)(42)(A), 1158(b)(1)(A), 1231(b)(3)(A).
    This last requirement is known as the “nexus”
    requirement. Reyes, 842 F.3d at 1132 n.3. The majority in
    this case acknowledges the “well-established principle” that
    a social group “must exist independently of the harm
    asserted.” Maj. Op. 20. But the majority does little to
    explain the rationale for that principle, which contributes to
    the misunderstandings in today’s opinion. The logic of the
    rule is important to this case.
    Because a petitioner must establish a nexus between the
    persecution and her membership in a proposed social group,
    she cannot bake into the definition of the group the very
    group-motivated persecution she must otherwise prove. That
    would create a circularity problem, because “[i]f a group is
    defined by the persecution of its members, then the definition
    of the group moots the need to establish actual persecution.”
    Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 335. Defining a group by
    the harm, in other words, eliminates a petitioner’s obligation
    to demonstrate persecution because of membership in the
    group, effectively satisfying the nexus requirement in every
    case.
    46                 DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    This anti-circularity principle is not controversial and is
    fundamental in this area of immigration law. Indeed, the
    majority itself cites various cases from other circuits that have
    acknowledged this rule. See, e.g., Perez-Rabanales v.
    Sessions, 
    881 F.3d 61
    , 67 (1st Cir. 2018) (“A sufficiently
    distinct social group must exist independent of the
    persecution claimed to have been suffered by the alien and
    must have existed before the alleged persecution began.”);
    Paloka v. Holder, 
    762 F.3d 191
    , 196 (2d Cir. 2014)
    (explaining that a proposed social group “must exist
    independently of the persecution”) (quoting Matter of
    W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 215); Rreshpja v. Gonzales,
    
    420 F.3d 551
    , 556 (6th Cir. 2005) (“[A] social group may not
    be circularly defined by the fact that it suffers persecution.”);
    Maj. Op. 22 n.5, 23 (citing these cases).
    Various other cases make the same point. See, e.g.,
    Amezcua-Preciado v. U.S. Attorney Gen., 
    943 F.3d 1337
    ,
    1343 (11th Cir. 2019) (“[T]he proffered group must be
    independent of, and cannot be defined by, the persecution.”);
    Gonzales-Veliz v. Barr, 
    938 F.3d 219
    , 229 (5th Cir. 2019)
    (“[T]he social group must exist independently of the fact of
    persecution.”) (quoting Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec.
    at 236 n.11) (alteration in original); Lukwago v. Ashcroft,
    
    329 F.3d 157
    , 172 (3d Cir. 2003) (“We agree that under the
    statute a ‘particular social group’ must exist independently of
    the persecution suffered by the applicant for asylum.”).
    Perhaps tellingly, of the many court of appeals cases the
    majority cites on this point of law, Maj. Op. 22 n.5, all of
    them denied petitions for review with the exception of one,
    and that case only remanded to the BIA in light of intervening
    precedent.
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                     47
    B
    In Matter of A-R-C-G-, 
    26 I. & N. Dec. 388
     (BIA 2014),
    the BIA recognized as a particular social group “married
    women in Guatemala who are unable to leave their
    relationship.” 
    Id. at 392
    . In treating this proposed social
    group as cognizable, the BIA relied primarily on the
    government’s concessions “that a particular social group
    exist[ed]” and that the proposed group was “defined with
    particularity.” 
    Id.
     at 393–94. Based on A-R-C-G-, the BIA
    then began to grant asylum and withholding of removal to
    victims of domestic violence. That is what ultimately led to
    the Attorney General’s intervention in Matter of A-B-, 
    27 I. & N. Dec. 316
     (A.G. 2018), the opinion most directly before
    us.
    The petitioner in Matter of A-B- claimed persecution in
    the form of domestic violence based on her membership in
    the claimed social group “El Salvadoran women who are
    unable to leave their domestic relationships where they have
    children in common.” 
    Id. at 321
    . The BIA held that this
    proposed group was cognizable under Matter of A-R-C-G-
    and ordered that the petitioner receive asylum. 
    Id.
     The
    Attorney General then intervened in Matter of A-B-, see
    
    8 U.S.C. §§ 1103
    (a)(1), (g)(2); 
    8 C.F.R. § 1003.1
    (h)(1), and
    “overrule[d]” Matter of A-R-C-G-. See Matter of A-B-, 27
    I. & N. Dec. at 317, 319, 340, 346. In the Attorney General’s
    considered view, Matter of A-R-C-G- improperly elevated the
    government’s concessions into binding precedent,
    “recogniz[ing] a new particular social group without correctly
    applying” the legal standards discussed above. Id. at 317; see
    also id. at 333.
    48                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    Matter of A-R-C-G- was “wrongly decided,” the Attorney
    General explained, because “[t]o be cognizable, a particular
    social group must ‘exist independently’ of the harm asserted
    in an application for asylum or statutory withholding of
    removal.” Id. at 333–34 (emphasis in original) (citing, e.g.,
    Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 236 n.11, 243; Matter
    of W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 215; Perez-Rabanales,
    881 F.3d at 67). That longstanding principle was fatal to the
    proposed social group in Matter of A-R-C-G-. As the
    Attorney General explained, the BIA in “A-R-C-G- never
    considered that ‘married women in Guatemala who are
    unable to leave their relationship’ was effectively defined to
    consist of women in Guatemala who are victims of domestic
    abuse because the inability ‘to leave’ was created by harm or
    threatened harm.” Id. at 335. The proposed social group in
    Matter of A-R-C-G- thus violated the anti-circularity
    principle. Id. at 334–35.
    Although the Attorney General in Matter of A-B- did “not
    decide that violence inflicted by non-governmental actors
    may never serve as the basis for an asylum or withholding
    application,” he explained that such claims based on domestic
    violence “are unlikely to satisfy the statutory grounds for
    proving group persecution.” Id. at 320.
    II
    In this case, petitioner claims her husband acted violently
    toward her because of her membership in the claimed social
    group “indigenous women in Guatemala who are unable to
    leave their relationship.” The BIA held that petitioner’s
    proposed group was not cognizable because it “suffers from
    the same circularity problem articulated by the Attorney
    General in Matter of A-B-.” In Part IV of its opinion, the
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                      49
    majority correctly rejects petitioner’s arguments that Matter
    of A-B- is arbitrary and capricious and undeserving of
    Chevron deference. Maj. Op. 16–19. But the majority
    nonetheless concludes in Part V that the BIA misinterpreted
    Matter of A-B-, requiring a remand to the agency.
    Part V is where the problem lies. The petitioner’s
    proposed social group of “indigenous women in Guatemala
    who are unable to leave their relationship” is virtually
    identical to the proposed social group in Matter of A-R-C-G-,
    which was “married women in Guatemala who are unable to
    leave their relationship.” The Attorney General in Matter of
    A-B- clearly determined that the latter group was “not
    cognizable.” 27 I. & N. Dec. at 334. Yet when the BIA
    then applied Matter of A-B- to petitioner’s materially
    indistinguishable proposed group, our court now tells the BIA
    it erred in not following Matter of A-B-.
    That holding is quite mistaken, turning on a misreading of
    Matter of A-B- and a related misunderstanding of the core
    principles of immigration law on which Matter of A-B- is
    premised. While today’s opinion might initially appear to
    reject a challenge to Matter of A-B- and narrowly remand on
    case-specific grounds, in reality that is not so. Instead, the
    court’s opinion improperly recasts Matter of A-B-, with
    widespread consequences for the many cases that today’s
    decision is sure to affect. The result is also that the federal
    immigration law that applies in this circuit will differ
    considerably from the law applied elsewhere in this country.
    A central problem with today’s opinion—and one of the
    reasons I fear it will engender confusion—is that the majority
    offers what I see as varying and inconsistent rationales for
    why the BIA erred. Each of those grounds for decision is
    50                 DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    incorrect and each reflects a noted departure from governing
    law.
    A
    1
    In articulating why a remand is required, the majority first
    explains that “[t]he BIA seems to have erroneously
    understood Matter of A-B- to forbid any mention of feared
    harm within a proposed social group.” Maj. Op. 19–20. The
    majority consequently “disagree[s]” that “in order to exist
    independently from the petitioner’s feared harm, a proposed
    group may not refer to that harm at all.” Id. at 23. This
    reflects legal error and departs from the decisions of our sister
    circuits. See, e.g., Gonzales-Veliz, 938 F.3d at 232 (holding
    that a proposed group of “Honduran women unable to leave
    their relationship” was not cognizable because it was “defined
    by, and d[id] not exist independently of, the harm—i.e., the
    inability to leave”).
    Simply stated, a proposed group that incorporates harm
    within its definition is not a group that “exist[s] independently
    of the harm asserted in an application for asylum or statutory
    withholding of removal.” Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec.
    at 334 (emphasis added) (quotations omitted). Recall that the
    overall framework requires an asylum or withholding
    applicant to prove three things: (1) the existence of a
    cognizable particular social group; (2) membership in that
    group; and (3) “a risk of persecution on account of” (or
    “because of”) “his membership.” Reyes, 842 F.3d at 1132 n.3
    (emphasis added).
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                     51
    Now imagine a proposed social group that is transparently
    based in part on the harm, such as “Guatemalan men who are
    harmed by gangs.” Saying that a petitioner was harmed by
    gangs based on his membership in the group “Guatemalan
    men who are harmed by gangs” would collapse the inquiries.
    And it would create the very circularity problem that Matter
    of A-B- sought to avoid in the domestic violence context,
    allowing nexus to be proven by the group definition itself.
    See Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 334 (citing, e.g.,
    Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 236 n.11, 243; Matter
    of W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 215). The majority thus errs in
    claiming that I “do not explain why a person seeking relief on
    the basis of membership in a particular social group should be
    required to omit any mention of threatened persecution.”
    Maj. Op. 28. The reason, as I have explained, is the anti-
    circularity principle.
    Contrary to the suggestion in the majority opinion, Matter
    of A-B- did not endorse the concept of a particular social
    group that references harm in its definition. Maj. Op. 23–25.
    Matter of A-B- in fact confirms that such a group is
    impermissible. Matter of A-B- expressly rejected the
    proposed social group in Matter of A-R-C-G-, which was
    “married women in Guatemala who are unable to leave their
    relationship.” Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 319. This
    proposed group obviously does contain some immutable
    characteristics not defined by the harm, namely, “married
    women in Guatemala.” But the Attorney General concluded
    the proposed social group still incorporated a reference to
    harm, because a claimed “inability to leave” was “effectively
    defined to consist of women in Guatemala who are victims of
    domestic abuse.” Id. at 335. For that reason, the group
    violated the anti-circularity principle and was “not
    cognizable.” Id. at 334.
    52                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    If referring to harm within the group definition were
    allowed, Matter of A-B- on this central point should have
    come out the other way. It is thus true, as the majority
    explains, that Matter of A-B- did not “identify a categorical
    ‘circularity problem.’” Maj. Op. 20 (emphasis added). But
    that is only because the anti-circularity rule had long existed
    in the law. Matter of A-B- thus did not “identify” and
    announce this rule, but it certainly applied it. Whether the
    anti-circularity rule applies is determined on a case-by-case
    basis by examining the proposed social group that an
    applicant brings forward. See Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec.
    at 340; Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 251. But
    when the rule does apply, it is, indeed, a categorical one.
    Matter of A-B-’s reliance on Rreshpja v. Gonzales,
    
    420 F.3d 551
     (6th Cir. 2005), only confirms this point. The
    Attorney General in Matter of A-B- specifically cited
    Rreshpja for the rule that “[t]he individuals in the group must
    share a narrowing characteristic other than their risk of being
    persecuted.” 27 I. & N. Dec. at 335 (alteration in original)
    (quoting Rreshpja, 
    420 F.3d at 556
    ). In Rreshpja, the court
    understood the proposed social group to be “young (or those
    who appear to be young), attractive Albanian women who are
    forced into prostitution.” 
    420 F.3d at 555
    . The Sixth Circuit
    rejected this group because “a social group may not be
    circularly defined by the fact that it suffers persecution.” 
    Id. at 556
     (emphasis added).
    The proposed particular social group in Rreshpja was not
    completely defined by the harm, but the court rejected it
    because it was still partially defined by the harm. 
    Id.
     The
    majority therefore gets Rreshpja backwards. Maj. Op. 23.
    The Attorney General in Matter of A-B- was not purporting
    to allow a group defined in part by the harm by relying on a
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                       53
    Sixth Circuit opinion that rejected a proposed social group
    that was itself partially defined by the harm, and that
    therefore suffered from the same problem as the proposed
    group in this case.
    Notably, both petitioner and her amicus agree with my
    interpretation of Matter of A-B-. Petitioner herself regards
    the “holding” of Matter of A-B- to be that a particular social
    group “cannot be defined, even in part, by the fact of
    persecution.” (Emphasis added). And amicus Center for
    Gender & Refugee Studies likewise agrees that under Matter
    of A-B-, the circularity rule “require[s] a group to be defined
    completely independently of the harm.” (Emphasis in
    original). Petitioner and the amicus both regard this as a new
    rule, but it is not. It is the same rule that has always applied:
    “[t]o be cognizable, a particular social group must exist
    independently of the harm asserted.” Matter of A-B-, 27
    I. & N. Dec. at 334 (emphasis in original) (quotations
    omitted); see also Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 236
    n.11.
    Unlike the majority, my interpretation of Matter of A-B-
    is also aligned with that of other circuits. The majority
    opinion “recognize[s] that, consistent with Matter of A-B-,
    numerous courts have deemed proposed social groups that
    referred to feared harm to be impermissibly circular.” Maj.
    Op. 31. The concession is well-taken. But it is, if anything,
    a considerable understatement, because other circuits have
    routinely denied petitions for review presenting materially
    identical proposed social groups to the one at issue here, that
    also referenced harm in the group definition itself.
    In Gonzales-Veliz v. Barr, 
    938 F.3d 219
     (5th Cir. 2019),
    the Fifth Circuit denied a petition for review seeking asylum
    54                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    and withholding of removal based on the proposed social
    group “Honduran women unable to leave their relationship.”
    Id. at 223. The Fifth Circuit explained that “under A-B-’s
    analysis, [this] group cannot constitute a particular social
    group” because “[t]he group is defined by, and does not exist
    independently of, the harm—i.e., the inability to leave.” Id.
    at 232. In other words, the Fifth Circuit held, this group was
    not cognizable because it was “impermissibly defined in a
    circular manner.” Id.
    Several months later, the Eleventh Circuit issued a similar
    decision in Amezcua-Preciado v. U.S. Attorney General, 
    943 F.3d 1337
     (11th Cir. 2019) (per curiam). There, the Eleventh
    Circuit denied a petition for review seeking relief based on
    the proposed social group “women in Mexico who are unable
    to leave their domestic relationships.” Id. at 1339. The
    Eleventh Circuit recognized that the petitioner’s “proposed
    social group suffers from the kinds of problems the Attorney
    General identified in A-B- as likely to render most groups of
    victims of private violence not cognizable.” Id. at 1344. And
    the Eleventh Circuit made clear that “to the extent [the
    petitioner’s] proposed group of Mexican women . . . are
    unable to leave their domestic relationships because they fear
    physical or psychological abuse by their spouse or domestic
    partner, this group is defined by the underlying harm
    asserted.” Id. at 1345. In reading Matter of A-B- to allow
    proposed social groups that include feared harm in the group
    definition, the majority departs from both the reasoning and
    the results of the Fifth and Eleventh Circuit decisions.
    Indeed, the majority’s decision is inconsistent with many
    cases from other circuits that have denied petitions for review
    that advanced proposed social groups materially identical to
    the one advanced here. See, e.g., Perez-Agustin v. U.S.
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                      55
    Attorney Gen., 798 F. App’x 608, 609 (11th Cir. 2020) (per
    curiam) (rejecting as impermissibly circular proposed social
    group of “indigenous women from Guatemala, who are native
    Mam speakers, who are victim[s] of sexual violence”)
    (alteration in original); Martinez Casco v. U.S. Attorney Gen.,
    800 F. App’x 835, 838 (11th Cir. 2020) (per curiam)
    (rejecting as impermissibly circular proposed social group of
    “female domestic violence victims who are unable to leave”);
    Serrano-de Portillo v. Barr, 792 F. App’x 341, 342–43 (5th
    Cir. 2020) (per curiam) (rejecting as impermissibly circular
    proposed social group of “El Salvadoran women targeted by
    gang members to be gang girlfriends”); Garcia-Ventura v.
    Barr, 788 F. App’x 969, 970–71 (5th Cir. 2019) (per curiam)
    (rejecting as impermissibly circular proposed social groups of
    “victims of domestic violence at the hands of their domestic
    partner and unable to leave their domestic partner” and
    “victims of domestic violence who are viewed as property by
    virtue of their positions within a domestic relationship”);
    Gonzalez-De Moreira v. U.S. Attorney Gen., 787 F. App’x
    659, 662 (11th Cir. 2019) (per curiam) (rejecting as
    impermissibly circular proposed social groups of “Salvadoran
    women who are victims of violence” and “Salvadoran
    children who are victims of violence”); Reyes v. Sessions,
    750 F. App’x 656, 659 (10th Cir. 2018) (rejecting as
    impermissibly circular proposed social group of “female
    victims of domestic violence”). Indeed, our court in an
    unpublished decision rejected as impermissibly circular a
    proposed group of “women who have been harassed and
    threatened by men and whose complaints to police have
    failed to result in protection,” because the group was “defined
    by the claimed persecutory conduct” and thus did “not exist
    56                    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    independently from the claimed persecution.” Calderon-
    Espejo v. Barr, 771 F. App’x 371, 372–73 (9th Cir. 2019).2
    The majority acknowledges this “plethora of unpublished
    decisions that rejected groups similar to the one advanced
    here,” but claims it “cannot discern the reasoning of those
    decisions simply from their outcome.” Maj. Op. 32 & n.9.
    Setting aside that the Fifth and Eleventh Circuits have
    rejected proposed social groups materially identical to the one
    here in published opinions, see Amezcua-Preciado, 943 F.3d
    at 1345; Gonzales-Veliz, 938 F.3d at 232, the numerous
    unpublished decisions reaching the same result easily reveal
    their straightforward reasoning: the proposed group in each
    case failed because it included a reference to harm, thus
    presenting the circularity issue.
    The groups in these cases were defined in part by
    immutable characteristics that were separate and apart from
    2
    Even before Matter of A-B-, courts also routinely rejected proposed
    social groups as circular if they referred to alleged harm or persecution.
    See e.g., Soto-Ambrocio v. Sessions, 724 F. App’x 456, 458 (6th Cir.
    2018) (per curiam) (rejecting as impermissibly circular proposed social
    group of “young women from Guatemala subject to abuse from families”);
    Moreno v. Lynch, 628 F. App’x 862, 865 (4th Cir. 2015) (rejecting as
    impermissibly circular proposed social group of “Hondurans who have
    been targeted by the police and their criminal associates to engage in drug
    trafficking”); Rreshpja, 
    420 F.3d at
    555–56 (rejecting as impermissibly
    circular proposed social group of “young (or those who appear to be
    young), attractive Albanian women who are forced into prostitution”).
    The majority is thus not correct that the government and this dissent (and
    by implication, the other circuits) “confuse the definition of a ‘particular
    social group’ with one of its components—i.e., the group’s shared
    immutable characteristic.” Maj. Op. 27. The requirement that a proposed
    social group exist independent of the harm is its own separate
    requirement. Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 236 n.11.
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                                57
    the harm, such as women from a certain country. But they
    were also defined in part by an “inability to leave” or some
    similar formulation that was regarded as a reference to harm.
    Unlike today’s opinion, however, none of these cases treated
    the BIA decisions on review as having “erroneously
    understood Matter of A-B- to forbid any mention of feared
    harm within a proposed social group.” Maj. Op. 19–20.
    Instead, they treated the “mention” of that harm as a
    dispositive violation of the longstanding anti-circularity
    principle.3
    2
    The majority gives two primary reasons for departing
    from the case law of other circuits and allowing proposed
    3
    The majority is correct that the D.C. Circuit recently stated (in a case
    challenging a policy memorandum not at issue here) that the notion that
    “the group must be ‘separate’ from the harm, not consisting of the harm,
    even in part,” is “flatly inconsistent” with Matter of A-B-. Grace v. Barr,
    — F.3d —, 
    2020 WL 4032652
    , at *16 (D.C. Cir. 2020). However, the
    D.C. Circuit premised this point on an asserted government concession as
    to whether the phrase “inability to leave” could be a reference to
    something other than harm, 
    id.,
     which is a different issue (the majority
    addresses this issue in its Part V.C and I address it in Part II.C below). In
    Grace, the D.C. Circuit held that the policy memorandum at issue there
    correctly stated the “circularity rule” as set forth in Matter of A-B-. 
    Id.
    The court described the “circularity rule” as requiring that “social groups
    must ‘exist independently’ of the harm claimed by the applicant, that is,
    the applicant must be able to establish the group’s existence ‘without
    defining [it] by the fact of persecution.’” Id. at *14 (quoting Matter of
    A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 334) (alteration in original). To the extent Grace
    “endorsed the view that a proposed social group is not disqualified if it
    includes mention of feared persecution” as the majority claims, Maj. Op.
    29, the D.C. Circuit offered no explanation for this point, which is both
    incorrect and against the weight of authority applying Matter of A-B-, as
    detailed in this dissent.
    58                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    social groups that include a reference to harm.          Both
    rationales fail as a matter of law.
    First, the majority holds that a proposed social group
    definition can include a reference to harm because
    “persecution may be relevant to a group’s social distinction.”
    Maj. Op. 20; see also id. at 23–24. This reflects a
    misunderstanding of BIA precedent and the conflation of two
    independent requirements for a “particular social group” to be
    cognizable: (1) that the group exist independent of the harm
    and (2) that it be socially distinct in the relevant society.
    These are different requirements. Indeed, in explaining the
    “social distinction” element, the BIA in Matter of M-E-V-G-
    pointed out that while “the social group must exist
    independently of the fact of persecution,” this is a separate
    criterion from “social distinction.” Matter of M-E-V-G-,
    26 I. & N. Dec. at 236 n.11.
    The majority dismisses this as “mechanistic[],” Maj. Op.
    27, but these separate requirements perform meaningful
    analytical work. It is certainly true that persecution can be
    used to demonstrate that a proposed group is “socially
    distinct.” As the BIA has explained, “[t]he act of persecution
    by the government may be the catalyst that causes the society
    to distinguish [a proposed social group] in a meaningful way
    and consider [it] a distinct group.” Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I.
    & N. Dec. at 243. But this does not mean that the definition
    of the group itself can include the harm. Why? Because the
    entire reason the group “must exist independently of the harm
    asserted,” Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 334 (emphasis
    in original) (quotations omitted), is to avoid the circularity
    problem that would otherwise allow petitioners automatically
    to fulfill the separate nexus requirement by injecting the harm
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                     59
    itself into the very definition of the group whose membership
    is supposedly causing the persecution.
    The majority’s hypotheticals only prove this point. Maj.
    Op. 25–26. The first one, used in Matter of M-E-V-G-,
    consists of the proposed particular social group “former
    employees of a country’s attorney general.” Matter of
    M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 242. The second hypothetical
    is found in United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees
    (UNHCR) Guidelines and involves the proposed social group
    of left-handed men. UNHCR, Guidelines on International
    Protection, ¶ 14, U.N. Doc. HCR/GIP/02/02 (May 7, 2002)
    [hereinafter UNHCR Guidelines]. Critically, unlike the
    proposed social group in this case, neither hypothetical
    involves a proposed group defined in any way by the harm
    itself.
    But though the fact of persecution does not define the
    group, these hypotheticals show that the harm may
    permissibly be used to show the group is socially distinct in
    the relevant society. Take “former employees of a country’s
    attorney general” as an example. As the BIA explained,
    “[a]lthough such a shared past experience is immutable and
    the group is sufficiently discrete, the employees may not
    consider themselves a separate group within the society.”
    Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 242. But if “the
    government begins persecuting them,” “[u]pon their
    mistreatment, it is possible that these people would
    experience a sense of ‘group,’ and society would discern that
    this group of individuals, who share a common immutable
    characteristic, is distinct in some significant way.” Id.
    at 242–43.
    60                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    That is consistent with the anti-circularity principle,
    because while “[t]he act of persecution by the government
    may be the catalyst that causes the society to distinguish the
    former employees in a meaningful way and consider them a
    distinct group,” “the immutable characteristic of their shared
    past experience exists independent of the persecution.” Id.
    at 243 (emphasis added). The UNHCR made the same point
    about its “[l]eft-handed men” hypothetical: the group would
    still be defined by “the attribute of being left-handed and not
    the persecutory acts.” UNHCR Guidelines ¶ 14 (emphasis
    added).
    The majority’s two hypotheticals thus demonstrate the
    very analytical distinction the majority sweeps aside. Just
    because persecution may show that a group is socially distinct
    does not mean the group itself can be defined in some way by
    that persecution. The majority apparently suggests it would
    create no issue to define the hypothetical group of “former
    employees of the attorney general” as “former employees of
    the attorney general, who are being hunted down and killed.”
    Maj. Op. 26. But that is exactly the type of group courts have
    routinely rejected under the anti-circularity principle. See
    ante at 53–56 & n.2. The majority is thus incorrect in
    suggesting that I overlook that BIA precedent “unequivocally
    establishes that a group’s persecution may be relevant to” the
    social distinction requirement. Maj. Op. 27. Persecution is
    relevant to the requirement of social distinction, as I have
    explained. But that does not mean groups can include in their
    definitions a reference to harm, contrary to the separate
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                               61
    requirement that the group exist independent of the harm.
    See, e.g., Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 236 n.11.4
    Second, and relying on snippets of language in BIA
    decisions, the majority holds that a particular social group can
    include harm in its definition because “[t]he BIA [has]
    explained that a ‘social group cannot be defined exclusively
    by the fact that it is targeted for persecution.’” Maj. Op. 21
    (quoting Matter of C-A-, 
    23 I. & N. Dec. 951
    , 960 (BIA 2006)
    (emphasis in original)). The majority quotes other BIA
    decisions that use this “exclusively” language, but these
    decisions in turn rely on the BIA’s earlier opinion in Matter
    of C-A-. See 
    id.
     at 21–22, 31.
    The majority’s reliance on “exclusively” is not correct.
    That a proposed social group cannot be defined “exclusively”
    by the harm does not somehow mean it could then be based
    in part on the harm. If that were true, Matter of A-B-—which
    rejected a proposed social group that was not based
    exclusively on the harm—would have come out the other way
    on this critical issue. And if the only limit was that a group
    cannot be based “exclusively” on the harm, there would have
    4
    The majority’s hypothetical of Tutsis fleeing Rwanda is inapt. Maj.
    Op. 28–29. There, the proposed social group would be defined based on
    ethnicity, not harm. See Donchev v. Mukasey, 
    553 F.3d 1206
    , 1220 (9th
    Cir. 2009). A person who experienced genocide based on ethnicity would
    have no reason to define his proposed social group by including the harm
    in the group definition itself. Petitioner here, by contrast, had
    understandable strategic reasons to try that approach here, as I explain
    below. The majority is correct that the anti-circularity rule is not specific
    to the domestic violence context. But that makes the majority’s departure
    from the rule more problematic, not less. Under the majority’s approach,
    the many cases that have rejected proposed social groups that referenced
    harm were all wrongly decided on this point.
    62                 DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    been no reason for the BIA repeatedly to articulate the
    principle that the group “must exist independently of the harm
    asserted.” Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 334 (emphasis
    altered) (quotations omitted); Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N.
    Dec. at 236 n.11. Indeed, cases the majority cites that use the
    “exclusively” formulation also state the rule that the group
    must exist independent of the harm. See Maj. Op. 22 n.5
    (citing Perez-Rabanales, 881 F.3d at 67; Paloka, 762 F.3d
    at 196).
    I suppose it is possible to imagine a proposed social group
    that is defined “exclusively” by harm (e.g., “victims of
    physical assaults”). But most proposed social groups that
    have the circularity problem are defined in part by the harm
    and in part by something else, such as gender or nationality.
    There is nothing in the BIA’s precedent suggesting it did not
    intend those proposed social groups to come within the anti-
    circularity principle, whose logic clearly extends to them. To
    the contrary, the BIA’s formulation—“must exist
    independently”—ensures that groups defined in part by the
    harm are not allowed.
    The origins of the “exclusively” phrasing also
    demonstrate it was not intended to operate in the way the
    majority uses it, i.e., implicitly to allow groups defined in part
    by the harm. As noted, this “exclusively” language can be
    traced to the BIA’s decision in Matter of C-A-. But there, the
    BIA stated that “the [UNHCR] Guidelines state that ‘a social
    group cannot be defined exclusively by the fact that it is
    targeted for persecution,’” although “persecutory action
    toward a group may be a relevant factor in determining the
    visibility of a group in a particular society.” Matter of C-A-,
    23 I. & N. Dec. at 960 (emphasis in original) (quoting
    UNHCR Guidelines ¶¶ 2, 14).
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                       63
    The quoted language drives home the distinction that the
    majority elides, which is that persecution can be relevant for
    social distinction (previously known as social visibility), but
    not for the definition of the group itself. The quoted language
    also shows that the majority is misusing the “exclusively”
    phrasing on its own terms. The BIA in Matter of C-A- used
    this language when quoting the UNHCR Guidelines, which
    I discussed earlier. Matter of C-A-, 23 I. & N. Dec. at 960.
    And these Guidelines likewise make clear that a group cannot
    be defined in part by the harm.
    In the Guidelines, the UNHCR used the left-handed men
    hypothetical to show that persecution can be relevant to what
    we now call social distinction. UNHCR Guidelines ¶ 14; see
    Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 228. But the
    UNHCR made clear that in that circumstance, “it would be
    the attribute of being left-handed and not the persecutory acts
    that would identify them as a particular social group.”
    UNHCR Guidelines ¶ 14. That is a rejection of the majority’s
    view that a group can be defined in part by the harm.
    The majority opinion is thus incorrect in claiming that I
    “ignore the word ‘exclusively’—along with similar limiting
    language in the BIA’s decisions and those from our sister
    circuits.” Maj. Op. 24. Instead, as the extensive discussion
    above confirms, it is the majority that is incorrectly using the
    “exclusively” formulation in service of authorizing groups
    that refer to harm, contrary to other circuits that have
    addressed substantially identical proposed social groups.
    B
    Equally mistaken is the majority’s suggestion that the
    BIA erred in this case because it is possible to bracket out a
    64                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    reference to harm in the definition of a proposed social group
    in considering whether petitioner has put forward an
    “otherwise cognizable” group. Maj. Op. 21–22, 27, 39–40;
    see also id. at 20 (“If a group is otherwise cognizable, Matter
    of A-B- does not demand that it be devoid of any reference to
    an applicant’s claimed persecution.”) (emphasis added). The
    majority’s analysis suggests that we may consider some
    elements of a proffered social group as relevant to the
    immutable characteristic inquiry, consider other elements for
    their relevance to social distinction, and do so without
    impermissibly rewriting the petitioner’s proposed social
    group. See Maj. Op. 27–28.
    That is not correct. I am aware of no case, and the
    majority cites none, that would allow a court (or the BIA) to
    take a petitioner’s proposed social group, break it down into
    constituent elements, and then assign those elements out to
    the distinct requirements that a petitioner must meet to
    demonstrate a cognizable social group. In my respectful
    view, that is not how this area of law works.
    BIA precedent is clear that the agency must evaluate the
    proposed social group exactly as the petitioner has defined it.
    In precedent the majority cites, Maj. Op. 27, 28, 39 n.12, the
    BIA has held that “[w]here an applicant raises membership in
    a particular social group as the enumerated ground that is the
    basis of her claim, she has the burden to clearly indicate ‘the
    exact delineation of any particular social group(s) to which
    she claims to belong.’” Matter of W-Y-C- & H-O-B-, 
    27 I. & N. Dec. 189
    , 191 (BIA 2018) (quoting Matter of A-T-, 
    25 I. & N. Dec. 4
    , 10 (BIA 2009)). The Immigration Judge (IJ) must
    then analyze “the specific group” identified, and “[i]f an
    applicant is not clear as to the exact delineation of the
    proposed social group, the Immigration Judge should seek
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                      65
    clarification.” 
    Id.
     On appeal, the BIA may only consider the
    specific proposed social group that the petitioner presented to
    the IJ. 
    Id.
     at 191–92.
    These various requirements are not empty formalities.
    Instead, they follow from the fact that a petitioner bears the
    burden of proof in demonstrating “the existence of a
    cognizable particular social group” and persecution because
    of her membership in that group. Reyes, 842 F.3d at 1132 n.3
    (quoting Matter of W-G-R-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 223); see also
    Cantarero-Lagos v. Barr, 
    924 F.3d 145
    , 151 (5th Cir. 2019)
    (“Requiring asylum and withholding applicants to delineate
    their [particular social group] to an IJ is simply a logical
    extension of this burden of proof.”).
    Requiring the petitioner to delineate her proposed social
    groups has important practical benefits as well. It ensures
    that appropriate fact-finding is conducted at the IJ level.
    Matter of W-Y-C- & H-O-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 191;
    Cantarero-Lagos, 924 F.3d at 152. And it creates a “rational
    administrative process” that allows the government to
    respond to a petitioner’s proposed social group, while
    preventing repeated remands to the IJ. Cantarero-Lagos,
    924 F.3d at 152.
    Consistent with this scheme, we have repeatedly
    determined that we lack jurisdiction to consider a new or
    different proposed social group that the petitioner did not
    present to the agency. See, e.g., Lozano Fuerte v. Barr,
    804 F. App’x 742, 742–43 (9th Cir. 2020); Nesta-Najar v.
    Barr, 804 F. App’x 604, 606 (9th Cir. 2020); Perez Perez v.
    Barr, 804 F. App’x 597, 598 (9th Cir. 2020); Vasquez-Leon
    v. Barr, 804 F. App’x 612, 613 (9th Cir. 2020); Romero-
    Castro v. Barr, 790 F. App’x 64, 65 (9th Cir. 2020); Lopez-
    66                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    Velasquez v. Sessions, 742 F. App’x 195, 196 n.1 (9th Cir.
    2018).
    The majority agrees that “courts cannot rewrite proposed
    social groups.” Maj. Op. 27. But the majority’s suggestion
    that we or the BIA can splice out elements of a proposed
    group and consider them for some, but not other purposes, is
    inconsistent with established precedent and practice. The
    same can be said of petitioner’s analogous suggestion that we
    should “look[] beyond the language used to describe [her]
    proposed social group.” (Emphasis added). Petitioners can
    propose multiple and alternative particular social groups to
    the agency; many petitioners do so. E.g., Honcharov v. Barr,
    
    924 F.3d 1293
    , 1295 (9th Cir. 2019) (per curiam). But under
    the authority set forth above, we cannot take a petitioner’s
    proposed group and alter it. Indeed, the very idea that there
    are severable elements in the proposed social group is
    misplaced. There are no such elements; there is only the
    proposed group.
    By the same token, if we subtract one element (here
    “inability to leave”), we likewise create a different group than
    the one the petitioner articulated. Tellingly, in none of the
    cases cited above denying petitions with similar proposed
    groups to the one here did the courts proceed to consider a
    version of the proposed group minus the impermissibly
    circular reference to the harm. Nor did those courts remand
    to the BIA with instructions to do this. The majority opinion
    thus fails to recognize that the definition of the proposed
    group—as the petitioner has defined it—is central to how this
    entire scheme works.
    The majority errs in suggesting it can refashion
    petitioner’s proposed group because “[t]he BIA has taken
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                      67
    pains to state that ‘the shared trait of persecution does not
    disqualify an otherwise valid social group.’” Maj. Op. 24
    (quoting Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 243). The
    BIA in Matter of M-E-V-G- was not implying that if a group
    is defined to include the harm, that the BIA (or a court) could
    carve out the reference to harm to produce an “otherwise
    valid social group.” Instead, the BIA said that if the
    petitioner had come forward with an “otherwise valid social
    group,” using the fact of persecution to demonstrate the social
    distinction requirement would not invalidate the group.
    Matter of M-E-V-G-, 26 I. & N. Dec. at 243.
    Equally mistaken is the majority’s assertion that the
    Attorney General in Matter of A-B- “faulted the BIA[]” in
    Matter of A-R-C-G- for not considering the petitioner’s
    proposed social group without its reference to harm. Maj.
    Op. 29. In Matter of A-B-, the Attorney General was
    certainly not instructing the BIA to ignore a reference to harm
    and to come up with an “otherwise cognizable” social group
    using some of the other characteristics the petitioner brought
    forth.
    To the contrary, when the Attorney General in Matter of
    A-B- faulted the BIA in Matter of A-R-C-G- for “avoid[ing]
    considering whether [the petitioner] could establish the
    existence of a cognizable particular social group without
    defining the group by the fact of persecution,” it was because
    the government in Matter of A-R-C-G- “conceded” that the
    petitioner there was a member of a cognizable social group.
    Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 334. The BIA’s error in
    Matter of A-R-C-G- was in accepting that concession without
    any further inquiry. Id. And had the BIA “properly analyzed
    the issues,” Matter of A-B- went on, it would have been “clear
    that the particular social group was not cognizable.” Id.
    68                 DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    (emphasis added). As a result, whether petitioner here
    included an “inability to leave” in her proposed group by
    mistake or not, it is part of the group as she has defined it, and
    such a group is not valid under the anti-circularity principle.
    Id. at 334–35.
    Of course, it is highly doubtful that the petitioner’s
    inclusion of “unable to leave” in her group definition was a
    mistake. Had petitioner omitted this phrase, and advanced
    only the remaining portions of her proposed group
    (“indigenous women in Guatemala”), that may have made it
    more difficult for her to meet other requirements for a
    particular social group, most notably “particularity” and
    “social distinction.” As the First Circuit recently recognized,
    the inclusion of “‘unable to leave’ in the group definition”
    was likely a response to “[s]ome case law [that] gave rise to
    a fear that ‘women,’ or ‘women in country X,’ or even
    ‘women in a domestic relationship,’ might be too large or too
    indistinct a group to serve as a particular social group.” De
    Pena-Paniagua v. Barr, 
    957 F.3d 88
    , 95 (1st Cir. 2020)
    (collecting cases); see also Matter of A-B-, 27. I. & N. Dec.
    at 336 (explaining that applicants sought “to avoid
    particularity issues by defining a narrow class—such as
    ‘Guatemalan women who are unable to leave their domestic
    relationships where they have children in common’”).
    In fact, it was Matter of A-R-C-G-—the very case that
    Matter of A-B- overruled—that “held out ‘unable to leave’ as
    a supposedly smaller, better-suited safe harbor for women
    seeking asylum and withholding of removal.” De Pena-
    Paniagua, 957 F.3d at 95. In other words, the petitioner here
    almost certainly defined her proposed social group as she did
    to match what the BIA in Matter of A-R-C-G- then regarded
    as cognizable. The problem is that the Attorney General has
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                       69
    since overruled Matter of A-R-C-G- and held “that the
    particular social group [there] was not cognizable.” Matter
    of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 334.
    In short, the majority’s suggestion that we can ignore the
    petitioner’s reference to harm in her proposed social group is
    contrary to settled law. The same is true of the majority’s
    determination that we can extract the reference to harm from
    the definition of the group and treat is as relevant only to the
    social distinction requirement. Today’s decision breaks new
    ground in suggesting that any of this is permissible.
    C
    The majority’s analysis in Parts V.A–B treated a
    reference to harm in the definition of a proposed social group
    as permissible under Matter of A-B-. In Part V.C, the
    majority concludes that the BIA erred in dismissing
    petitioner’s appeal because the BIA “assumed her inability to
    leave her relationship was attributable to domestic violence,”
    when “[t]here are many reasons a petitioner might be unable
    to leave a relationship, including a variety of cultural,
    societal, religious, economic, or other factors.” Maj. Op.
    33–34, 34 n.11 (quotations omitted). The majority holds that
    the BIA “avoided the case-specific inquiry demanded by
    Matter of A-B-” and failed to “carefully analyze[]”
    petitioner’s claim because it “assumed that domestic violence
    was the only reason [petitioner] was unable to leave her
    relationship.” Id. at 33–34, 36.
    I will explain why this is mistaken momentarily. But it is
    first important to point out that this rationale is inconsistent
    with the rationales in Parts V.A–B. The import of Part V.C
    is that if “inability to leave” were based on the harm, the BIA
    70                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    could have denied petitioner’s appeal on this basis as
    impermissibly circular. By the logic of this rationale, the
    problem instead is that here “inability to leave” may not be
    based on harm but on other factors, and the BIA erred by not
    considering that possibility.
    But if a particular social group can reference harm in the
    group definition, then a remand for the reasons given in Part
    V.C is unnecessary. Under Parts V.A–B of the majority
    opinion, the BIA should be instructed to treat the proposed
    group as written as non-circular and to analyze the group only
    for its compliance with the other requirements (e.g.,
    particularity and social distinction). If the BIA can just
    ignore the reference to harm in the proposed group (as a
    mistake or otherwise) and treat it as relevant only to social
    distinction or some other requirement, there is no reason for
    the BIA to now consider whether “inability to leave” may be
    a reference to something other than the harm alleged.
    Instead, the BIA should be instructed to excise “inability to
    leave” and consider whether the proposed social group is
    “otherwise cognizable.”
    Or we can think of it this way: imagine the BIA had not
    made the supposed error that the majority identifies in Part
    V.C of its opinion and had even more explicitly regarded
    “inability to leave” as based on harm. In that circumstance,
    wouldn’t the BIA still have erred under Parts V.A–B of the
    majority opinion? The answer apparently is “yes,” because
    the majority says that one of the “problems with the BIA’s
    reasoning” below is that “the BIA misunderstood Matter of
    A-B-’s holding.” Maj. Op. 33. That reasoning would seem to
    necessitate a remand separate and apart from any particular
    arguments petitioner may have advanced to the BIA about
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                      71
    whether her “inability to leave” was based on something
    other than domestic violence. Id. at 33.
    Regardless, the majority is wrong to hold the BIA erred
    by “assum[ing]” that petitioner’s “inability to leave her
    relationship was attributable to domestic violence” and
    “avoid[ing] the case-specific inquiry demanded by Matter of
    A-B- and the BIA’s precedents.” Maj. Op. 33, 36. Petitioner
    herself recognizes in her opening brief that in Matter of A-B-,
    the Attorney General “specifically rejected the applicant’s
    proposed social group of ‘El Salvadoran women who are
    unable to leave their domestic relationships where they have
    children in common with their partners.’” (Emphasis added).
    Applying Matter of A-B-, which the court today upholds
    under Chevron, the BIA here simply considered petitioner’s
    specific articulation of her proposed social group under the
    governing standards.
    The BIA recognized that the petitioner’s proposed social
    group was “substantially similar to the group in Matter of
    A-R-C-G-.” The BIA at this point cited and incorporated the
    decision of the IJ, which made clear that the entire basis for
    petitioner’s proposed social group was her fear of domestic
    violence. For this reason, the BIA could (and did) determine
    that as in Matter of A-B-, “inability to leave” here was
    “effectively defined to consist of women . . . who are victims
    of domestic abuse because the inability ‘to leave’ was created
    by harm or threatened harm.” Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec.
    at 334; see also Larita-Martinez v. INS, 
    220 F.3d 1092
    , 1096
    (9th Cir. 2000) (explaining “the presumption” that the BIA
    “did review the evidence”).
    The BIA thus concluded that—because petitioner’s group
    definition contained the same “inability to leave”
    72                DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    reference—it “suffer[ed] from the same circularity problem
    articulated by the Attorney General in Matter of A-B-.” This
    was not a “shortcut[],” as the majority claims, Maj. Op. 33,
    but an application of Matter of A-B- of the type that has been
    routinely affirmed in other circuits. Nor did the BIA offer a
    “one-sentence analysis,” as the majority claims. Maj. Op. 32.
    The BIA opinion devoted several paragraphs to this issue and
    also incorporated two pages of the IJ’s decision.
    The majority is thus incorrect in asserting that the BIA
    here “committed the very same error it made in Matter of A-
    B-.” Maj. Op. 35. Again, the fatal misstep identified in
    Matter of A-B- was that the BIA in Matter of A-R-C-G- relied
    on concessions to hold a similar proposed group was
    cognizable. Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N. Dec. at 334. In
    contrast, the BIA here did the opposite of what the BIA did in
    Matter of A-R-C-G-, because here it evaluated petitioner’s
    proposed social group under the longstanding anti-circularity
    principle that Matter of A-B- reaffirmed. It is hard to
    understand why the BIA was required to say more when
    petitioner’s claim clearly failed for a specific reason. As the
    Fifth Circuit explained in denying a petition with a materially
    identical proposed social group to the one here, “[a]s an
    adjudicatory body, the BIA necessarily relies on established
    precedents to decide matters pending before it and to avoid
    re-inventing the wheel every time.” Gonzales-Veliz, 938 F.3d
    at 232. And the “BIA did not blindly apply A-B- as a
    categorical ban” when “A-B-’s substantive reasoning
    happened to squarely foreclose [the petitioner’s] group.” Id.
    Of course, even allowing that the vague phrase “unable to
    leave” could be based on something other than harm (such as
    cultural factors), I am hard-pressed to understand how the
    BIA was supposed to derive that nuance from petitioner’s
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                      73
    brief to the BIA. Relying on Matter of A-R-C-G-, petitioner’s
    counseled brief in the BIA argued that the proposed social
    group “‘married women in Guatemala who are unable to
    leave their relationship’ may share an immutable trait, where
    specific facts demonstrated a woman’s inability to leave her
    abusive marriage.” (Emphasis added). Petitioner’s brief to
    the BIA then discussed the “repugnant abuse” and “weekly
    beatings” at issue in Matter of A-R-C-G- and compared them
    to petitioner’s own experience, explaining that petitioner
    “[s]imilarly” “demonstrated that she suffered deplorable harm
    and abuse by her ‘common law’ husband.” Contrary to the
    majority opinion, the BIA thus did not “pluck[] one fact
    identified by [petitioner]—that her husband physically abused
    her.” Maj. Op. 35. This abuse was the central thrust of
    petitioner’s entire submission to the BIA.
    The majority opinion nevertheless states that the
    petitioner “advanced evidence of economic, societal, and
    cultural factors that also may have prevented her from leaving
    her relationship.” Maj. Op. 34. But what the majority cites
    for this are pages from the petitioner’s brief to the IJ, which
    extensively discuss how the “inability to leave” is based on
    domestic violence. To the extent petitioner and her expert
    cited societal and cultural factors in Guatemala before the IJ,
    they repeatedly intermixed them with domestic violence
    itself. In other words, petitioner’s own application thus
    specifically wove domestic violence into its identification of
    the proposed group, at a time when Matter of A-R-C-G- was
    the prevailing BIA precedent. But in all events, petitioner
    certainly did not present “inability to leave” as a concept
    distinct from the harm itself. And presenting the proposed
    group in that way would likely have created problems for
    other aspects of petitioner’s required showing, such as social
    distinction and nexus.
    74                    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    Under all these circumstances, I cannot fault the BIA for
    not divining an interpretation of “inability to leave” that
    petitioner did not clearly advance. On this point, this court
    reviews denials of withholding of removal “for substantial
    evidence.” Yali Wang v. Sessions, 
    861 F.3d 1003
    , 1007 (9th
    Cir. 2017) (quotations omitted). “Under the substantial
    evidence standard, the court upholds the BIA’s determination
    unless the evidence in the record compels a contrary
    conclusion.” Arteaga v. Mukasey, 
    511 F.3d 940
    , 944 (9th Cir.
    2007). Given the (at best) imprecise nature of the phrase
    “inability to leave” and the record in this case, I cannot
    conclude that the BIA’s assessment that the proposed social
    group was effectively defined by the harm lacks substantial
    evidence.5
    Finally, the majority errs in premising its own remand on
    the BIA’s remand in Matter of A-B-. According to the
    majority, “the best indication that [mention of physical abuse]
    does not categorically disqualify [petitioner’s] social group is
    that the Attorney General remanded Matter of A-B- for the
    BIA to conduct a proper analysis, . . . [r]ather than simply
    invalidating th[e] group.” Maj. Op. 35. This is not correct.
    5
    The majority relies on De Pena-Paniagua v. Barr, 957 F.3d at 94,
    for the proposition that “[t]here are many reasons a petitioner might be
    unable to leave a relationship, including a variety of ‘cultural, societal,
    religious, economic, or other factors.’” Maj. Op. 34 n.11. But for this
    observation, the First Circuit cited Matter of A-R-C-G-, see De Pena-
    Paniagua, 957 F.3d at 94, which the Attorney General of course overruled
    in Matter of A-B-. In all events, De Pena-Paniagua theorized that “a
    woman’s inability to leave a relationship may be the product of forces
    other than physical abuse.” Id. at 93. The question in this case is whether
    the record supports such a characterization of the proposed social group.
    For the reasons set forth above, the record does not compel the conclusion
    that the BIA erred in construing the petitioner’s proposed group in the way
    that it did.
    DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR                       75
    The Attorney General in Matter of A-B- was unequivocal that
    “[h]ad the [BIA] properly analyzed the issues” in Matter of A-
    R-C-G-, “then it would have been clear that the particular
    social group was not cognizable.” Matter of A-B-, 27 I. & N.
    Dec. at 334 (emphasis added). The Attorney General in
    Matter of A-B- was therefore not somehow suggesting that
    the BIA in any further proceedings that may occur in Matter
    of A-B- itself could somehow treat as cognizable the very
    proposed social group that Matter of A-B- expressly rejected.
    The standard remand language in Matter of A-B- “for further
    proceedings consistent with this opinion,” id. at 346, should
    thus not be construed as a basis for our court to remand a
    petition where the BIA complied with Matter of A-B-.
    *    *    *
    In upholding the Attorney General’s decision in Matter of
    A-B-, we should have faithfully interpreted it. And in
    reviewing the BIA’s decision applying Matter of A-B- to
    petitioner’s application, we should have recognized the BIA’s
    adherence to an Attorney General decision that is itself based
    on longstanding precedent and at the very least reasonable.
    The Attorney General in Matter of A-B- emphasized that
    under the INA, claims for asylum and withholding of removal
    based on domestic violence “are unlikely to satisfy the
    statutory grounds for proving group persecution.” 27 I. & N.
    Dec. at 320. Today’s decision does not directly quarrel with
    that understanding, but it sets forth an internally inconsistent
    analytical framework that is at odds with it, and also at odds
    with how other circuits have handled this issue.
    Where all of this will lead is uncertain. The majority’s
    opinion remands this case “for further consideration” so the
    BIA can conduct a “case-specific inquiry” under “the
    76                 DIAZ-REYNOSO V. BARR
    required framework.” Maj. Op. 37, 39, 40. The BIA can be
    forgiven if it finds this directive unclear. The only certainty
    is that these issues will be before us again, as the BIA tries to
    comply with both Matter of A-B- and today’s ruling. I
    respectfully dissent.
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 18-72833

Filed Date: 8/7/2020

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 8/7/2020

Authorities (26)

Immigration & Naturalization Service v. Cardoza-Fonseca , 107 S. Ct. 1207 ( 1987 )

Mayo Foundation for Medical Education & Research v. United ... , 131 S. Ct. 704 ( 2011 )

Francisco Ornelas-Chavez v. Alberto R. Gonzales, Attorney ... , 458 F.3d 1052 ( 2006 )

Immigration & Naturalization Service v. Aguirre-Aguirre , 119 S. Ct. 1439 ( 1999 )

Judulang v. Holder , 132 S. Ct. 476 ( 2011 )

Chevron U. S. A. Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Council, ... , 104 S. Ct. 2778 ( 1984 )

Cole v. Holder , 659 F.3d 762 ( 2011 )

Jose Guadalupe Larita-Martinez v. Immigration and ... , 220 F.3d 1092 ( 2000 )

Rosmery Andia Amilcar E. Torrez v. John Ashcroft, Attorney ... , 359 F.3d 1181 ( 2004 )

Li Chen Zheng, AKA Zheng Li Chen v. John Ashcroft, Attorney ... , 332 F.3d 1186 ( 2003 )

Go v. Holder , 640 F.3d 1047 ( 2011 )

Sarhan v. Holder , 658 F.3d 649 ( 2011 )

Navaratwam Kamalthas v. Immigration and Naturalization ... , 251 F.3d 1279 ( 2001 )

Arteaga v. Mukasey , 511 F.3d 940 ( 2007 )

Bernard Lukwago A/K/A Melvin Haft v. John Ashcroft, ... , 329 F.3d 157 ( 2003 )

Ernesto Adolfo Recinos De Leon v. Alberto Gonzales, ... , 400 F.3d 1185 ( 2005 )

Vitore Rreshpja v. Alberto Gonzales, Attorney General of ... , 420 F.3d 551 ( 2005 )

Diego F. Castillo-Arias v. U.S. Attorney General , 446 F.3d 1190 ( 2006 )

Victor E. Sepulveda v. Alberto R. Gonzales , 464 F.3d 770 ( 2006 )

Eunice Oritsegbeyiwa Azanor v. John Ashcroft, United States ... , 364 F.3d 1013 ( 2004 )

View All Authorities »