Thaler v. Perlmutter ( 2023 )


Menu:
  •                              UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT
    FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA
    STEPHEN THALER,
    Plaintiff,
    Civil Action No. 22-1564 (BAH)
    v.
    Judge Beryl A. Howell
    SHIRA PERLMUTTER, Register of
    Copyrights and Director of the United States
    Copyright Office, et al.
    Defendants.
    MEMORANDUM OPINION
    Plaintiff Stephen Thaler owns a computer system he calls the “Creativity Machine,”
    which he claims generated a piece of visual art of its own accord. He sought to register the work
    for a copyright, listing the computer system as the author and explaining that the copyright
    should transfer to him as the owner of the machine. The Copyright Office denied the application
    on the grounds that the work lacked human authorship, a prerequisite for a valid copyright to
    issue, in the view of the Register of Copyrights. Plaintiff challenged that denial, culminating in
    this lawsuit against the United States Copyright Office and Shira Perlmutter, in her official
    capacity as the Register of Copyrights and the Director of the United States Copyright Office
    (“defendants”). Both parties have now moved for summary judgment, which motions present
    the sole issue of whether a work generated entirely by an artificial system absent human
    involvement should be eligible for copyright. See Pl.’s Mot. Summ. J. (Pl.’s Mot.”), ECF No.
    16; Defs.’ Cross-Mot. Summ. J. (“Defs.’ Mot.”), ECF No. 17. For the reasons explained below,
    defendants are correct that human authorship is an essential part of a valid copyright claim, and
    1
    therefore plaintiff’s pending motion for summary judgment is denied and defendants’ pending
    cross-motion for summary judgment is granted.
    I.     BACKGROUND
    Plaintiff develops and owns computer programs he describes as having “artificial
    intelligence” (“AI”) capable of generating original pieces of visual art, akin to the output of a
    human artist. See Pl.’s Mem. Supp. Mot. Summ. J. (“Pl.’s Mem.”) at 13, ECF No. 16. One such
    AI system—the so-called “Creativity Machine”—produced the work at issue here, titled “A
    Recent Entrance to Paradise:”
    Admin. Record (“AR”), Ex. H, Copyright Review Board Refusal Letter Dated February 14, 2022
    “(Final Refusal Letter”) at 1, ECF No. 13-8.
    2
    After its creation, plaintiff attempted to register this work with the Copyright Office. In
    his application, he identified the author as the Creativity Machine, and explained the work had
    been “autonomously created by a computer algorithm running on a machine,” but that plaintiff
    sought to claim the copyright of the “computer-generated work” himself “as a work-for-hire to
    the owner of the Creativity Machine.” Id., Ex. B, Copyright Application (“Application”) at 1,
    ECF No. 13-2; see also id. at 2 (listing “Author” as “Creativity Machine,” the work as “[c]reated
    autonomously by machine,” and the “Copyright Claimant” as “Steven [sic] Thaler” with the
    transfer statement, “Ownership of the machine”). The Copyright Office denied the application
    on the basis that the work “lack[ed] the human authorship necessary to support a copyright
    claim,” noting that copyright law only extends to works created by human beings. Id., Ex. D,
    Copyright Office Refusal Letter Dated August 12, 2019 (“First Refusal Letter”) at 1, ECF No.
    13-4.
    Plaintiff requested reconsideration of his application, confirming that the work “was
    autonomously generated by an AI” and “lack[ed] traditional human authorship,” but contesting
    the Copyright Office’s human authorship requirement and urging that AI should be
    “acknowledge[d] . . . as an author where it otherwise meets authorship criteria, with any
    copyright ownership vesting in the AI’s owner.” Id., Ex. E, First Request for Reconsideration at
    2, ECF No. 13-5. Again, the Copyright Office refused to register the work, reiterating its
    original rationale that “[b]ecause copyright law is limited to ‘original intellectual conceptions of
    the author,’ the Office will refuse to register a claim if it determines that a human being did not
    create the work.” Id., Ex. F, Copyright Office Refusal Letter Dated March 30, 2020 (“Second
    Refusal Letter”) at 1, ECF No. 13-6 (quoting Burrow-Giles Lithographic Co. v. Sarony, 
    111 U.S. 53
    , 58 (1884) and citing 
    17 U.S.C. § 102
    (a); U.S. Copyright Office, Compendium of U.S.
    3
    Copyright Office Practices § 306 (3d ed. 2017)). Plaintiff made a second request for
    reconsideration along the same lines as his first, see id., Ex. G, Second Request for
    Reconsideration at 2, ECF No. 13-7, and the Copyright Office Review Board affirmed the denial
    of registration, agreeing that copyright protection does not extend to the creations of non-human
    entities, Final Refusal Letter at 4, 7.
    Plaintiff timely challenged that decision in this Court, claiming that defendants’ denial of
    copyright registration to the work titled “A Recent Entrance to Paradise,” was “arbitrary,
    capricious, an abuse of discretion and not in accordance with the law, unsupported by substantial
    evidence, and in excess of Defendants’ statutory authority,” in violation of the Administrative
    Procedure Act (“APA”), 
    5 U.S.C. § 706
    (2). See Compl. ¶¶ 62–66, ECF No. 1. The parties agree
    upon the key facts narrated above to focus, in the pending cross-motions for summary judgment,
    on the sole legal issue of whether a work autonomously generated by an AI system is
    copyrightable. See Pl.’s Mem. at 13; Defs.’ Mem. Supp. Cross-Mot. Summ. J. & Opp’n Pl.’s
    Mot. Summ. J. (“Defs.’ Opp’n”) at 7, ECF No. 17. Those motions are now ripe for resolution.
    See Defs.’ Reply Supp. Cross-Mot. Summ. J. (“Defs.’ Reply”), ECF No. 21.
    II.     LEGAL STANDARD
    A.      Administrative Procedure Act
    The APA provides for judicial review of any “final agency action for which there is no
    other adequate remedy in a court,” 
    5 U.S.C. § 704
    , and “instructs a reviewing court to set aside
    agency action found to be ‘arbitrary, capricious, an abuse of discretion, or otherwise not in
    accordance with law,’” Cigar Ass’n of Am. v. FDA, 
    964 F.3d 56
    , 61 (D.C. Cir. 2020) (quoting 
    5 U.S.C. § 706
    (2)(A)). This standard “‘requires agencies to engage in reasoned decisionmaking,’
    and . . . to reasonably explain to reviewing courts the bases for the actions they take and the
    conclusions they reach.” Brotherhood of Locomotive Eng’rs & Trainmen v. Fed. R.R. Admin.,
    4
    
    972 F.3d 83
    , 115 (D.C. Cir. 2020) (quoting Dep’t of Homeland Sec. v. Regents of Univ. of Cal.
    (“Regents”), 
    140 S. Ct. 1891
    , 1905 (2020)). Judicial review of agency action is limited to “the
    grounds that the agency invoked when it took the action,” Regents, 
    140 S. Ct. at 1907
     (quoting
    Michigan v. EPA, 
    576 U.S. 743
    , 758 (2015)), and the agency, too, “must defend its actions based
    on the reasons it gave when it acted,” 
    id. at 1909
    .
    B.      Summary Judgment
    Pursuant to Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 56, “[a] party is entitled to summary
    judgment only if there is no genuine issue of material fact and judgment in the movant’s favor is
    proper as a matter of law.” Soundboard Ass’n v. FTC, 
    888 F.3d 1261
    , 1267 (D.C. Cir. 2018)
    (quoting Ctr. for Auto Safety v. Nat'l Highway Traffic Safety Admin., 
    452 F.3d 798
    , 805 (D.C.
    Cir. 2006)); see also Fed. R. Civ. P. 56(a). In APA cases such as this one, involving cross-
    motions for summary judgment, “the district judge sits as an appellate tribunal. The ‘entire case’
    on review is a question of law.” Am. Bioscience, Inc. v. 
    Thompson, 269
     F.3d 1077, 1083–84
    (D.C. Cir. 2001) (footnote omitted) (collecting cases). Thus, a court need not and ought not
    engage in fact finding, since “[g]enerally speaking, district courts reviewing agency action under
    the APA’s arbitrary and capricious standard do not resolve factual issues, but operate instead as
    appellate courts resolving legal questions.” James Madison Ltd. by Hecht v. Ludwig, 
    82 F.3d 1085
    , 1096 (D.C. Cir. 1996); see also Lacson v. U.S. Dep’t of Homeland Sec., 
    726 F.3d 170
    , 171
    (D.C. Cir. 2013) (noting, in an APA case, that “determining the facts is generally the agency’s
    responsibility, not [the court’s]”). Judicial review, when available, is typically limited to the
    administrative record, since “[i]t is black-letter administrative law that in an [APA] case, a
    reviewing court should have before it neither more nor less information than did the agency
    when it made its decision.” CTS Corp. v. EPA, 
    759 F.3d 52
    , 64 (D.C. Cir. 2014) (internal
    quotation marks and citation omitted).
    5
    III.   DISCUSSION
    Under the Copyright Act of 1976, copyright protection attaches “immediately” upon the
    creation of “original works of authorship fixed in any tangible medium of expression,” provided
    those works meet certain requirements. Fourth Estate v. Public Benefit Corporation v. Wall-
    Street.com, LLC, 
    139 S. Ct. 881
    , 887 (2019); 
    17 U.S.C. § 102
    (a). A copyright claimant can also
    register the work with the Register of Copyrights. Upon concluding that the work is indeed
    copyrightable, the Register will issue a certificate of registration, which, among other
    advantages, allows the claimant to pursue infringement claims in court. 
    17 U.S.C. §§ 410
    (a),
    411(a); Unicolors v. H&M Hennes & Mauritz, L.P., 
    142 S. Ct. 941
    , 944–45 (2022). A valid
    copyright exists upon a qualifying work’s creation and “apart” from registration, however; a
    certificate of registration merely confirms that the copyright has existed all along. See Fourth
    Estate, 
    139 S. Ct. at 887
    . Conversely, if the Register denies an application for registration for
    lack of copyrightable subject matter—and did not err in doing so—then the work at issue was
    never subject to copyright protection at all.
    In considering plaintiff’s copyright registration application as to “A Recent Entrance to
    Paradise,” the Register concluded that “this particular work will not support a claim to
    copyright” because the work lacked human authorship and thus no copyright existed in the first
    instance. First Refusal Letter at 1; see also Final Refusal Letter at 3 (providing the same
    rationale in the final reconsideration decision). By design in plaintiff’s framing of the
    registration application, then, the single legal question presented here is whether a work
    generated autonomously by a computer falls under the protection of copyright law upon its
    creation.
    6
    Plaintiff attempts to complicate the issues presented by devoting a substantial portion of
    his briefing to the viability of various legal theories under which a copyright in the computer’s
    work would transfer to him, as the computer’s owner; for example, by operation of common law
    property principles or the work-for-hire doctrine. See Pl.’s Mem. at 31–37; Pl.’s Reply Supp.
    Mot. Summ. J. & Opp’n Def.’s Cross-Mot. Summ. J. (“Pl.’s Opp’n”) at 11–15, ECF No. 18.
    These arguments concern to whom a valid copyright should have been registered, and in so doing
    put the cart before the horse.1 By denying registration, the Register concluded that no valid
    copyright had ever existed in a work generated absent human involvement, leaving nothing at all
    to register and thus no question as to whom that registration belonged.
    The only question properly presented, then, is whether the Register acted arbitrarily or
    capriciously or otherwise in violation of the APA in reaching that conclusion. The Register did
    not err in denying the copyright registration application presented by plaintiff. United States
    copyright law protects only works of human creation.
    Plaintiff correctly observes that throughout its long history, copyright law has proven
    malleable enough to cover works created with or involving technologies developed long after
    traditional media of writings memorialized on paper. See, e.g., Goldstein v. California, 
    412 U.S. 546
    , 561 (1973) (explaining that the constitutional scope of Congress’s power to “protect the
    ‘Writings’ of ‘Authors’” is “broad,” such that “writings” is not “limited to script or printed
    material,” but rather encompasses “any physical rendering of the fruits of creative intellectual or
    aesthetic labor”); Burrow-Giles Lithographic Co. v. Sarony, 
    111 U.S. 53
    , 58 (1884) (upholding
    1
    In pursuing these arguments, plaintiff elaborates on his development, use, ownership, and prompting of the
    AI generating software in the so-called “Creativity Machine,” implying a level of human involvement in this case
    entirely absent in the administrative record. As detailed, supra, in Part I, plaintiff consistently represented to the
    Register that the AI system generated the work “autonomously” and that he played no role in its creation, see
    Application at 2, and judicial review of the Register’s final decision must be based on those same facts.
    7
    the constitutionality of an amendment to the Copyright Act to cover photographs). In fact, that
    malleability is explicitly baked into the modern incarnation of the Copyright Act, which provides
    that copyright attaches to “original works of authorship fixed in any tangible medium of
    expression, now known or later developed.” 
    17 U.S.C. § 102
    (a) (emphasis added). Copyright is
    designed to adapt with the times. Underlying that adaptability, however, has been a consistent
    understanding that human creativity is the sine qua non at the core of copyrightability, even as
    that human creativity is channeled through new tools or into new media. In Sarony, for example,
    the Supreme Court reasoned that photographs amounted to copyrightable creations of “authors,”
    despite issuing from a mechanical device that merely reproduced an image of what is in front of
    the device, because the photographic result nonetheless “represent[ed]” the “original intellectual
    conceptions of the author.” Sarony, 
    111 U.S. at 59
    . A camera may generate only a “mechanical
    reproduction” of a scene, but does so only after the photographer develops a “mental conception”
    of the photograph, which is given its final form by that photographer’s decisions like “posing the
    [subject] in front of the camera, selecting and arranging the costume, draperies, and other various
    accessories in said photograph, arranging the subject so as to present graceful outlines, arranging
    and disposing the light and shade, suggesting and evoking the desired expression, and from such
    disposition, arrangement, or representation” crafting the overall image. 
    Id.
     at 59–60. Human
    involvement in, and ultimate creative control over, the work at issue was key to the conclusion
    that the new type of work fell within the bounds of copyright.
    Copyright has never stretched so far, however, as to protect works generated by new
    forms of technology operating absent any guiding human hand, as plaintiff urges here. Human
    authorship is a bedrock requirement of copyright.
    8
    That principle follows from the plain text of the Copyright Act. The current incarnation
    of the copyright law, the Copyright Act of 1976, provides copyright protection to “original works
    of authorship fixed in any tangible medium of expression, now known or later developed, from
    which they can be perceived, reproduced, or otherwise communicated, either directly or with the
    aid of a machine or device.” 
    17 U.S.C. § 102
    (a). The “fixing” of the work in the tangible
    medium must be done “by or under the authority of the author.” 
    Id.
     § 101. In order to be
    eligible for copyright, then, a work must have an “author.”
    To be sure, as plaintiff points out, the critical word “author” is not defined in the
    Copyright Act. See Pl.’s Mem. at 24. “Author,” in its relevant sense, means “one that is the
    source of some form of intellectual or creative work,” “[t]he creator of an artistic work; a painter,
    photographer, filmmaker, etc.” Author, MERRIAM-WEBSTER UNABRIDGED DICTIONARY,
    https://unabridged.merriam-webster.com/unabridged/author (last visited Aug. 18, 2023); Author,
    OXFORD ENGLISH DICTIONARY, https://www.oed.com/dictionary/author_n (last visited Aug. 10,
    2023). By its plain text, the 1976 Act thus requires a copyrightable work to have an originator
    with the capacity for intellectual, creative, or artistic labor. Must that originator be a human
    being to claim copyright protection? The answer is yes.2
    The 1976 Act’s “authorship” requirement as presumptively being human rests on
    centuries of settled understanding. The Constitution enables the enactment of copyright and
    patent law by granting Congress the authority to “promote the progress of science and useful
    arts, by securing for limited times to authors and inventors the exclusive right to their respective
    2
    The issue of whether non-human sentient beings may be covered by “person” in the Copyright Act is only
    “fun conjecture for academics,” Justin Hughes, Restating Copyright Law’s Originality Requirement, 44 COLUMBIA
    J. L. & ARTS 383, 408–09 (2021), though useful in illuminating the purposes and limits of copyright protection as AI
    is increasingly employed. Nonetheless, delving into this debate is an unnecessary detour since “[t]he day sentient
    refugees from some intergalactic war arrive on Earth and are granted asylum in Iceland, copyright law will be the
    least of our problems.” Id. at 408.
    9
    writings and discoveries.” U.S. Const. art. 1, cl. 8. As James Madison explained, “[t]he utility
    of this power will scarcely be questioned,” for “[t]he public good fully coincides in both cases
    [of copyright and patent] with the claims of individuals.” THE FEDERALIST NO. 43 (James
    Madison). At the founding, both copyright and patent were conceived of as forms of property
    that the government was established to protect, and it was understood that recognizing exclusive
    rights in that property would further the public good by incentivizing individuals to create and
    invent. The act of human creation—and how to best encourage human individuals to engage in
    that creation, and thereby promote science and the useful arts—was thus central to American
    copyright from its very inception. Non-human actors need no incentivization with the promise
    of exclusive rights under United States law, and copyright was therefore not designed to reach
    them.
    The understanding that “authorship” is synonymous with human creation has persisted
    even as the copyright law has otherwise evolved. The immediate precursor to the modern
    copyright law—the Copyright Act of 1909—explicitly provided that only a “person” could
    “secure copyright for his work” under the Act. Act of Mar. 4, 1909, ch. 320, §§ 9, 10, 
    35 Stat. 1075
    , 1077. Copyright under the 1909 Act was thus unambiguously limited to the works of
    human creators. There is absolutely no indication that Congress intended to effect any change to
    this longstanding requirement with the modern incarnation of the copyright law. To the contrary,
    the relevant congressional report indicates that in enacting the 1976 Act, Congress intended to
    incorporate the “original work of authorship” standard “without change” from the previous 1909
    Act. See H.R. REP. NO. 94-1476, at 51 (1976).
    The human authorship requirement has also been consistently recognized by the Supreme
    Court when called upon to interpret the copyright law. As already noted, in Sarony, the Court’s
    10
    recognition of the copyrightability of a photograph rested on the fact that the human creator, not
    the camera, conceived of and designed the image and then used the camera to capture the image.
    See Sarony, 
    111 U.S. at 60
    . The photograph was “the product of [the photographer’s]
    intellectual invention,” and given “the nature of authorship,” was deemed “an original work of
    art . . . of which [the photographer] is the author.” 
    Id.
     at 60–61. Similarly, in Mazer v. Stein, the
    Court delineated a prerequisite for copyrightability to be that a work “must be original, that is,
    the author’s tangible expression of his ideas.” 
    347 U.S. 201
    , 214 (1954). Goldstein v.
    California, too, defines “author” as “an ‘originator,’ ‘he to whom anything owes its origin,’” 
    412 U.S. at 561
     (quoting Sarony, 
    111 U.S. at 58
    ). In all these cases, authorship centers on acts of
    human creativity.
    Accordingly, courts have uniformly declined to recognize copyright in works created
    absent any human involvement, even when, for example, the claimed author was divine. The
    Ninth Circuit, when confronted with a book “claimed to embody the words of celestial beings
    rather than human beings,” concluded that “some element of human creativity must have
    occurred in order for the Book to be copyrightable,” for “it is not creations of divine beings that
    the copyright laws were intended to protect.” Urantia Found. v. Kristen Maaherra, 
    114 F.3d 955
    , 958–59 (9th Cir. 1997) (finding that because the “members of the Contact Commission
    chose and formulated the specific questions asked” of the celestial beings, and then “select[ed]
    and arrange[d]” the resultant “revelations,” the Urantia Book was “at least partially the product
    of human creativity” and thus protected by copyright); see also Penguin Books U.S.A., Inc. v.
    New Christian Church of Full Endeavor, 96-cv-4126 (RWS), 
    2000 WL 1028634
    , at *2, 10–11
    (S.D.N.Y. July 25, 2000) (finding a valid copyright where a woman had “filled nearly thirty
    stenographic notebooks with words she believed were dictated to her” by a “‘Voice’ which
    11
    would speak to her whenever she was prepared to listen,” and who had worked with two human
    co-collaborators to revise and edit those notes into a book, a process which involved enough
    creativity to support human authorship); Oliver v. St. Germain Found., 
    41 F. Supp. 296
    , 297, 299
    (S.D. Cal. 1941) (finding no copyright infringement where plaintiff claimed to have transcribed
    “letters” dictated to him by a spirit named Phylos the Thibetan, and defendant copied the same
    “spiritual world messages for recordation and use by the living” but was not charged with
    infringing plaintiff’s “style or arrangement” of those messages). Similarly, in Kelley v. Chicago
    Park District, the Seventh Circuit refused to “recognize[] copyright” in a cultivated garden, as
    doing so would “press[] too hard on the[] basic principle[]” that “[a]uthors of copyrightable
    works must be human.” 
    635 F.3d 290
    , 304–06 (7th Cir. 2011). The garden “ow[ed] [its] form to
    the forces of nature,” even if a human had originated the plan for the “initial arrangement of the
    plants,” and as such lay outside the bounds of copyright. 
    Id. at 304
    . Finally, in Naruto v. Slater,
    the Ninth Circuit held that a crested macaque could not sue under the Copyright Act for the
    alleged infringement of photographs this monkey had taken of himself, for “all animals, since
    they are not human” lacked statutory standing under the Act. 
    888 F.3d 418
    , 420 (9th Cir. 2018).
    While resolving the case on standing grounds, rather than the copyrightability of the monkey’s
    work, the Naruto Court nonetheless had to consider whom the Copyright Act was designed to
    protect and, as with those courts confronted with the nature of authorship, concluded that only
    humans had standing, explaining that the terms used to describe who has rights under the Act,
    like “‘children,’ ‘grandchildren,’ ‘legitimate,’ ‘widow,’ and ‘widower[,]’ all imply humanity and
    necessarily exclude animals.” 
    Id. at 426
    . Plaintiff can point to no case in which a court has
    recognized copyright in a work originating with a non-human.
    12
    Undoubtedly, we are approaching new frontiers in copyright as artists put AI in their
    toolbox to be used in the generation of new visual and other artistic works. The increased
    attenuation of human creativity from the actual generation of the final work will prompt
    challenging questions regarding how much human input is necessary to qualify the user of an AI
    system as an “author” of a generated work, the scope of the protection obtained over the resultant
    image, how to assess the originality of AI-generated works where the systems may have been
    trained on unknown pre-existing works, how copyright might best be used to incentivize creative
    works involving AI, and more. See, e.g., Letter from Senators Thom Tillis and Chris Coons to
    Kathi Vidal, Under Secretary of Commerce for Intellectual Property and Director of the U.S.
    Patent and Trademark Office, and Shira Perlmutter, Register of Copyrights and Director of the
    U.S. Copyright Office (Oct. 27, 2022), https://www.copyright.gov/laws/hearings/Letter-to-
    USPTO-USCO-on-National-Commission-on-AI-1.pdf (requesting that the United States Patent
    and Trademark Office and the United States Copyright Office “jointly establish a national
    commission on AI” to assess, among other topics, how intellectual property law may best
    “incentivize future AI related innovations and creations”).
    This case, however, is not nearly so complex. While plaintiff attempts to transform the
    issue presented here, by asserting new facts that he “provided instructions and directed his AI to
    create the Work,” that “the AI is entirely controlled by [him],” and that “the AI only operates at
    [his] direction,” Pl.’s Mem. at 36–37—implying that he played a controlling role in generating
    the work—these statements directly contradict the administrative record. Judicial review of a
    final agency action under the APA is limited to the administrative record, because “[i]t is black-
    letter administrative law that in an [APA] case, a reviewing court should have before it neither
    more nor less information than did the agency when it made its decision.” CTS Corp., 
    759 F.3d 13
    at 64 (internal quotation marks and citation omitted). Here, plaintiff informed the Register that
    the work was “[c]reated autonomously by machine,” and that his claim to the copyright was only
    based on the fact of his “[o]wnership of the machine.” Application at 2. The Register therefore
    made her decision based on the fact the application presented that plaintiff played no role in
    using the AI to generate the work, which plaintiff never attempted to correct. See First Request
    for Reconsideration at 2 (“It is correct that the present submission lacks traditional human
    authorship—it was autonomously generated by an AI.”); Second Request for Reconsideration at
    2 (same). Plaintiff’s effort to update and modify the facts for judicial review on an APA claim is
    too late. On the record designed by plaintiff from the outset of his application for copyright
    registration, this case presents only the question of whether a work generated autonomously by a
    computer system is eligible for copyright. In the absence of any human involvement in the
    creation of the work, the clear and straightforward answer is the one given by the Register: No.
    Given that the work at issue did not give rise to a valid copyright upon its creation,
    plaintiff’s myriad theories for how ownership of such a copyright could have passed to him need
    not be further addressed. Common law doctrines of property transfer cannot be implicated
    where no property right exists to transfer in the first instance. The work-for-hire provisions of
    the Copyright Act, too, presuppose that an interest exists to be claimed. See 17 U.S.C § 201(b)
    (“In the case of a work made for hire, the employer . . . owns all of the rights comprised in the
    copyright.”).3 Here, the image autonomously generated by plaintiff’s computer system was
    3
    In any event, plaintiff’s attempts to cast the work as a work-for-hire must fail as both definitions of a “work
    made for hire” available under the Copyright Act require that the individual who prepares the work is a human
    being. The first definition provides that “a ‘work made for hire’ is . . . a work prepared by an employee within the
    scope of his or her employment,” while the second qualifies certain eligible works “if the parties expressly agree in
    a written instrument signed by them that the work shall be considered a work made for hire.” 
    17 U.S.C. § 101
    (emphasis added). The use of personal pronouns in the first definition clearly contemplates only human beings as
    eligible “employees,” while the second necessitates a meeting of the minds and exchange of signatures in a valid
    contract not possible with a non-human entity.
    14
    never eligible for copyright, so none of the doctrines invoked by plaintiff conjure up a copyright
    over which ownership may be claimed.
    IV.    CONCLUSION
    For the foregoing reasons, defendants are correct that the Copyright Office acted properly
    in denying copyright registration for a work created absent any human involvement. Plaintiff’s
    motion for summary judgment is therefore denied and defendants’ cross-motion for summary
    judgment is granted.
    An Order consistent with this Memorandum Opinion will be entered contemporaneously.
    Date: August 18, 2023
    ___________________________
    BERYL A. HOWELL
    United States District Judge
    15