Bilbao v. Goodwin ( 2019 )


Menu:
  • ***********************************************
    The “officially released” date that appears near the be-
    ginning of each opinion is the date the opinion will be pub-
    lished in the Connecticut Law Journal or the date it was
    released as a slip opinion. The operative date for the be-
    ginning of all time periods for filing postopinion motions
    and petitions for certification is the “officially released”
    date appearing in the opinion.
    All opinions are subject to modification and technical
    correction prior to official publication in the Connecticut
    Reports and Connecticut Appellate Reports. In the event of
    discrepancies between the advance release version of an
    opinion and the latest version appearing in the Connecticut
    Law Journal and subsequently in the Connecticut Reports
    or Connecticut Appellate Reports, the latest version is to
    be considered authoritative.
    The syllabus and procedural history accompanying the
    opinion as it appears in the Connecticut Law Journal and
    bound volumes of official reports are copyrighted by the
    Secretary of the State, State of Connecticut, and may not
    be reproduced and distributed without the express written
    permission of the Commission on Official Legal Publica-
    tions, Judicial Branch, State of Connecticut.
    ***********************************************
    JESSICA BILBAO v. TIMOTHY R. GOODWIN
    (SC 20078)
    Robinson, C. J., and Palmer, McDonald, D’Auria,
    Mullins, Kahn and Ecker, Js.
    Syllabus
    The defendant appealed from the judgment of the trial court dissolving his
    marriage to the plaintiff and awarding her certain pre-embryos that the
    parties had cryopreserved after having created them through in vitro
    fertilization during their marriage. The parties had entered into a storage
    agreement with the reproductive services center responsible for cryo-
    preserving the pre-embryos. The storage agreement contained checkbox
    options that provided for disposition of the pre-embryos under certain
    circumstances. The parties checked the box indicating that they agreed
    to have the pre-embryos discarded in the event that they divorced,
    initialed their selection, and signed the agreement. The plaintiff asked
    the trial court to order that the pre-embryos be discarded in accordance
    with the storage agreement, whereas the defendant claimed that he had
    changed his mind, was no longer bound by that provision of the storage
    agreement, and wanted the pre-embryos preserved so that the parties
    could have children in the event that they reconciled or, in the alternative,
    wanted the pre-embryos to be donated. The trial court determined that
    the storage agreement was not enforceable because it lacked consider-
    ation. The court then awarded the pre-embryos to the plaintiff, conclud-
    ing that the plaintiff’s interest in them outweighed the defendant’s inter-
    est. On appeal, the defendant claimed that the trial court incorrectly
    determined that a pre-embryo is property subject to distribution under
    the statute (§ 46b-81) governing distribution of the marital estate upon
    divorce and also claimed that, even if it is property, in the absence of
    an enforceable contractual agreement, the court failed to employ a legal
    presumption in his favor as the party seeking to preserve the pre-embryos
    because they are human beings. Held:
    1. This court concluded that the contractual approach to determining the
    disposition of a pre-embryo upon divorce, pursuant to which an agree-
    ment between progenitors governing the disposition of a pre-embryo
    is presumed valid and enforceable in a dispute between them, is the
    appropriate first step in such a determination, reasoning that progenitors
    should be the primary decision makers regarding the disposition of their
    pre-embryos, there are significant benefits to making such a decision
    in advance rather than at the moment of disposition, such an approach
    is consistent with Connecticut’s public policy and the current practices
    of most state courts that have confronted the issue, and various profes-
    sional associations focusing on the field of reproductive medicine recom-
    mend advance directives regarding the disposition of pre-embryos in
    the event of divorce; moreover, this court clarified that such an approach
    applies in cases in which an agreement, if enforced, will not result in
    procreation and declined to decide whether such an approach would
    apply to a scenario in which one party would be compelled to become
    a genetic parent against his or her wishes or what approach a court
    should take in the absence of an enforceable agreement.
    2. The trial court incorrectly determined that the parties had not entered
    into an enforceable agreement to discard the pre-embryos upon divorce,
    and, accordingly, this court reversed the trial court’s judgment insofar
    as that court determined that their agreement was not enforceable,
    vacated the trial court’s order awarding the pre-embryos to the plaintiff,
    and remanded the case with direction to order the disposition of the
    pre-embryos in accordance with the agreement: there was an offer and
    an acceptance of definite terms, as each party offered the other the
    opportunity to create pre-embryos by contributing gametic material
    under the terms of the agreement, and each party accepted the other’s
    offer by signing the agreement and contributing gametic material; more-
    over, the trial court’s determination that the storage agreement lacked
    consideration was clearly erroneous, as the plaintiff and the defendant
    made mutual promises to contribute gametic material, and the reproduc-
    tive services center promised to store the pre-embryos in exchange for
    the certainty provided by the parties’ election of a disposition in the
    event of the parties’ divorce; furthermore, the trial court’s focus on the
    checkbox nature of the storage agreement to conclude that the agree-
    ment was unenforceable was misplaced, as agreements in which parties
    use checkboxes to indicate their rights and responsibilities are not
    insufficient for that reason alone, checkboxes, sometimes accompanied
    by the parties’ initials, are routinely used in important and binding legal
    documents, and any suggestion that the checkboxes were evidence that
    the parties had not seriously considered the matter of disposition was
    contradicted by the storage agreement and the parties’ testimony.
    3. This court having determined that there was an enforceable agreement,
    the defendant could not prevail on his claims that, in the absence of a
    contractual agreement, a pre-embryo is not property within the meaning
    of § 46b-81 because it is a human life or, if it is deemed property, that
    the trial court should have applied a presumption in favor of preserving
    the pre-embryos, as those claims incorrectly presupposed that there
    was no enforceable contract between the parties; moreover, to the extent
    that the defendant claimed that an agreement that provides for the
    disposition of a pre-embryo is unenforceable on the ground that a pre-
    embryo is a human life, this court declined to review that claim for lack
    of an adequate record, as the defendant did not raise such a claim at
    trial and did not even appear to make that argument on appeal.
    Argued April 30—officially released November 5, 2019
    Procedural History
    Action for the dissolution of a marriage, and for other
    relief, brought to the Superior Court in the judicial dis-
    trict of Hartford and tried to the court, Nastri, J.; judg-
    ment dissolving the marriage and granting certain other
    relief, from which the defendant appealed. Reversed in
    part; vacated in part; order directed.
    Joseph P. Secola, with whom, on the brief, was Timo-
    thy R. Goodwin, self-represented, for the appellant
    (defendant).
    Scott T. Garosshen, with whom were Brendon P.
    Levesque and, on the brief, Michael S. Taylor, for the
    appellee (plaintiff).
    Leslie I. Jennings-Lax and Louise T. Truax filed
    a brief for the Connecticut Chapter of the American
    Academy of Matrimonial Lawyers as amicus curiae.
    Rita Louise Lowery Gitchell, pro hac vice, Philip S.
    Walker and Joanne F. Davis filed a brief for the Ameri-
    can Association of Pro-Life Obstetricians and Gynecolo-
    gists as amicus curiae.
    Opinion
    D’AURIA, J. In this appeal, we are called on to deter-
    mine how pre-embryos created through in vitro fertiliza-
    tion should be distributed upon the divorce of their
    progenitors. The plaintiff, Jessica Bilbao, and the defen-
    dant, Timothy R. Goodwin, were married and under-
    went in vitro fertilization in an effort to have children.
    Several pre-embryos resulting from that treatment were
    stored for implantation in the future.1 As part of a stor-
    age agreement with the fertility clinic, the parties
    unequivocally stated that they wanted the pre-embryos
    discarded if they ever divorced. Their marriage has
    since been dissolved, and the plaintiff now seeks to
    have the pre-embryos discarded in accordance with
    the storage agreement. The defendant argues that the
    agreement is unenforceable, however, and wants the
    pre-embryos preserved or donated. The trial court con-
    cluded that the storage agreement was unenforceable
    but awarded the pre-embryos to the plaintiff. We con-
    clude that the storage agreement is enforceable and,
    therefore, reverse the trial court’s judgment insofar as
    the court determined that the agreement was not
    enforceable.
    The record reveals the following undisputed facts
    as found by the trial court and contained in exhibits
    submitted by the parties. The parties were married in
    2011. Soon after, they began efforts to have a child
    through in vitro fertilization with the assistance of the
    University of Connecticut School of Medicine’s Center
    for Advanced Reproductive Services (center). The treat-
    ment produced several pre-embryos, one of which was
    transferred to the plaintiff’s uterus and resulted in the
    birth of a child. The center cryopreserved the remaining
    pre-embryos.2
    Originally, the parties had planned to have another
    child using the remaining pre-embryos. But, together,
    they also planned for certain contingencies by entering
    into a storage agreement with the center: a four page
    form entitled ‘‘Consent for Cryopreservation and Stor-
    age of Embryos’’ that provided for the disposition of
    the pre-embryos upon death or divorce. Specifically,
    the agreement offered four checkbox options relative
    to divorce: leave the pre-embryos to the female party,
    to the male party, to a third-party designee of their
    choice, or have them ‘‘discarded according to American
    Society for Reproductive Medicine Ethical Guidelines.’’
    The parties opted to have the pre-embryos discarded,
    which they manifested by checking the appropriate box,
    initialing that selection, and signing the agreement in
    full on the next page. The parties also acknowledged
    in the agreement that they had discussed the agreement
    with a physician, and the agreement provided that the
    parties could modify their selection through written
    consent signed by both of them.
    In September, 2016, the plaintiff filed this action for
    dissolution of marriage. With the assistance of counsel,
    the parties reached a settlement agreement that
    resolved all of their disputes except for the allocation
    of debt from a home loan and the disposition of the
    pre-embryos. The debt allocation is not part of this
    appeal. Regarding the pre-embryos, the plaintiff asked
    the trial court to order that they be discarded in accor-
    dance with the storage agreement. The defendant
    wanted the pre-embryos preserved so that the parties
    could try to have additional children in the event they
    reconciled or, alternatively, wanted the pre-embryos to
    be put up for adoption.3
    The record also reveals the following procedural his-
    tory. Although the parties each had counsel in drafting
    the settlement agreement, they represented themselves
    in this matter before the trial court. To resolve the
    disputes regarding the debt allocation and pre-embryos,
    the trial court held a brief proceeding at which both
    parties testified. The plaintiff submitted the settlement
    agreement and storage agreement as exhibits, but nei-
    ther party filed a substantive motion, submitted a brief,
    or argued legal matters to the court.
    The trial court issued a memorandum of decision in
    which it incorporated the settlement agreement and
    resolved the debt dispute. Regarding the pre-embryos,
    it determined that the storage agreement was not
    enforceable. In the absence of an enforceable agree-
    ment, the court proceeded as if the pre-embryos were
    ‘‘property’’ subject to distribution under General Stat-
    utes § 46b-81,4 concluded that the plaintiff’s interest in
    the pre-embryos outweighed the defendant’s interest
    and, therefore, awarded them to her.
    The defendant appealed to the Appellate Court from
    the trial court’s judgment awarding the pre-embryos to
    the plaintiff. The appeal was then transferred to this
    court. See General Statutes § 51-199 (c); Practice Book
    § 65-1.
    On appeal, the defendant appears to make two claims
    of error, both of which presuppose that the trial court
    correctly determined that the parties lacked an enforce-
    able agreement. The defendant agrees with this portion
    of the trial court’s analysis but disagrees with the trial
    court’s determination that the plaintiff’s interest in the
    pre-embryos outweighed his interest. Specifically, both
    of the defendant’s claims are rooted in his factual prem-
    ise that a pre-embryo is a human being. First, he claims
    that the trial court incorrectly determined that a pre-
    embryo is ‘‘property’’ subject to distribution under
    § 46b-81. Specifically, he argues that a pre-embryo is
    human life and, as such, must be awarded to the party
    seeking to preserve it. Second, he claims that, even if
    a pre-embryo is property under § 46b-81, the trial court
    improperly failed to employ a legal presumption in favor
    of the party seeking to preserve it because it is a
    human being.5
    In response, the plaintiff argues that the trial court
    was incorrect that the parties had no enforceable agree-
    ment and, therefore, urges us to affirm the judgment
    on this alternative ground. See Practice Book §§ 63-4
    and 84-11. We agree with the plaintiff that the parties’
    agreement providing for the disposition of their pre-
    embryos upon divorce is enforceable. Our holding nec-
    essarily defeats the defendant’s claims, which are prem-
    ised on the prerequisite determination that the contract
    was unenforceable. To the extent that the defendant’s
    claims include an argument that a contract requiring
    the destruction of pre-embryos is unenforceable as a
    matter of public policy because a pre-embryo is a human
    being, we find this issue unreviewable because he failed
    to present any evidence at trial to support the factual
    premise that a pre-embryo is a human being. See foot-
    notes 5 and 8 of this opinion.
    As a predicate to the defendant’s claims, we first
    must determine whether the parties’ storage agreement,
    which unambiguously provided that the pre-embryos
    should be discarded in the event of divorce, is enforce-
    able between the plaintiff and the defendant. The trial
    court held that it was not enforceable because it lacked
    consideration and indicated the parties’ disposition
    selection in the form of a checkbox. The defendant
    agrees with the trial court’s analysis. The plaintiff
    argues that the agreement was supported by consider-
    ation and that the checkbox nature of the agreement
    did not render it insufficient. We agree with the plaintiff.
    The following additional procedural history is rele-
    vant. At trial, the enforceability of the storage agree-
    ment was central to the dispute, and the parties’ respec-
    tive positions were clear. The plaintiff submitted the
    storage agreement as evidence and stated that she
    wanted its terms enforced, as the parties had originally
    agreed. The defendant admitted that he originally had
    agreed to discard the pre-embryos if the couple ever
    divorced but argued that he had since changed his mind
    and that this provision of the agreement no longer
    bound him.
    In its memorandum of decision, the trial court noted
    the lack of Connecticut authority on this issue, consid-
    ered the law in other jurisdictions, and adopted a two
    step approach to resolve the dispute. First, it would
    decide whether the parties had an enforceable agree-
    ment that provided for the disposition of the pre-
    embryos. Second, in the absence of an agreement, it
    would balance their respective interests in the pre-
    embryos. In conducting the first step, the trial court
    concluded that the consent form was not an enforceable
    agreement because it ‘‘was little more than a ‘check the
    box questionnaire,’ which had ‘‘neither consideration
    nor a promise.’’ It then proceeded to the second step,
    determined that the plaintiff’s interests in the pre-
    embryos outweighed the defendant’s interests, and
    awarded them to her.
    In the sections of this opinion that follow, we describe
    the current state of the law on pre-embryo disposition
    upon divorce and conclude that the trial court properly
    considered whether the parties had an enforceable
    agreement, but we also conclude that the trial court
    incorrectly determined that the storage agreement was
    unenforceable. We also clarify the narrow scope of
    our decision.
    I
    There are three leading approaches to determining
    the disposition of a pre-embryo upon divorce: (1) the
    contractual approach, (2) the balancing approach, and
    (3) the contemporaneous mutual consent approach.
    Each approach attempts to resolve disputes between
    progenitors by emphasizing different policies: the pro-
    genitors’ autonomy in deciding the fate of pre-embryos
    created with their own gametic material, the reality that
    progenitors may change their minds as time passes,
    or both.
    Under the contractual approach, an agreement
    between progenitors governing disposition of the pre-
    embryos is presumed valid and enforceable in a dispute
    between them. E.g., In re Marriage of Rooks, 
    429 P.3d 579
    , 595 (Colo. 2018), cert. denied sub nom. Rooks v.
    Rooks,         U.S.     , 
    139 S. Ct. 1447
    , 
    203 L. Ed. 2d 681
     (2019). These agreements often appear as consent
    forms or storage agreements between progenitors and
    a fertility clinic. E.g., 
    id., 587
    .
    Proponents of the contractual approach primarily
    argue that this approach allows ‘‘the progenitors—not
    the [s]tate and not the courts . . . [to] make this deeply
    personal life choice.’’ Kass v. Kass, 
    91 N.Y.2d 554
    , 566,
    
    696 N.E.2d 174
    , 
    673 N.Y.S. 2d 350
     (1998). They also note
    that, by validating and enforcing a contract based rule,
    the approach promotes serious discussion between the
    progenitors in advance of divorce, gives progenitors
    and storage facilities a measure of certainty to plan
    for the future, and helps avoid costly and emotionally
    taxing litigation. See, e.g., Terrell v. Torres, 
    246 Ariz. 312
    , 318, 
    438 P.3d 681
     (App. 2019), review granted,
    Arizona Supreme Court, Docket No. CV-19-0106-PR
    (August 27, 2019); Szafranski v. Dunston, 
    993 N.E.2d 502
    , 515 (Ill. App.), appeal denied, 
    996 N.E.2d 24
     (Ill.
    2013); Kass v. Kass, 
    supra,
     565–66.
    Critics of this approach focus on the fact that pre-
    embryos can be stored indefinitely and that progenitors
    might change their minds about disposition as time
    passes. E.g., Terrell v. Torres, supra, 
    246 Ariz. 318
     (con-
    tractual approach ignores ‘‘numerous uncertainties
    inherent in the [in vitro fertilization] process that extend
    . . . the viability of [embryos] indefinitely and allow
    . . . time for minds, and circumstances, to change’’
    [internal quotation marks omitted]); In re Marriage of
    Witten, 
    672 N.W.2d 768
    , 777 (Iowa 2003) (contractual
    approach ‘‘binds individuals to previous obligations,
    even if their priorities or values change’’ [internal quota-
    tion marks omitted]). For some commentators, the fail-
    ure to account for changed circumstances can be so
    great that dispositional agreements ‘‘smack of uncon-
    scionability.’’ E. Waldman, ‘‘Disputing Over Embryos:
    Of Contracts and Consents,’’ 
    32 Ariz. St. L.J. 897
    , 926
    (2000).
    Under the balancing approach, a court weighs each
    progenitor’s interest in the pre-embryos. Factors to con-
    sider include the intended use of the pre-embryos, the
    ability of each respective spouse to reproduce through
    other means, reasons for pursuing in vitro fertilization,
    emotional consequences, and bad faith. See, e.g., In re
    Marriage of Rooks, supra, 
    429 P.3d 588
    , 592–93.
    New Jersey has adopted this approach as the first
    and only step in resolving disputes over the disposition
    of pre-embryos upon divorce. See J.B. v. M.B., 
    170 N.J. 9
    , 29, 
    783 A.2d 707
     (2001). The New Jersey Supreme
    Court has emphasized that it permits progenitors to
    reconsider their initial stances up to the point of disposi-
    tion, which is consistent with that state’s public policy
    of preserving parental rights ‘‘in all but statutorily
    approved circumstances.’’ 
    Id., 27
    . But most courts use
    the balancing approach as a second step, only to be
    employed after it is determined that no enforceable
    agreement between the progenitors exists and, thus,
    that the contractual approach does not resolve the
    issue. See, e.g., In re Marriage of Rooks, supra, 
    429 P.3d 593
    ; Reber v. Reiss, 
    42 A.3d 1131
    , 1136 (Pa. Super.),
    appeal denied, 
    619 Pa. 680
    , 
    62 A.3d 380
     (2012); Davis
    v. Davis, 
    842 S.W.2d 588
    , 604 (Tenn. 1992), cert. denied
    sub nom. Stowe v. Davis, 
    507 U.S. 911
    , 
    113 S. Ct. 1259
    ,
    
    122 L. Ed. 2d 657
     (1993). This is because the balancing
    approach ultimately puts the disposition of a pre-
    embryo in the hands of a court and not in the hands
    of the progenitors.
    Under the contemporaneous mutual consent
    approach, both progenitors must agree to a disposition
    at the time of the disposition. See In re Marriage of
    Witten, 
    supra,
     
    672 N.W.2d 783
     (‘‘no transfer, release,
    disposition, or use of the embryos can occur without
    the signed authorization of both donors’’). If the parties
    do not agree, the pre-embryos remain in storage indefi-
    nitely. See 
    id.
    This third approach attempts to accommodate the
    competing principles driving both the contractual
    approach—progenitors, not courts, should decide the
    disposition of their pre-embryos—and the balancing
    approach—progenitors should be allowed to change
    their minds at any point. Id., 782. Only Iowa has affirma-
    tively adopted this approach, however. See id., 783; see
    also McQueen v. Gadberry, 
    507 S.W.3d 127
    , 157 (Mo.
    App. 2016) (upholding trial court decision that relied
    on contemporaneous mutual consent approach when
    parties had no enforceable agreement). Other courts
    have criticized the contemporaneous mutual consent
    approach as ‘‘totally unrealistic’’; Reber v. Reiss, 
    supra,
    42 A.3d 1135
     n.5; see also 
    id.
     (‘‘[i]f the parties could
    reach an agreement, they would not be in court’’); and
    unfair because it ‘‘gives one party a de facto veto over
    the other party by avoiding any resolution until the
    issue is eventually mooted by the passage of time’’ and
    creates ‘‘incentives for one party to leverage his or her
    power . . . .’’ In re Marriage of Rooks, supra, 
    429 P.3d 589
    .
    A majority of states that have addressed the issue
    employ the contractual approach as the first step in
    resolving a dispute over pre-embryos upon divorce. To
    date, courts in eight states have done so. See Terrell v.
    Torres, supra, 
    246 Ariz. 320
    ; In re Marriage of Rooks,
    supra, 
    429 P.3d 592
    ; Szafranski v. Dunston, supra, 
    993 N.E.2d 514
    ; Kass v. Kass, 
    supra,
     
    91 N.Y.2d 564
    –66; In
    re Marriage of Dahl, 
    222 Or. App. 572
    , 583, 
    194 P.3d 834
     (2008), review denied, 
    346 Or. 65
    , 
    204 P.3d 95
     (2009);
    Davis v. Davis, 
    supra,
     
    842 S.W.2d 597
    ; Roman v.
    Roman, 
    193 S.W.3d 40
    , 50 (Tex. App. 2006), review
    denied, Texas Supreme Court, Docket No. 06-554
    (August 24, 1997), cert. denied, 
    552 U.S. 1258
    , 
    128 S. Ct. 1662
    , 
    170 L. Ed. 2d 356
     (2008); Litowitz v. Litowitz,
    
    146 Wn. 2d 514
    , 528, 
    48 P.3d 261
     (2002), cert. denied,
    
    537 U.S. 1191
    , 
    123 S. Ct. 1271
    , 
    154 L. Ed. 2d 1025
     (2003).
    Courts in two states have expressly reserved decision
    on whether to adopt the contractual approach because
    an enforceable contract did not exist in the cases in
    which the question arose. See McQueen v. Gadberry,
    supra, 
    507 S.W.3d 156
     n.32; id., 157 (upholding trial court
    decision relying on contemporaneous mutual consent
    approach); Reber v. Reiss, 
    supra,
     
    42 A.3d 1136
     (applying
    balancing approach). One state court has expressly
    declined to enforce a contract that was to result in the
    implantation of pre-embryos but reserved decision on
    whether it would enforce a contract that would result
    in the discarding of pre-embryos. See A.Z. v. B.Z., 
    431 Mass. 150
    , 159, 160 n.22, 
    725 N.E.2d 1051
     (2000) (uphold-
    ing trial court’s decision relying on balancing
    approach). And, as we discussed previously, two state
    courts have expressly rejected the contractual
    approach in favor of either the balancing approach; see
    J.B. v. M.B., supra, 
    170 N.J. 29
    –30; or the contemporane-
    ous mutual consent approach. See In re Marriage of
    Witten, 
    supra,
     
    672 N.W.2d 783
    .
    II
    The standard of review applicable to the enforceabil-
    ity of dispositional agreements presents a question of
    law; therefore, our review is plenary. See, e.g., Bedrick
    v. Bedrick, 
    300 Conn. 691
    , 697, 
    17 A.3d 17
     (2011). We
    conclude that the contractual approach is the appro-
    priate first step in determining the disposition of pre-
    embryos upon divorce for several reasons.
    First, we agree with courts adopting the contractual
    approach that, when possible, progenitors should be
    the primary decision makers regarding disposition of
    their pre-embryos. This ‘‘maximize[s] procreative lib-
    erty by reserving to the progenitors the authority to
    make what is in the first instance a quintessentially
    personal, private decision.’’ Kass v. Kass, 
    supra,
     
    91 N.Y.2d 565
    . It ‘‘is in keeping with the proposition that
    the progenitors, having provided the gametic material
    giving rise to the [pre-embryos], retain decision-making
    authority as to their disposition.’’ Davis v. Davis, 
    supra,
    842 S.W.2d 597
    .
    Second, there are significant benefits to making this
    decision in advance, rather than at the moment of dispo-
    sition. Preexisting agreements ‘‘promote serious discus-
    sions between the parties prior to participating in in
    vitro fertilization’’; Szafranski v. Dunston, supra, 
    993 N.E.2d 515
    ; and manifest choices ‘‘made before disputes
    erupt . . . .’’ Kass v. Kass, 
    supra,
     
    91 N.Y.2d 566
    . This
    ‘‘minimize[s] misunderstandings’’ that might arise in the
    future, provides certainty for progenitors and fertility
    clinics, and decreases the likelihood of litigation. Id.,
    565; see also Szafranski v. Dunston, supra, 515.
    Of course, as in the present case, progenitors might
    change their preferences for disposition as time passes.
    Although the contractual approach prioritizes progeni-
    tor autonomy and certainty over an absolute ability to
    change one’s mind, as offered by the balancing and
    contemporaneous mutual consent approaches, advance
    directives that permit joint, written modifications
    address this concern by offering a measure of flexibility.
    See, e.g., Terrell v. Torres, supra, 
    246 Ariz. 319
     (‘‘[c]ourts
    have addressed these concerns by permitting parties
    to subsequently jointly modify their initial agreement’’);
    Kass v. Kass, 
    supra,
     
    91 N.Y.2d 566
     (‘‘advance directives,
    subject to mutual change of mind that must be jointly
    expressed, both minimize misunderstandings and max-
    imize procreative liberty by reserving to the progenitors
    the authority to make what is in the first instance a
    quintessentially personal, private decision’’); Davis v.
    Davis, 
    supra,
     
    842 S.W.2d 597
     (‘‘[p]roviding that the ini-
    tial agreements may later be modified by agreement
    will, we think, protect the parties against some of the
    risks they face in this regard’’); Roman v. Roman, 
    supra,
    193 S.W.3d 50
     (allowing parties voluntarily to decide
    disposition of frozen embryos in advance of cryopreser-
    vation, subject to mutual change of mind, jointly
    expressed, best serves public policy and parties’ inter-
    ests). This seems particularly reasonable in light of the
    asymmetrical consequences, under the contemporane-
    ous mutual consent approach, of changing one’s mind.
    To the extent one party benefits from the option to
    change his or her dispositional preference, the other
    party is deprived of the agreement he or she originally
    bargained for and relied on in agreeing to create the
    pre-embryos.
    Third, the contractual approach is consistent with
    Connecticut’s public policy. By statute, a fertility clinic
    must provide a progenitor with ‘‘timely, relevant and
    appropriate information sufficient to allow that person
    to make an informed and voluntary choice regarding
    the disposition of any embryos,’’ including ‘‘the option
    of storing, donating to another person, donating for
    research purposes, or otherwise disposing of any
    unused embryos . . . .’’ General Statutes § 32-41jj (c)
    (1) and (2). Moreover, the contractual approach is con-
    sistent with the state’s well settled policy of enforcing
    intimate partner agreements; see, e.g., General Statutes
    § 46b-66 (settlement agreement); General Statutes
    § 46b-36g (premarital agreement); Bedrick v. Bedrick,
    
    supra,
     
    300 Conn. 698
    –99 (postnuptial agreement);
    Boland v. Catalano, 
    202 Conn. 333
    , 342, 
    521 A.2d 142
    (1987) (agreement between unmarried cohabitants);
    and gestational agreements. See, e.g., General Statutes
    § 7-48a (permitting intended parents in gestational
    agreement to obtain birth certificate). In many cases,
    these agreements ‘‘encourage the private resolution of
    family issues. In particular, they may allow couples to
    eliminate a source of emotional turmoil . . . .’’ Bedrick
    v. Bedrick, 
    supra, 698
    .
    Fourth, the contractual approach accords with the
    current practices of most state courts that have con-
    fronted the issue. As discussed previously, a substantial
    majority of state courts that have addressed the pre-
    embryo disposition issue have applied the contractual
    approach when an enforceable contract exists. See part
    I of this opinion. The contractual approach furthers this
    policy of informed consent regarding the disposition of
    pre-embryos. Moreover, at least one state legislature
    requires progenitors to enter into disposition agree-
    ments; 
    Fla. Stat. Ann. § 742.17
     (West 2016); and, as
    in Connecticut, at least three other state legislatures
    require that fertility clinics provide progenitors with
    options for disposition in the event of various contin-
    gencies. See 
    Cal. Health & Safety Code § 125315
     (Deer-
    ing 2012); Mass. Gen. Laws Ann. c. 111L, § 4 (LexisNexis
    2018); 
    N.J. Stat. Ann. § 26
    :2Z-2 (West 2018). But see,
    e.g., 
    Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 25-318.03
     (A) (1) (2018) (in
    divorce proceeding, awarding pre-embryo ‘‘to spouse
    who intends to allow the in vitro human pre-embryos
    to develop to birth,’’ regardless of disposition agree-
    ment); 
    La. Stat. Ann. § 9:129
     (Supp. 2018) (‘‘[a] viable
    in vitro fertilized human ovum is a juridical person
    which shall not be intentionally destroyed’’).
    Finally, various professional associations focusing
    on the field of reproductive medicine recommend that
    progenitors provide advance directives regarding dis-
    position of their pre-embryos in various scenarios,
    including divorce. E.g., Ethics Committee of the Ameri-
    can Society for Reproductive Medicine, ‘‘Disposition
    of Abandoned Embryos: A Committee Opinion,’’ 99
    Fertility & Sterility 1848, 1848 (2013), available at
    https://www.asrm.org/globalassets/asrm/asrm-content/
    news-and-publications/ethics-committee-opinions/
    disposition_of_abandoned_embryos-pdfmembers.pdf
    (last visited October 29, 2019); see also American Medi-
    cal Association, Code of Medical Ethics (2017) Opinion
    4.2.5, pp. 70–71. Advance directives provide practical
    certainty for storage facilities, reduce the likelihood of
    abandonment, and ensure that facilities will be able to
    satisfy their ethical obligations.
    Therefore, we conclude that, in the absence of formal
    legislative guidance on the question, the contractual
    approach is the appropriate first step in determining
    the disposition of pre-embryos upon divorce. As set
    forth in part IV of this opinion, we do not decide how
    a court should determine the disposition of pre-embryos
    in the absence of an enforceable agreement.
    III
    Finally, we conclude that the trial court incorrectly
    determined that the parties had not entered into an
    enforceable agreement in this case.
    As set forth previously, the trial court concluded that
    the storage agreement was not an enforceable contract
    because it ‘‘was little more than a ‘check the box ques-
    tionnaire,’ ’’ which had ‘‘neither consideration nor a
    promise.’’ In support of this conclusion, it cited Rucker
    v. Rucker, Docket No. A16-0942, 
    2016 WL 7439094
    (Minn. App. December 27, 2016).
    Although a disposition agreement between progeni-
    tors is presumed enforceable between them; e.g., In re
    Marriage of Rooks, supra, 
    429 P.3d 592
    ; there must be
    an offer and acceptance of definite terms. See, e.g.,
    Saint Bernard School of Montville, Inc. v. Bank of
    America, 
    312 Conn. 811
    , 830, 
    95 A.3d 1063
     (2014). Also,
    ‘‘a contract must be supported by valuable consider-
    ation.’’ Connecticut National Bank v. Voog, 
    233 Conn. 352
    , 366, 
    659 A.2d 172
     (1995). ‘‘Consideration consists
    of a benefit to the party promising, or a loss or detriment
    to the party to whom the promise is made.’’ (Internal
    quotation marks omitted.) Viera v. Cohen, 
    283 Conn. 412
    , 440–41, 
    927 A.2d 843
     (2007). ‘‘[T]he exchange of
    promises is sufficient consideration . . . .’’ Christo-
    phersen v. Blount, 
    216 Conn. 509
    , 511 n.3, 
    582 A.2d 460
    (1990). In the present case, the trial court found that
    there were no promises exchanged between the parties
    and no consideration. To the extent that the trial court
    found that there was no exchange of promises and, thus,
    no consideration, we review the trial court’s findings
    for clear error. See, e.g., Viera v. Cohen, 
    supra, 442
    ; see
    also 
    id.
     (whether agreement is supported by consider-
    ation is factual issue reviewed under clearly erroneous
    standard). To the extent that the trial court found that
    there was insufficient consideration, our review is ple-
    nary. See, e.g., Milaneseo v. Calvanese, 
    92 Conn. 641
    ,
    643, 
    103 A. 841
     (1918) (adequacy of consideration is
    conclusion of law subject to plenary review).6
    Neither party contests the existence of their offer
    and acceptance of definite terms. They each offered
    one another the opportunity to create pre-embryos by
    contributing gametic material under the terms spelled
    out in the agreement, including the unambiguous condi-
    tion that the pre-embryos would be discarded if they
    ever divorced. Each party accepted this offer by signing
    the agreement, even specifically indicating their ‘‘under-
    stand[ing], agree[ment] and consent’’ that the pre-
    embryos would be discarded upon divorce by initialing
    directly below that option in the agreement. If there
    was any doubt, they further indicated their assent by
    performing (i.e., their contribution of gametic material).
    Moreover, the parties do not dispute that, to the
    extent that they entered into a contract, the contract
    is enforceable as against each other. We note that other
    jurisdictions have determined that a pre-embryo storage
    agreement, entered into by a fertility clinic and the
    progenitors, that provides for the disposition of the pre-
    embryos is presumed enforceable not only against the
    clinic but also as between the progenitors. See Kass
    v. Kass, 
    supra,
     
    91 N.Y.2d 565
     (‘‘[a]greements between
    progenitors, or gamete donors, regarding disposition of
    their pre-zygotes should generally be presumed valid
    and binding, and enforced in any dispute between
    them’’); see also In re Marriage of Rooks, supra, 
    429 P.3d 592
     (holding ‘‘that a court should look first to
    any existing agreement expressing the spouses’ intent
    regarding disposition of the couple’s remaining pre-
    embryos in the event of divorce’’); Roman v. Roman,
    
    supra,
     
    193 S.W.3d 48
     (noting that case law evinces
    ‘‘emerging majority view that written embryo agree-
    ments between embryo donors and fertility clinics . . .
    are valid and enforceable’’).
    The trial court’s finding that the storage agreement
    lacked a mutual exchange of promises between the
    plaintiff and the defendant and, thus, lacked consider-
    ation was clearly erroneous for three reasons. First, the
    parties made mutual promises to contribute gametic
    material. Specifically, in exchange for the plaintiff’s
    promise to contribute gametic material under the terms
    of the agreement, the defendant promised to contribute
    gametic material under the terms of the agreement,
    and vice versa. Moreover, in exchange for the certainty
    provided by the parties’ election of a disposition in the
    event of divorce, the center promised to store the pre-
    embryos. Thus, all parties to the agreement received
    consideration. Additionally, to the extent that the trial
    court found that this exchange of promises was inade-
    quate consideration, as a matter of law, we disagree.
    Although no court has directly addressed the issue in
    the context of pre-embryo disposition agreements,
    courts and commentators have opined that this
    exchange of promises is sufficient. See, e.g., Roman v.
    Roman, 
    supra,
     
    193 S.W.3d 50
     n.14 (‘‘consideration in
    embryo agreements is the gamete donation process that
    both husband and wife experience’’); D. Forman,
    ‘‘Embryo Disposition and Divorce: Why Clinic Consent
    Forms Are Not the Answer,’’ 
    24 J. Am. Acad. Matrim. Law. 57
    , 103 n.180 (2011) (‘‘contracts also typically
    require consideration, which in this type of case may
    be provided by the gamete donation process undergone
    by both husband and wife’’). Generally, though, it is
    well settled that ‘‘the exchange of promises is sufficient
    consideration . . . .’’ Christophersen v. Blount, supra,
    
    216 Conn. 511
     n.3.
    Second, the trial court’s focus on the checkbox nature
    of the storage agreement to conclude that the agree-
    ment was unenforceable was misplaced. An agreement
    in which parties indicate rights or responsibilities by
    checking a box is not insufficient for that reason alone.
    Checkboxes, sometimes accompanied by the parties’
    initials, are routinely used in a wide range of important
    and legally binding documents. Even Connecticut trial
    courts ‘‘routinely use’’ checkbox forms to issue legally
    binding orders. In re Leah S., 
    284 Conn. 685
    , 687 n.2,
    
    935 A.2d 1021
     (2007). In the context of pre-embryo
    disposition agreements, several courts have held that
    the agreements were enforceable when progenitors
    indicated a disposition choice in some manner other
    than by writing it out in full. See, e.g., Terrell v. Torres,
    supra, 
    246 Ariz. 316
     (progenitors ‘‘selected and initialed’’
    next to disposition choice); Kass v. Kass, 
    supra,
     
    91 N.Y.2d 566
    –67 (progenitors signed consents indicating
    their dispositional intent). Moreover, any suggestion
    that the checkboxes were evidence that the parties had
    not seriously considered the issue is contradicted by
    the storage agreement itself and the testimony of
    both parties.7
    Third, the trial court’s reliance on Rucker v. Rucker,
    supra, 
    2016 WL 7439094
    , also was misplaced. That case
    involved a storage agreement between progenitors and
    a fertility clinic that included a checkbox term providing
    for ‘‘ ‘transfer’ ’’ of the pre-embryos upon divorce. Id.,
    *9. The Minnesota Court of Appeals held that the trial
    court had misinterpreted the word ‘‘transfer.’’ Id., *10.
    The appeals court then provided the correct interpreta-
    tion and remanded the case to the trial court to decide
    how the pre-embryos should be distributed in light of
    this new interpretation. Id., *11. The court did not even
    remotely suggest that the checkbox nature of the agree-
    ment was relevant (much less significant), as the trial
    court did in this case. See id., *9–11.
    Therefore, we conclude that the parties had an
    enforceable agreement.
    Because we determine that there was an enforceable
    contract, the defendant’s claims that, in the absence of a
    contractual agreement, a pre-embryo is not ‘‘property’’
    under § 46b-81 because it is a human life or, if it is
    ‘‘property,’’ that a trial court should employ a presump-
    tion in favor of its preservation because it is a human
    life, necessarily fail. The defendant’s claims presuppose
    that there was no enforceable contract. The defendant
    does not argue that if there is an enforceable contract,
    there should be a presumption in favor of preservation.
    Thus, because we determine that there was an enforce-
    able contract, the defendant’s claims that the trial court
    should have either awarded the pre-embryos to the
    party seeking to preserve them or applied a presump-
    tion in favor of preservation fail.
    To the extent that the defendant responds that there
    is no enforceable contract because, as a general matter
    of law, any agreement providing for the disposition of
    a pre-embryo, which constitutes human life, is unen-
    forceable, the claim is not reviewable because it was not
    preserved at trial, and, therefore, we lack an adequate
    record to address it. See footnotes 5 and 8 of this opin-
    ion. The defendant did not argue at trial that the agree-
    ment was unenforceable because it concerned a human
    life. Even if we generously construe his testimony as
    legal argument, we conclude that he did not broach
    this issue. Rather, his sole point was that he should be
    permitted to change his mind. Nor does he even appear
    to make this argument on appeal other than through his
    general contention that a pre-embryo is a human being.
    Whether a pre-embryo is a human being is, at least
    in part, a question of fact. It is certainly not a question
    an appellate court can determine without some measure
    of fact-finding.8 The defendant concedes this. Neverthe-
    less, he offered no evidence at trial to establish it. Fur-
    ther, to the extent that this claim might implicate consti-
    tutional rights, it would be reviewable under State v.
    Golding, 
    213 Conn. 233
    , 239–40, 
    567 A.2d 823
     (1989);
    see In re Yasiel R., 
    317 Conn. 773
    , 781, 
    120 A.3d 1188
    (2015) (modifying third condition of Golding); only if
    it were supported by an adequate record. For the rea-
    sons just stated, however, it is not supported by an
    adequate record. Accordingly, we decline to review
    this claim.
    IV
    We make two additional points to clarify the scope
    of our holding. First, our decision applies to contracts
    that, if enforced, will not result in procreation. We do
    not decide whether the contractual approach applies
    in a scenario that would force one party to become
    a genetic parent against his or her wishes or, if the
    contractual approach does apply, whether such a con-
    tract would be unenforceable for other reasons, includ-
    ing public policy.
    Second, because we conclude that the parties in this
    case had an enforceable agreement, we do not decide
    what a court must do in the absence of an enforceable
    agreement. For example, we leave for another day
    whether, in the absence of an enforceable agreement,
    balancing or contemporaneous mutual consent is the
    appropriate approach, and what the details of such an
    approach would entail.
    The judgment is reversed insofar as the trial court
    determined that the parties’ storage agreement is not
    enforceable, the trial court’s order awarding the pre-
    embryos to the plaintiff is vacated, and the case is
    remanded with direction to order the disposition of the
    pre-embryos in accordance with the storage agreement;
    the judgment is affirmed in all other respects.
    In this opinion the other justices concurred.
    1
    Although the parties did not introduce any scientific evidence at trial,
    like other courts, we take judicial notice of the following basic facts of in
    vitro fertilization: ‘‘Typically the [in vitro fertilization] procedure begins with
    hormonal stimulation of a woman’s ovaries to produce multiple eggs. The
    eggs are then removed by laparoscopy or ultrasound-directed needle aspira-
    tion and placed in a glass dish, where sperm are introduced. Once a sperm
    cell fertilizes the egg, this fusion, or pre-zygote, divides until it reaches the
    four-to-eight cell stages, after which several pre-zygotes are transferred to
    the woman’s uterus by a cervical catheter. If the procedure succeeds, an
    embryo will attach itself to the uterine wall, differentiate, and develop into
    a fetus. As an alternative to immediate implantation, pre-zygotes may be
    cryopreserved indefinitely in liquid nitrogen for later use. Pre-embryo is a
    medically accurate term for a zygote or fertilized egg that has not been
    implanted in a uterus. It refers to the approximately 14-day period of develop-
    ment from fertilization to the time when the embryo implants in the uterine
    wall and the primitive streak, the precursor to the nervous system, appears.
    An embryo proper develops only after implantation. The term frozen
    embryos is a term of art denoting cryogenically preserved pre-embryos.’’
    (Internal quotation marks omitted.) McQueen v. Gadberry, 
    507 S.W.3d 127
    ,
    134 n.4 (Mo. App. 2016).
    2
    The parties were aware that some of the pre-embryos resulting from the
    treatment might not be transferred to the plaintiff’s uterus immediately and
    could require storage. The storage agreement with the center, which we
    will discuss in more detail, informed them: ‘‘If numerous eggs are retrieved
    during our (my) cycle, the number of eggs exposed to sperm will be decided
    by us (me) and our (my) doctor. If we (I) elect to expose most or all of
    our (my) eggs to sperm in order to develop as many embryos as possible,
    any viable embryos not transferred to the uterus will be frozen (cryopre-
    served). . . . [I]f we (I) have a miscarriage, or if a successful pregnancy
    does occur but we (I) subsequently desire another child, the frozen embryos
    will be available to us (me) for thawing and transfer during a subsequent
    menstrual cycle. This procedure may be repeated until all the frozen embryos
    have been utilized.’’
    3
    ‘‘[A]lternative methods to preembryo destruction that are currently avail-
    able . . . include preembryo donation for procreation (essentially, a form
    or preembryo ‘adoption’) . . . .’’ O. Lin, ‘‘Bioethics and the Disposition of
    Cryopreserved Preembryos: Why Autonomy-Based Contract Theory Does
    Not Work,’’ 34 Fam. Advoc. 38, 40 (2011).
    4
    General Statutes § 46b-81 provides in relevant part: ‘‘(a) At the time of
    . . . dissolving a marriage . . . the Superior Court may assign to either
    spouse all or any part of the estate of the other spouse. . . .
    ‘‘(c) In fixing the nature and value of the property, if any, to be assigned,
    the court, after considering all the evidence presented by each party, shall
    consider the length of the marriage, the causes for the . . . dissolution of
    the marriage or legal separation, the age, health, station, occupation, amount
    and sources of income, earning capacity, vocational skills, education,
    employability, estate, liabilities and needs of each of the parties and the
    opportunity of each for future acquisition of capital assets and income. The
    court shall also consider the contribution of each of the parties in the
    acquisition, preservation or appreciation in value of their respective estates.’’
    Although the trial court did not cite § 46b-81, we assume it applied this
    statute because it considered several of the factors enumerated in that
    statute and held that the pre-embryos were the ‘‘property’’ of the plaintiff.
    Regarding § 46b-81, we have stated: ‘‘[T]he trial court need not give each
    factor equal weight . . . or recite the statutory criteria that it considered
    in making its decision or make express findings as to each statutory factor
    . . . .’’ (Internal quotation marks omitted.) Greco v. Greco, 
    275 Conn. 348
    ,
    355, 
    880 A.2d 872
     (2005).
    5
    We note that the defendant’s precise concerns on appeal are not clear.
    He was not represented by counsel in proceedings before the trial court.
    On appeal, he submitted his principal brief without counsel, and his only
    request for relief was that this court ‘‘certify’’ his case to the United States
    Supreme Court as a vehicle for that court’s reconsideration of Roe v. Wade,
    
    410 U.S. 113
    , 
    93 S. Ct. 705
    , 
    35 L. Ed. 2d 147
     (1973). The defendant then
    retained counsel, who submitted a reply brief on his behalf (which made
    the claims set forth previously for reversal of the trial court’s judgment)
    and represented him at oral argument before this court. At oral argument,
    the defendant’s counsel also withdrew his client’s original request to certify
    the case to the United States Supreme Court.
    The appeal, construed strictly, could be considered moot because this
    court cannot grant the defendant his only claim for relief. See, e.g., Seymour
    v. Region One Board of Education, 
    261 Conn. 475
    , 481, 
    803 A.2d 318
     (2002).
    This court is not capable of granting the defendant’s original request for
    relief, as the United States Supreme Court does not accept certified cases
    or questions from state courts. Cf. U.S. Sup. Ct. R. 19 (‘‘[a] United States
    court of appeals may certify to this [c]ourt a question or proposition of law
    on which it seeks instruction’’). This request also was withdrawn. Further,
    it is well established that we are not obligated to review claims raised for
    the first time in a reply brief. E.g., Reardon v. Zoning Board of Appeals,
    
    311 Conn. 356
    , 367 n.10, 
    87 A.3d 1070
     (2014).
    Mindful that we construe our rules of practice liberally, especially when
    a party is self-represented, we will, in this case, consider the claims that
    the defendant raised in his reply brief, but only to the extent that they do
    not prejudice the plaintiff and the record supports our review. See Practice
    Book § 60-1; Oliphant v. Commissioner of Correction, 
    274 Conn. 563
    , 569,
    
    877 A.2d 761
     (2005) (‘‘Connecticut courts [are] to be solicitous of pro se
    litigants and when it does not interfere with the rights of other parties to
    construe the rules of practice liberally in favor of the pro se party’’ [internal
    quotation marks omitted]). The plaintiff has not asked us to do otherwise.
    6
    We also note that intimate partner contracts generally warrant ‘‘special
    scrutiny . . . .’’ Bedrick v. Bedrick, 
    supra,
     
    300 Conn. 703
    . This is justified
    by, among other things, the nature of these intimate relationships, in which
    partners tend to be less cautious in contracting with one another than they
    would be in contracting with others; id.; and by the recognition that events
    may occur before the dissolution of the relationship that go beyond their
    contemplation at the time they entered into the agreement. See McHugh v.
    McHugh, 
    181 Conn. 482
    , 485–86, 
    436 A.2d 8
     (1980). Although we see no
    abuse of trust (the defendant concedes that he intelligently entered the
    agreement) or unforeseen circumstances (the parties’ agreement expressly
    contemplates the very event at issue: divorce) in this case that would cause
    us to hold that the agreement is unenforceable, we recognize that these
    circumstances could arise in other cases.
    7
    The storage agreement provided, just above the parties’ selection for
    disposition upon divorce: ‘‘We (I) understand, agree and consent that if we
    divorce . . . .’’ (Emphasis omitted.) The plaintiff also testified that she and
    the defendant had expressly discussed the issue of disposition upon divorce:
    ‘‘When we talked about it, we said, in the event that one of us divorce[s]
    or we died or anything like that, that we would. And we talked about that.
    That’s when we both signed the contract on the day we went to speak to
    the center.
    ***
    So, then we spoke about them, and then we agreed that should—in case
    of divorce, you know, whichever party initiated it, that we would do this.
    So, also the understanding that we agreed upon, that’s what we did. . . .
    We both spoke about—we both talked about it, and then we both signed
    off on it.’’ The defendant did not expressly confirm that they had discussed
    disposition upon divorce but conceded that he had agreed to the disposition
    in the storage agreement because ‘‘at the time, I never thought we’d get
    divorced, number one; and number two, that’s what my wife wanted, and
    I agreed, because I was trying to do as she wanted.’’ His change of heart only
    occurred at some point after he had entered the agreement: ‘‘In hindsight,
    I realize it was the wrong thing to do, and I’ve changed my mind . . . .’’
    8
    In concluding that we lack an adequate record for review, we are aware
    of the abundance of information outside the record regarding the science
    behind in vitro fertilization and on every other aspect of the complex and
    difficult issues raised in cases in which it is implicated. We also recognize
    that courts occasionally and to varying degrees have taken judicial notice
    of this evidence. E.g., McQueen v. Gadberry, supra, 
    507 S.W.3d 134
     n.4
    (considering basic scientific evidence related to pre-embryos, even though
    ‘‘there was no evidence introduced at trial with respect to the science of
    [in vitro fertilization], related scientific terms, or the division or cell stages
    of the frozen pre-embryos at issue’’). In this light, the defendant notes that
    ‘‘[s]ome argue [that] the question of when human life beings has been
    definitely answered by scientific knowledge,’’ and his counsel at oral argu-
    ment before this court suggested that we consider the medical literature
    referenced by the amicus as evidence of this point. See, e.g., R. Gitchell,
    ‘‘Should Legal Precedent Based on Old, Flawed, Scientific Analysis Regard-
    ing When Life Begins, Continue To Apply to Parental Disputes over the Fate
    of Frozen Embryos, When There Are Now Scientifically Known and Observed
    Facts Proving Life Begins at Fertilization?’’ 
    20 DePaul J. Health Care L. 1
    ,
    2 (2018) (‘‘[o]bservable facts of human development can be seen in films
    of one cell human embryos that were cryopreserved’’). But see, e.g., P.
    Peters, ‘‘The Ambiguous Meaning of Human Conception,’’ 
    40 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 199
    , 201 (2006) (‘‘[m]ost of the governmental commissions that have
    studied the propriety of scientific research using early embryos have con-
    cluded that embryos less than two weeks old are not moral persons’’).
    We note, however, the fundamental difference between establishing the
    facts of fertilization and establishing that human life begins at fertilization.
    We cannot seriously consider the latter issue on a record devoid of any
    evidence whatsoever and with an argument aimed only at one facet of this
    ‘‘difficult question . . . .’’ Roe v. Wade, 
    410 U.S. 113
    , 159, 
    93 S. Ct. 705
    , 
    35 L. Ed. 2d 147
     (1973); see 
    id.
     (‘‘We need not resolve the difficult question of
    when life begins. When those trained in the respective disciplines of medi-
    cine, philosophy, and theology are unable to arrive at any consensus, the
    judiciary, at this point in the development of man’s knowledge, is not in a
    position to speculate as to the answer.’’).