Gilead Tenofovir Cases ( 2024 )


Menu:
  • Filed 2/1/24 (unmodified opn. attached)
    CERTIFIED FOR PUBLICATION
    IN THE COURT OF APPEAL OF THE STATE OF CALIFORNIA
    FIRST APPELLATE DISTRICT
    DIVISION FOUR
    GILEAD TENOFOVIR CASES
    GILEAD LIFE SCIENCES, INC.,
    Petitioner,                                 A165558
    v.
    (San Francisco City & County
    THE SUPERIOR COURT OF THE                          Super. Ct. No. CJC-19-005043,
    CITY AND COUNTY OF SAN                             JCCP No. 5043)
    FRANCISCO,
    Respondent;                                 ORDER MODIFYING
    OPINION AND DENYING
    REHEARING
    [NO CHANGE IN
    PLAINTIFFS IN JCCP NO. 5043,
    JUDGMENT]
    Real Parties in Interest.
    THE COURT:
    It is ordered that the opinion filed herein on January 9, 2024, be
    modified as follows.
    1.     On page 11, delete the text of footnote 4 and replace it with the
    following text:
    Gilead cites some evidence in the summary judgment record that
    it contends supports its rebuttal of plaintiffs’ factual allegations,
    whereas plaintiffs contend that evidence they submitted in
    opposition to the summary judgment motion supports them.
    However, Gilead did not seek summary judgment on the ground
    that undisputed evidence established that it lacked actual
    knowledge that TAF was safer and at least as effective as TDF,
    and in its petition for rehearing, Gilead contends that it did not
    consider plaintiffs’ allegations of knowledge and motivation
    material to the legal issues its motion raised.
    2.    At the top of page 59, after the sentence ending “and, if necessary, on
    appeal from an adverse judgment.” add as footnote 20 the following
    footnote, which will require renumbering of the subsequent footnote:
    20 In its petition for rehearing, Gilead requests that we direct the
    trial court to permit further development of a record as to the
    appropriateness of the narrower Rowland exception, and to permit
    Gilead to file a summary judgment motion on the issues of whether
    Gilead possessed actual knowledge in 2004 that TAF was safer
    than, and as effective as, TDF, and whether Gilead’s narrower
    Rowland exception is appropriate. Our intent in the above
    discussion is that on remand the parties will have an opportunity
    to develop the record further, and to present potentially dispositive
    legal issues to the court for adjudication. While we see no reason
    why the trial court could not proceed as Gilead proposes, we also do
    not preclude it from employing other procedures, in the exercise of
    its sound discretion, to effectuate our intent.
    There is no change in the judgment.
    The petition for rehearing, filed January 24, 2024, is denied.
    Dated: _____________________                           BROWN, P. J.
    2
    Filed 1/9/24 (unmodified opinion)
    CERTIFIED FOR PUBLICATION
    IN THE COURT OF APPEAL OF THE STATE OF CALIFORNIA
    FIRST APPELLATE DISTRICT
    DIVISION FOUR
    GILEAD TENOFOVIR CASES.
    GILEAD LIFE SCIENCES,
    INC.,                                   A165558
    Petitioner,
    (San Francisco City &
    v.
    County Super. Ct.
    THE SUPERIOR COURT OF                   No. CJC-19-005043,
    THE CITY AND COUNTY OF                  JCCP No. 5043)
    SAN FRANCISCO,
    Respondent;
    PLAINTIFFS IN JCCP NO.
    5043,
    Real Parties in Interest.
    Defendant Gilead Life Sciences, Inc. (Gilead), a
    pharmaceutical manufacturer, developed and sold one of the first
    medications to treat HIV/AIDS. That drug, tenofovir disoproxil
    fumarate (TDF), was approved for sale by the Food and Drug
    Administration (FDA) in 2001. Although TDF was effective in
    suppressing the effects of HIV, its use carried a risk of skeletal
    and kidney damage. The 24,000 plaintiffs in this coordinated
    proceeding allege that they suffered these or other adverse effects
    from their use of TDF.
    While Gilead was developing TDF, it discovered a similar,
    but chemically distinct, potential drug, tenofovir alafenamide
    fumarate (TAF). Plaintiffs allege that Gilead’s early testing
    indicated TAF could be as effective as TDF at treating HIV/AIDS,
    while carrying a lower risk of adverse effects. According to
    plaintiffs, however, Gilead elected to defer development of TAF
    because it was concerned that the immediate development of TAF
    would reduce its financial return from TDF. Years later, Gilead
    resumed the development of TAF and obtained FDA approval for
    its sale in 2015.
    Although plaintiffs are seeking compensation for injuries
    caused by their use of TDF, they do not assert any claim seeking
    to prove that TDF is defective. Instead, they characterize their
    claim as one for ordinary negligence, contending that Gilead’s
    decision to defer development of TAF to maximize its profits
    breached its duty of reasonable care to users of TDF. They also
    assert a claim for fraudulent concealment, reasoning that Gilead
    had a duty to disclose information about TAF to users of TDF.
    Gilead filed a motion for summary judgment or summary
    adjudication. With respect to plaintiffs’ claim for negligence,
    Gilead argued that a plaintiff seeking to recover for harm caused
    by a manufactured product must prove that the product was
    defective. Given plaintiffs’ decision not to prove a defect, Gilead
    contended, they cannot recover for harm caused by their use of
    TDF. With respect to fraudulent concealment, Gilead argued
    2
    that it had no duty to disclose facts relating to TAF when it had
    not been approved as an alternative to TDF for the treatment of
    HIV/AIDS. The trial court denied the motion in its entirety.
    Gilead then filed a writ petition in this court. Because of the
    potentially dispositive nature of these issues for this large
    coordinated proceeding, we issued an order to show cause. After
    oral argument, we requested supplemental briefing on certain
    issues raised by plaintiffs’ negligence claim, including whether, if
    the law does not require proof of a defect, the factors set forth in
    Rowland v. Christian (1968) 
    69 Cal.2d 108
     (Rowland)
    nonetheless warrant an exception to the duty of care in this
    context.
    We now grant the petition for writ of mandate in part and
    deny it in part. We affirm the trial court’s denial of Gilead’s
    motion insofar as it sought summary adjudication of plaintiffs’
    negligence claim. First, we conclude that the legal duty of a
    manufacturer to exercise reasonable care can, in appropriate
    circumstances, extend beyond the duty not to market a defective
    product. Second, in light of that conclusion, we then explain why
    Rowland supplies the appropriate framework for evaluating
    plaintiffs’ negligence claim. Third, applying Rowland, we
    consider two proposed exceptions to the duty of care. The first
    exception mirrors Gilead’s original argument by precluding
    negligence liability for prescription drugs without proof of a
    defect. The second exception is narrower in that it would allow
    plaintiffs to assert a claim for negligence without proof of a
    defect, but only as to decisions the drug manufacturer made after
    3
    obtaining the results of Phase III clinical trials of the alternative
    drug. We find that the broader proposed exception is
    unwarranted, and that the narrower exception is unsupported on
    the present record, although we do not preclude the possibility
    that Gilead could establish it on a more developed record.
    Finally, we reverse the trial court’s decision insofar as it
    denied Gilead’s motion for summary adjudication of plaintiffs’
    claim for fraudulent concealment. We conclude that Gilead’s
    duty to plaintiffs did not extend to the disclosure of information
    about TAF.
    BACKGROUND
    I.    Plaintiffs’ Allegations
    Plaintiffs allege that in 1991 Gilead obtained an exclusive
    license to develop tenofovir, a substance known to be “an
    incredibly potent antiretroviral,” as a treatment for HIV/AIDS.
    Tenofovir could not be used as a medication in its pure form,
    however, because it is not effective when administered orally and
    produces “rapid and severe decline in kidney function” when
    injected directly into the body. To create a usable medication
    from tenofovir, Gilead was required to develop an alternative
    form of the chemical, known generally as a “prodrug,” that would
    be safe and effective when administered orally.
    Gilead eventually created TDF, a prodrug form of tenofovir,
    and focused its development efforts on that compound. TDF was
    approved by the FDA for sale as a treatment for HIV/AIDS
    in 2001. It was recognized at the time, however, that use of TDF
    carried the potential for harmful side effects.
    4
    At some point during its work, Gilead developed a second
    prodrug form of tenofovir, TAF, that also showed promise in the
    treatment of HIV/AIDS. Plaintiffs allege that TAF is more stable
    in the body than TDF, a property that permits TAF to be
    administered at a lower dose than TDF. The use of a smaller
    dose allegedly makes TAF more effective as a treatment while
    reducing adverse side effects.
    Plaintiffs allege that even before Gilead obtained
    regulatory approval to market TDF in 2001, the company “knew
    [TAF] to be more efficacious and less toxic to kidneys and bones
    than TDF.” In 2002, Gilead undertook Phase I/II testing of TAF.
    According to the complaint, apparently quoting a Gilead
    document, this testing was done with the “explicit goal of ‘. . .
    deliver[ing] a more potent version of tenofovir that can be taken
    in lower doses, resulting in better antiviral activity and fewer
    side effects.’ ” In 2004, however, Gilead discontinued
    development of TAF. At the time, Gilead allegedly explained its
    decision by stating publicly that the differences between TDF and
    TAF were insufficient to justify further investment in TAF’s
    development.
    Plaintiffs allege, on the contrary, that Gilead’s decision to
    discontinue work on TAF was actually driven by a conscious
    business strategy to maximize the financial value of TDF. If TAF
    were developed immediately as a treatment, plaintiffs allege, its
    superiority to TDF would have resulted in its replacement of TDF
    as an HIV/AIDS treatment. By deferring development of TAF, in
    contrast, Gilead was able to maximize its sales of TDF, while
    5
    using the later release of TAF to extend the patent coverage of
    tenofovir-related medications. As plaintiffs allege, this strategy
    “would effectively monetize both drugs.”
    Following its pause in the development of TAF in 2004, and
    continuing through 2011, Gilead obtained FDA approval to sell a
    series of HIV/AIDS medications that featured TDF in
    combination with antiviral drugs produced by other
    manufacturers. Gilead eventually resumed work on TAF and
    received FDA approval to sell TAF as a treatment for HIV/AIDS
    in 2015. In 2011, Gilead’s President allegedly told investors that
    TAF would be a “kinder, gentler” version of TDF.1
    The complaint asserted claims for negligence, strict
    products liability, breach of express and implied warranties, and
    fraudulent concealment. Over the course of the litigation,
    however, plaintiffs significantly narrowed the scope of their
    claims. In two separate stipulations, plaintiffs dismissed with
    prejudice their causes of action for strict liability and breach of
    warranty, as well as any claims “that solely provide support for
    failure to warn liability.” By the time of the summary judgment
    motion, plaintiffs’ only remaining claims were for negligence and
    fraudulent concealment.
    1 According to the statement of undisputed material facts
    Gilead submitted in connection with the summary judgment
    motion, Gilead resumed work on TAF in 2011 and conducted a
    Phase III study to compare TDF- and TAF-based medications
    in 2013. That study, Gilead’s motion conceded, provided
    “substantial evidence that TAF had less impact than TDF on
    renal function [and] bone metabolism.”
    6
    II.   Gilead’s Summary Judgment Motion
    Although the allegations on which plaintiffs’ negligence
    cause of action is based did not change over the course of the
    litigation, the framing of their claim evolved. By the time Gilead
    filed its summary judgment motion, plaintiffs’ contention was
    that Gilead’s 2004 decision to postpone development of TAF,
    despite its knowledge that TAF presented a safer alternative to
    TDF, breached its duty of reasonable care to users of its TDF
    medications. Plaintiffs aver that they will not attempt to
    demonstrate that TDF’s design was defective, nor that TDF
    should be withdrawn from the market. Rather, what matters is
    that “Plaintiffs and their physicians were deprived of the choice
    between TDF or TAF by Gilead’s actions.”
    Gilead did not, for purposes of the summary judgment
    motion, dispute plaintiffs’ primary allegations of actionable
    conduct. Rather, its motion was premised solely on evidence of
    the FDA’s approval of a series of medications featuring TDF.
    Based on this approval, Gilead argued that plaintiffs’ claim for
    negligence (1) is preempted by federal law and (2) fails to state a
    claim under state tort law. The latter argument was premised on
    Gilead’s contention that a product seller is liable only for harm
    caused by products proven to be defective. Because plaintiffs do
    not seek to prove that TDF-containing medications are defective,
    Gilead argued, plaintiffs cannot hold the company liable for harm
    caused by TDF. Acknowledging plaintiffs’ current claim that
    Gilead had a duty of reasonable care to commercialize a TAF-
    based medication once it knew of TAF’s superiority to TDF,
    7
    Gilead argued that “there is no such thing as a claim to redress
    alleged injuries caused by a defendant’s product without
    ‘prov[ing] that a defect caused [the] injury’—i.e., without proving
    a design defect.”
    Plaintiffs’ claim for fraudulent concealment alleged that
    Gilead actively concealed that TAF was a safer means for
    delivering tenofovir into the body; that the toxicity of tenofovir
    was not unavoidable; and that Gilead’s true motive for shelving
    TAF development was financial. With respect to this claim,
    Gilead argued that (1) it was preempted by federal law; (2) Gilead
    had no duty to disclose to plaintiffs information “about an
    unapproved drug that they were not taking”; and (3) plaintiffs
    could not demonstrate that information about TAF’s safety,
    provided prior to TAF’s approval by the FDA, would have been
    material to their doctors’ decisions to prescribe TDF. As noted,
    the summary judgment motion was denied, and these writ
    proceedings followed.2
    DISCUSSION
    I.    Negligence
    Civil Code section 1714 (section 1714), which states the
    statutory rule of negligence, provides that “[e]veryone is
    responsible . . . for an injury occasioned to another by his or her
    2 In connection with its writ petition and again in
    connection with a subsequent motion to stay proceedings, Gilead
    filed separate motions for judicial notice. Although we granted
    the relief sought by Gilead in both instances, we did not expressly
    rule on its motions for judicial notice in doing so. Because both
    motions for judicial notice were rendered moot by our grant of the
    relief Gilead was seeking, we now deny the motions.
    8
    want of ordinary care or skill in the management of his or her
    property or person.” (Civ. Code, § 1714, subd. (a).) The familiar
    elements of a negligence cause of action are duty, breach,
    causation, and damages. (Achay v. Huntington Beach Union
    High School Dist. (2022) 
    80 Cal.App.5th 528
    , 535.) “In
    California, the ‘general rule’ is that people owe a duty of care to
    avoid causing harm to others and that they are thus usually
    liable for injuries their negligence inflicts.” (Southern California
    Gas Leak Cases (2019) 
    7 Cal.5th 391
    , 308; see Brown v. USA
    Taekwondo (2021) 
    11 Cal.5th 204
    , 214 (USA Taekwondo)
    [section 1714 “establishes the default rule that each person has a
    duty ‘to exercise, in his or her activities, reasonable care for the
    safety of others’ ”].) “Whether a duty exists is a question of law to
    be resolved by the court.” (USA Taekwondo, at p. 213.)
    Drawing on the language of section 1714, plaintiffs
    characterize Gilead’s duty as simply the duty “to exercise
    reasonable care not to cause foreseeable injury to the users of its
    products.” But it is generally more appropriate to consider the
    claimed duty in its factual context. (See, e.g., Verdugo v. Target
    Corp. (2014) 
    59 Cal.4th 312
    , 336 [considering whether duty of
    reasonable care obligates department store to maintain an AED
    for use in a medical emergency]; Conte v. Wyeth, Inc. (2008)
    
    168 Cal.App.4th 89
    , 103 (Conte) [considering “whether a name-
    brand prescription drug manufacturer in disseminating product
    warnings owes a duty of care to patients who take a generic
    version of the drug pursuant to a prescription written in reliance
    on the name-brand maker’s information”].) Doing so is
    9
    particularly important here because Gilead occasionally describes
    plaintiffs’ proposed duty as imposing obligations—such as a “duty
    to innovate”—that plaintiffs expressly disavow. Plaintiffs do not
    claim that a manufacturer that obtains FDA approval to sell a
    prescription drug has a legal duty to invent a safer alternative
    drug, and by failing to do so may be held liable to users of the
    existing drug for injuries caused by the disclosed side effects of its
    use.3 On the contrary, their negligence claim is premised on
    Gilead’s possession of such an alternative in TAF; they complain
    of Gilead’s knowing and intentional withholding of such a
    treatment following its invention. While we agree with Gilead
    that a duty that placed manufacturers “under an endless
    obligation to pursue ever-better new products or improvements to
    existing products” would be unworkable and unwarranted,
    plaintiffs are not asking us to recognize such a duty.
    The factual basis for plaintiffs’ claim, as alleged in the
    complaint and confirmed by their supplemental briefing, is that
    (1) Gilead voluntarily invented TAF as part of the same research
    effort that led to the development of TDF; (2) prior to pausing
    work on TAF, Gilead had developed TAF sufficiently to evaluate
    its performance in a controlled trial, referred to as a Phase I/II
    trial; (3) by the time it paused work in 2004, Gilead knew that
    3 We use the term “invent” here, rather than “develop,”
    because the meaning of “develop” in the pharmaceutical context
    is ambiguous. Gilead refers to the entire process of drug creation,
    from invention through FDA approval, as drug development.
    Because plaintiffs’ claim is focused only on the latter stages of
    this process, Gilead’s general reference to a “duty to develop”
    obscures the precise nature of plaintiffs’ claim.
    10
    TAF would treat HIV/AIDS as effectively as TDF, yet would
    allow patients to avoid the bone and kidney side effects
    associated with TDF; and (4) Gilead made the decision to defer
    further commercialization of TAF for the purpose of extending
    the duration of its patent protection for tenofovir-related
    treatments, thereby increasing its financial return, rather than
    because of any concerns for TAF’s successful commercialization.
    Again, while Gilead’s briefing disputes plaintiffs’ assertions about
    its knowledge and motivation, it did not contest those assertions
    for the purposes of the summary judgment motion presently
    under review. We therefore accept the allegations of the
    complaint in adjudicating Gilead’s present arguments.4
    In context, then, the duty question we must address is
    whether a drug manufacturer, having invented what it knows is
    a safer, and at least equally effective, alternative to a
    prescription drug that it is currently selling and that is not
    shown to be defective, has a duty of reasonable care to users of
    the current drug when making decisions about the
    commercialization of the alternative drug.5
    4 Although Gilead cites some evidence in the appellate
    record to support its rebuttal of plaintiffs’ factual allegations,
    that evidence was submitted in connection with proceedings in
    the litigation that occurred prior to the summary judgment
    motion. Plaintiffs contend that Gilead’s evidence is contradicted
    by evidence similarly submitted by plaintiffs.
    5 At a few points in the complaint, plaintiffs allege that
    Gilead knew “or should have known” that TAF was safer than
    TDF. In general, however, plaintiffs’ complaint, summary
    judgment papers, and briefs in this court, assert without
    11
    A.     Negligence Without Proof of Defect
    Gilead’s original argument against plaintiffs’ negligence
    claim in its writ petition was based on plaintiffs’ decision to
    abandon any attempt to prove that TDF is defective. (Plaintiffs
    state that their decision is not a concession that TDF is not
    defective, but rather arises from a concern that any claim
    requiring proof that TDF is defective would be subject to federal
    preemption.6) Gilead argued that, in the products liability
    context, a manufacturer satisfies its duty of reasonable care by
    making a product that is not defective. Therefore, according to
    Gilead, a manufacturer cannot be held liable in negligence for
    harm its product causes if the plaintiff’s showing does not include
    proof that the injury was caused by a defect.
    The concept of a “defect” is one of the defining components
    of the doctrine of strict products liability, which provides that the
    manufacturer of a product is liable “if a defect in . . . its product
    qualification that Gilead knew TAF was safer than TDF.
    Moreover, actual knowledge appears to be necessary to the
    motivation plaintiffs attribute to Gilead’s decision—Gilead’s
    alleged concern that TAF would “cannibalize” sales of TDF and
    its belief that TAF’s later release would allow Gilead to maximize
    its financial return by extending the duration of its patent
    protection for tenofovir-related treatments. We therefore analyze
    plaintiffs’ claim as premised on actual knowledge, although we
    take no position on whether plaintiffs should be permitted to
    include a constructive knowledge theory on remand, should they
    seek to do so.
    6 Plaintiffs contend that the doctrine has developed in such
    a way as to severely limit the availability of design defect claims.
    (See, e.g., Bernstein, (Almost) No Bad Drugs: Near-Total
    Products Liability Immunity for Pharmaceuticals Explained
    (2020) 77 Wash. & Lee L.Rev. 3, 32–37 (Bernstein).)
    12
    causes injury while the product is being used in a reasonably
    foreseeable way.” (Soule v. General Motors Corp. (1994) 
    8 Cal.4th 548
    , 560 (Soule).)7 Prior to California’s adoption of the doctrine
    in Greenman v. Yuba Power Products, Inc. (1963) 
    59 Cal.2d 57
    (Greenman), negligence was the primary tort theory under which
    persons could recover for injuries caused by a manufactured
    product. (E.g., Escola v. Coca Cola Bottling Co. (1944) 
    24 Cal.2d 453
    , 457.) Because strict liability “focusses not on the conduct of
    the manufacturer but on the product itself ” (Brown, supra,
    44 Cal.3d at p. 1056), it was intended to simplify a consumer
    plaintiff’s evidentiary burden, as well as to serve the public policy
    function of placing the financial burdens associated with
    defective products on manufacturers, who are liable regardless of
    any fault in their conduct. (See Cronin v. J.B.E. Olson Corp.
    7 Product defects fall into three categories:  manufacturing
    defects, design defects, and defects of warning. A manufacturing
    defect occurs from “a flaw in the manufacturing process, resulting
    in a product that differs from the manufacturer’s intended
    result.” (Brown v. Superior Court (1988) 
    44 Cal.3d 1049
    , 1057
    (Brown).) A design defect can be found (1) “if the plaintiff
    demonstrates that the product failed to perform as safely as an
    ordinary consumer would expect when used in an intended or
    reasonably foreseeable manner” (Barker v. Lull Engineering Co.
    (1978) 
    20 Cal.3d 413
    , 429 (Barker)) or (2) “if the jury finds that
    the risk of danger inherent in the challenged design outweighs
    the benefits of such design.” (Id. at p. 430; see generally Kim v.
    Toyota Motor Corp. (2018) 
    6 Cal.5th 21
    , 30.) A failure-to-warn
    defect results if the manufacturer “did not adequately warn of a
    particular risk that was known or knowable in light of the
    generally recognized and prevailing best scientific and medical
    knowledge available at the time of manufacture and
    distribution.” (Carlin v. Superior Court (1996) 
    13 Cal.4th 1104
    ,
    1112 (Carlin).)
    13
    (1972) 
    8 Cal.3d 121
    , 133 (Cronin) [“the very purpose of our
    pioneering efforts in this field was to relieve the plaintiff from
    problems of proof inherent in pursuing negligence [citation] and
    warranty [citation] remedies, and thereby ‘to insure that the
    costs of injuries resulting from defective products are borne by
    the manufacturers’ ”].)
    The purpose of requiring proof of a defect is to prevent
    strict liability from expanding into absolute liability, in which
    manufacturers would effectively be made insurers for the safety
    of their products. (See, e.g., Cronin, supra, 8 Cal.3d at pp. 133–
    134; Soule, 
    supra,
     8 Cal.4th at p. 568, fn. 5; Daly v. General
    Motors Corp. (1978) 
    20 Cal.3d 725
    , 733; see also Jiminez v. Sears,
    Roebuck & Co. (1971) 
    4 Cal.3d 379
    , 383 (Jiminez) [noting that
    “the manufacturer’s strict liability depends upon what is meant
    by defect”].) Early commentators, including Greenman’s author,
    Justice Traynor, remarked on the difficulty of defining what
    constitutes a “defect.” (See Traynor, The Ways and Meanings of
    Defective Products and Strict Liability (1965) 32 Tenn. L.Rev.
    363, 366–367; Wade, On the Nature of Strict Tort Liability for
    Products (1973) 
    44 Miss. L.J. 825
    , 832 [“It is not without reason
    that some people, in writing about it, speak of the requirement of
    being ‘legally defective,’ including the quotation marks”]; see also
    Barker, supra, 20 Cal.3d at p. 427 [“the term defect as utilized in
    the strict liability context is neither self-defining nor susceptible
    to a single definition applicable in all contexts”].) But while the
    “formidable task” (id. at p. 418) of defining the term “defect” may
    have been necessary to constrain the reach of strict liability, in
    14
    negligence the requirement of a duty of care imposes its own
    limits on the potential scope of liability, governed by an array of
    policy considerations as they bear on a particular context. (See,
    e.g., Kesner v. Superior Court (2016) 
    1 Cal.5th 1132
    , 1143
    (Kesner) [“ ‘ “Courts . . . invoke[] the concept of duty to limit
    generally ‘the otherwise potentially infinite liability which would
    follow from every negligent act. . . .’ ” ’ ”] (quoting Bily v. Arthur
    Young & Co. (1992) 
    3 Cal.4th 370
    , 397); Rowland, supra,
    69 Cal.2d at pp. 112–113.) In our view, neither logic nor
    jurisprudential history compels the conclusion that the two
    concepts must be coextensive in every case in which a plaintiff is
    injured by a product.
    The adoption of strict liability in Greenman did not purport
    to displace negligence as a cause of action. It was soon settled
    that a plaintiff seeking compensation for harm caused by a
    product can plead and prove a claim for negligence as well as
    strict liability. (E.g., Jiminez, supra, 4 Cal.3d at p. 387 [“No valid
    reason appears to require a plaintiff to elect whether to proceed
    on the theory of strict liability in tort or on the theory of
    negligence”]; T.H. v. Novartis Pharmaceuticals Corp. (2017)
    
    4 Cal.5th 145
    , 177, fn. 4 (T.H.) [affirming that strict liability and
    negligence furnish distinct bases for liability].) After Greenman,
    plaintiffs harmed by products can focus on the product and prove
    a defect, or they can focus on the manufacturer’s conduct and
    prove a breach of the duty of care—or both. In theory, there is no
    reason why a plaintiff who suffers harm as a proximate result of
    a manufacturer’s breach of the duty of reasonable care should be
    15
    denied relief merely because the product that was the direct
    cause of harm did not satisfy the legal definition of “defective.”
    That said, Gilead’s argument that proof of a defect is a
    necessary element of a negligence claim for injury from a product
    is not new to the law. The same argument was made, although
    not resolved, early in the development of strict liability law in
    Hasson v. Ford Motor Co. (1977) 
    19 Cal.3d 530
     (Hasson). The
    plaintiff there was injured when the brakes failed on his four-
    year-old car. (Id. at p. 536.) The jury concluded that the car was
    not defective at the time it was sold, but it found the
    manufacturer liable in negligence. (Id. at p. 539.) The
    manufacturer argued that the jury’s verdict was fatally
    inconsistent because “strict liability based upon a ‘defect’ of
    design or manufacture encompasses all of the conceptual bases
    which would give rise to a traditional common law liability for
    negligence of a manufacturer. In effect, the newer law subsumes
    the old. Accordingly, . . . a special finding that there was no
    ‘defect’ obviates any finding of ‘negligence.’ ” (Id. at p. 540.)
    Unfortunately for our present purposes, the Supreme Court
    declined to “examine in detail the abstract legal relationship
    between the terms ‘defect’ and ‘negligence’ ” and did not render a
    ruling on the manufacturer’s argument. (Ibid.)8 Since Hasson,
    8 Hasson did conclude that the jury’s finding of no defect at
    the time the car was manufactured did not preclude a finding of
    negligence liability, but it did so by construing the negligence
    claim in a way that did not involve design. The court reasoned
    that, in light of the instructions given, the jury could have
    concluded “that the braking system and the fluid were, at the
    16
    no California case appears to have expressly considered the issue
    before us.9 Nonetheless, a variety of cases demonstrate, contrary
    to Gilead’s argument, that a manufacturer’s duty of reasonable
    care can extend more broadly than the duty to make a non-
    defective product, thereby permitting recovery even when there is
    no showing that the injury resulted from a product defect.
    outset, sound and fit for their intended purpose,” giving rise to
    the finding of no defect, “but that Ford was nonetheless liable for
    its failure during the ensuing four years to warn of conditions
    which might develop in use.” (Hasson, supra, 19 Cal.3d at
    p. 543.) The court pointed out that, while the instructions
    permitted the jury to construe Ford’s failure to warn as a product
    defect, they did not require it to do so, and thus the failure to
    warn could have been the predicate for the jury’s negligence
    finding without also leading to a finding of defect. (Ibid.)
    9 In Toner v. Lederle Laboratories (9th Cir. 1987) 
    828 F.2d 510
    , 513 (Toner), the Ninth Circuit held, based on the Idaho
    Supreme Court’s answers to certified questions (see Toner v.
    Lederle Laboratories (1987) 
    112 Idaho 328
    , 330), that under
    Idaho law the jury’s verdict absolving the vaccine manufacturer
    under strict liability was not fatally inconsistent with its verdict
    finding it liable in negligence. The court concluded that the jury
    could have found that the vaccine that harmed the plaintiff was
    not defective, while also finding the manufacturer negligent for
    failing to develop an alternative, safer vaccine of which it was
    aware. (Toner, 828 F.2d at p. 513; but see, e.g., Burton v. E.I. du
    Pont de Nemours and Co., Inc. (7th Cir. 2021) 
    994 F.3d 791
    , 817–
    819 [concluding that, under Wisconsin law, a negligence claim
    requires proof of a defect].) In a federal case arising out of the
    same facts at issue here, the court recently “reject[ed] Gilead’s
    argument to the extent it asserts it cannot be held liable for
    negligence if it is not liable under a strict-liability theory,” but
    the question there was whether certain states require a plaintiff
    asserting a negligence claim to prove that the product was
    “unreasonably dangerous.” (Holley v. Gilead Sciences, Inc.
    (N.D.Cal. Sept. 28, 2023, No. 18-cv-06972-JST) 2023 U.S.
    Dist.Lexis 176115, at *61–*62.)
    17
    The most prominent such case is Mexicali Rose v. Superior
    Court (1992) 
    1 Cal.4th 617
     (Mexicali Rose), which considered
    whether restaurants can be held liable for injury caused by a
    naturally occurring substance in their food—there, a chicken
    bone in a chicken enchilada. (Id. at p. 620.) In its analysis, the
    Supreme Court first summarized the prevailing rule: “If the
    injury-producing substance is natural to the preparation of the
    food served, it can be said that it was reasonably expected by its
    very nature and the food cannot be determined to be unfit for
    human consumption or defective.” (Id. at p. 630.) “Thus,” the
    court concluded, “a plaintiff in such a case has no cause of action
    in implied warranty or strict liability.” (Id. at pp. 630–631.)
    The inability to prove a defect, however, was not fatal to a
    plaintiff ’ s recovery for injury caused by a naturally occurring
    substance. Plaintiffs may still, the court held, assert a claim for
    negligence and prove that the presence of the substance resulted
    from the restaurant’s failure to exercise ordinary care in
    preparation of the non-defective dish. As the court confirmed,
    “[t]he expectations of the consumer do not, however, negate a
    defendant’s duty to exercise reasonable care in the preparation
    and service of the food. Therefore, if the presence of the natural
    substance is due to a defendant’s failure to exercise due care in
    the preparation of the food, an injured plaintiff may state a cause
    of action in negligence.” (Mexicali Rose, supra, 1 Cal.4th at
    p. 631.)
    Mexicali Rose expressly rejected the argument that a
    restaurant’s liability should be limited to food classified as
    18
    defective under the law of strict liability, thereby barring any
    claim for recovery “when a substance natural to the preparation
    of the food product has caused injury.” (Mexicali Rose, supra,
    1 Cal.4th at p. 632.) The court reasoned that allowing a cause of
    action for negligence “corresponds to modern developments in
    tort law,” including “our modern emphasis on Civil Code
    section 1714.” (Ibid.) “[W]e believe it is a question for the trier of
    fact to determine whether the presence of the injury-producing
    substance was caused by the failure of the defendants to exercise
    reasonable care in the preparation of the food, and whether the
    breach of the duty to exercise such care caused the consumer’s
    injury.” (Id. at p. 633.)
    Although Mexicali Rose did not expressly consider the issue
    raised by Gilead—the need to prove a defect to recover for harm
    caused by a product—its holding effectively resolves the claim.
    Mexicali Rose holds that a plaintiff may recover under the
    doctrine of negligence for harm caused by a product otherwise
    subject to the doctrine of strict liability, notwithstanding the
    plaintiff’s inability to prove a product defect. And although the
    decision arose in the atypical context of restaurant “products,” it
    does not suggest that its ruling is limited to that context, and
    Gilead, when asked to address the decision at oral argument,
    provided no justification for restricting the decision to food
    products. Importantly, Mexicali Rose illustrates the continued
    utility of the negligence cause of action in products liability
    actions. Although the legal concept of a “defect” is
    extraordinarily useful, it should not in every case constitute the
    19
    outer boundary of a manufacturer’s liability for its conduct. The
    circumstances under which a manufacturer might appropriately
    be held liable for injury caused by its products are simply too
    varied to be so constrained. Under section 1714, harm resulting
    from a manufacturer’s failure to exercise reasonable care may be
    compensable, even if the product causing the harm does not meet
    the legal definition of “defective.”
    The Courts of Appeal have also permitted recovery under
    claims of negligence in the absence of a defect. (See, e.g., Lunghi
    v. Clark Equipment Co. (1984) 
    153 Cal.App.3d 485
     (Lunghi);
    Hernandez v. Badger Construction Equipment Co. (1994)
    
    28 Cal.App.4th 1791
     (Hernandez).) The plaintiff’s decedent in
    Lunghi was killed by a machine manufactured several years
    earlier. The jury entered judgment for the defendant, finding no
    defect in the product’s design. (Lunghi, at p. 489.) The Court of
    Appeal reversed, concluding the trial court had erred in refusing
    to instruct on negligence. (Id. at p. 491.) As the court explained,
    “[e]ven if, properly instructed, the jury had found that none of the
    mechanical design features in issue . . . constituted a defect, it
    could still have found that [the defendant’s] knowledge of the
    injuries caused by these features imposed a duty to warn of the
    danger, and/or a duty to conduct an adequate retrofit campaign.
    A finding that [defendant] had not met the standard of
    reasonable care with regard to either of these duties would have
    had some support in the evidence, and would have been
    consistent with a finding that the product’s design was not
    defective.” (Id. at p. 494, italics omitted.) To similar effect is
    20
    Hernandez, which also involved an injury from heavy equipment
    manufactured several years prior. Although the jury found
    against the plaintiff on the issue of design defect (Hernandez, at
    p. 1802), the court affirmed a verdict of negligence on the theory
    that the manufacturer, once it began offering as standard
    equipment a safety device that would have prevented the
    plaintiff’s injury, could be found liable under a duty to take
    reasonable steps to prevent injury to users of earlier models
    lacking the device. (Id. at p. 1828.)
    Gilead argues that Hernandez and Lunghi are inapposite
    because, in its view, they stand only for the proposition that a
    product can be free of defects at the time it is manufactured and
    sold, but can “become defective,” for example as a result of
    technological developments or new information or understanding.
    Neither case, however, held that the products had become
    “defective” as that term is used in strict products liability law,
    nor characterized such a finding as a prerequisite to imposing a
    duty to warn or to retrofit under principles of negligence.
    Whether or not the products could have been characterized as
    “defective” at the time of the plaintiffs’ injuries, the plaintiffs did
    not have to prove that they were, and the characterization is
    legally irrelevant to a finding of negligence liability.
    In short, although the utility of a cause of action for
    negligence in products liability actions has been greatly reduced
    by the doctrine of strict liability, it has not been eliminated. In
    those circumstances in which a manufacturer’s duty of
    reasonable care properly extends beyond the duty not to market a
    21
    defective product, a claim for negligence continues to provide a
    remedy.
    We are not persuaded by Gilead’s arguments to the
    contrary. Gilead relies on isolated language from a variety of
    decisions that characterize products liability law as premised on
    the existence of a defect. Because the doctrine of strict liability
    provides the rule of law for the vast majority of products liability
    cases, this is an understandable generalization. As the Supreme
    Court has had frequent reason to observe, however, “ ‘ “ ‘cases are
    not authority for propositions not considered.’ ” ’ ” (Geiser v.
    Kuhns (2022) 
    13 Cal.5th 1238
    , 1252.) The mere fact that a
    decision contains language that can be construed to suggest that
    a defect is a sine qua non for recovery against a manufacturer
    does not make the decision authority for that proposition unless
    the issue has been considered and the conclusion embraced. (Id.
    at p. 1252 [the cited case “is not controlling because that issue
    was not presented in [the case]”].)
    Merrill v. Navegar, Inc.
    Gilead places primary reliance on Merrill v. Navegar, Inc.
    (2001) 
    26 Cal.4th 465
     (Merrill), which considered the connection
    between claims of negligent and defective design in construing
    former Civil Code section 1714.4. That statute, repealed in 2002
    (Stats. 2002, ch. 906, § 2), prohibited recovery against gun
    manufacturers on a classic risk/benefit theory of design defect.10
    10 Former Civil Code section 1714.4, subdivision (a), read:
    “In a products liability action, no firearm or ammunition shall be
    deemed defective in design on the basis that the benefits of the
    22
    (Merrill, at p. 470.) The plaintiffs attempted to avoid the bar of
    former section 1714.4 by alleging that semi-automatic assault
    pistols were negligently designed “because, given their particular
    characteristics, the benefits of making them available to the
    general public—which were nonexistent—did not outweigh the
    risk they might inflict serious injury or death when discharged.”
    (Ibid.)
    In rejecting the attempt, the court recognized that a
    plaintiff in a products liability action can recover under theories
    of both strict liability and negligence. (Id. at p. 478.) In a
    products liability action based on negligence in the design of a
    product, however, “the test of negligent design ‘involves a
    balancing of the likelihood of harm to be expected from a machine
    with a given design and the gravity of harm if it happens against
    the burden of the precaution which would be effective to avoid the
    harm.’ ” (Id. at p. 479.) “Thus,” the court observed, “ ‘most of the
    evidentiary matters’ relevant to applying the risk/benefit test in
    strict liability cases ‘are similar to the issues typically presented
    in a negligent design case.’ ” (Id. at p. 480.) Although the
    plaintiffs argued “that they seek to hold [the defendant] liable for
    ‘negligent conduct, not for making a defective product,’ ” the court
    found the distinction immaterial because “in asserting that the
    [assault pistol] had a ‘negligent design’ and that [the defendant]
    ‘negligently designed’ it, plaintiffs have in fact alleged that the
    product do not outweigh the risk of injury posed by its potential
    to cause serious injury, damage, or death when discharged.”
    (Merrill, supra, 26 Cal.4th at p. 478.)
    23
    [assault pistol] is, in the words of [former] section 1714.4,
    subdivision (a), ‘defective in design.’ ” (Ibid.) The court rejected
    the plaintiffs’ effort to recast the claim as one for “negligent
    distribution to the public,” because it was already implicit in
    negligence and strict liability theories of products liability that
    the manufacturer was in the business of distributing goods to the
    public. (Id. at p. 481.) Therefore, the court concluded, the
    plaintiffs’ allegation that the defendant made the assault pistol
    available to the general public “adds nothing to the standard
    products liability action.” (Ibid.)
    As this summary suggests, Merrill did not consider
    whether every negligence claim against a manufacturer must
    include proof of a defect. Rather, it concluded that, regardless of
    how the plaintiffs labeled it, the gravamen of their purported
    negligence claim was that the assault pistol “was defective in
    design because the risks of making it available to the general
    public outweighed the benefits of that conduct, and that
    defendants knew or should have known this fact.” (Merrill,
    supra, 26 Cal.4th at p. 481.) This is not a holding that every
    negligence claim to recover for injuries from a product (unless
    based on failure to warn or manufacturing defects) is necessarily
    one for negligent design, measured by one of Barker’s two tests
    for design defects.
    In arguing for a broader interpretation of Merrill, Gilead
    relies on the decision’s introductory summary of the law of
    products liability: “As Professors Prosser and Keeton explain,
    ‘Products liability is the name currently given to the area of the
    24
    law involving the liability of those who supply goods or products
    for the use of others to purchasers, users, and bystanders for
    losses of various kinds resulting from so-called defects in those
    products.’ [Citation.] As relevant here, a plaintiff may seek
    recovery in a ‘products liability case’ either ‘on the theory of strict
    liability in tort or on the theory of negligence.’ [Citations.] The
    rules of products liability ‘focus responsibility for defects, whether
    negligently or nonnegligently caused, on the manufacturer of the
    completed product.’ [Citation.] Thus, under either a negligence or
    a strict liability theory of products liability, to recover from a
    manufacturer, a plaintiff must prove that a defect caused injury.
    [Citations.] Under a negligence theory, a plaintiff must also
    prove ‘an additional element, namely, that the defect in the
    product was due to negligence of the defendant.’ ” (Merrill,
    supra, 26 Cal.4th at pp. 478–479, italics added.) Read in
    isolation, the italicized language from Merrill certainly supports,
    if not flatly confirms, Gilead’s legal theory.
    We decline to find Merrill controlling on this issue for three
    reasons. First, as explained above, the requirement of a defect in
    every products liability case was not an issue actually considered
    in Merrill. Rather, the court addressed only whether the legal
    test for negligent design overlapped with the test for defective
    design in such a way that the plaintiffs could not evade a ban on
    recovery under a theory of design defect by alleging negligent
    design.
    Second, the authority cited by Merrill in its summary of the
    law did not consider this issue, either. The primary authority
    25
    was an early law review article on products liability law by
    Professor William Prosser, which was published only three years
    after California adopted strict products liability in Greenman—
    well before the doctrine’s legal framework was well defined.
    (Prosser, Strict Liability to the Consumer (1966) 
    18 Hastings L.J. 9
    .) The cited portion of the article did not purport to opine on the
    requirements of a negligence claim in products liability actions;
    the point was that the evidence supporting a claim of defect
    under strict liability “does not appear to differ in any significant
    respect from the proof of negligence.” (Id. at p. 50.) The
    California cases cited by Merrill as authority, Jiminez, supra,
    
    4 Cal.3d 379
    , and Cronin, supra, 
    8 Cal.3d 121
    , are similarly
    beside the point. Cronin considered whether a plaintiff alleging
    defective design must demonstrate that the alleged defect made
    the product “unreasonably dangerous” and ultimately rejected
    this element. (Id. at pp. 132–134.) Jiminez held that a trial
    court erred in refusing to instruct the jury on negligence and res
    ipsa loquitur in a products liability case. (Jiminez, supra,
    4 Cal.3d at pp. 384–387.) Neither decision holds that a plaintiff
    alleging negligence in a products liability action must in every
    case prove a product defect; although Jiminez adopted, without
    discussion, defendant’s assertion that proof of a defect was
    required, it explained that “under the facts of the case before us
    instructions on negligence would serve the plaintiff better than
    instructions on defect in several respects,” suggesting the jury
    26
    might have found the manufacturer liable in negligence without
    finding the product defective. (Id. at pp. 383–384.)11
    Third, accepting Merrill as controlling authority on this
    point would require a conclusion that the decision was intended
    to overrule, sub silentio, the various cases discussed above that
    permit a negligence claim to proceed in the absence of proof of a
    product defect. There is simply no indication that Merrill
    intended such a change.
    Although Gilead does not expressly distinguish the
    argument, it also contends that, even if Merrill does not establish
    that proof of a defect is required in every case, the court’s
    analysis demonstrates that plaintiffs here are likewise asserting
    a claim for negligent design, and only repudiate the label in an
    effort “to avoid their concession that the TDF medications are not
    defective.” As an initial matter, plaintiffs’ decision to forgo a
    claim that TDF is defective is not a concession that TDF is not
    defective. (Cf. Toner, supra, 828 F.2d at p. 513 [“We decline to
    treat Toner’s litigation decision not to pursue the warning theory
    11 The plaintiff was injured by a ladder that broke while he
    was using it on the cement floor of his garage. He had tried to
    use it only once previously to prune a tree but stopped because
    the ground was too muddy. (Jiminez, supra, 4 Cal.3d at p. 381.)
    There was some evidence that the ladder may have broken
    because its previous use on soft soil caused the load on its legs to
    be unevenly distributed. (Id. at p. 382.) The court opined that a
    jury instructed on negligence might have found the manufacturer
    liable for failing to warn that the ladder should not be used on
    soft ground, but if instructed only on strict products liability,
    could have concluded that the ladder was not defective because it
    was safe for use on hard ground, even if use on soft ground would
    be considered a normal use of the product. (Id. at p. 385.)
    27
    as if it were a stipulation that Toner had adequate warning”].)
    And in any event, we find plaintiffs’ claim to be significantly
    different from the negligence claim in Merrill. Plaintiffs do not
    contend that Gilead was negligent because it made TDF available
    for sale, or because the risks of TDF outweighed its benefits.
    Rather, they contend that Gilead breached its duty of reasonable
    care by postponing, solely to maximize profit, its effort to
    commercialize TAF as a treatment for HIV/AIDS while
    continuing to market a medication with serious side effects that
    it knew TAF would have enabled patients to avoid.
    Unlike in Merrill, we cannot say that these allegations
    “add[] nothing to the standard products liability action.” (Merrill,
    supra, 26 Cal.4th at p. 481.) Gilead’s alleged financially
    motivated deferral of the development of TAF for seven years,
    despite its recognition of TAF’s superiority, is discrete conduct
    independent of the design and marketing of TDF. For this
    reason, plaintiffs’ cause of action, unlike a typical negligent
    design case, will focus on “the reasonableness of the
    manufacturer’s conduct,” rather than “the condition of the
    product itself.” (Barker, supra, 20 Cal.3d at p. 434.)
    Brown v. Superior Court
    Gilead also relies on Brown, supra, 
    44 Cal.3d 1049
    , which
    held that prescription drugs are exempt from strict liability
    claims of defective design pursuant to comment k to section 402A
    of the Restatement Second of Torts, pages 353–354. (Brown, at
    28
    p. 1061.)12 The court did not exempt prescription drugs from
    such claims because it concluded that prescription drugs cannot
    be defectively designed. On the contrary, as the court recognized,
    the design of a prescription drug might be found defective under
    the risk/benefit test if, for example, the plaintiff demonstrates
    that a particular component of the drug rendered it unsafe and
    that removal of that component would not have affected the
    efficacy of the drug or if other, less harmful drugs were available
    to treat the same condition. (Id. at p. 1062.) Rather, the court’s
    decision was grounded in public policy concerns. Subjecting
    prescription drug manufacturers to strict liability for design
    defects, the court worried, might discourage drug development or
    inflate the cost of otherwise affordable drugs. (Id. at p. 1063.)
    Gilead points to the first two sentences of Brown’s
    footnote 12, which read as follows: “Our conclusion does not
    mean, of course, that drug manufacturers are free of all liability
    for defective drugs. They are subject to liability for
    manufacturing defects, as well as under general principles of
    negligence, and for failure to warn of known or reasonably
    knowable side effects.” (Id. at p. 1069, fn. 12.) According to
    Gilead, the first sentence establishes that “a defect is a necessary
    precondition of any such suit.”
    12 Section 402A of the Restatement Second of Torts governs
    claims for strict products liability; comment k exempts from such
    claims “unavoidably unsafe products,” which the comment
    defines as “products which, in the present state of human
    knowledge, are quite incapable of being made safe for their
    intended and ordinary use.” (Rest.2d Torts, § 402A, com. k,
    pp. 353–354; Brown, supra, 44 Cal.3d at p. 1058.)
    29
    As with Merrill, however, the court in Brown was not
    considering whether every claim against a manufacturer of
    prescription drugs must prove that the drug was defective. The
    “conclusion” to which the first sentence of footnote 12 refers is the
    court’s holding that “a manufacturer is not strictly liable for
    injuries caused by a prescription drug so long as the drug was
    properly prepared and accompanied by warnings of its dangerous
    propensities that were either known or reasonably scientifically
    knowable at the time of distribution.” (Brown, supra, 44 Cal.3d
    at p. 1069.) Since the existence of a defect is the sine qua non of
    strict products liability—and the plaintiffs alleged that the drug
    was defective (id. at p. 1055)—it is not surprising that the court
    referred to manufacturers of “defective drugs” when explaining
    that its holding about strict liability did not exempt them from
    liability on other grounds. Those words reflect the issue before
    the court. Because the court had no occasion to consider any
    claim that was not premised on a defect, in context the sentence
    cannot be read to mean that every viable claim against a
    prescription drug manufacturer requires proof that the drug was
    defective.
    Gilead further contends that the reference to “general
    principles of negligence” in the second sentence of the footnote
    could only mean claims for negligent design defect, which here
    plaintiffs have abandoned. It is true that footnote 12 has been
    read to preserve claims for negligent design defect in light of the
    court’s rejection of strict liability design defect claims. (See, e.g.,
    Garrett v. Howmedica Osteonics Corp. (2013) 
    214 Cal.App.4th 30
    173, 182; Artiglio v. Superior Court (1994) 
    22 Cal.App.4th 1388
    ,
    1393.) But even if the court had in mind claims of negligent
    design defect, again the context of the footnote prevents us from
    construing it to say that no other negligence claims are
    cognizable. Nothing in the case presented that question.
    Gilead also suggests that Brown’s reasoning may call into
    question some aspects even of negligent design defect claims
    insofar as the court’s policy concerns about evaluating the merits
    of a drug’s design are relevant whether the claim is based in
    strict liability or negligence.13 It is unnecessary for us to explore
    this issue in depth given plaintiffs’ disavowal of a design defect
    claim, and we again note that we do not view the negligence
    claim here as a disguised claim that TDF, at the time of its
    distribution to plaintiffs, was negligently designed. Not only does
    the claim require the trier of fact to consider conduct independent
    of TDF’s design—Gilead’s alleged recognition of TAF’s superiority
    and its reasons for pausing development—but even as to TDF’s
    design, the claim does not depend on an evaluation of the risks
    13 Gilead echoes an argument expressed by some
    commentators that there is a tension between Brown’s
    preservation of claims for negligent design defect and its rejection
    (Brown, supra, 44 Cal.3d at pp. 1066–1068) of the case-by-case
    approach to the application of comment k adopted in Kearl v.
    Lederle Laboratories (1985) 
    172 Cal.App.3d 812
    . (See Conk, Is
    There A Design Defect in the Restatement (Third) of Torts:
    Products Liability? (2000) 
    109 Yale L.J. 1087
    , 1125–1126; O’Neill,
    Jr., Unavoidably Unsafe Products and the Design Defect Theory:
    An Analysis of Applying Comment K to Strict Liability and
    Negligence Claims (1989) 15 Wm. Mitchell L.Rev. 1049, 1061–
    1062 & fn. 90.)
    31
    and benefits of TDF as an HIV/AIDS medication, as would be
    necessary in a claim for negligent design. Although the
    characteristics of TDF as a medication are central to plaintiffs’
    claim, these characteristics will not be evaluated in the abstract
    to determine, on balance, whether TDF should have been
    marketed at all. The risks and benefits of TDF relative to each
    other are irrelevant to plaintiffs’ claim, which does not call into
    question Gilead’s decision to market TDF. On the contrary,
    plaintiffs’ claim is entirely consistent with a conclusion that the
    benefits of TDF use for hundreds of thousands of HIV/AIDS
    sufferers have vastly exceeded the harm from its side effects.
    Rather, the critical question for plaintiffs’ purposes is simply
    whether Gilead’s years-long delay in bringing TAF to market,
    despite knowing its equivalent efficacy and superior safety to
    TDF, breached a duty of reasonable care to users of TDF if the
    reason was solely to maximize Gilead’s profits. Such a claim is
    meaningfully different from the abstract consideration of risks
    and benefits central to a claim of negligent design.
    Other Cases
    Although a lengthy discussion is not required, the other
    cases Gilead cites similarly do not stand for the proposition that
    any negligence claim in the products liability context requires
    proof of a defect. Gilead points to the Supreme Court’s statement
    in Soule, supra, 8 Cal.4th at page 568, footnote 5, that
    manufacturers “are liable in tort only when ‘defects’ in their
    products cause injury.” But the court was not considering any
    question about negligence liability or its scope; the question
    32
    before it was whether a jury should be instructed on Barker’s
    “consumer expectations” test for product defect in every case, or
    whether in some cases only the risk/benefit test is appropriate.
    (Soule, at p. 568.) The statement quoted by Gilead came in a
    footnote responding to an argument that “any limitation on use of
    the consumer expectations test contravenes Greenman’s purpose
    to aid hapless consumers,” and the court’s point was simply that
    strict liability is not unlimited. (Id. at p. 568, fn. 5.)
    Likewise, Gilead’s reliance on Milwaukee Electric Tool
    Corp. v. Superior Court (1993) 
    15 Cal.App.4th 547
     ignores its
    context. In suggestive introductory language quoted by Gilead,
    Milwaukee Tool states, “we conclude Milwaukee owes a general
    duty to produce defect-free products, which translates into a duty
    similar to that in negligence law not to depart from the
    appropriate standards of care in manufacturing its product.” (Id.
    at p. 551.) The issue actually considered in Milwaukee Tool,
    however, was the application of a then-recent Supreme Court
    decision concerning the defenses of assumption of the risk and
    comparative fault. (Id. at pp. 550, 559–564.) Although the court
    discussed the relationship between strict liability and negligence
    (id. at pp. 555–559), the discussion occurred entirely in this
    context. Milwaukee Tool did not consider whether a claim for
    negligence could be asserted in the absence of a product defect.
    33
    Accordingly, we conclude that plaintiffs’ negligence claim is
    not foreclosed by their decision to forgo any attempt to prove that
    TDF is defective.14
    B.   New Duty Versus Exception to Existing Duty
    We pause here to consider the parties’ dispute about the
    proper legal framework for analyzing plaintiffs’ negligence claim,
    since it is relevant to how we proceed in light of our conclusion in
    the preceding subsection. According to Gilead, the question is
    whether plaintiffs can establish a “new” duty—one that would
    impose further obligations on manufacturers that have produced
    a non-defective prescription drug. According to plaintiffs, the
    duty they are invoking is simply the one imposed on all persons
    by section 1714, so the question is whether Gilead can establish
    that an exception to that duty is warranted under the Rowland
    factors. Both in the trial court, and originally in these writ
    proceedings, Gilead’s view of the proper question led it to disavow
    any invocation of Rowland, citing the Supreme Court’s
    explanation that “[t]he multifactor test set forth in Rowland was
    not designed as a freestanding means of establishing duty, but
    instead as a means for deciding whether to limit a duty derived
    from other sources.” (USA Taekwondo, supra, 11 Cal.5th at
    p. 217.)
    14 Although plaintiffs now disavow any intent to prove
    negligent design, we agree with Gilead that the trial court’s
    ruling was in error to the extent it suggested plaintiffs can
    pursue a claim for negligent design without proving the
    equivalent of a design defect. Plaintiffs do not argue otherwise
    on appeal.
    34
    Gilead’s position has some logical appeal if one accepts the
    premise that, in the products liability context, the duty
    section 1714 imposes on a manufacturer is simply to ensure that
    any product it offers for sale is not defective. In that case,
    plaintiffs would have to identify a proper basis for the imposition
    of a greater duty.15 Because we have disagreed with the premise,
    however, we are unpersuaded that the burden lies with plaintiffs
    to establish the existence of a duty beyond that imposed by
    section 1714.
    In arguing that plaintiffs should be required to establish
    the existence of a new duty, Gilead relies on cases that concern
    the existence of a duty to protect against harm from third parties.
    (E.g., USA Taekwondo, supra, 11 Cal.5th at p. 215; Golick v.
    State of California (2022) 
    82 Cal.App.5th 1127
    , 1140.) In that
    context, there must be a “special relationship” between the
    plaintiff and the defendant to give rise to a duty; the duty cannot
    be created through application of the Rowland factors. (USA
    Taekwondo, at pp. 216–222.) But the reason for requiring a
    special relationship is that “the law imposes a general duty of
    care on a defendant only when it is the defendant who has
    15 Plaintiffs argue that Gilead can be held liable under a
    “negligent undertaking” theory. (See Artiglio v. Corning Inc.
    (1998) 
    18 Cal.4th 604
    , 612–614.) Gilead responds, first, that this
    theory is waived both because it was not pled in the complaint
    and because plaintiffs failed to raise it in response to Gilead’s
    summary judgment motion, and second, that it fails on the merits
    in any event. We do not address these arguments given our
    conclusion that Gilead has not established its entitlement to
    summary adjudication under an “ordinary negligence” theory
    pursuant to section 1714.
    35
    ‘ “created a risk” ’ of harm to the plaintiff, including when ‘ “the
    defendant is responsible for making the plaintiff’s position
    worse.” ’ ” (Id. at p. 214.) Here, Gilead itself created the risk of
    harm to plaintiffs by selling TDF, a drug with harmful side
    effects, making inapposite the cases on which Gilead relies.16
    Gilead also argues that its conduct, which it characterizes
    as the failure to bring a product to market, constitutes
    nonfeasance, rather than misfeasance, and quotes USA
    Taekwondo’s observation that the law is “ ‘reluctan[t] to impose
    liability’ ” for nonfeasance. (USA Taekwondo, supra, 11 Cal.5th
    at p. 214.) The court’s observation, however, was made in
    support of the general rule that a party has no duty to prevent
    harm by a third person, and was not a ruling that a party’s
    failure to act cannot constitute a breach of the duty of reasonable
    care. As the court clarified in a footnote, “[a]lthough our
    precedents have sometimes referred to the distinction between
    ‘misfeasance’ and ‘nonfeasance,’ we now understand this
    terminology to be imprecise and prone to misinterpretation. ‘The
    proper question is not whether an actor’s failure to exercise
    reasonable care entails the commission or omission of a specific
    act.’ [Citation.] Rather, it is ‘whether the actor’s entire conduct
    created a risk of harm.’ ” (Id. at p. 214, fn. 6.) We are satisfied
    that, in this case, that question can be answered affirmatively,
    and accordingly that Gilead must establish that an exception to
    16 The fact that Gilead was the manufacturer of both drugs
    is also an essential element of its alleged motivation for delaying
    the commercialization of TAF and breaching its duty of care.
    36
    the imposition of a duty of care is warranted under the Rowland
    factors.
    Gilead’s failure to offer a Rowland analysis in the trial
    court—to say nothing of its failure to do so in this court before we
    requested supplemental briefing—constitutes sufficient reason
    for us to decline to reach the issue. However, in its response to
    our request, Gilead urged us to decide the applicability of a
    Rowland exception if we concluded that it furnished the proper
    framework for analyzing the claimed duty. Given the posture in
    which the case has come to us—on writ review of the denial of
    Gilead’s summary judgment motion—we believe that, to avoid to
    the extent possible the need for piecemeal adjudication and to
    provide guidance for the parties and the trial court, it is
    appropriate to exercise our discretion to address the Rowland
    factors to the extent the record permits us to do so.
    C.    Application of the Rowland Factors
    In Rowland, the California Supreme Court “identified
    several considerations that, when balanced together, may justify
    a departure from the fundamental principle embodied in Civil
    Code section 1714.” (Cabral v. Ralphs Grocery Co. (2011)
    
    51 Cal.4th 764
    , 771 (Cabral).) The Rowland analysis “is
    conducted ‘at a relatively broad level of factual generality.’
    [Citation.] We analyze the Rowland factors to determine ‘not
    whether they support an exception to the general duty of
    reasonable care on the facts of the particular case before us, but
    whether carving out an entire category of cases from that general
    duty rule is justified by clear considerations of
    37
    policy.’ ” (Kuciemba v. Victory Woodworks, Inc. (2023) 
    14 Cal.5th 993
    , 1021 (Kuciemba).) “By making exceptions to Civil Code
    section 1714’s general duty of ordinary care only when
    foreseeability and policy considerations justify a categorical no-
    duty rule, we preserve the crucial distinction between a
    determination that the defendant owed the plaintiff no duty of
    ordinary care, which is for the court to make, and a
    determination that the defendant did not breach the duty of
    ordinary care, which in a jury trial is for the jury to make. . . .
    While the court deciding duty assesses the foreseeability of injury
    from ‘the category of negligent conduct at issue,’ if the defendant
    did owe the plaintiff a duty of ordinary care the jury ‘may
    consider the likelihood or foreseeability of injury in determining
    whether, in fact, the particular defendant’s conduct was negligent
    in the first place.’ ” (Cabral, at p. 773.)
    The Rowland factors fall into two categories. “Three
    factors—foreseeability, certainty, and the connection between the
    plaintiff and the defendant—address the foreseeability of the
    relevant injury, while the other four—moral blame, preventing
    future harm, burden, and availability of insurance—take into
    account public policy concerns that might support excluding
    certain kinds of plaintiffs or injuries from relief.” (Kesner, supra,
    1 Cal.5th at p. 1145). Issues related to foreseeability are assessed
    on the basis of information available at the time of the alleged
    negligence, while “ ‘our duty analysis is forward-looking’ in
    regard to policy issues surrounding burdens that would be placed
    on defendants.” (Kuciemba, supra, 14 Cal.5th at p. 1022.)
    38
    1. Gilead’s Proposed Expansive Exception
    In requesting a Rowland exception to the duty of
    section 1714, Gilead proposes two alternatives. The first, the
    more expansive exception, would hold that when an FDA-
    approved prescription drug is accompanied by an adequate
    warning of its side effects, and is not shown to be defective in
    design or manufacture, the manufacturer does not owe users of
    the current drug a duty of reasonable care in its decisions about
    commercializing any alternative drug the manufacturer might
    invent. We emphasize that it is a necessary premise of this
    analysis that the same manufacturer has developed both drugs.
    As discussed above, the manufacturer’s duty with respect to any
    alternative drug arises only because its sale of the first drug has
    created the risk of harm. (See O’Neil v. Crane Co. (2012)
    
    53 Cal.4th 335
    , 342 (O’Neil) [“a product manufacturer may not be
    held liable . . . for harm caused by another manufacturer’s
    product unless the defendant’s own product contributed
    substantially to the harm, or the defendant participated
    substantially in creating a harmful combined use of the
    products”].)
    Because plaintiffs assert that Gilead knew TAF was safer
    than TDF, we also conduct the Rowland analysis under the
    assumption that the drug manufacturer knows that the
    alternative drug is safer than (and at least as effective as) the
    current drug. As noted earlier, we offer no opinion about whether
    plaintiffs should be permitted to argue constructive knowledge on
    remand, assuming they were to seek to do so, but we think a
    39
    different Rowland analysis would be required for a claim based
    on constructive knowledge. Among other things, a constructive
    knowledge standard would be more susceptible to hindsight bias
    by the jury, and would therefore present more challenging policy
    issues than in a case in which no duty arises in the absence of
    proof that the manufacturer knew it had developed a safer and at
    least equally effective alternative.
    i.     Foreseeability factors
    The first three Rowland factors are commonly referred to
    as the foreseeability factors: “the foreseeability of harm to the
    plaintiff, the degree of certainty that the plaintiff suffered injury,
    and the closeness of the connection between the defendant’s
    conduct and the injury suffered.” (Rowland, supra, 69 Cal.2d at
    p. 113.) Again, we evaluate these factors on the basis of
    information available at the time of the alleged negligence.
    (Kuciemba, supra, 14 Cal.5th at p. 1022.) In considering
    foreseeability, we focus not on particularities of the defendant’s
    conduct and the plaintiff ’ s injury, but on “whether the category of
    negligent conduct at issue is sufficiently likely to result in the
    kind of harm experienced that liability may appropriately be
    imposed . . . .” (Cabral, supra, 51 Cal.4th at p. 772.)
    Foreseeability of injury. Of the seven Rowland factors, the
    foreseeability of harm to a plaintiff from the defendant’s conduct
    is “[t]he most important factor to consider in determining
    whether to create an exception to the general duty to exercise
    ordinary care articulated by section 1714.” (Kesner, supra,
    1 Cal.5th at p. 1145.)
    40
    In any case involving a drug with a proper warning of side
    effects, it is a given that injury from side effects is foreseeable.
    We agree with Gilead, however, that in this context the relevant
    question is whether it is foreseeable that the new, safer, drug
    would enable users to avoid the injury. Gilead posits several
    considerations that it contends weigh against foreseeability, such
    as the degree to which the new drug avoids side effects, the
    relative efficacy of the new drug, and any additional side effects
    of the new drug. However, because Gilead’s proposed expansive
    exception would impose no duty of care notwithstanding the
    manufacturer’s knowledge that the new drug is at least equally
    effective and poses a lower risk of side effects, we think it is
    foreseeable that the manufacturer’s delay in commercializing the
    new drug will cause some users to suffer injury they could have
    avoided had the new drug been available. Although the factors
    Gilead identifies affect the extent of harm that will be
    anticipated, and therefore will factor into any evaluation of the
    reasonableness of the manufacturer’s conduct, they do not alter
    the conclusion that Gilead’s proposed expansive exception will
    result in foreseeable injury. Speaking generally, as we must in
    applying Rowland, Gilead’s proposed expansive exception, which
    would permit manufacturers to delay the release of a safer drug
    indefinitely, will make otherwise avoidable injury foreseeable.
    Degree of certainty that the plaintiff suffered injury. “The
    second Rowland factor, the degree of certainty that the plaintiff
    suffered injury, ‘has been noted primarily, if not exclusively,
    when the only claimed injury is an intangible harm such as
    41
    emotional distress.’ ” (Kesner, supra, 1 Cal.5th at p. 1148.)
    Because we assume the existing drug creates identifiable and
    characteristic physical injury, the fact of injury is certain.
    Closeness of the connection between the defendant’s conduct
    and the injury. This factor is “strongly related to the question of
    foreseeability itself.” (Cabral, supra, 51 Cal.4th at p. 779.) The
    premise of our analysis is that some patients will suffer the
    warned-of side effects associated with the existing drug and the
    manufacturer knows that the alternative drug would allow some
    of those patients to avoid them. We therefore find the connection
    close even though, as Gilead points out in its foreseeability
    analysis, there are two additional steps in the causal chain that
    are necessary in order for patients to avoid the harm: first, the
    FDA must approve the alternative drug candidate, and second,
    the patient’s doctor must decide to switch the patient to the new
    medication after it is approved. Of the two, we view the second
    consideration as less significant because once the FDA has
    approved an alternative that is safer and at least equally
    effective for the patient concerned, the manufacturer would
    reasonably expect doctors to prescribe the new medication in
    place of the old. (Cf. T.H., 
    supra,
     4 Cal.5th at p. 167 [close
    connection where defective label led doctor to prescribe the
    drug].)
    As to the question of FDA approval, we do not doubt that
    there is often considerable uncertainty associated with it. While
    plaintiffs’ claim here was brought after the FDA approved TAF,
    hindsight bias should not be permitted to affect the analysis.
    42
    Plaintiffs do not dispute the assertion by Gilead and its amici
    that, of medicines entering clinical trials, fewer than one out of
    eight will obtain FDA approval. However, because we are
    considering a categorical exception that would apply at any point
    in the development process to a drug candidate that the
    manufacturer knows to be as effective as, and safer than, an
    existing drug, these two common grounds for denial of FDA
    approval are likely to be adequately addressed. That makes FDA
    approval far less uncertain than might otherwise be the case.17
    While the record does not tell us whether the example of
    TAF is typical, plaintiffs emphasize that TAF was another form
    of the known compound tenofovir; Gilead made its decision to
    pause development after TDF had already been approved by the
    FDA, and after Gilead had the results of its Phase I/II testing of
    TAF. Plaintiffs contend that Gilead knew FDA approval of TAF
    would not be difficult, and their allegation that Gilead was
    motivated by its concern that TAF would cannibalize sales of
    TDF and believed it could maximize profitability by extending
    the life of its tenofovir patents necessarily assumes as much.
    Nothing in the record presented to us establishes that drug
    17 Some commentators have argued that any design defect
    claim that requires a court to predict whether the FDA would
    approve what a plaintiff proposes as a “reasonable alternative
    design” of the allegedly defective drug is unworkable given the
    uncertainty involved. (See, e.g., Twerski, The Demise of Drug
    Design Litigation: Death by Federal Preemption (2018) 68 Am. U.
    L.Rev. 281, 295.) We do not see the same uncertainty, at least as
    a categorical matter, in a situation in which the manufacturer
    has developed an alternative drug that it knows to be safer than
    its original drug.
    43
    companies are never able, at any point, to assess the likelihood of
    FDA approval of a particular medicine beyond what can be
    gleaned from general industry averages. Drug manufacturers’
    decisions about whether to continue to pursue commercialization
    of a drug are presumably informed in part by their assessment of
    the likelihood of FDA approval; Gilead does not argue to the
    contrary. We are not persuaded that the need for FDA approval
    necessarily renders the harm unforeseeable or severs what would
    otherwise be a close connection between the manufacturer’s
    decisions and the patients’ harm.
    Finally, citing O’Neil, supra, 53 Cal.4th at p. 365, Gilead
    argues that we should not find a close connection because the
    alleged negligent conduct is not the manufacturer’s sale of the
    injurious product, i.e., the existing drug. But O’Neil concerned
    the circumstances under which a manufacturer could be held
    liable for injuries caused by products it did not manufacture, sell,
    or supply. That is not the situation we are considering here, and
    the fact that the alleged negligence is the decision to delay
    commercialization of the alternative drug rather than the sale of
    the existing, more dangerous drug does not make the connection
    between the negligent conduct and the injury remote where the
    manufacturer has control over the timing of the availability of
    the safer drug. (See T.H., 
    supra,
     4 Cal.5th at p. 168
    [distinguishing O’Neil based on brand-name drug manufacturer’s
    control over the content of the label].)
    44
    Accordingly, the foreseeability factors weigh against
    Gilead’s proposed expansive Rowland exception to the duty of
    reasonable care.
    ii.    Public policy factors
    “[F]oreseeability alone is not sufficient to create an
    independent tort duty. ‘ “ . . . [The] existence [of a duty] depends
    upon the foreseeability of the risk and a weighing of policy
    considerations for and against imposition of liability.” ’ ” (Erlich
    v. Menezes (1999) 
    21 Cal.4th 543
    , 552.) “The overall policy of
    preventing future harm is ordinarily served, in tort law, by
    imposing the costs of negligent conduct upon those responsible.
    The policy question is whether that consideration is outweighed,
    for a category of negligent conduct, by laws or mores indicating
    approval of the conduct or by the undesirable consequences of
    allowing potential liability.” (Cabral, 
    supra,
     51 Cal.4th at p. 781;
    see Merrill, 
    supra,
     26 Cal.4th at p. 502 [foreseeability may be
    overcome “where the social utility of the activity concerned is so
    great, and avoidance of the injuries so burdensome to society, as
    to outweigh the compensatory and cost-internalization values of
    negligence liability”].)
    The final four factors of the Rowland test are referred to as
    the “public policy factors” (Cabral, supra, 51 Cal.4th at p. 781):
    “the moral blame attached to the defendant’s conduct, the policy
    of preventing future harm, the extent of the burden to the
    defendant and consequences to the community of imposing a duty
    to exercise care with resulting liability for breach, and the
    45
    availability, cost, and prevalence of insurance for the risk
    involved.” (Rowland, supra, 69 Cal.2d at p. 113.)
    Moral blame. Developing and selling a life-saving drug,
    even one with potentially severe side-effects, is morally
    praiseworthy. But that is not the conduct at issue; Gilead seeks
    an exception that would allow, in a sense, the opposite conduct: a
    manufacturer’s decision not to market, or to delay marketing, a
    drug it invented that would avoid the harm caused by an existing
    drug that the manufacturer continues to sell. “We have said that
    if there were reasonable ameliorative steps the defendant could
    have taken, there can be moral blame ‘attached to the
    defendants’ failure to take steps to avert the foreseeable harm.’ ”
    (Vasilenko v. Grace Family Church (2017) 
    3 Cal.5th 1077
    , 1091
    (Vasilenko).)
    Moral blame is typically found when the defendant benefits
    financially from its conduct. (Kuciemba, supra, 15 Cal.5th at
    p. 1025; Kesner, 
    supra,
     1 Cal.5th at p. 1151.) In general, drug
    manufacturers reasonably expect to profit from the medicines
    they sell, and the exception Gilead seeks would allow them to
    extend the time patients are subjected to the risks associated
    with a more dangerous drug precisely because delaying the
    commercialization of a safer alternative would confer a financial
    benefit.
    In addition, “[r]elative inequality between the parties may
    also bear upon moral blame. ‘We have previously assigned moral
    blame, and we have relied in part on that blame in finding a
    duty, in instances where the plaintiffs are particularly powerless
    46
    or unsophisticated compared to the defendants or where the
    defendants exercised greater control over the risks at issue.’ ”
    (Kuciemba, supra, 15 Cal.5th at p. 1026.) Users of a particular
    medicine generally have no ability to avoid its harmful side
    effects. (Brown, supra, 44 Cal.3d at p. 1063.) And it is the
    manufacturer’s decisions about commercialization of the safer
    alternative that are the primary determinants of whether
    patients will continue to be subject to those risks. (Compare
    Vasilenko, 
    supra,
     3 Cal.5th at p. 1091 [finding little moral blame
    because “landowners have limited ability to reduce the danger
    and generally exercise no greater control over the danger than
    the invitees who cross” public streets] with Kesner, 
    supra,
    1 Cal.5th at p. 1151 [finding moral blame because “commercial
    users of asbestos benefitted financially from their use of asbestos
    and had greater information and control over the hazard than
    employees’ households”].)
    We can agree with Gilead that a manufacturer’s decision to
    delay the commercialization of a safer drug may be made for
    morally neutral, or even worthy, reasons. But while we do not
    assume in considering the requested exception that any claimed
    violation of duty will involve the precise conduct that plaintiffs
    attribute to Gilead in this case, our task is to evaluate the degree
    of moral blame that attaches to negligence in a drug
    manufacturer’s decisions about commercializing a safer drug, not
    to potential non-negligent reasons for its actions. (See, e.g.,
    Kesner, 
    supra,
     1 Cal.5th at p. 1151 [“negligence in their use of
    asbestos is morally blameworthy”]; Regents of University of
    47
    California v. Superior Court (2018) 
    4 Cal.5th 607
    , 631 [“Some
    measure of moral blame does attach to a university’s negligent
    failure to prevent violence against its students”].) Gilead argues
    that we are concerned here only with drugs that are not shown to
    be defective and so should be considered “reasonably safe.” But
    even putting aside what plaintiffs contend are increasingly
    insurmountable legal barriers to the assertion of design defect
    claims notwithstanding their substantive merit, a life-saving
    drug may be considered reasonably safe, in the sense that its
    risks are outweighed by its benefits, even when its side effects
    are grievously injurious. That such side effects are an acceptable
    trade-off when life is at stake does not mean that the
    manufacturer’s decision to continue to subject patients to those
    injuries unnecessarily by delaying or withholding a safer
    alternative is morally unobjectionable.
    In sum, although moral blame “can be difficult to assess in
    the absence of a factual record” (Kesner, 
    supra,
     1 Cal.5th at
    p. 1151), we conclude based on the considerations above that
    negligence in a decision that deprives people of a safer drug and
    leaves them reliant on a more dangerous drug is morally
    blameworthy.
    Policy of preventing future harm. The “policy of preventing
    future harm is ordinarily served, in tort law, by imposing the
    costs of negligent conduct upon those responsible.” (Cabral,
    supra, 51 Cal.4th at p. 781.) For the purpose of the Rowland
    analysis, “[t]he policy question is whether that consideration is
    outweighed, for a category of negligent conduct, by laws or mores
    48
    indicating approval of the conduct or by the undesirable
    consequences of allowing potential liability.” (Id. at pp. 781–782.)
    This factor thus “examines both the positive and the negative
    societal consequences of recognizing a tort duty.” (Kuciemba,
    supra, 15 Cal.5th at p. 1026.)
    Plaintiffs argue that recognizing a duty would result in
    speedier delivery of improved medications, whereas Gilead
    contends that the fear of liability or litigation would
    disincentivize manufacturers from undertaking the development
    of improved drugs in the first place, or would perversely skew
    their development priorities once they have produced some data
    suggesting that a drug candidate is safer.
    Gilead purports to find support for its argument in Brown,
    because the court rejected strict liability out of a concern that it
    would make pharmaceutical manufacturers reluctant to
    undertake research projects to develop new drugs or to distribute
    others that are available to be marketed. (Brown, supra,
    44 Cal.3d at p. 1063.) But as the court pointed out in its analysis,
    that possibility arises in significant part because strict liability
    makes manufacturers liable for unforeseen and unforeseeable
    harm. (See id. at pp. 1063–1064; see also Carlin, 
    supra,
    13 Cal.4th at p. 1117 [Brown’s policy-based rejection of strict
    liability for design defects was premised on the fact that it would
    “potentially subject drug manufacturers to liability for flaws in
    their products that they have not, and could not have,
    discovered”].) As we have discussed, the court expressly declined
    to protect them from claims based in negligence, in which the
    49
    harm must be foreseeable. (Brown, at p. 1069, fn. 12.)18
    Moreover, while drug manufacturers have continued to resist the
    imposition of liability in other contexts by asserting that it would
    chill innovation, courts after Brown have declined to accept those
    assertions as unsupported by an evidentiary showing. (See, e.g.,
    Carlin, 
    supra,
     13 Cal.4th at p. 1117; T.H., 
    supra,
     4 Cal.5th at
    p. 173; Conte, 
    supra,
     168 Cal.App.4th at p. 106.) It is similarly
    unsupported here.
    Gilead elsewhere argues that the imposition of the duty
    plaintiffs propose is unnecessary, contending that “[i]f a drug
    manufacturer has a treatment that is much better or safer than
    what is already on the market, it has an economic imperative to
    bring it to market as soon as possible.” Plaintiffs disagree,
    arguing that the patent system incentivizes drug manufacturers
    to try to extend their monopolies for as long as possible, with
    deleterious effects on innovation and competition. (See, e.g.,
    Bernstein, supra, at pp. 71–74; Gurgula, Strategic Patenting by
    Pharmaceutical Companies—Should Competition Law Intervene?,
    IIC Int Rev Ind Prop Copyr Law 2020; 51(9): 1062–1085,
    https://doi.org/10.1007/s40319-020-00985-0 [as of Jan. 4, 2024].)
    18 Plaintiffs also note that Brown’s categorical exemption
    for strict liability design defect claims is the minority view among
    courts that have adopted comment k (see Moss v. Wyeth Inc.
    (D. Conn. 2012) 
    872 F.Supp.2d 162
    , 167–168), and assert that
    fear of potential liability in other jurisdictions has not damaged
    the pharmaceutical industry. The significance of that point,
    however, may be diminished by what plaintiffs elsewhere
    describe as the substantial elimination of design defect claims by
    federal preemption.
    50
    Plaintiffs’ argument supports a conclusion that the duty of care
    serves an important policy function, but even if we credit Gilead’s
    suggestion that the duty aligns with economic imperatives that
    drug manufacturers already face, it would tend to undermine the
    hypothesis that imposition of the duty would radically alter their
    incentives to improve existing drugs or develop new ones. And
    again, we are considering here a duty that arises only with the
    manufacturer’s knowledge that the alternative drug candidate it
    has invented is safer and would allow harm to be avoided. (See
    T.H., 
    supra,
     4 Cal.5th at p. 185 [policy of preventing future harm
    is furthered when the duty is placed on the entity with the power
    to act].) Moreover, although below we conclude that Gilead has
    not supported its proposed narrower exception on the existing
    record, the potential availability of a narrower exception
    militates against a conclusion that the broader one is necessary
    to avoid the undesirable social consequences that Gilead posits.
    Finally, we emphasize that the duty of reasonable care does
    not require the pursuit of commercialization at all costs. Even if
    we assume that there will be some circumstances in which the
    duty causes a manufacturer to pursue a potentially safer product
    longer than it otherwise would have, resulting in some failed or
    wasted efforts, that loss must be weighed against the benefit to
    the community from successful efforts, which will result in safer
    products.
    In short, we are not persuaded that Gilead has established
    that there are “undesirable consequences of allowing potential
    liability” (Cabral, supra, 51 Cal.4th at p. 782) that should
    51
    override the ordinary rule “imposing the costs of negligent
    conduct upon those responsible” in these circumstances (id. at
    p. 781).
    The burden to the defendant and consequences to the
    community. Because the “consequences to the community”
    portion of this factor overlaps with our discussion of the policy of
    preventing future harm (cf. T.H., supra, 4 Cal.5th at pp. 168–
    173), we focus here on what Gilead contends will be an additional
    burden; namely, a flood of lawsuits because patients will contend
    that every improved medicine released by a manufacturer should
    have been made available sooner.
    We think Gilead overstates the threat given the
    narrowness of the duty at issue. It does not apply generally to
    “improved” products, but only to products that the manufacturer
    knows will avoid significant side effects of a manufacturer’s
    existing product. Gilead does not establish that this situation
    arises so frequently as to result in a flood of litigation. On the
    contrary, if this situation were common, the claim likely would
    have arisen long ago. Nor, contrary to Gilead’s argument, will
    the duty upend products liability by creating a “perfect product”
    law. As we have noted, the duty does not require manufacturers
    to perfect their drugs, but simply to act with reasonable care for
    the users of the existing drug when the manufacturer has
    developed an alternative that it knows is safer and at least
    equally efficacious. Manufacturers already engage in this type of
    innovation in the ordinary course of their business, and most
    52
    plaintiffs would likely face a difficult road in establishing a
    breach of the duty of reasonable care.
    Availability and cost of insurance. Gilead contends that
    recognition of a duty “would massively expand manufacturers’
    existing exposure to liability,” which in turn would increase the
    cost of insurance “if it were available at all” and thereby raise the
    price of prescription medicines. But for the reasons discussed
    above, we are not persuaded that the expansion of liability is
    anywhere near as “massive” as Gilead suggests, and as plaintiffs
    note, there is nothing in the record regarding the cost and
    availability of insurance. We find that the parties have not
    supplied enough information “to settle the question of insurance
    one way or the other.” (Vasilenko, 
    supra,
     3 Cal.5th at p. 1091.)
    Again, the most important factor to be evaluated in
    applying Rowland is the prevention of foreseeable harm. In the
    narrow circumstances in which it applies, plaintiffs’ duty would
    prevent manufacturers from delaying the development of safer
    treatments, thereby avoiding foreseeable harm to a potentially
    large class of persons. Although the duty may impose some
    burdens on pharmaceutical manufacturers, we are not persuaded
    that they would be so great as to overcome the benefit of safer
    products. The expansive exception proposed by Gilead is
    therefore not appropriate.
    2. Gilead’s Narrower Exception
    Although Gilead does not offer two separate Rowland
    analyses, at various points in its supplemental briefing it
    suggests, as a fallback position, a narrower exception tied to
    53
    manufacturers’ Phase III clinical trials, which are the final stage
    in the process required to obtain approval of a new drug.
    Following the submission of preclinical trial data to the FDA, the
    manufacturer conducts clinical trials in three phases. (
    21 C.F.R. §§ 312.23
    (a)(8), 312.21(a)–(c) (2022).) “Phase I clinical trials are
    conducted on healthy volunteers to determine the maximum
    tolerated dose, adverse events, and pharmacokinetics of a
    product. Phase II studies are conducted on a statistically
    relevant number of patients having a specific disease to
    determine initial efficacy in humans for that disease, and to
    identify possible adverse effects and safety risks. Phase III
    studies consist of wide-scale studies on patients with the disease
    for which the drug is intended and evaluate the overall risks and
    benefits of the drug.” (Deveny v. Entropin, Inc. (2006)
    
    139 Cal.App.4th 408
    , 413, fn. 2.) Phase I trials “are generally
    conducted on a small number of healthy volunteer subjects,”
    whereas Phase II trials “usually involve several hundred people”
    and Phase III trials consist of “several hundred to several
    thousand” subjects. (Schiff v. Prados (2001) 
    92 Cal.App.4th 692
    ,
    696, fn. 2.)
    Gilead’s narrower exception would hold that when an FDA-
    approved prescription drug is accompanied by an adequate
    warning of adverse side effects, and is not shown to be defective
    in design or manufacture, the manufacturer does not owe users of
    the previously-approved drug a duty of reasonable care in its
    decisions about commercializing an alternative drug until
    Phase III trials have established its safety and effectiveness.
    54
    We conducted our analysis of the broader Rowland
    exception under the assumption that the duty of care arises when
    the manufacturer knows that the alternative drug candidate is
    safer than, and at least as effective as, the existing drug. But in
    many cases the parties will dispute, as they do in this case,
    whether the manufacturer actually knew that the alternative
    candidate was superior when the manufacturer made the
    decision or decisions at issue. Gilead’s narrower exception
    essentially proposes, as a policy matter, that the amount of
    knowledge necessary to trigger the imposition of a duty of care
    cannot exist before the manufacturer has the results of Phase III
    trials of the alternative drug.19
    i.     Foreseeability factors
    It is reasonable to expect a manufacturer to learn more
    about a drug candidate’s safety and efficacy at each stage of the
    investigation process, so as a general matter, we see no reason to
    doubt that a manufacturer will be able to foresee with greater
    confidence that a new drug will avoid the harmful side effects
    associated with the existing drug, while providing the same
    therapeutic benefit, after Phase III than after Phase II.
    19 Notwithstanding its Phase III proposal, Gilead actually
    contends that “[t]he earliest point at which it would be
    reasonably foreseeable that injury from an existing non-defective
    medicine could be prevented by a new product is when the FDA
    approves the drug and the drug’s comparative safety has been
    proven in head-to-head to studies.” According to Gilead, head-to-
    head studies are not necessary to obtain FDA approval, but are
    required to justify any claim comparing the safety or
    effectiveness of two drugs, and can be conducted during Phase III
    trials or after FDA approval.
    55
    Plaintiffs, however, argue that a manufacturer’s knowledge prior
    to the conclusion of Phase III trials will vary, depending on how
    much is already known about the compound being studied and on
    what the Phase I and II results show.
    While some generalizations are probably necessary to
    evaluate the appropriateness of any proposed Rowland exception,
    here no factual record has been developed in the trial court that
    would allow us to assess the parties’ competing claims. In the
    absence of such a record, we cannot say whether it is possible to
    make any meaningful generalizations about what can reasonably
    be known after Phase II trials as compared to Phase III trials,
    and what those generalizations would be. And we do not know,
    for example, how often, or under what circumstances, a drug’s
    apparent promise after Phase II is undermined by unexpected
    results in Phase III—or how often uncertain Phase II results are
    followed by confirmed successes in Phase III. Thus, on the
    existing record, Gilead has not established that it is not
    foreseeable before Phase III trials that the manufacturer’s
    conduct would cause otherwise avoidable injury.
    ii.   Public policy factors
    The policy rationale for Gilead’s narrow exception is that
    allowing a jury to decide on a case-by-case basis whether the
    manufacturer had the requisite knowledge creates too much
    uncertainty, giving rise to unacceptable burdens on
    manufacturers, such as disincentivizing innovation and causing
    excessive and unwarranted litigation. The exception would
    create a safe harbor period in the drug development process in
    56
    which manufacturers may make decisions without fear that they
    may be second-guessed by a jury, and conversely, would let them
    know with certainty at what point their decisions could be
    scrutinized for failure to exercise reasonable care.
    We do not rule out the possibility that such an exception
    could be warranted. “In conducting its [duty] analysis, the court
    may take into account factors that might escape the jury’s
    attention in a particular case, such as the overall social impact of
    imposing a significant precautionary obligation on a class of
    actors. These cases are properly decided as duty or no-duty
    cases. When no such categorical considerations apply and
    reasonable minds could differ about the competing risks and
    burdens or the foreseeability of the risks in a specific case,
    however, courts should not use duty and no-duty determinations
    to substitute their evaluation for that of the factfinder.” (Cabral,
    
    supra,
     51 Cal.4th at p. 773, fn. 3 [quoting Rest.3d Torts, Liability
    for Physical and Emotional Harm, § 7, com. i, pp. 81–82].) As
    Brown indicates, “categorical considerations” may come into play
    in the prescription drug context, although nothing in that case
    suggests that manufacturers need greater protection than the
    decision itself supplies.
    Still, we believe a decision to delay commercialization of a
    new drug, when it is made earlier in the development process,
    may be more complicated and challenging for a jury to evaluate,
    and more susceptible to hindsight bias, than one made after
    Phase III trials are completed. Phase III trials are likely to be
    substantially more difficult and expensive than those occurring
    57
    during Phases I and II, so the burden on pharmaceutical
    manufacturers is undoubtedly greater if those trials are
    undertaken out of a “precautionary obligation.” On the other
    hand, plaintiffs counter that the proposed exception would render
    the remaining duty of care largely toothless because
    manufacturers often have sufficient information after Phase II
    and, like Gilead, could simply make the relevant decisions at that
    point in order to avoid liability.
    Ultimately, however, the problem remains the lack of a
    factual record by which to assess whether it is appropriate to
    recognize a categorical exception for decisions made before the
    completion of Phase III trials. We recognize that the
    appropriateness of a Rowland exception can sometimes be
    identified early in a case, even on a motion addressed to the
    pleadings. (See, e.g., Kuciemba, supra, 14 Cal.5th at p. 1004;
    Kesner, 
    supra,
     1 Cal.5th at p. 1142.) In other cases, it is raised
    later, at summary judgment or even after a jury verdict. (E.g.,
    Vasilenko, 
    supra,
     3 Cal.5th at pp. 1082–1083; Cabral, 
    supra,
    51 Cal.4th at p. 770.) While the Rowland analysis does not focus
    on the defendant’s specific conduct, it may still present difficult
    factual questions that cannot be reliably resolved simply by
    weighing competing assertions in briefs by the parties and their
    amici. We conclude that Gilead has failed to establish that its
    narrow exception is warranted on the current record. However,
    our conclusion does not prevent Gilead from seeking the
    exception based on a record developed later in the trial court,
    58
    both before that court and, if necessary, on appeal from an
    adverse judgment.
    II.   Fraudulent Concealment
    Plaintiffs’ cause of action for fraudulent concealment
    alleges that Gilead was required to disclose that (1) TAF was a
    safer means for delivering tenofovir into the body, (2) the toxicity
    of tenofovir was not unavoidable, and (3) Gilead’s true motive for
    shelving TAF development was financial. Gilead argues that it is
    entitled to summary adjudication of this claim because it was
    under no duty to disclose to plaintiffs facts relating to TAF, which
    was not available as an alternative to TDF for the treatment of
    HIV/AIDS. We agree.
    “ ‘[T]he elements of an action for fraud and deceit based on
    a concealment are: (1) the defendant must have concealed or
    suppressed a material fact, (2) the defendant must have been
    under a duty to disclose the fact to the plaintiff, (3) the defendant
    must have intentionally concealed or suppressed the fact with the
    intent to defraud the plaintiff, (4) the plaintiff must have been
    unaware of the fact and would not have acted as he did if he had
    known of the concealed or suppressed fact, and (5) as a result of
    the concealment or suppression of the fact, the plaintiff must
    have sustained damage.’ ” (Roddenberry v. Roddenberry (1996)
    
    44 Cal.App.4th 634
    , 665–666.)
    As explained in Bigler-Engler v. Breg, Inc. (2017)
    
    7 Cal.App.5th 276
    , in the absence of a fiduciary relationship
    between the parties, the law “ ‘presuppose[s] the existence of
    some other relationship between the plaintiff and defendant in
    59
    which a duty to disclose can arise.’ [Citation.] . . . [¶] Our
    Supreme Court has described the necessary relationship giving
    rise to a duty to disclose as a ‘transaction’ between the plaintiff
    and the defendant . . . . Such a transaction must necessarily
    arise from direct dealings between the plaintiff and the
    defendant; it cannot arise between the defendant and the public
    at large.” (Id. at pp. 311–312.) Once the necessary relationship
    is found, a duty arises “to disclose facts material to the
    transaction.” (LiMandri v. Judkins (1997) 
    52 Cal.App.4th 326
    ,
    337.) We have recently held, for example, that a vehicle
    manufacturer owes a duty to purchasers of its vehicles to disclose
    known defects. (Dhital v. Nissan North America, Inc. (2022)
    
    84 Cal.App.5th 828
    , 844; see similarly, Snow v. A. H. Robins Co.
    (1985) 
    165 Cal.App.3d 120
    , 134–135 [manufacturer of
    intrauterine device had duty to disclose higher pregnancy rates
    from its use].)
    Assuming that plaintiffs’ use of Gilead’s product, TDF,
    created the relationship necessary to invoke the law of
    concealment, we nonetheless conclude that such a duty did not
    extend to the disclosure of information about TAF. Gilead owed a
    duty to plaintiffs to disclose information material to the
    transaction that created the disclosure relationship—plaintiffs’
    use of TDF as a medicine. The facts material to this treatment
    decision concerned the efficacy, side effects, risks, and cost of
    TDF, which plaintiffs and their physicians could compare with
    similar information about other available medicines in deciding
    the best course of treatment. For the 14 years between the
    60
    commencement of Gilead’s sales of TDF and the FDA’s approval
    of TAF as an HIV/AIDS medication, TAF was not available to
    patients as a treatment. Information about a chemical compound
    that was not available as a treatment, and could not possibly
    become available as a treatment for many years as a result of the
    time-consuming FDA approval process, would not have been
    material to the treatment decision. Even the acknowledgment by
    Gilead that the toxicity of tenofovir was avoidable, as plaintiffs
    allege, would have been of no use to patients in deciding whether
    to take TDF, since their choice was between TDF and other
    available medications, not between TDF and its allegedly safer
    counterpart, TAF.
    Plaintiffs argue that disclosure of information about TAF
    might have affected physicians’ practices in prescribing TDF, but
    their reasoning is impermissibly speculative. Plaintiffs argue, in
    effect, that the disclosure of information suggesting that TAF was
    a superior alternative to TDF might have biased physicians
    against the use of TDF. This bias, they theorize, would have
    caused physicians to decrease their use of TDF, even though the
    disclosure would have in no way changed the value of TDF
    relative to other available treatments.20 It is not clear, however,
    20 For example, plaintiffs cite evidence suggesting some
    Gilead employees were concerned that disclosure of information
    about TAF would change medical perceptions of the risk profile of
    TDF. Such a change in perception, however, would not have been
    based on the relative value of TDF and other available
    medications. Rather, it would have been the result of bias
    against TDF generated by physicians’ knowledge that Gilead
    could, if it chose, have produced a safer drug.
    61
    that information about TAF should be considered material to the
    treatment decision merely because it might have changed that
    decision for irrational reasons. Plaintiffs’ contention is, in any
    event, entirely speculative and does not make information about
    TAF material to the decision to use TDF.
    Plaintiffs also cite their allegation that Gilead stopped
    work on TAF because Gilead believed that a TAF-containing
    medication would “cannibalize” its sales of TDF. Even if true,
    that motivation did not create a duty to disclose information
    about TAF. TAF could cannibalize TDF sales only if TAF existed
    as an alternative treatment. So long as Gilead chose to avoid
    cannibalization by keeping TAF from the market, information
    about TAF’s efficacy and risks relative to TDF had no bearing on
    physicians’ or patients’ treatment decisions.
    DISPOSITION
    Gilead’s petition for a writ of mandate is denied in part and
    granted in part. Let a peremptory writ of mandate issue
    directing the superior court to vacate its order denying Gilead’s
    motion for summary judgment, dated June 13, 2022, and enter a
    new and different order denying summary adjudication of
    Count I of plaintiffs’ Master Long Form Complaint for Damages
    and granting summary adjudication of Count V of that document.
    The stay imposed in our order of September 9, 2022, shall remain
    in effect until issuance of the remittitur. Plaintiffs shall recover
    their costs on appeal.
    GOLDMAN, J.
    WE CONCUR:
    62
    BROWN, P. J.
    BURNS, J. *
    * Associate Justice of the Court of Appeal, First Appellate
    District, Division Five, assigned by the Chief Justice pursuant to
    article VI, section 6 of the California Constitution.
    63
    Trial Court:                             City and County of San Francisco Superior
    Court
    Trial Judge:                             Honorable Andrew Y.S. Cheng
    Gilead Sciences, Inc., Defendant and     SIDLEY AUSTIN, Debra Pole, Joshua
    Petitioner:                              Anderson, Sean Commons, David Carpenter,
    Collin Wedel
    ORRICK, HERRINGTON & SUTCLIFFE,
    Andrew Silverman, Siobhan Atkins, Cesar
    Lopez-Morales, E. Joshua Rosenkranz
    Superior Court of the City & County of   No attorneys listed
    San Francisco, Respondent:
    Plaintiffs in JCCP No. 5043 Gilead       GRANT & EISENHOFFER, M. Elizabeth
    Tenofovir Cases, Real Parties in         Graham
    Interest                                 JENNER LAW, Robert K. Jenner
    MOSKOVITZ APPELLATE TEAM, Myron
    Moskovitz
    KERSHAW, COOK & TALLEY, William A.
    Kershaw
    SCHNEIDER WALLACE COTTRELL
    KONECKY, Amy Eskin
    ESNER, CHANG & BOYER, Andrew N.
    Chang, Holly N. Boyer
    The California Chamber of Commerce,      DLA PIPER, Justin R. Sarno, Adam Pierson,
    The Chamber of Commerce of the           Ilana H. Eisenstein, Ben C. Fabens-Lassen
    U.S.A., The Alliance for Automotive
    Innovation, The Washington Legal
    Foundation, Amici
    Washington Legal Foundation, Amicus      WASHINGTON LEGAL FOUNDATION,
    Cory L. Andrews
    Pharmaceutical Research and              COVINGTON & BURLING, Ashley M.
    Manufacturers of America                 Simonsen, Alice L. Phillips, Michael X.
    (“PHRMA”), Amicus                        Imbroscio, Emily Ullman, Gregory L.
    Halperin
    American Association for Justice and     THE ARKIN LAW FIRM, Sharon J. Arkin
    Consumer Attorneys of California,        AMERICAN ASSOCIATION FOR JUSTICE,
    Amici                                    Jeffrey R. White
    64
    Product Liability Advisory Council,    BUCHALTER, Mary-Christine Sungaila, Paul
    Inc., Amicus                           A. Alarcon
    Public Justice, Amicus                 PUBLIC JUSTICE, Karla Gilbride
    65
    

Document Info

Docket Number: A165558M

Filed Date: 2/1/2024

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 2/1/2024