Federal Trade Commission v. Facebook Inc. ( 2021 )


Menu:
  •                             UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT
    FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA
    FEDERAL TRADE COMMISSION,
    Plaintiff,
    v.                                      Civil Action No. 20-3590 (JEB)
    FACEBOOK, INC.,
    Defendant.
    MEMORANDUM OPINION
    At the time of the last great antitrust battle in our courthouse — between the United
    States and Microsoft — Mark Zuckerberg was still in high school. Only after his arrival at
    Harvard did he launch “The Facebook” from his dorm room. Nearly twenty years later, both
    federal and state regulators contend, in two separate actions before this Court, that Facebook is
    now the one violating the antitrust laws. The company, they allege, has long had a monopoly in
    the market for what they call “Personal Social Networking Services.” And it has allegedly
    maintained that monopoly, in violation of Section 2 of the Sherman Act, through two different
    kinds of actions: first, by acquiring firms that it believed were well positioned to erode its
    monopoly — most notably, Instagram and WhatsApp; and second, by adopting policies
    preventing interoperability between Facebook and certain other apps that it saw as threats,
    thereby impeding their growth into viable competitors. Both suits seek equitable relief from this
    conduct, including forced “divestiture or reconstruction of businesses” as well as orders not to
    undertake similar conduct in the future. See ECF No. 3 (Redacted Compl.) at 51–52. (The
    1
    Court here cites a copy of the FTC’s Complaint that has minor redactions to protect confidential
    business information, and it mentions certain redacted facts only with the parties’ permission.)
    Facebook now separately moves to dismiss both the State action and the FTC action.
    This Opinion resolves its Motion as to the FTC’s Complaint, and the Court analyzes the States’
    largely parallel claims in its separate Opinion in No. 20-3589. Although the Court does not
    agree with all of Facebook’s contentions here, it ultimately concurs that the agency’s Complaint
    is legally insufficient and must therefore be dismissed. The FTC has failed to plead enough facts
    to plausibly establish a necessary element of all of its Section 2 claims — namely, that Facebook
    has monopoly power in the market for Personal Social Networking (PSN) Services. The
    Complaint contains nothing on that score save the naked allegation that the company has had and
    still has a “dominant share of th[at] market (in excess of 60%).” Redacted Compl., ¶ 64. Such
    an unsupported assertion might (barely) suffice in a Section 2 case involving a more traditional
    goods market, in which the Court could reasonably infer that market share was measured by
    revenue, units sold, or some other typical metric. But this case involves no ordinary or intuitive
    market. Rather, PSN services are free to use, and the exact metes and bounds of what even
    constitutes a PSN service — i.e., which features of a company’s mobile app or website are
    included in that definition and which are excluded — are hardly crystal clear. In this unusual
    context, the FTC’s inability to offer any indication of the metric(s) or method(s) it used to
    calculate Facebook’s market share renders its vague “60%-plus” assertion too speculative and
    conclusory to go forward. Because this defect could conceivably be overcome by re-pleading,
    however, the Court will dismiss only the Complaint, not the case, and will do so without
    prejudice to allow Plaintiff to file an amended Complaint. See Ciralsky v. CIA., 
    355 F.3d 661
    ,
    666–67 (D.C. Cir. 2004).
    2
    To guide the parties in the event amendment occurs, this Opinion also explains two
    further conclusions of law. First, even if the FTC had sufficiently pleaded market power, its
    challenge to Facebook’s policy of refusing interoperability permissions with competing apps
    fails to state a claim for injunctive relief. As explained herein (and in the Court’s separate
    Opinion in the States’ case), there is nothing unlawful about having such a policy in general.
    While it is possible that Facebook’s implementation of that policy as to certain specific
    competitor apps may have violated Section 2, such finding would not change the outcome here:
    all such revocations of access occurred in 2013, seven years before this suit was filed, and the
    FTC lacks statutory authority to seek an injunction “based on [such] long-past conduct.” FTC v.
    Shire ViroPharma, Inc., 
    917 F.3d 147
    , 156 (3d Cir. 2019). Regardless of whether the FTC can
    amend its Complaint to plausibly allege market power and advance this litigation, then, the
    conduct it has alleged regarding Facebook’s interoperability policies cannot form the basis for
    Section 2 liability. Second, the agency is on firmer ground in scrutinizing the acquisitions of
    Instagram and WhatsApp, as the Court rejects Facebook’s argument that the FTC lacks authority
    to seek injunctive relief against those purchases. Whether other issues arise in a subsequent
    phase of litigation is dependent on how the Government wishes to proceed.
    3
    Table of Contents
    I.         Background ............................................................................................................................. 5
    A.        Social Networking .............................................................................................................. 5
    B.        Facebook Blue .................................................................................................................... 6
    C.        Alleged Monopoly Maintenance......................................................................................... 7
    1.        Instagram ........................................................................................................................ 8
    2.        WhatsApp ..................................................................................................................... 10
    3.        Interoperability Permissions ......................................................................................... 11
    a.         Facebook Platform .................................................................................................... 11
    b.         Conditioning Access ................................................................................................. 13
    D.        Procedural History ............................................................................................................ 15
    II.        Legal Standard ...................................................................................................................... 16
    III. Analysis ................................................................................................................................. 17
    A.        Monopoly Power ............................................................................................................... 18
    1.        Market Definition ......................................................................................................... 19
    a.         Legal Framework ...................................................................................................... 19
    b.         Market-Definition Allegations .................................................................................. 21
    c.         Analysis..................................................................................................................... 23
    2.        Market Share ................................................................................................................. 27
    B.        Platform Policies ............................................................................................................... 33
    1.        Refusal to Deal.............................................................................................................. 34
    a.         Legal Framework ...................................................................................................... 34
    b.         Application ................................................................................................................ 39
    i.       Facebook Policies ................................................................................................. 39
    ii.      Specific Refusals ................................................................................................... 41
    2.        Conditional Dealing ...................................................................................................... 46
    C.        Challenging Acquisitions under Section 13(b) ................................................................. 50
    IV. Conclusion ............................................................................................................................ 53
    4
    I.     Background
    A. Social Networking
    At the dawn of our century, in the much earlier days of the internet, a number of websites
    began to offer what came to be known as “social networking” services. See Redacted Compl.,
    ¶ 38. Friendster and Myspace, both launched in 2002, were among the earliest. 
    Id.
     Although
    the precise definition of a “Personal Social Networking Service” is disputed (as that is the market
    in which Facebook has its alleged monopoly), it can be summarized here as one that enables
    users to virtually connect with others in their network and to digitally share their views and
    experiences by posting about them in a shared, virtual social space. Id., ¶ 40. For example, users
    might view and interact with a letter-to-the-editor-style post on politics by a neighbor, pictures
    from a friend’s recent party, or a birth announcement for a newborn cousin. Id.
    Perhaps because humans are naturally social, this new way of interacting became hugely
    popular. Although Myspace and Friendster had an early lead, by 2009 they had been surpassed
    by a new competitor. Id., ¶¶ 38, 41. Created at Harvard in 2004, “The Facebook,” as it was
    initially called, was a social-networking service initially limited to college students. Id., ¶ 41.
    Within a few years, it had expanded to the general public (and dropped “The” from its name).
    Id. By at least 2011, it was the dominant player in personal social networking. Id., ¶ 62. Today,
    the FTC alleges, its flagship product, Facebook Blue, has hundreds of millions of users in the
    United States. Id., ¶ 3. The following details of Facebook’s conduct are drawn from the FTC’s
    Complaint, as the Court must consider its allegations true at this stage. The allegations are quite
    similar, though not identical, to those made by the States in the parallel case and recounted in the
    Court’s companion Opinion.
    5
    B. Facebook Blue
    Facebook Blue is what its millions of users think of when they think of “Facebook.”
    Generally speaking, using Facebook Blue entails interacting with user-created content — i.e.,
    content created or shared by one’s Facebook “friends,” id., ¶¶ 40, 89 — or creating content
    oneself by posting. That is not all that users see or do, however. They may also, for instance,
    encounter “publisher-created content like news articles . . . and advertisements” in their “news
    feed.” Id., ¶ 54; see also id., ¶¶ 44, 134. Such content can come in text, photo, or video form.
    Id., ¶ 54. In addition, Facebook users can play games or use other applications built either by
    Facebook or by third parties. Id., ¶¶ 97, 129. Facebook also offers other services beyond
    Facebook Blue to its users, such as Facebook Messenger, a free mobile-messaging service. Id.,
    ¶¶ 37, 115.
    Unlike most businesses, Facebook charges users no fee; instead, it makes money by
    selling advertising. Id., ¶¶ 43–51. By leveraging “the vast quantity of user data [it] collects,” the
    company “allows advertisers to target different campaigns and messages to different groups of
    users.” Id., ¶ 44; see also id., ¶ 4. Under this business model, as the Complaint puts it, Facebook
    “refrain[s] from charging a monetary price . . . to users, relying instead on monetizing user data
    and engagement through advertising.” Id., ¶ 42. Put differently, users exchange their time,
    attention, and personal data, rather than money, for access to Facebook. That approach has been
    highly profitable: in 2019, for instance, global advertisers paid Facebook nearly $70 billion, and
    it made profits of more than $18 billion. Id., ¶¶ 4, 44. To be clear, although Facebook’s data-
    collection and -use practices have been subject to increasing scrutiny, they are not the subject of
    this action.
    6
    C. Alleged Monopoly Maintenance
    Instead, this suit alleges that Facebook has violated and is violating the antitrust laws, the
    focus of which, generally speaking, is to promote and ensure competition. After rising to
    become the “dominant personal social networking provider in the United States” around 2011,
    id., ¶ 62, Facebook allegedly made a fateful strategic pivot: rather than competing to provide the
    best product, it would instead protect its monopoly by leveraging its power to foreclose and
    forestall the rise of new competitors. Id., ¶¶ 5, 9. In particular, the company’s executives saw a
    substantial threat to Facebook’s dominance in the advent of mobile devices — first and foremost,
    smartphones — capable of accessing the internet. Id., ¶ 70. Although Facebook had mobile
    functionality, it had been built with websites and desktop or laptop computers in mind and thus
    “offered a relatively poor experience for mobile users” compared to newer competitors. Id.; see
    also id., ¶¶ 78–79. Zuckerberg and other Facebook executives fretted over the possibility that
    other apps might create attractive mobile-native features and then leverage those features into
    exponential user growth, end-running Facebook’s established position. Id., ¶¶ 107–112. Even if
    such an app was not already providing social-network-like functionality, once it had a big
    enough base of users, it would still pose a potential threat to Facebook Blue. Id. Facebook
    executives feared fast-growing mobile-messaging services in particular, nervous that such apps
    could easily morph into direct competitors by adding social features.
    In response to these perceived threats, the company allegedly used its monopoly power to
    eliminate or destroy competitors in order to maintain its market dominance. Id., ¶¶ 5–9. The
    FTC claims that this exclusionary conduct had “three main elements.” Id., ¶¶ 9, 71. First (and
    second), Facebook reached deep into its very deep pockets to acquire Instagram and WhatsApp,
    two promising potential competitors, thereby preventing their emergence as serious rivals. Id.,
    7
    ¶ 71. (Attempts to purchase other competitors such as Snapchat and Twitter were rebuffed. Id.,
    ¶ 73.) Third, it adopted and then enforced policies that blocked rival apps from interconnecting
    their product with Facebook Blue, thereby both (i) blunting the growth of potential competitors
    that might have used that interoperability to attract new users, and (ii) deterring other developers
    from building new apps or features or functionalities that might compete with Facebook, lest
    they lose access as well. Id., ¶¶ 23–26.
    1. Instagram
    Begin with Insta, as those in the know — viz., our children — refer to it. Launched in
    late 2010, Instagram was an innovative photo-editing and -sharing app designed for the era of
    smartphones with built-in cameras. Id., ¶¶ 79–80. Plaintiff alleges that Instagram’s photo-
    sharing app also qualifies as a PSN service, meaning that it was a direct competitor to Facebook
    Blue. Id., ¶ 63. From the get-go, Instagram’s user base grew explosively, eventually attracting
    the attention of Facebook executives who feared that their own photo-sharing features paled in
    comparison. Id., ¶¶ 81–85. That disparity gave Instagram a chance to reach a large enough scale
    to be threatening as a new, mobile- and photo-first social network — whether the firm got there
    on its own or if, as worried Facebook, it were purchased by a large company like Google or
    Apple. Id., ¶ 86. After about eighteen months of watching Instagram’s rise, Zuckerberg and his
    team eventually shifted from trying (and failing) to compete to instead trying to buy. Aiming to
    both neutralize Instagram as a competitor and “integrate” the “mechanics” of its popular photo-
    sharing features with Facebook Blue in order to forestall the growth of future Instagrams, id.,
    ¶ 91, Zuckerberg offered to purchase the company for $1 billion in April 2012. Id., ¶ 95.
    Instagram’s founders agreed. Id.
    8
    As required by the Hart-Scott-Rodino Act, 15 U.S.C. § 18a, the FTC reviewed the
    acquisition prior to closing to assess whether it posed anticompetitive concerns. Whereas most
    mergers are cleared quickly, in this instance the review took over four months. During that
    scrutiny, the agency took the rare step of “requir[ing] the submission [by the parties] of
    additional information or documentary material relevant to the proposed acquisition.” 15 U.S.C.
    § 18a(e)(1)(A). Eventually, however, Facebook and Instagram satisfied the agency’s concerns,
    and in August (over four months after the merger was announced), the Commission voted 5–0 to
    allow it to proceed without any challenge or conditions. See FTC, FTC Closes its Investigation
    into Facebook’s Proposed Acquisition of Instagram Photo Sharing Program (Aug. 22, 2012),
    https://bit.ly/3bDa2mp. Although the FTC conveniently omits any mention of this review in its
    Complaint, the Court may take judicial notice of that public agency action. See Pharm. Rsch. &
    Manufacturers of Am. v. U.S. Dep’t of Health & Hum. Servs., 
    43 F. Supp. 3d 28
    , 33 (D.D.C.
    2014); Herron v. Fannie Mae, No. 10-943, 
    2012 WL 13042852
    , at *1 (D.D.C. Mar. 28, 2012).
    With Instagram safely in the fold, Facebook scaled back and eventually shut down its
    own mobile photo-sharing app. See Redacted Compl., ¶ 98. Internal emails cited by the
    Complaint reveal that it also fretted less about competition from other similar apps, since its
    ownership of Instagram meant it now “effectively dominate[d] photo sharing.” Id., ¶ 99. As
    time went on, Facebook also limited Facebook Blue’s promotion of the technically separate
    Instagram app and website, allegedly to avoid Instagram’s “cannibalizing” user engagement on
    its flagship service. Id., ¶¶ 102–04. All this post-acquisition conduct, the FTC claims, confirms
    that Facebook’s executives saw, and continue to see, Instagram as a significant competitive
    threat in the social-networking arena. Id., ¶ 102.
    9
    2. WhatsApp
    The other high-profile acquisition Plaintiff focuses on here involves not a competitor in
    the PSN market, like Instagram, but a company that might quickly become one. As noted above,
    Facebook’s executives saw mobile-native apps in general as a threat. They were particularly
    concerned with internet-based, so-called “over-the-top mobile messaging services” such as
    WhatsApp. Id., ¶ 107. Since 2011, OTT messaging services have grown astronomically in use
    while SMS or MMS messaging (the kind of classic texting that relies on cellular networks rather
    than internet) has stagnated. Id. Even though mobile messaging services did not directly
    compete with Facebook Blue (as they are not PSN services), Facebook feared that such apps
    might well become competitors in the future; given the ubiquity of text messaging in modern
    life, a widely adopted messaging app could leverage its network effects to transition into a
    “mobile-first social network” by adding functions such as “gaming platforms, profiles, and news
    feeds.” Id., ¶ 111; see id., ¶¶ 108–112.
    Facebook executives saw WhatsApp as the most potent threat among mobile-messaging
    services. Id., ¶ 113. Launched in 2009, it had approximately 450 million active users worldwide
    five years later and was growing exponentially thanks to its superior product. Id., ¶¶ 113–18.
    Zuckerberg and his team hoped that their Facebook Messenger app, released in 2011, would
    compete. Id., ¶¶ 115–16. But as WhatsApp continued to thrive and expand, Facebook instead
    resolved to try to buy it. Id., ¶ 120. After being initially rebuffed in late 2012, id., ¶ 121, that
    tactic found success in February 2014, when the two companies agreed on a purchase price of
    $19 billion. Id. The transaction was also subject to Hart-Scott-Rodino Act pre-merger review,
    see 18 U.S.C. § 18b, but the FTC, once again, did not block it.
    10
    Since acquiring WhatsApp, the agency alleges, Facebook has “kept [it] cabined to
    providing mobile messaging services rather than allowing” it to grow into a standalone PSN
    service. See Redacted Compl., ¶ 126. As with Instagram, Facebook has also limited its
    promotion of WhatsApp on its other services in the United States. Id. It follows, Plaintiff
    further claims, that “Facebook’s monopolization” via both its WhatsApp and Instagram
    acquisitions “is ongoing,” as it both “continues to hold and operate [the two companies], which
    neutralizes their direct competitive threats to Facebook,” and “continues to keep them positioned
    to provide a protective ‘moat’ around its [PSN] monopoly.” Id., ¶ 76.
    3. Interoperability Permissions
    a. Facebook Platform
    Not long after it expanded to the general public, Facebook released “Facebook Platform,”
    a set of tools that allowed software developers to create interoperability between their products
    and Facebook Blue. Id., ¶ 129. As initially launched, Platform “encouraged software developers
    to build an entire ecosystem of apps and tools” that would be displayed and used within the
    Facebook website itself. Id. Such apps “rang[ed] games and page design tools to video-sharing
    tools and e-marketing apps.” Id. (The States’ Complaint in the parallel case refers to these apps
    as “canvas” apps. See No. 20-3589, ECF No. 4 (State Redacted Compl.), ¶ 190.) Such apps
    would make money by allowing users to purchase virtual goods or items within the app on a
    “freemium” model or via ad sales.
    Three years later, in 2010, Facebook added new functionalities to Platform that expanded
    its reach off the Facebook site itself. These tools — called application programming interfaces
    or APIs — created mechanisms for sharing data between Facebook and other, freestanding third-
    party apps. See Redacted Compl., ¶ 130. One important API that Facebook offered to
    11
    developers was the “Find Friends” API, id., which enabled third-party apps to allow Facebook
    account holders to find and connect with Facebook friends within their separate apps, or to invite
    Facebook friends to join that app. Id. For instance, when first starting to use an independent
    chess app — i.e., an app used separately as opposed to on the Facebook site itself — a user with
    a Facebook account could nonetheless search within the app for other Facebook friends already
    using it, or invite them to join via Facebook, all without leaving the app. Another API allowed
    Facebook users to sign into third-party websites or apps using their Facebook log-in credentials.
    Id., ¶¶ 144, 154.
    Facebook went even further in that direction later in the year when it launched its Open
    Graph API. Id., ¶ 131. Open Graph allowed third-party apps and websites to essentially
    integrate pieces of Facebook within their own service; for instance, apps could install the famous
    “Like” button, which, if clicked, would share a user’s “like” on the user’s Facebook profile. Id.
    Users could do this without even navigating away from the third-party service. Id., ¶¶ 131, 134.
    A user reading an article on WashingtonPost.com, for instance, could now like an article directly
    on-site and further choose to post a link of the article to the user’s Facebook profile. This sort of
    integration was, unsurprisingly, massively popular among app developers. “By July 2012, Open
    Graph was being used to share nearly one billion pieces of social data each day to Facebook
    Blue, giving Facebook substantially greater and richer information about its users and their
    online activities.” Id., ¶ 132.
    According to Plaintiff, Facebook benefited significantly from its Platform program and
    open APIs. The company garnered goodwill and continued to increase its growth and user
    engagement. Id., ¶¶ 133–34. It also obtained access to a massive new trove of off-site user data.
    Id., ¶ 134. Third-party app developers likewise gained, improving the quality of users’
    12
    experience by integrating social functionality and benefiting from Facebook’s sizeable network
    of highly engaged users. Id., ¶¶ 132–33. Users, too, presumably enjoyed the increased
    efficiency and convenience.
    b. Conditioning Access
    Nonetheless, Facebook eventually began to use the power of its Platform tools over the
    growth trajectory of nascent apps to “deter and suppress competitive threats to its personal social
    networking monopoly.” Id., ¶ 136. Specifically, the FTC alleges, the company adopted policies
    under which its APIs would be “available to developers only on the condition that their apps” did
    not compete with Facebook Blue (or Facebook Messenger). Id. The company then enforced
    those policies against “apps that violated the[] conditions by cutting off their use of
    commercially significant APIs.” Id.
    Facebook announced the first iteration of these policies in July 2011, alerting developers
    that going forward, “Apps on Facebook [could] not integrate, link to, promote, distribute, or
    redirect to any app on any other competing social platform.” Id., ¶ 139. This policy, by its
    terms, applied only to “[a]pps on Facebook” — i.e, the “canvas” apps described above that could
    only be accessed and used on the Facebook website itself. Id. Put differently, this initial policy
    did not affect the sort of freestanding, independent apps discussed above, such as our chess app
    or the Washington Post app. It was not until later that Facebook “imposed several other policies
    restricting” freestanding apps’ “use of Facebook Platform, including [the] APIs” just discussed.
    Id., ¶ 141. The first of those additional policies, announced in 2012, prohibited developers from
    “us[ing] Facebook Platform to export [Facebook] user data into a competing social network
    without our permission.” Id., ¶ 142. The next year, Facebook went further by instructing
    developers that their apps could “not use Facebook Platform to promote, or to export user data
    13
    to, a product or service that replicates a core Facebook product or service without our
    permission.” Id., ¶ 143.
    Armed with these policies, Facebook then enforced them by cutting off API access to
    certain apps. As Plaintiff describes it, those cutoffs were “generally directed against apps in
    three groups.” Id., ¶ 152. First, Facebook terminated the API access of promising apps that were
    directly competing with Facebook Blue by providing Personal Social Networking Services, such
    as Path, a feed-based sharing app that limited the number of friends a user could have to
    encourage more intimate sharing. Id., ¶ 153. Second, Facebook targeted “promising apps with
    some social functionality” but which were not yet full-fledged competitors to Facebook Blue.
    Id., ¶ 154. As examples, the Complaint provides Vine, a video-sharing app owned by Twitter to
    which Facebook shut down API access in January 2013, and Circle, a “local social network” that
    had its permissions revoked in December of that year. Id., ¶¶ 154–55. Last, “Facebook blocked
    mobile messaging apps from using commercially significant APIs”; at one point, in August
    2013, it “undertook an enforcement strike against a number” of such apps “simultaneously.” Id.,
    ¶ 156.
    Each of these revocations of access, the FTC alleges, significantly “hindered the ability
    of [the targeted] businesses to grow and threaten Facebook’s personal social networking
    monopoly.” Id., ¶ 157. During the period in which Circle had Facebook API access, for
    example, it was growing at a rate of 600,000-800,000 users per day; after losing its Facebook
    interconnections (particularly the Find Friends tool), however, its “daily new users dropped . . .
    to nearly zero.” Id., ¶ 154. Facebook’s actions also allegedly “alerted other apps that they would
    lose access . . . if they, too, posed a threat to Facebook’s . . . monopoly,” thereby deterring other
    apps from adding features or functionality that would attract the company’s ire. Id., ¶ 158.
    14
    There is an important coda to this story, however: Facebook “removed its ‘core
    functionality’ restrictions” in December 2018. Id., ¶ 148 (emphasis added). Although the
    company has not reinstated the policies (or, according to the Complaint, revoked any apps’ API
    access) since that time, the FTC alleges that Facebook “is likely to reinstitute such policies if
    [public] scrutiny passes.” Id., ¶¶ 149, 172.
    D. Procedural History
    The FTC filed this action on December 9, 2020, asserting that the above conduct amounts
    to one count of monopoly maintenance under Section 2 of the Sherman Act. Id., ¶¶ 169–73.
    Unlike the States, the agency does not also allege a violation of Section 7 of the Clayton Act,
    which prohibits acquisitions that will substantially decrease competition. Plaintiff brings this
    suit under Section 13(b) of the FTC Act, which authorizes it to seek an injunction against an
    entity that “is violating” or “is about to violate” the antitrust laws, including Section 2. See 
    15 U.S.C. § 53
    (b). It hopes to procure an injunction aimed at preventing such conduct in the future
    as well as an order mandating “divestiture of assets, divestiture or reconstruction of businesses
    (including, but not limited to, Instagram and/or WhatsApp), and such other relief sufficient to
    restore the competition that would exist absent the conduct alleged in the Complaint.” Redacted
    Compl. at 51.
    This case was initially assigned to Judge Christopher R. Cooper of this district. As noted
    above, however, a number of State Plaintiffs filed a very similar suit against Facebook just
    before this action was filed. That case, No. 20-3589, was assigned to this Court. Pursuant to
    Local Rule 40.5(c)(2), which governs related cases, Judge Cooper was required to reassign this
    action to this Court because it presides over the earlier-filed State case. See No. 20-3590,
    Minute Order of Jan. 12, 2021.
    15
    Facebook has now moved to dismiss both actions. See ECF No. 56 (MTD FTC); No. 20-
    3589, ECF No. 114 (MTD States). While the cases could be consolidated, the Court believes
    that clarity will be enhanced by resolving the two Motions to Dismiss in separate,
    contemporaneously issued Opinions. As explained in its separate Opinion, it will grant the
    Motion to Dismiss the States’ entire case. See Mem. Op., No. 20-3589. By contrast, the Court
    here will dismiss only the Complaint, not the case, leaving the agency the chance to replead if it
    believes it can successfully remedy the infirmities described below.
    II.    Legal Standard
    Facebook moves to dismiss this action under Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 12(b)(6) for
    failure to state a claim upon which relief can be granted. See MTD FTC at 1. In evaluating such
    Motion to Dismiss, the Court must “treat the complaint’s factual allegations as true . . . and must
    grant plaintiff ‘the benefit of all inferences that can be derived from the facts alleged.’” Sparrow
    v. United Air Lines, Inc., 
    216 F.3d 1111
    , 1113 (D.C. Cir. 2000) (quoting Schuler v. United
    States, 
    617 F.2d 605
    , 608 (D.C. Cir. 1979)). Although “detailed factual allegations” are not
    necessary to withstand a Rule 12(b)(6) motion, Bell Atlantic Corp. v. Twombly, 
    550 U.S. 544
    ,
    555 (2007), “a complaint must contain sufficient factual matter, accepted as true, to ‘state a claim
    to relief that is plausible on its face,” Ashcroft v. Iqbal, 
    556 U.S. 662
    , 678 (2009) (quoting
    Twombly, 
    550 U.S. at 570
    ) — that is, the facts alleged in the complaint “must be enough to raise
    a right to relief above the speculative level.” Twombly, 
    550 U.S. at 555
    . The Court need not
    accept as true, then, “a legal conclusion couched as a factual allegation,” Trudeau v. FTC, 
    456 F.3d 178
    , 193 (D.C. Cir. 2006) (quoting Papasan v. Allain, 
    478 U.S. 265
    , 286 (1986)), nor
    “inferences . . . unsupported by the facts set out in the complaint.” 
    Id.
     (quoting Kowal v. MCI
    Commc’ns Corp., 
    16 F.3d 1271
    , 1276 (D.C. Cir. 1994)). And it may consider not only “the facts
    16
    alleged in the complaint,” but also “any documents either attached to or incorporated in the
    complaint[,] and matters of which [courts] may take judicial notice.” Equal Emp’t Opportunity
    Comm’n v. St. Francis Xavier Parochial Sch., 
    117 F.3d 621
    , 624 (D.C. Cir. 1997).
    III.   Analysis
    The offense of monopoly maintenance under Section 2 of the Sherman Act “has two
    elements: ‘(1) the possession of monopoly power in the relevant market and (2) the willful . . .
    maintenance of that power as distinguished from growth or development as a consequence of a
    superior product, business acumen, or historic accident.’” United States v. Microsoft Corp., 
    253 F.3d 34
    , 50 (D.C. Cir. 2001) (quoting United States v. Grinnell Corp., 
    384 U.S. 563
    , 570–71
    (1966)). This second element is usually referred to by the shorthand of “anticompetitive” or
    “exclusionary conduct.” Id. at 58. Facebook, in seeking dismissal, contends that the Complaint
    does not allege facts establishing either element. The Court agrees that the first — the
    possession of monopoly power in the market for Personal Social Networking Services (as
    defined by the agency) — is not adequately pleaded here. No more is needed to conclude that
    the Complaint must be dismissed.
    To promote clarity and efficiency going forward in the event Plaintiff amends its
    Complaint, however, the Court will also address two other issues in this Opinion. Both pertain
    to Section 13(b) of the FTC Act, which the agency relies on to seek an injunction here, and
    which authorizes such relief only where the defendant “is violating, or is about to violate,” the
    antitrust laws. See 
    15 U.S.C. § 53
    (b). First, to the extent that Facebook’s Platform-related
    conduct is actionable, it occurred nearly eight years ago, rendering an injunction under Section
    13(b) unavailable as a matter of law. Second, and on the other hand, Section 13(b) does allow
    17
    the FTC to challenge Facebook’s acquisitions of Instagram and WhatsApp, contrary to the
    company’s contention otherwise.
    A. Monopoly Power
    Begin with the linchpin of this Opinion: whether the FTC has plausibly alleged, as it
    must, that Facebook exercises monopoly power. As explained by the Circuit in Microsoft,
    monopoly power is the “the power to control prices or exclude competition,” such that a firm is a
    monopolist “if it can profitably raise prices substantially above the competitive level.” 
    253 F.3d at 51
     (citations omitted). Where a plaintiff can provide direct proof that a “firm has in fact
    profitably done so, the existence of monopoly power is clear.” 
    Id.
     Because such proof is rare,
    however, plaintiffs and courts usually search for indirect or “circumstantial evidence” of
    monopoly power by inferring it from “a firm’s possession of a dominant share of a relevant
    market.” Id.; see also Toys “R” Us, Inc. v. FTC, 
    221 F.3d 928
    , 937 (7th Cir. 2000) (noting that
    market power can be proven “through direct evidence of anticompetitive effects” or, “more
    conventional[ly],” “by proving relevant product and geographic markets and by showing that the
    defendant’s share exceeds [some] threshold”); S. Pac. Commc’ns Co. v. Am. Tel. & Tel. Co.,
    
    740 F.2d 980
    , 1000 (D.C. Cir. 1984) (“[C]ourts frequently approach the problem of measuring
    market power by defining the relevant product and geographic market and computing the
    defendant’s market share. Monopoly power is then ordinarily inferred from a predominant share
    of the market.”). Because “[m]arket power is meaningful only if it is durable,” a plaintiff
    proceeding by the indirect method of providing a relevant market and share thereof must also
    show that there are “barriers to entry” into that market. Lenox MacLaren Surgical Corp. v.
    Medtronic, Inc., 
    762 F.3d 1114
    , 1123–25 (10th Cir. 2014); Microsoft, 
    253 F.3d at 51
     (explaining
    that defendant’s “share of a relevant market” must be “protected by entry barriers,” defined as
    18
    “factors . . . that prevent new rivals from timely responding to an increase in price above the
    competitive level”).
    Although the FTC briefly suggests in its Opposition that it can offer direct proof of
    market power, see ECF No. 59 (FTC Opp.) at 8, it spends nearly its entire brief arguing why it
    has sufficiently pleaded indirect proof — viz., that Facebook has a dominant share of a relevant
    product and geographic market (the United States market for Personal Social Networking
    Services) protected by entry barriers. 
    Id.
     at 8–19. Because the agency thus makes no real direct-
    proof argument, the Court will analyze the Complaint’s market-power allegations using the
    indirect framework. Again, that framework first requires the plaintiff to “establish[] the relevant
    market” in which the defendant firm allegedly has monopoly power. Sky Angel U.S., LLC v.
    Nat’l Cable Satellite Corp., 
    947 F. Supp. 2d 88
    , 102 (D.D.C. 2013) (quoting Neumann v.
    Reinforced Earth Co., 
    786 F.2d 424
    , 429 (D.C. Cir. 1986)). It then demands that a plaintiff
    establish that the defendant has a dominant share of that market protected by entry barriers. Id.;
    see, e.g., FTC v. AbbVie Inc., 
    976 F.3d 327
    , 373–74 (3d Cir. 2020) (above 60% market share
    sufficient); Image Tech. Servs. v. Eastman Kodak Co., 
    125 F.3d 1195
    , 1206 (9th Cir. 1997)
    (“Courts generally require a 65% market share to establish a prima facie case of market
    power.”). As the Court explains below, it is the market-share step that trips up the FTC here.
    1. Market Definition
    a. Legal Framework
    Although the definition of a relevant antitrust market is typically a “factual” rather than a
    “legal” inquiry, certain “legal principles” nevertheless govern. Newcal Indus., Inc. v. Ikon Off.
    Sol., 
    513 F.3d 1038
    , 1045 (9th Cir. 2008). An antitrust market includes “two components: the
    product market and the geographic market.” Sky Angel, 947 F. Supp. 2d at 102. Because the
    19
    parties do not dispute here that the geographic market — that is, “the terrain in which
    competition takes place,” Novell, Inc. v. Microsoft Corp., 
    731 F.3d 1064
    , 1071 (10th Cir. 2013)
    — is the United States, see FTC Opp. at 10, the only issue is the “[t]he outer boundaries of [the
    relevant] product market” in which Facebook operates. Sky Angel, 947 F. Supp. 2d at 102
    (quoting Brown Shoe Co. v. United States, 
    370 U.S. 294
    , 325 (1962)).
    “A ‘relevant product market’ is a term of art in antitrust analysis,” United States v. H&R
    Block, Inc., 
    833 F. Supp. 2d 36
    , 50 (D.D.C. 2011), and is defined as “all products reasonably
    interchangeable by consumers for the same purposes.” Microsoft, 
    253 F.3d at 52
    . “Because the
    ability of consumers to turn to other suppliers restrains a firm from raising prices above the
    competitive level,” 
    id. at 51
    , the analysis of market power (which simply means the power to do
    just that) must use, as its denominator, all products “roughly equivalent to another for the use to
    which [they are] put.” Queen City Pizza, Inc. v. Domino’s Pizza, Inc., 
    124 F.3d 430
    , 437 (3d
    Cir. 1997) (citation omitted). “In other words, courts look at whether two products can be used
    for the same purpose, and, if so, whether and to what extent purchasers are willing to substitute
    one for the other.” H&R Block, 833 F. Supp. 2d at 51 (citation omitted). At bottom, products
    that are sufficiently interchangeable compete with each other in the relevant legal sense. See
    Hicks v. PGA Tour, Inc., 
    897 F.3d 1109
    , 1120 (9th Cir. 2018).
    Unsurprisingly, many “case[s] hing[e]” on this fight over what is included in this
    denominator. See, e.g., FTC v. Staples, Inc., 
    970 F. Supp. 1066
    , 1073 (D.D.C. 1997)
    (considering whether product market includes only “consumable office supplies” such as paper,
    pens, and post-it notes, or instead all office products, including computers, office furniture, and
    fax machines); H&R Block, 833 F. Supp. 2d at 50 (considering whether product market includes
    only “digital do-it-yourself tax preparation products” or instead includes “all tax preparation
    20
    methods,” including professional assistance and do-it-yourself using pen and paper); FTC v.
    Swedish Match, 
    131 F. Supp. 2d 151
    , 156 (D.D.C. 2000) (considering whether product market
    includes only loose-leaf chewing tobacco or instead also includes moist snuff).
    b. Market-Definition Allegations
    The market-definition inquiry in this case is somewhat unusual because, unlike familiar
    consumer goods like tobacco or office supplies, there is no obvious or universally agreed-upon
    definition of just what a personal social networking service is. As a result, to discharge its
    “burden to define the relevant market,” Gross v. Wright, 
    185 F. Supp. 3d 39
    , 50 (D.D.C. 2016)
    (citation omitted), the FTC must do two things here. First, it must provide a definition of PSN
    services (which, obviously, would include at least Facebook Blue). Second, it must further
    explain whether and why other, non-PSN services available to the public either are or are not
    reasonably interchangeable substitutes with PSN services. Ultimately, that analysis should
    demonstrate that Facebook holds a dominant share of a market that includes such substitutes, if
    any.
    On the first point, the agency explains that PSN services are “online services that enable
    and are used by people to maintain personal relationships and share experiences with friends,
    family, and other personal connections in a shared social space.” Redacted Compl., ¶ 52. Such
    services are allegedly defined, and distinguished, by their having “[t]hree key elements.” 
    Id.
    “First, [they] are built on a social graph that maps the connections between users and their
    friends, family, and other personal connections.” Id., ¶ 53. “Second, [they] include features that
    many users regularly employ to interact with personal connections and share their personal
    experiences in a shared [virtual] social space, including in a one-to-many ‘broadcast’ format.”
    Id., ¶ 54. And “[t]hird, [they] include features that allow users to find and connect with other
    21
    users, to make it easier for each user to build and expand their set of personal connections. The
    social graph also supports this feature by informing [the user] which [new] connections” might
    be available based on her existing network. Id., ¶ 55.
    Having defined PSN services, Plaintiff then alleges that there are in fact no “other types
    of internet services” that are “adequate substitutes.” Id., ¶ 57. It buttresses that conclusion by
    explaining why four different kinds of arguably comparable online services are not “reasonably
    interchangeable” with PSN services. Id., ¶ 58. First, “specialized social networking services”
    that “focus on professional . . . connections” (e.g., LinkedIn) are not substitutes because they are
    designed for and used primarily by professionals for sharing professional content. Id., ¶ 58.
    They therefore would not be used, as PSN services are, to “maintain personal relationships and
    share experiences with friends, family, and other personal connections.” Id., ¶ 52. The same is
    true, alleges the FTC, for “interest-based” social-networking services such as Strava (which
    relates to physical exercise). Id., ¶ 58. The agency also pleads that PSN services are not
    reasonably interchangeable with services that allow for consuming and sharing video or audio
    content, such as YouTube, Spotify, Netflix, or Hulu. Id., ¶ 59. That is because users of such
    services mostly consume such content passively or share content created by others (rather than
    content they have created), and such sharing, where it occurs, is not to the user’s network of
    personal connections but rather to a general and wide audience of unknown users. Id. In such a
    setting, users do not usually “communicate with friends, family, and other personal connections,”
    which is the hallmark of a PSN service. Id. Finally, Plaintiff explains that “mobile messaging
    services” cannot be substituted for PSN services because the former (i) lack a “shared social
    space” for interaction and (ii) do not employ a social graph to facilitate users’ finding and
    “friending” other users they may know. Id., ¶ 60. Zuckerberg himself has colorfully explained
    22
    one key difference in use that allegedly flows from these disparate features: a PSN service is “the
    digital equivalent of a town square,” whereas a mobile messaging service is “the digital
    equivalent of [a] living room.” Id.
    According to the FTC, then, the relevant market here thus includes PSN services — such
    as Facebook Blue, Instagram, and Path, id., ¶¶ 63, 153 — and no other kinds of services.
    c. Analysis
    On this issue, Facebook contends that, for a number of reasons, Plaintiff’s allegations
    regarding market definition fall short of the pleading-stage requirement that such “alleged
    product market . . . be plausible.” Sky Angel, 947 F. Supp. 2d at 103 (quoting Todd v. Exxon
    Corp., 
    275 F.3d 191
    , 200 (2d Cir. 2001)). While there are certainly bones that one could pick
    with the FTC’s market-definition allegations, the Court does not find them fatally devoid of
    meat.
    First, Facebook contends that the FTC’s Complaint contains an internal contradiction: its
    market definition appears to exclude services like Circle and Vine, yet one of the core allegations
    in this case is that Facebook’s revocation of API permissions from those apps was
    anticompetitive. See MTD FTC at 14–15. Both cannot be true, Defendant insists. As the FTC
    explains in response, though, the D.C. Circuit rejected exactly this argument in Microsoft.
    There, Microsoft argued that the district court had been wrong to exclude “middleware” software
    from the relevant product market for computer operating systems because much of the
    Government’s Section 2 case turned on “Microsoft’s attempts to suppress middleware’s threat to
    its operating system monopoly.” 
    253 F.3d at 54
    . The Circuit explained that “no contradiction
    exist[ed],” as middleware was still a “nascent” threat even though it was not yet competing
    directly in Microsoft’s operating-system market, and “[n]othing in § 2 of the Sherman Act limits
    23
    its prohibition to actions taken against threats that are already well-developed enough to serve as
    present substitutes.” Id. So too here: actions taken against Vine and Circle may have been
    anticompetitive even though those firms were not Facebook Blue’s competitors in a properly
    drawn product market.
    Second, Defendant maintains, the FTC has neglected to allege any facts regarding the
    “cross-elasticity of demand between [PSN services] and [potential] substitutes for it.” Sky
    Angel, 947 F. Supp. 2d at 103 (citation omitted); see MTD FTC at 11–12. Cross-elasticity of
    demand is a measure of the degree to which “the rise in the price of [one] good] . . . would tend
    to create a greater demand for other like goods.” Queen City Pizza, 
    124 F.3d at
    437–38 & n.6.
    It is thus one “measure of reasonable interchangeability.” 
    Id.
     at 438 n.6. There is no authority,
    however, supporting Facebook’s argument that Plaintiff must plead specific facts regarding the
    price or non-price terms under which PSN-service users would switch (if ever) to alternatives.
    Instead, at this stage the FTC may permissibly plead that certain “factors” of both the service at
    issue and its potential substitutes — e.g., their “price, use[,] and qualities” — render them not
    “reasonably interchangeable” in the eyes of users. Tunis Bros. Co., Inc. v. Ford Motor Co., 
    952 F.2d 715
    , 722 (3d Cir. 1991); see, e.g., RealPage, Inc. v. Yardi Sys., Inc., 
    852 F. Supp. 2d 1215
    ,
    1225 (C.D. Cal. 2012) (denying motion to dismiss where complaint explained in qualitative
    terms why certain “conceivably interchangeable substitutes” were not “specialized to the needs”
    of defendant’s customers); CollegeNet, Inc. v. Common Application, Inc., 
    355 F. Supp. 3d 926
    ,
    958 (D. Or. 2018) (same where complaint alleged that product’s “distinct features” made it such
    that customers “would not turn to [alternatives] in response to” price increase); see also Phillip E.
    Areeda & Herbert Hovenkamp, Antitrust Law vol. IIB, ¶ 531f, at 252 & n.24 (4th ed. 2014)
    (suggesting only that “some detail about lack of interchangeability should be given” in
    24
    complaint). That is what the agency has done here, albeit in a somewhat lean fashion. See
    Redacted Compl., ¶¶ 58–60.
    Defendant next directly takes aim at the FTC’s allegation that users of PSN services
    would not switch, if prodded by a price increase or quality decrease in a PSN service, to other
    means of communicating and sharing with their personal connections that lack a “connection-
    finder” built on the user’s social graph (the third leg of the agency’s definition of a PSN). See
    MTD FTC at 17–19; see also ECF No. 62 (Reply FTC) at 7. That is implausible, Facebook
    contends, because it is “obvious that people” also know how to “connect and share with family
    and friends . . . via many [other] technologies,” such as “email, messaging, photo-sharing, and
    video-chats.” MTD FTC at 18 (internal quotation marks omitted). This argument asks the Court
    to engage in the sort of “deeply fact-intensive inquiry” that is improper at this stage. E.I. du Pont
    de Nemours & Co. v. Kolon Indus., Inc., 
    637 F.3d 435
    , 443–44 (4th Cir. 2011) (quoting Todd,
    
    275 F.3d at 200
    ). Although open to dispute, the agency’s allegation that users view services with
    and without a social-graph-based connection-finder as fundamentally different and non-
    interchangeable is “at least . . . theoretically rational,” Bayer Schering Pharma AG v. Sandoz,
    Inc., 
    813 F. Supp. 2d 569
    , 577 (S.D.N.Y. 2011) (citation omitted), and thus hardly “facially
    unsustainable,” RealPage, 852 F. Supp. 2d at 1224, or “untenable on its face.” Suture Exp., Inc.
    v. Cardinal Health 200, LLC, 
    963 F. Supp. 2d 1212
    , 1222 (D. Kan. 2013). This is therefore not
    one of the “relatively rare” cases of a “glaring deficienc[y]” in the market-definition pleadings
    that renders dismissal at the 12(b)(6) stage appropriate. Kolon Indus., 537 F.3d at 444.
    Facebook’s final fruitless market-definition argument is that the Complaint
    impermissibly distinguishes PSN services from other possible substitutes based on their
    “primar[y] uses.” MTD FTC at 19. The company asserts that the question is whether other
    25
    services “can perform the same function[s]” as PSN services, not whether they are primarily
    used that way. Id. (quoting and adding emphasis to Cupp v. Alberto-Culver USA, Inc., 
    310 F. Supp. 2d 963
    , 970 (W.D. Tenn. 2004)). That misstates the law. The analysis looks to both
    “whether two products can be used for the same purpose, and, if so, whether and to what extent
    purchasers are willing to substitute one for the other.” H&R Block, 833 F. Supp. 2d at 51
    (emphasis added); see also United States v. Aetna Inc., 
    240 F. Supp. 3d 1
    , 19 (D.D.C. 2017)
    (asking “whether there are other products offered to consumers which are similar in character or
    use, and how far buyers will go to substitute one commodity for another”) (emphasis added). It
    is for this reason that pen-and-paper do-it-yourself tax prep and assisted tax prep could be
    outside the market for digital do-it-yourself tax-prep services despite both providing the same
    basic function, H&R Block, 833 F. Supp. 2d at 54, and that Medicare Advantage plans and
    Original Medicare plans could constitute distinct product markets despite both being capable of
    providing healthcare insurance to seniors. Aetna, 240 F. Supp. 3d at 19, 41. All Plaintiff must
    do at this stage is provide a “plausible explanation as to why” users would not switch, even if
    they technically could, from PSN services to other services if prompted by a price hike. Todd,
    
    275 F.3d at 200
    ; cf. Concord Assocs., L.P. v. Ent. Properties Tr., 
    817 F.3d 46
    , 54 (2d Cir. 2016)
    (requiring “a plausible basis for explaining why [a proffered distinction] makes the difference” to
    consumers). While the agency certainly could have provided more on that front, the fact that
    other services are not primarily used for the sort of personal sharing that is the hallmark of a PSN
    service seems a plausible reason why little switching would occur. Whether due to network
    effects or the norms around what sort of content is generally posted on different platforms, it is
    not a stretch to imagine that users are reluctant to share a highly personal milestone on LinkedIn
    or post a video of their child’s first steps to YouTube.
    26
    2. Market Share
    Although the Court therefore finds that the Complaint’s allegations do enough to make
    out a plausible market for PSN services, that hardly ends the analysis. After all, while courts
    typically evaluate market definition and market share separately, the two inquiries ultimately
    come together to produce the conclusion that matters: the defendant’s market power. See Cupp,
    
    310 F. Supp. 2d at 971, 975
    . That point can be lost if courts “compartmentalize the two issues”
    and examine the sufficiency of a plaintiff’s market-share showings without looking back to how
    convincingly, or “how tenuously,” the market has been defined. See Areeda & Hovenkamp,
    ¶ 531, at 257. Particularly where “the market is idiosyncratically drawn,” the treatise authors
    explain, findings or allegations as to a “particular ‘market share’ carr[y] much less meaning.” 
    Id.
    This case, at least as pleaded by the FTC, exemplifies that principle. Although the Court,
    as just explained, finds the contours of the asserted product market plausible, the Complaint is
    undoubtedly light on specific factual allegations regarding consumer-switching preferences.
    Given that thin showing, and the fact that the PSN-services product market is somewhat
    “idiosyncratically drawn” to begin with, the Court must demand something more robust from
    Plaintiff’s market-share allegations. As it happens, however, those allegations are even more
    tentative: the FTC alleges only that Facebook has “maintained a dominant share of the U.S.
    personal social networking market (in excess of 60%)” since 2011, see Redacted Compl., ¶ 64,
    and that “no other social network of comparable scale exists in the United States.” Id., ¶ 3. That
    is it. These allegations — which do not even provide an estimated actual figure or range for
    Facebook’s market share at any point over the past ten years — ultimately fall short of plausibly
    establishing that Facebook holds market power. Given that finding, the court need not address
    the issue of whether the FTC has sufficiently alleged entry barriers.
    27
    Off the bat, there is ample authority that the FTC’s bare assertions would be too
    conclusory to plausibly establish market power in any context. See Synthes, Inc. v. Emerge
    Med., Inc., No. 11-1566, 
    2012 WL 4473228
    , at *11 (E.D. Pa. Sept. 28, 2012) (allegation that
    defendant “is a monopoly . . . with over 50% market share” was a “threadbare recital
    unsupported by factual allegations [that] the Court need not accept . . . as true”); Syncsort Inc. v.
    Sequential Software, Inc., 
    50 F. Supp. 2d 318
    , 330 (D.N.J. 1999) (“Here, [plaintiff] recited in
    conclusory fashion that [defendant] ‘controls the majority of the [relevant] market.’ . . . [T]his
    single statement of market power in the pleadings . . . is an insufficient allegation of the
    possession of monopoly power.”); Korea Kumho Petrochemical v. Flexsys Am. LP, No. 07-
    1057, 
    2008 WL 686834
    , at *9 (N.D. Cal. Mar. 11, 2008) (holding that “[a]lthough [p]laintiff
    need not necessarily quantify [defendant’s] market share with precision,” allegation that
    defendant “domina[ted] . . . the [relevant] market” fell short of requirement to “assert some facts
    in support of its assertions of market power”); EuroTec Vertical Flight Sols., LLC. v. Safran
    Helicopter Engines S.A.A., No. 15-3454, 
    2019 WL 3503240
    , at *3 (N.D. Tex. Aug. 1, 2019)
    (noting that bare allegation of “market share of over 50 percent” was “conclusory”); Sherwin-
    Williams Co. v. Dynamic Auto Images, Inc., No. 16-1792, 
    2017 WL 3081822
    , at *7 (C.D. Cal.
    Mar. 10, 2017) (“[Claimants’] allegation that [firm] maintains a ‘a stranglehold in the automotive
    paint industry’ is . . . conclusory” and thus “lacks sufficient detail for the Court to plausibly infer
    . . . sufficient market power.”). It is hard to imagine a market-share allegation that is much more
    conclusory than the FTC’s here.
    Even accepting that merely alleging market share “in excess of 60%” might sometimes
    be acceptable, it cannot suffice in this context, where Plaintiff does not even allege what it is
    measuring. Indeed, in its Opposition the FTC expressly contends that it need not “specify which
    28
    . . . metrics . . . [or] ‘method’ [it] used to calculate Facebook’s [market] share.” FTC Opp. at 18.
    In a case involving a more typical goods market, perhaps the Court might be able to reasonably
    infer how Plaintiff arrived at its calculations — e.g., by proportion of total revenue or of units
    sold. See U.S. Dep’t of Justice & FTC, Horizontal Merger Guidelines § 5.2 (2010) (suggesting
    these to be the typical methods). As the above market-definition analysis underscores, however,
    the market at issue here is unusual in a number of ways, including that the products therein are
    not sold for a price, meaning that PSN services earn no direct revenue from users. The Court is
    thus unable to understand exactly what the agency’s “60%-plus” figure is even referring to, let
    alone able to infer the underlying facts that might substantiate it.
    Rather than undergirding any inference of market power, Plaintiff’s allegations make it
    even less clear what the agency might be measuring. The overall revenues earned by PSN
    services cannot be the right metric for measuring market share here, as those revenues are all
    earned in a separate market — viz., the market for advertising. See Redacted Compl., ¶ 164; see
    also, e.g., id., ¶ 101 (noting that prior to its acquisition, in addition to competing in the PSN
    services market, “Instagram also planned and expected to be an important advertising
    competitor” to Facebook). Percent of “daily users [or] monthly users” of PSN services —
    metrics the Complaint mentions offhandedly, see Redacted Compl., ¶¶ 3, 97 — are not much
    better, as they might significantly overstate or understate any one firm’s market share depending
    on the various proportions of users who have accounts on multiple services, not to mention how
    often users visit each service and for how long.
    What about the share of total time spent by users on PSN services? Plaintiff says nothing
    about that metric in its Complaint. And although it seems tenable at first glance, that metric may
    also be of limited utility. That is because at least some of the features offered by a Facebook or
    29
    Instagram or Path are not, seemingly, part of those firms’ PSN-services offerings as defined by
    the FTC; time spent on those apps or websites, accordingly, is not necessarily time spent on a
    PSN service. The Commission, for instance, expressly alleges that social-networking services
    based on “interest-based . . . connections” such as Strava are not, by its definition, PSN services.
    Id., ¶ 58. That definition of what is in the market, perhaps counterintuitively to Facebook users,
    would mean that time a user spends engaging with specific interest-based Facebook pages or
    groups may not qualify as time spent on a PSN service. The same problem arises when a user
    “passive[ly] consum[es]” “online video” on a PSN service. Id., ¶ 59. To the extent that, say,
    Instagram users spend their time on the site or app watching a comedy routine posted by the
    official page of a famous comedian, are they spending time on a PSN service? If not, as the
    Complaint suggests is the case, id., then time spent “on Facebook” or “on Instagram” bears an
    uncertain relationship to the actual metric that would be relevant: time spent using their PSN
    services in particular. Put another way, the uncertainty left open by the Complaint as to exactly
    which features of Facebook, Instagram, et al. do and do not constitute part of their PSN services,
    while not necessarily rendering the alleged PSN-services market implausible, compounds the
    trouble created by the FTC’s vaguer-still allegations regarding Facebook’s share of that market.
    Nor do the difficulties stop there. Readers may well have noticed that the discussion to
    this point has consistently referred to Instagram and Facebook as examples of PSN services.
    That is because, outside of Path, Myspace, and Friendster, all of which seem to be long defunct
    or quite small, see id., ¶¶ 38, 41, 153, Plaintiff’s Complaint does not identify any other providers
    of PSN services. Yet the FTC is apparently unwilling to allege that Facebook has ever (pre- or
    post-Instagram acquisition) had something like 85% or even 75% market share; instead it hedges
    by offering only that the number is somewhere north of 60%. The question naturally arises:
    30
    which firms make up the remaining 30–40%? Cf. Cupp, 
    310 F. Supp. 2d at 971
     (“Without a[n]
    . . . accounting of the brands and suppliers to be included in the relevant market, the Court cannot
    determine [its] boundaries . . . . [and] is thus unable to assess Defendants’ market power.”); Total
    Benefits Plan. Agency, Inc. v. Anthem Blue Cross & Blue Shield, 
    552 F.3d 430
    , 437 (6th Cir.
    2008) (“Without an explanation of the other insurance companies involved, and their products
    and services, the court cannot determine the boundaries of the relevant product market and must
    dismiss the case for failure to state a claim.”). Although Plaintiff is correct that it is not required
    to identify every alleged competitor in its pleadings, its choice to identify essentially none is
    striking. Especially when combined with its refusal to offer any clue as to how it calculated its
    noncommittal market-share number, the Court cannot see how the Commission has “nudged [its
    market power] claims across the line from conceivable to plausible.” Twombly, 
    550 U.S. at 570
    .
    Its “complaint must [therefore] be dismissed.” 
    Id.
    The Court’s decision here does not rest on some pleading technicality or arcane feature of
    antitrust law. Rather, the existence of market power is at the heart of any monopolization claim.
    As the Supreme Court explained in Twombly, itself an antitrust case, “[A] district court must
    retain the power to insist upon some specificity in pleading before allowing a potentially massive
    factual controversy to proceed.” 
    Id. at 558
     (citations omitted). Here, this Court must exercise
    that power. The FTC’s Complaint says almost nothing concrete on the key question of how
    much power Facebook actually had, and still has, in a properly defined antitrust product market.
    It is almost as if the agency expects the Court to simply nod to the conventional wisdom that
    Facebook is a monopolist. After all, no one who hears the title of the 2010 film “The Social
    Network” wonders which company it is about. Yet, whatever it may mean to the public,
    “monopoly power” is a term of art under federal law with a precise economic meaning: the
    31
    power to profitably raise prices or exclude competition in a properly defined market. To merely
    allege that a defendant firm has somewhere over 60% share of an unusual, nonintuitive product
    market — the confines of which are only somewhat fleshed out and the players within which
    remain almost entirely unspecified — is not enough. The FTC has therefore fallen short of its
    pleading burden.
    That said, because it believes that the agency may be able to “cure [these] deficiencies”
    by repleading, Foman v. Davis, 
    371 U.S. 178
    , 182 (1962), the Court will dismiss without
    prejudice only the Complaint, not the entire case, leaving Plaintiff “free to amend [its] pleading
    and continue the litigation.” Ciralsky, 
    355 F.3d at 666
     (citation omitted) (explaining that
    dismissal without prejudice of the complaint, as opposed to the case, is not final). Whether and
    how the agency chooses to do so is up to it.
    ***
    While the court could end here, it believes it profitable to provide some guidance to the
    parties should the case proceed. It thus offers some further legal analysis on two issues raised by
    the FTC’s allegations. For ease of organization, that discussion will “analyze the various”
    components of the agency’s Section 2 claim — namely, the Platform-policies component and the
    acquisitions component — “individually,” even though Plaintiff technically frames its challenge
    as an attack on Facebook’s overall course of anticompetitive conduct. See City of Groton v.
    Connecticut Light & Power Co., 
    662 F.2d 921
    , 928–29 (2d Cir. 1981). It begins by explaining
    why, in accord with its analysis in the parallel State case, even assuming that the FTC can
    establish market power here, its allegations as to Facebook’s Platform-related conduct cannot be
    a basis for injunctive relief under Section 13(b). It then offers the agency some consolation:
    32
    assuming again that market power can be demonstrated, Section 13(b) does, pace Facebook,
    allow the FTC to seek injunctive relief based on the Instagram and WhatsApp acquisitions.
    B. Platform Policies
    By way of refresher, Plaintiff alleges that Facebook adopted and enforced a number of
    anticompetitive policies governing the use of its APIs. Most prominently, in 2013 it announced
    a policy of refusing to allow third-party, freestanding apps (like the chess app or the Washington
    Post app discussed above) to access those APIs if they “replicate[d] [Facebook’s] core
    functionality” — i.e., if they competed with Facebook Blue. See Redacted Compl., ¶¶ 136, 143.
    Facebook then enforced that policy against a number of freestanding apps, revoking API
    permissions after having previously offering them access. 
    Id.,
     ¶¶ 152–56. The FTC, like the
    States in the parallel action, see Mem. Op., No. 20-3589 at 22, contends that these actions
    represent unlawful “conditional dealing” or unlawful “refusal[s] to deal” with apps that had their
    API access revoked or blocked. See FTC Opp. at 31, 33.
    This Court, however, agrees with Facebook’s bottom-line contention that neither theory
    offers a viable basis for an injunction under Section 13(b) of the FTC Act. That result follows
    from three conclusions. First, under current antitrust doctrine, Facebook’s general policy of
    refusing to provide API access to its competitors does not itself violate Section 2. Second,
    although specific instances in which Facebook revoked a competitor’s API permissions (after
    previously providing it access) might have violated Section 2, the last alleged instance occurred
    in 2013, so there is no way in which Facebook “is violating” or “is about to violate” the antitrust
    laws, which is a necessary condition for an injunction under Section 13(b). See 
    15 U.S.C. § 53
    (b). Third, and more prosaically, Plaintiff has failed to plead facts to support a “conditional
    dealing” theory. The Court looks at the first two together and then moves to the third.
    33
    For those who will consider this Opinion alongside the Court’s companion Opinion in the
    State case, the following “legal framework” section is the same in both. The analysis that
    follows diverges somewhat given the different legal regimes governing suits by States and suits
    by the FTC, although the outcome is similar.
    1. Refusal to Deal
    a. Legal Framework
    The central principle that governs refusal-to-deal claims is that, as a general matter, a
    monopolist has “the right to refuse to deal with other firms,” which includes the right to “refus[e]
    to cooperate with rivals.” Verizon Commc’ns Inc. v. L. Offs. of Curtis V. Trinko, LLP, 
    540 U.S. 398
    , 408 (2004) (citing Aspen Skiing Co. v. Aspen Highlands Skiing Corp., 
    472 U.S. 585
    , 601
    (1985)). That is because “[m]onopolists are both expected and permitted to compete like any
    other firm,” and “[p]art of competing like everyone else is the ability to make decisions about
    with whom and on what terms one will deal.” Viamedia, Inc. v. Comcast Corp., 
    951 F.3d 429
    ,
    454 (7th Cir. 2020) (citations omitted). This general no-duty-to-deal rule holds even where a
    monopolist refuses to deal with its competitor merely “in order to limit entry,” Trinko, 
    540 U.S. at
    407 — in other words, because it wants to prevent that rival from competing with it. See, e.g.,
    Olympia Equip. Leasing Co. v. W. Union Tel. Co., 
    797 F.2d 370
    , 375–76 (7th Cir. 1986)
    (“Today it is clear that a firm with lawful monopoly power has no general duty to help its
    competitors” and thus no duty “to extend a helping hand to new entrants [or] help [rivals] survive
    or expand . . . .”); Novell, Inc. v. Microsoft Corp., 
    731 F.3d 1064
    , 1074 (10th Cir. 2013) (“Even
    a monopolist generally has no duty to share . . . its intellectual or physical property with a
    rival.”); FTC v. Qualcomm Inc., 
    969 F.3d 974
    , 993 (9th Cir. 2020) (“As the Supreme Court has
    repeatedly emphasized, there is no duty to deal under the terms and conditions preferred by a
    34
    competitor’s rivals.”) (quoting Pac. Bell Tel. Co. v. Linkline Commc’ns, Inc., 
    555 U.S. 438
    , 457
    (2009)); Aerotec Int’l, Inc. v. Honeywell Int’l, Inc., 
    836 F.3d 1171
    , 1184 (9th Cir. 2016)
    (rejecting argument that refusal to deal is unlawful because it was motivated by “intent to
    foreclose competition”).
    These decisions, to be clear, “are not premised on the view that [monopolist refusals to
    deal] are incapable of harming competition”; obviously, “refusals to aid new entrants can
    indeed” have that effect. See Daniel A. Crane, Does Monopoly Broth Make Bad Soup?, 76
    Antitrust L.J. 663, 669 (2010). Rather, the rule declaring unilateral refusals to deal essentially
    “per se lawful,” id. at 666, or “presumptive[ly] legal[],” Novell, 731 F.3d at 1073, rests on three
    overriding considerations of antitrust policy. First, and most importantly, “[f]irms may acquire
    monopoly power by establishing an infrastructure that renders them uniquely suited to serve their
    customers. Compelling such firms to share the source of their advantage is in some tension with
    the underlying purpose of antitrust law, since it may lessen the incentive for the monopolist, the
    rival, or both to invest in those economically beneficial facilities.” Trinko, 
    540 U.S. at
    407–08.
    Put another way, already large and successful firms “might be deterred from investing,
    innovating, or expanding . . . with the knowledge [that] anything [they] creat[e] [they] could be
    forced to share,” while “smaller [competitors] might be [similarly] deterred, knowing [they]
    could just demand the right to piggyback on [their] larger rival.” Novell, 
    731 F.3d 1073
    . That
    equilibrium would hinder, rather than advance, consumer welfare. See Olympia Equip. Leasing,
    
    797 F.2d at 379
     (“Consumers would be worse off if a firm with monopoly power had a duty to
    extend positive assistance to new entrants, or having extended it voluntarily a duty to continue it
    indefinitely.”). Second, “compelled sharing puts federal courts in the role of central planners,”
    requiring them to pick and choose the applicable terms and conditions of the forced sharing they
    35
    would order “despite their being ill-equipped to assume this role.” Aerotec, 836 F.3d at 1183.
    Finally, “compelled sharing may actually provide opportunities for collusion” between the
    monopolist and its rival or rivals. Id. Collusion is “the supreme evil of antitrust,” Trinko, 
    540 U.S. at 408
    , and itself quite “injuri[ous] to consumers and the competitive process alike.”
    Novell, 731 F.3d at 1073.
    Nevertheless, the general no-duty-to-deal rule does have a “narrow-eyed needle” of an
    exception, id., at 1074, traceable to the Supreme Court’s decision in Aspen Skiing. In that case,
    the defendant owned three of the four ski resorts in the Aspen, Colorado, market (making it a
    monopolist), and it had long operated a joint venture with the fourth (a rival mountain) that
    provided a ticket good for all four. See 
    472 U.S. at
    588–92. That joint ticket was profitable for
    both parties and made customers happy. 
    Id. at 610
    . The defendant Aspen Skiing, however,
    eventually terminated the joint ticket. Plaintiff Highlands “tried a variety of increasingly
    desperate measures to re-create the joint ticket,” including eventually “offering to buy the
    defendant’s tickets at retail price.” Trinko, 
    540 U.S. at
    408–09. Aspen Skiing refused to even
    accept those tickets at its resorts. According to the Court, based on these facts, the jury (which
    had found liability) could have reasonably concluded that Aspen Skiing “was not motivated by
    efficiency concerns and . . . was [instead] willing to sacrifice short-run benefits and consumer
    goodwill in exchange for a perceived long-run impact on its smaller rival.” 
    472 U.S. at
    610–11.
    That, the Court held, was sufficient for Section 2 liability.
    As the case has come to be understood, Aspen Skiing ran afoul of the Sherman Act —
    despite the general no-duty-to-deal rule — because it acted in a predatory fashion, which is to
    say it deliberately harmed itself (and consumers) in order to harm its competitor more. Consider
    the analogy of a predatory pricing scheme, in which a firm prices its goods below its costs and
    36
    below its rivals’ costs with the goal of driving those rivals out of the market and leaving it
    standing alone; such a scheme works where the predatory firm takes advantage of its greater
    ability to withstand the losses caused by its below-cost pricing. See Novell, 731 F.3d at 1075
    (drawing this comparison); Brooke Grp. Ltd. v. Brown & Williamson Tobacco Corp., 
    509 U.S. 209
    , 224 (1993) (explaining predatory-pricing doctrine). Aspen Skiing was doing something
    very similar. By terminating a profitable and customer-pleasing joint venture, and refusing to
    even recreate it by accepting vouchers bought at retail price, it was enduring short-term pain with
    the exclusive goal of driving its rival (which could not stand that pain) out of the market. The
    defendant thus lost the usual protection of the general no-duty-to-deal rule, since it had used its
    general right to choose with whom it deals “as part of a larger anticompetitive enterprise” — i.e.,
    an enterprise aimed at “harming competition,” and therefore consumers, “by entrenching a
    dominant firm and enabling it to extract monopoly rents once the competitor is killed off.”
    Viamedia, 951 F.3d at 462 (quoting Novell, 731 F.3d at 1075) (cleaned up); see also Areeda &
    Hovenkamp vol. IIIB, ¶ 772d3, at 235.
    The “larger anticompetitive enterprise” that characterizes an Aspen Skiing violation,
    crucially, cannot simply be an intent to harm — or, the flip side of the same coin, to avoid
    helping — a rival or rivals. “In concentrated markets the intent to maintain or improve one’s
    own market position always entails the knowledge that rivals must suffer,” and if antitrust law
    were to condemn every action taken by a monopolist with the “effect or purpose of limiting
    competition with itself,” there would be little left to the rule that monopolists have no duty to aid
    their competitors. See Areeda & Hovenkamp, ¶ 772c2, at 220–21. That is why the Supreme
    Court has described Aspen Skiing as “at or near the outer boundary of § 2 liability,” Trinko, 
    540 U.S. at 399
    , and “refused to extend liability to various other refusal to deal scenarios.” Novell,
    37
    731 F.3d at 1074; but see Steward Health Care Sys., LLC v. Blue Cross & Blue Shield of Rhode
    Island, 
    311 F. Supp. 3d 468
    , 483 (D.R.I. 2018) (arguing that Trinko should not be read as
    “pulling back the reins on refusal-to-deal claims”). And that is why the touchstone for liability is
    the sort of predatory design described above: “where the only conceivable rationale or purpose”
    for the refusal to deal is “to sacrifice short-term benefits in order to obtain higher profits in the
    long run from the exclusion of competition.” Aerotec, 836 F.3d at 1184 (citation omitted).
    Courts have accordingly coalesced around a three-part test for unlawful refusals to deal,
    drawn from Aspen Skiing’s particular facts and aimed at sniffing out predation while avoiding
    over-inclusiveness. First, “there must be a preexisting voluntary and presumably profitable
    course of dealing between the monopolist and rival” with which the monopolist later refuses to
    deal. Novell, 731 F.3d at 1074; Qualcomm, 969 F.3d at 993. It was the absence of this
    preexisting relationship that doomed the plaintiffs in Trinko, as the Court upheld the dismissal of
    their Aspen Skiing claim at the pleading stage on that basis, despite their allegations that
    Verizon’s refusal to deal with rivals was intended to, and did, blunt their growth. See 
    540 U.S. at
    404–05, 407, 409. Second, “the refusal to deal [must] involve[] products that the defendant
    already sells in the existing market to other similarly situated customers.” Qualcomm, 969 F.3d
    at 994; see Areeda & Hovenkamp, ¶ 773d3, at 233 (defendant must be “selling [the] particular
    product or service to others but refu[sing] to sell that same product or service to” the rival)
    (citing Trinko, 
    540 U.S. at 410
    ). Third, and most importantly, “the monopolist’s discontinuation
    of the preexisting course of dealing must suggest a willingness to forsake short-term profits to
    achieve an anti-competitive end,” Novell, 731 F.3d at 1075; see Qualcomm, 969 F.3d at 993,
    rather than to advance a valid business purpose. See also Covad Commc’ns Co. v. Bell Atl.
    Corp., 
    398 F.3d 666
    , 675 (D.C. Cir. 2005) (to prevail on refusal-to-deal claim, plaintiff “will
    38
    have to prove [that defendant’s] refusal to deal caused [defendant] short-term economic loss”).
    The cases, and the leading treatise, offer a demanding gloss on this prong of the test: Qualcomm
    requires the predatory motivation to be “the only conceivable rationale or purpose” for the
    otherwise inexplicable profit sacrifice, see 969 F.3d at 993; Novell asks whether the cessation of
    dealing was “irrational but for its tendency to harm competition,” 731 F.3d at 1076; and Areeda
    & Hovenkamp look for “an unexplained, apparently irrational change in an established course of
    dealing.” Areeda & Hovenkamp, ¶ 772d3, at 233.
    b. Application
    i. Facebook Policies
    Applying these principles, it is clear off the bat that Facebook’s adoption of a policy of
    not offering API access to competitors did not, standing alone, violate Section 2. As set out
    above, a monopolist has no duty to deal with its competitors, and a refusal to do so is generally
    lawful even if it is motivated, as Verizon’s was in Trinko, by a desire “to limit entry” by new
    firms or impede the growth of existing ones. See 
    540 U.S. at 407
    . It follows that a firm’s merely
    announcing its choice not to deal with competitors, whatever the motivation for doing so, cannot
    violate Section 2. The FTC’s core argument for why the policies themselves are unlawful —
    that their promulgation was intended to, and did, “change[] the incentives of third-party apps that
    relied upon the Facebook ecosystem [and thus] deterr[ed] them from including features and
    functionalities that might compete with Facebook,” Redacted Compl., ¶ 25; see also id., ¶¶ 77,
    137 — misses the boat. The central teaching of the cases discussed above is that Facebook had
    no antitrust duty to avoid creating that deterrent. See, e.g., Olympia Equipment Leasing, 
    797 F.2d at 375
     (“Today it is clear that a firm with lawful monopoly power has no general duty to
    help its competitors . . . by . . . pulling its competitive punches.”).
    39
    Facebook’s general policy of withholding API access from competitors, moreover, was
    plainly lawful to the extent it covered rivals with which it had no previous, voluntary course of
    dealing. (Other rivals are addressed in Section B.1.b.ii., infra.) Such prior history of dealing,
    recall, is a necessary element of an Aspen Skiing claim. That is yet another reason why the mere
    act of announcing or maintaining a general no-dealing-with-competitors policy cannot, in and of
    itself, violate Section 2; rather, the analysis must focus on particular acts. See Areeda &
    Hovenkamp, ¶ 773e, at 273 (explaining that Aspen Skiing violations are “visible and
    idiosyncratic event[s]”). Consider an example from the Complaint: citing its policies, in early
    2013 Facebook blocked the API access of Vine, a new app it viewed as a competitor, mere hours
    after its launch. See Redacted Compl., ¶ 155. That decision was plainly lawful, per Trinko,
    because it was prospective: Facebook had not previously allowed Vine to access its APIs.
    Although the company was enforcing its “replicating core functionality” general policy against
    Vine, that fact makes no difference to the Aspen Skiing analysis; rather, whether the specific
    refusal to deal with Vine contravened Section 2 depends on the details of the refusal itself.
    To be clear, it is possible that were a monopolist to embark on a concerted scheme of
    serial refusals to deal with rivals, that scheme or “course of conduct” could amount to a separate
    and independent violation of the Sherman Act. See Microsoft., 
    253 F.3d at 78
     (noting course-of-
    conduct theory without passing on its validity). Even if such a claim were cognizable, however,
    simply maintaining a policy of refusing to deal with rivals would not be enough. Rather, to be
    actionable, an unlawful refusal-to-deal scheme would have to be made up of refusals that were
    themselves independent violations of the Aspen Skiing test. See Simon & Simon, PC v. Align
    Tech., Inc., No. 19-506, 
    2020 WL 1975139
    , at *8 (D. Del. Apr. 24, 2020) (“Plaintiff’s
    characterization of [the defendant’s] otherwise non-actionable refusals to deal as a ‘scheme’
    40
    do[es] not save its claims.”); Eatoni Ergonomics, Inc. v. Rsch. In Motion Corp., 
    826 F. Supp. 2d 705
    , 709–10 (S.D.N.Y. 2011) (“[Plaintiff] does not, and cannot, cite any authority for the
    proposition that a series of unilateral acts that do not violate the antitrust laws may be aggregated
    into an unlawful ‘course of conduct.’”), aff’d, 486 F. App’x 186 (2d Cir. 2012); Masimo Corp. v.
    Tyco Health Care Grp., L.P., No. 02-4770, 
    2004 WL 5907538
    , at *5–6 (C.D. Cal. June 10, 2004)
    (explaining that a course-of-conduct liability theory cannot “allow for clearly legal acts to be
    thrown into the mix to bolster a plaintiff’s antitrust case”). Otherwise, as several scholars have
    persuasively explained, monopolists might face liability for refusals to deal that are categorically
    protected from scrutiny for the policy reasons explained above. See Crane, 76 Antitrust L.J. at
    666–69; Douglas H. Ginsburg & Koren Wong-Ervin, Challenging Consummated Mergers Under
    Section 2 (George Mason Univ. L. & Econ. Paper No. 20-14, May 2020),
    https://bit.ly/3wPRpnx. The FTC, therefore, cannot get anywhere by reframing Facebook’s
    adoption of a policy of refusing to deal with all competitors as the execution of an unlawful
    scheme of monopoly maintenance. Rather, to be actionable, such a scheme must involve
    specific instances in which that policy was enforced (i) against a rival with which the monopolist
    had a previous course of dealing; (ii) while the monopolist kept dealing with others in the
    market; (iii) at a short-term profit loss, with no conceivable rationale other than driving a
    competitor out of business in the long run.
    ii. Specific Refusals
    The FTC, to be sure, has alleged several specific refusals to deal that in fact may meet
    those requirements. All such pleaded instances, however, took place in 2013. See Redacted
    Compl., ¶¶ 153–56. That fact is fatal to the agency’s claim for injunctive relief under Section
    41
    13(b) here, regardless of whether those specific refusals to deal ran afoul of Aspen Skiing,
    because it means that no actionable violation is either ongoing or about to occur.
    Section 13(b) allows the FTC to “bring suit in a district court of the United States to
    enjoin” allegedly unlawful conduct only where it has “reason to believe . . . that any person,
    partnership, or corporation is violating, or is about to violate, any provision of law enforced by
    the [FTC].” 
    15 U.S.C. § 53
    (b). All agree that Section 2 of the Sherman Act is such a provision.
    As the Supreme Court has recently explained, given that provision’s requirement that the
    defendant “‘is violating’ or ‘is about to violate’ (not ‘has violated’)” the antitrust laws, it
    contemplates “relief that is prospective, not retrospective.” AMG Cap. Mgmt., LLC v. FTC, 
    141 S. Ct. 1341
    , 1348 (2021); see also FTC v. Credit Bureau Ctr., LLC, 
    937 F.3d 764
    , 774 (7th Cir.
    2019) (“Section 13(b) serves a . . . forward-facing role: enjoining ongoing and imminent future
    violations.”); FTC v. Evans Prod. Co., 
    775 F.2d 1084
    , 1087 (9th Cir. 1985) (holding that Section
    13(b) “contemplate[s] ongoing or future violations” and thus “an injunction will issue only if the
    wrongs are ongoing or likely to recur”). As one court has put it, Section 13(b) therefore “does
    not permit the FTC to bring a claim based on long-past conduct without some evidence that the
    defendant ‘is’ committing or ‘is about to’ commit another violation.” Shire ViroPharma, 917
    F.3d at 156.
    This constraint on Section 13(b)’s scope does not, it is worth noting, leave antitrust
    violations beyond the reach of the federal civil authorities. For one thing, the Department of
    Justice has broad authority to seek injunctive relief in antitrust cases. See 
    15 U.S.C. §§ 4
    , 25.
    And as to the FTC itself, “ever since [its] creation in 1914, it has been authorized to enforce the
    [law] through its own administrative proceedings” under Section 5(b) of the FTC Act. AMG
    Cap. Mgmt., 141 S. Ct. at 1346. Section 5(b) allows the agency to conduct such a proceeding
    42
    against “person [who] has been or is” violating the antitrust laws. See 
    15 U.S.C. § 45
    (b)
    (emphasis added). If it goes that route and prevails, the agency can then seek a court’s help in
    enforcing its orders, including via monetary penalties, 15 U.S.C. § 57b, “mandatory
    injunctions[,] and such other further and equitable relief as [the court] deem[s] appropriate.” Id.
    § 45(l). Thus, as Shire ViroPharma explained, “[i]f the FTC wants to [address] a past violation
    — where an entity ‘has been’ violating the law — it must use Section 5(b).” 917 F.3d at 159
    (quoting 
    15 U.S.C. § 45
    (b)). Section 13(b), by contrast, mainly exists to “address[] a specific
    problem, namely, that of stopping seemingly unfair practices” (including antitrust violations) that
    are ongoing or about to occur “from taking place” until the Commission can complete an
    adjudication. AMG Cap. Mgmt., 141 S. Ct. at 1348.
    Here, given the Court’s conclusions above, the FTC cannot use 13(b) to challenge
    Facebook’s Platform-related conduct because it has not pleaded that any actual Section 2
    violation is ongoing or about to occur. The closest the agency comes is its allegation that,
    “[h]aving suspended its anticompetitive platform policies [in December 2018] in response to
    anticipated public scrutiny, Facebook is likely to reinstitute such policies if such scrutiny
    passes.” Redacted Compl., ¶ 149 (emphasis added). Even if the mere resumption of Facebook’s
    no-dealing-with-competitors policies were itself unlawful — which, as just explained at length, it
    is not — that conditional and conclusory allegation would be insufficient to establish the
    requisite imminence. See, e.g., Shire ViroPharma, 917 F.3d at 153, 160 (finding allegation that
    “[a]bsent an injunction, there is a cognizable danger that [defendant] will engage in similar
    conduct” because it had the “incentive and opportunity” to do so “woefully inadequate to state a
    claim under Section 13(b)”). There are no facts alleged, moreover, suggesting that the antitrust
    43
    “scrutiny” the company is facing is “about to” pass or indeed will pass at any time in the
    foreseeable future. Indeed, a quick glance at any newspaper yields the contrary conclusion.
    The more fundamental problem, of course, is that Facebook would not only have to
    imminently reinstate its policies, but it would also have to imminently take the kind of further
    action that might come within Aspen Skiing: target its competitors with which it had a previous,
    voluntary course of dealing for API revocation in a manner that suggests predatory, short-term-
    profit-sacrificing behavior. The FTC has certainly not alleged that that specific sort of conduct is
    “about to” occur. Nor could it since, according to the Complaint, Facebook has not actually
    taken such an action in nearly eight years. See Shire ViroPharma, 917 F.3d at 160 (finding
    inadequate allegation that defendant would likely resume conduct where “complaint contain[ed]
    no allegations that [it] had engaged in [that behavior] in the five-year gap between the 2012
    cessation . . . and the 2017 lawsuit”); cf. FTC v. AdvoCare Int’l, L.P., No. 19-715, 
    2020 WL 6741968
    , at *5–6 (E.D. Tex. Nov. 16, 2020) (finding it “implausible” that defendant’s twenty-
    year scheme of “past misconduct,” which ended one year earlier, would recur and thus justify
    Section 13(b) injunction because the “channel[s] of misconduct [were] either permanently
    defunct . . . or reformed, lawful, and monitored for compliance”).
    The agency counters with an argument that is surprising in its breadth. Because the
    statute says that it may “bring suit” for an injunction “[w]henever [it] has reason to believe . . .
    that any person . . . is violating, or is about to violate” the antitrust laws, see 
    15 U.S.C. § 53
    (b),
    the FTC contends that the law “confers discretion” on it to decide if such “reason to believe”
    exists. See FTC Opp. at 41. The upshot, per the agency, is that its “‘reason to believe’
    determination [cannot] be reviewed” on a motion to dismiss. Id. at 39.
    44
    The Court finds this position wanting. The agency’s argument focuses on the statutory
    trigger for when it may “bring suit . . . to enjoin” antitrust violations. The question, however, is
    whether Section 13(b) empowers the agency, as opposed to a court, to decide whether the
    conditions for an injunction are actually met such that a decree should indeed issue. Whatever
    the law tells the agency about what it must believe before it may file suit, for the agency to
    actually succeed, it must convince the court to agree with it that a violation is either ongoing or
    about to occur and that an injunction is warranted. See Evans Products, 
    775 F.2d at 1087
     (“[A]n
    injunction will issue [under Section 13(b)] only if the wrongs are ongoing or likely to recur.”). It
    follows that the Rule 8 requirement that the FTC must “state a claim to [the relief that it seeks]
    that is plausible on its face” requires the agency to make a plausible showing that the defendant
    “is violating” or “is about to violate” the antitrust laws. Nothing in the text of the statute
    suggests otherwise. See Advocare, 
    2020 WL 6741968
    , at *4 (agreeing with this approach);
    Shire ViroPharma, 917 F.3d at 159 n.17 (declining to address argument that FTC has
    “unreviewable discretion to file suit” because it was not raised below, but expressing view that it
    is “unpersuasive”).
    Even accepting the FTC’s argument, the two cases it cites — only one of which really
    embraces its “internal standard argument,” FTC v. Hornbeam Special Situations, LLC, 
    391 F. Supp. 3d 1218
    , 1223 (N.D. Ga. 2019) — still appear to have required the agency to “set[] forth at
    least some facts to support a reasonable inference that the [unlawful] behavior will reoccur in the
    future in the absence of . . . injunctive relief.” Id.; see also FTC v. Vyera Pharms., LLC, 
    479 F. Supp. 3d 31
    , 44 (S.D.N.Y. 2020) (noting several facts alleged that supported a “‘reason to
    believe’ that the defendants [were then] engaging in violations”). Here, for the reasons given
    45
    above, the Court would find that Plaintiff’s Complaint does not clear even that somewhat lower
    bar.
    In sum, then, while it is possible that Facebook’s alleged scheme of revoking API access
    from competitor apps could form the basis of a plausible refusal-to-deal claim under Aspen
    Skiing, the Court need not address that question. Even assuming the answer is yes, injunctive
    relief is not available now for such a claim as a matter of law.
    2. Conditional Dealing
    Plaintiff gets no further by maintaining that Facebook’s policies also violated antitrust
    rules against what they call “conditional dealing.” FTC Opp. at 31. As an initial matter, the FTC
    is wrong to argue that a monopolist violates that so-called doctrine whenever it “induce[s] . . .
    trading partners or other firms not to compete with it . . . by conditioning access to some resource
    of the monopolist.” 
    Id.
     The main case they cite for that proposition, Lorain Journal Co. v.
    United States, 
    342 U.S. 143
    , 149 (1951), says nothing of the sort. That is unsurprising, as such a
    broadly formulated rule would cover refusals to deal with competitors, thus contradicting the
    cases discussed above — such refusals can always be reframed as offers to deal only on the
    condition that the third party refrains from competing. See, e.g., Herbert Hovenkamp, FRAND
    and Antitrust, 
    105 Cornell L. Rev. 1683
    , 1697 (2020) (defining “simple refusal[s] to deal”
    covered by Trinko rule to include “refusal[s] . . . conditioned on a firm’s status that cannot
    readily be changed,” such as where a firm “agree[s] to sell to [non]competitors but not
    []competitors”).
    To the extent any scholarly commentary uses the term “conditional dealing,” rather, the
    phrase generally refers to actions such as “tying” or “exclusive dealing.” Id. at 1697, 1708. The
    key fact distinguishing such conduct from a standard refusal to deal is that it is not “unilateral,”
    46
    but instead “involves some assay by the monopolist into the marketplace” that interferes with the
    relationship between rivals and third parties. Novell, 731 F.3d at 1072. Tying, for instance,
    occurs when a firm “require[s] third parties to purchase a bundle of goods rather than just the
    ones they really want,” id., thereby leveraging the monopolist’s power in the “tying” product
    market to harm its competitors (who lose access to customers) in the “tied” product market. See
    Microsoft, 
    253 F.3d at 84
    . “Exclusive dealing” is similar: it refers to a monopolist’s
    conditioning the sale of a product on the buyer’s agreement not to deal with its competitors. 
    Id.
    at 70–71. Again, these “conditional dealing” schemes are thus categorically different from
    unilateral conduct that involves only the monopolist’s competitors, such as its refusal to deal
    with them. The distinction is critical, as antitrust law is far more tolerant of unilateral behavior.
    See Novell, 731 F.3d at 1072–73 (citing cases) (“Put simply if perhaps a little too simply, today a
    monopolist is much more likely to be held liable for failing to leave its rivals alone than for
    failing to come to their aid.”); Hovenkamp, 105 Cornell L. Rev. at 1697.
    That brings us back to Lorain Journal, which, as it happens, involved a “a very special
    form of exclusive dealing, namely, a refusal to sell to end-user customers who purchase[d] from
    the monopolist’s competitor[].” Kenneth L. Glazer & Abbott B. Lipsky, Jr., Unilateral Refusals
    to Deal Under Section 2 of the Sherman Act, 63 Antitrust L.J. 749, 800 n.75 (1995). There, the
    Journal, a local newspaper, had a “commanding” position in the advertising market of the city of
    Lorain, Ohio. See 
    342 U.S. at 146
    . After a new radio station entered that market, the paper
    began to refuse to sell advertising space “in the Journal [to] any Lorain County advertiser who
    advertised or who [the paper] believed to be about to advertise” with the radio station. 
    Id. at 148
    .
    The paper’s bet was that many advertisers could not afford to lose out on the chance to advertise
    with it, and it was right; the scheme caused most firms to avoid advertising on the radio station,
    47
    restoring the Journal to its local monopoly. 
    Id.
     at 148–49. On those facts, the Court found a
    violation of Section 2 of the Sherman Act. 
    Id.
     at 152–53. The key point for our purposes is that
    the Journal did not simply refuse to deal with the competitor radio station — e.g., it did not
    merely refuse to print advertisements for the station itself in its pages. The Journal instead
    refused to deal with any and all customers unless those customers agreed not to deal with the
    competitor station, thereby interfering with its rival’s ability to compete on the merits.
    For “Facebook’s conditioning of access to its Platform [to be] unlawful under Lorain
    Journal” (or exclusive-dealing doctrine generally), as Plaintiff argues that it is, see FTC Opp. at
    34, the agency would thus have to allege that Facebook conditioned access to its Platform APIs
    on app developers’ agreeing not to deal with other social-networking services. And, indeed, the
    FTC’s Opposition suggests that Facebook did just that. See FTC Opp. at 32 (“Facebook . . .
    grant[ed] third parties full access to its Platform only on the condition that they not threaten its
    monopoly by [inter alia] connecting with or promoting other PSN providers.”); id. at 31
    (“Facebook conditioned access to its Platform on trading partners not competing with it or
    assisting competitors.”) (emphasis added). If Facebook’s policies had in fact interfered in that
    way with the ability of competing social-networking services to deal with app developers, that
    could plausibly have violated Section 2; such conduct might well have had a “significant effect
    in preserving [Facebook’s] monopoly” by keeping user engagement with competing social-
    networking services “below the critical level necessary for any rival to pose a real threat to [its]
    market share.” United States v. Dentsply Int’l, Inc., 
    399 F.3d 181
    , 191 (3d Cir. 2005) (finding
    Section 2 liability based on exclusive dealing); see also Microsoft, 
    253 F.3d at
    69–70 (same).
    Plaintiff, however, has not sufficiently pleaded the sort of conduct just described. It is
    true that Facebook’s 2011 policy prohibited “Apps on Facebook” from “integrat[ing], link[ing]
    48
    to, promot[ing], distribut[ing], or redirect[ing] to any app on any other competing social
    platform.” Redacted Compl., ¶ 139. But, as discussed above, that policy applied only to apps
    designed for use within the Facebook website, not freestanding, separate apps like our chess app
    or Washington Post app. The policy, moreover, does not appear to have prevented an app
    developer from building a version of its app that could be accessed and used within the website
    of another PSN service. For instance, the developer who built a personality-test app for
    Facebook could build the same app for Google+ without running afoul of the policy, cf. id.,
    ¶ 140; its terms simply prohibited the Facebook version of the app from linking or redirecting to
    the Google+ version. The 2011 policy was thus a far cry from a policy that told app developers
    that they could only access Facebook’s platform if they promised to only build their app for
    Facebook. By rough analogy, it is as if the Lorain Journal, rather than refusing to carry
    advertisements from any business that also advertised with the competing radio station, instead
    merely required that advertisements appearing in its paper had to avoid mentioning the radio
    station. Such a focused prohibition on the use of a monopolist’s own facilities obviously could
    not have “significantly limited” the “opportunities for [competitors] to enter into or remain in
    [the] market” for personal-social-networking services, as is required for Section 2 liability.
    Microsoft, 
    253 F.3d at 69
    .
    The 2012 and 2013 policies mentioned in the Complaint similarly did not much limit the
    opportunities for Facebook competitors to deal with third-party app developers. The 2012 policy
    allegedly prohibited freestanding apps (i.e., not “Apps on Facebook”) from “us[ing] Facebook
    Platform [APIs] to export [Facebook] user data into a competing social network.” Redacted
    Compl., ¶ 142. The 2013 policy went further, instructing that freestanding apps could not use
    Facebook’s APIs “to promote, or to export [Facebook] user data to, a product or service that
    49
    replicates a core Facebook product or service.” Id., ¶ 143. By their terms, neither of these
    policies imposed anything approaching a blanket prohibition on freestanding apps’ linking to or
    creating interoperability with Facebook competitors. It is not as if, say, Facebook instructed the
    Washington Post that its app could only allow a user to sign in with Facebook credentials (as
    opposed to, say, Google credentials), or only add a Facebook “Like” button and not a “share”
    button from Path or Circle. Nor did Facebook require the app to refrain from allowing users to
    search for their contacts from other social-networking services, as they did for their Facebook
    friends using the Find Friends API. Perhaps the FTC means to hang its hat on a very capacious
    reading of the policy’s prohibition on using Facebook Platform to “promote” competitors, but
    reading that term to prohibit the sort of dealings just described is implausible at best. That is
    especially true given that the Complaint alleges no specific instances of Facebook’s enforcing its
    policies to prevent dealing between rivals and other freestanding apps, even as it is replete with
    allegations regarding Defendant’s enforcement of its “no dealing with competitors” policies. See
    id., ¶¶ 153–58. Plaintiff’s “conditional dealing” theory of a Section 2 violation, accordingly, is
    not viable here given the conduct that it has alleged.
    In summary, the Court concludes — and advises the parties going forward — that in its
    view, Facebook’s “imposition and enforcement of anticompetitive conditions on access to [its]
    APIs,” id., ¶ 71, as that conduct has been pleaded, either does not amount to exclusionary
    conduct violating Section 2 of the Sherman Act or, to the extent that it might, cannot be the basis
    for an injunction under Section 13(b) of the FTC Act.
    C. Challenging Acquisitions under Section 13(b)
    Before closing, the Court addresses one further issue raised by Facebook in its Motion to
    Dismiss: whether, even assuming market power can be established, Section 13(b) allows the
    50
    FTC to attack Facebook’s acquisitions of Instagram and WhatsApp. See MTD FTC at 39.
    Facebook argues that because those acquisitions happened all the way back in 2012 and 2014,
    respectively, Plaintiff’s challenges do not contend that the company “is violating” or “is about to
    violate” Section 2. See 
    15 U.S.C. § 53
    (b). In other words, Defendant maintains that the FTC’s
    assault on its mergers is aimed at the sort of “long-past conduct” that cannot form the basis of an
    injunction under Section 13(b). Shire ViroPharma, 917 F.3d at 156. (Following the lead of the
    parties and the cases, the Court uses the terms “acquisition” and “merger” interchangeably for
    purposes of this analysis.)
    While Facebook’s argument has some intuitive appeal, it runs into contrary precedent.
    The Supreme Court has clearly stated that the term “acquisition” as used in Section 7 of the
    Clayton Act — which prohibits purchases “the effect of [which] may be substantially to lessen
    competition, or to tend to create a monopoly,” 
    15 U.S.C. § 18
     — does not refer to “a discrete
    transaction but [rather] a status which continues until the transaction is undone.” United States
    v. ITT Cont’l Baking Co., 
    420 U.S. 223
    , 241–42 (1975). In other words, “acquisition . . .
    mean[s] both the purchase of rights in another company and the retention of those rights,” such
    that Section 7’s “ban against [certain] acquisitions . . . include[s] a ban against holding certain
    assets,” not just “obtaining” them in the first place. 
    Id.
     (emphasis added); see also Concord Boat
    Corp. v. Brunswick Corp., 
    207 F.3d 1039
    , 1050 (8th Cir. 2000) (“Clayton Act claims are not
    limited to challenging the initial acquisition of stocks or assets . . . since holding as well as
    obtaining assets is potentially violative of section 7.”) (citation omitted). As ITT Continental
    Baking explained, that understanding is the necessary upshot of the Court’s earlier decision
    in United States v. E.I. du Pont, 
    353 U.S. 586
     (1957), which held that the United States could
    seek divestiture in 1949 of stock that du Pont had first acquired, and was still holding, in 1919.
    51
    The rule under Section 7 is thus that so long as an acquiring company continues to hold acquired
    assets, the Government may “at any time” argue that such company is violating Section 7. Du
    Pont, 
    353 U.S. at 597
    . In such a case, it would follow that the company “is violating . . . [a]
    provision of law enforced by the [Commission]” and thus comes within the ambit of Section
    13(b). See 
    15 U.S.C. § 53
    (b).
    Because the FTC’s challenges to Facebook’s acquisitions here arise under Section 2 of
    the Sherman Act, not Section 7 of the Clayton Act, the question becomes whether that same
    principle applies to claims brought under Section 2. The Court sees no reason why not, nor does
    Facebook offer one. Just as “the Government may proceed at any time that an acquisition may
    be said with reasonable probability to contain a threat that it may . . . tend to create a monopoly,”
    in violation of Section 7’s proscription against transactions having that effect, du Pont, 
    353 U.S. at 597
    , so too it should be able to proceed against an acquisition whenever “a threat of [Section
    2’s] prohibited effects is evident,” 
    id.
     at 598 — namely, that the acquisition is “tend[ing] to
    destroy competition itself” via “means other than competition on the merits.” Microsoft, 
    253 F.3d at 58, 62
     (citation omitted). It is well established that mergers may constitute one such
    “means.” See Grinnell, 
    384 U.S. at 576
     (finding Section 2 violation based in part on a number of
    acquisitions of competitors); BRFHH Shreveport, LLC v. Willis Knighton Med. Ctr., 
    176 F. Supp. 3d 606
    , 622 (W.D. La. 2016) (“[A]cquisitions of viable competitors alone may establish
    the anticompetitive conduct element of a section 2 claim.”); Behrend v. Comcast Corp., No. 03-
    6604, 
    2012 WL 1231794
    , at *20 (E.D. Pa. Apr. 12, 2012) (same); see also Areeda &
    Hovenkamp vol. III, ¶ 701a, at 201 (noting “overlap between Sherman Act and Clayton Act
    treatment of mergers,” including in “case of mergers as unlawful monopolistic acts by firms with
    significant market power”).
    52
    The Court will not speculate further as to how, if at all, the Section 2 analysis of a claim
    involving a long-ago merger might differ from that regarding a more recent (or even
    forthcoming) purchase, including on the issue of remedy. Cf. Areeda & Hovenkamp vol. II,
    ¶ 320g, at 375 (suggesting that “the considerations underlying the laches doctrine might well be
    applied against the government” in long-delayed challenges “possibly by adjustment in certain
    burdens of proof or the remedy”); United States v. Pullman Co., 
    50 F. Supp. 123
    , 127 (E.D. Pa.
    1943) (“While the doctrine of laches does not apply against the United States, we should
    approach the question of equitable relief with great hesitancy in a case where the last operative
    act was nearly half a century old.”). Facebook has made a number of arguments on this score
    that need not be addressed now. At this point, the Court simply holds that, contrary to the
    company’s main contention, an injunction under Section 13(b) is a theoretically available
    remedy in a Section 2 challenge to long-ago mergers so long as the defendant still holds the
    purchased assets or stock, as is the case here.
    IV.    Conclusion
    For the foregoing reasons, the Court will grant Facebook’s Motion to Dismiss, but it will
    dismiss without prejudice only the Complaint, not the case. The Court will also grant leave to
    amend and order Plaintiff to file any amended Complaint within thirty days. A contemporaneous
    Order so stating shall issue this day.
    /s/ James E. Boasberg
    JAMES E. BOASBERG
    United States District Judge
    Date: June 28, 2021
    53
    

Document Info

Docket Number: Civil Action No. 2020-3590

Judges: Judge James E. Boasberg

Filed Date: 6/28/2021

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 6/28/2021

Authorities (38)

Verizon Communications Inc. v. Law Offices of Curtis v. ... , 124 S. Ct. 872 ( 2004 )

Eatoni Ergonomics, Inc. v. Research in Motion Corp. , 826 F. Supp. 2d 705 ( 2011 )

olympia-equipment-leasing-company-alfco-telecommunications-company-and , 797 F.2d 370 ( 1986 )

Papasan v. Allain , 106 S. Ct. 2932 ( 1986 )

BAYER SCHERING PHARMA AG v. Sandoz, Inc. , 813 F. Supp. 2d 569 ( 2011 )

Cupp v. Alberto-Culver USA, Inc. , 310 F. Supp. 2d 963 ( 2004 )

Total Benefits Planning Agency, Inc. v. Anthem Blue Cross & ... , 552 F.3d 430 ( 2008 )

Frank A. Schuler, Jr. v. United States of America, ... , 617 F.2d 605 ( 1979 )

Sparrow, Victor H. v. United Airlines Inc , 216 F.3d 1111 ( 2000 )

Newcal Industries, Inc. v. IKON Office Solution , 513 F.3d 1038 ( 2008 )

Equal Employment Opportunity Commission v. St. Francis ... , 117 F.3d 621 ( 1997 )

city-of-groton-city-of-norwich-borough-of-jewett-city-second-taxing , 662 F.2d 921 ( 1981 )

Charles Kowal v. MCI Communications Corporation , 16 F.3d 1271 ( 1994 )

United States v. ITT Continental Baking Co. , 95 S. Ct. 926 ( 1975 )

Trudeau v. Federal Trade Commission , 456 F.3d 178 ( 2006 )

federal-trade-commission-v-evans-products-company-a-delaware-corporation , 775 F.2d 1084 ( 1985 )

Albert Neumann v. The Reinforced Earth Company , 786 F.2d 424 ( 1986 )

Aspen Skiing Co. v. Aspen Highlands Skiing Corp. , 105 S. Ct. 2847 ( 1985 )

Bell Atlantic Corp. v. Twombly , 127 S. Ct. 1955 ( 2007 )

Ashcroft v. Iqbal , 129 S. Ct. 1937 ( 2009 )

View All Authorities »