State of Iowa v. Jerry Lynn Burns ( 2023 )


Menu:
  •                    IN THE SUPREME COURT OF IOWA
    No. 20–1150
    Submitted September 30, 2022—Filed March 31, 2023
    STATE OF IOWA,
    Appellee,
    vs.
    JERRY LYNN BURNS,
    Appellant.
    Appeal from the Iowa District Court for Linn County, Fae Hoover Grinde,
    Judge.
    Jerry Lynn Burns appeals his conviction of first-degree murder.
    AFFIRMED.
    May, J., delivered the opinion of the court, in which Christensen, C.J., and
    Waterman, Mansfield, and McDonald, JJ., joined. McDonald, J., filed a
    concurring opinion. Oxley, J., filed a dissenting opinion. McDermott, J., filed a
    dissenting opinion, in which Oxley, J., joined except as to part I.B.
    Nicholas Curran (argued) and Kathleen T. Zellner of Kathleen T. Zellner &
    Associates, PC, Downers Grove, Illinois, and Elizabeth A. Araguás of Nidey
    Erdahl Meier & Araguás, PLC, Cedar Rapids, for appellant.
    Brenna Bird, Attorney General, and Tyler J. Buller (argued) (until
    withdrawal) and Bridget Chambers, Assistant Attorneys General, for appellee.
    2
    Nathan Freed Wessler (argued), Vera Eidelman, and Patrick Toomey of
    American Civil Liberties Union Foundation, New York, New York, for amicus
    curiae American Civil Liberties Union.
    Rita Bettis Austen of ACLU of Iowa Foundation Inc., Des Moines, for
    amicus curiae ACLU of Iowa Foundation, Inc.
    Jennifer Lynch of Electronic Frontier Foundation, San Francisco,
    California, for amicus curiae Electronic Frontier Foundation.
    3
    MAY, Justice.
    Someone murdered Michelle Martinko on the night of December 19, 1979.
    Cedar Rapids police found Martinko’s body in her car. Police collected what
    evidence they could, including her bloodstained dress. But police could not find
    Martinko’s killer.
    Decades passed. Technology developed. Police used advances in DNA
    technology and forensic genealogy to pursue the killer.
    By 2018, police determined that DNA found on Martinko’s dress would
    very likely match the DNA of one of three brothers: Donald, Kenneth, or Jerry
    Burns. All three brothers had grown up in Manchester, about an hour from
    Cedar Rapids. All three were living in Iowa in 2018.
    Police watched the brothers. The plan was to collect discarded items that
    might carry samples of the men’s DNA. Police collected a drinking straw that
    Kenneth discarded at a golf course clubhouse. And police collected a toothbrush
    from Donald’s garbage. Lab analysis of these items showed that neither man’s
    DNA could match the DNA found on Martinko’s dress.
    The third brother was Jerry Lynn Burns (Burns), the defendant in this
    case. Investigators saw Burns eating at a Pizza Ranch in Manchester. Burns was
    drinking soda through a clear plastic straw. When Burns finished eating, he got
    up and walked out of the restaurant. Burns left the drinking straw behind. Police
    retrieved the straw. A lab analyzed DNA on the straw. The lab report said that
    the “DNA donor could NOT be eliminated as the major contributor to the DNA
    profile previously developed” from Martinko’s dress.
    4
    So then police obtained a warrant to swab Burns’s mouth directly.
    Laboratory analysis then confirmed that Burns’s DNA profile matched DNA
    found on Martinko’s dress. According to the lab, the probability of finding the
    same DNA profile in a population of unrelated individuals would be “less than 1
    out of 100 billion.”
    Armed with this and other evidence, the State charged Burns with murder
    in the first degree. A jury found Burns guilty.
    On appeal, Burns argues that police violated his constitutional rights by
    failing to secure a warrant before analyzing the DNA on the straw that he left at
    the Pizza Ranch. Burns also argues that the court erred by failing to give a
    requested jury instruction. Finally, Burns claims that there was insufficient
    evidence to support the jury’s guilty verdict. We affirm.
    I. Background Facts and Proceedings.
    In December 1979, Martinko was an eighteen-year-old senior at Kennedy
    High School in Cedar Rapids, Iowa. On December 19, Martinko and classmates
    attended a choir banquet at the Sheraton Hotel. Martinko was wearing a black
    dress.
    Among her classmates, Martinko was well-known for driving a large 1972
    Buick. After the banquet, Martinko drove the Buick to Cedar Rapids’s recently-
    opened Westdale Mall. While there, Martinko spoke to several friends. Sometime
    between 9 p.m. and 10 p.m., she left the mall alone and headed out to the
    parking lot. Around 10:30–11:00 p.m., the assistant manager at a Pier 1 Imports
    saw Martinko’s Buick in the parking lot. The assistant manager described the
    5
    car as “just kind of out there by itself.” It seemed “out of place” for that time of
    night.
    Shortly after 4 a.m., Cedar Rapids police were dispatched to look for the
    Buick. Police found it in the mall parking lot. Inside the Buick, police found
    Martinko’s body. She was fully clothed and covered with blood. There were visible
    stab wounds to her chest. Her autopsy would reveal that she had suffered a total
    of twenty-nine sharp-edge wounds, including defensive wounds on her hands.
    The doctor concluded that “there was a struggle” that led to her death. “Her heart
    was still pumping” when the murderer inflicted the fatal stab “deep into [her]
    aorta,” a “major . . . blood-carrying organ of the body.” The doctor also thought
    that the killer could have cut themself during the assault.
    Police collected Martinko’s bloodstained dress. Otherwise, though, the
    crime scene was basically limited to the Buick and surrounding area. Police did
    not find any of the murderer’s fingerprints. Instead, inside the car, police found
    “chevron-type” glove prints of the kind made by commonly available rubber
    gloves. Police found these prints on “the operating parts of the car -- the shift
    lever, the steering wheel, the door handles, . . . the keys, [and the] light switch.”
    From this, police inferred that the rubber-glove-clad murderer had driven the
    Buick after the assault. Police collected blood from the Buick’s steering wheel
    and gearshift lever.
    Time passed, but no viable suspect emerged. Beginning in the late 1990s,
    though, law enforcement began conducting DNA analysis on the evidence that
    they had collected. Initial testing could only detect (1) Martinko’s DNA on the
    6
    dress and (2) the DNA of more than one indeterminate persons on the gearshift
    lever.
    Over time, DNA technology improved. In 2002 and 2003, testing of the
    dress allowed the development of a full DNA profile for Martinko. And testing of
    the gearshift lever sample yielded a mixed profile that included “[a]t least one
    male and one female” contributor.
    In 2005, the Iowa Division of Criminal Investigations (DCI) lab tested
    additional bloodstain locations on Martinko’s dress. One of those locations—
    referred to as “stain #5” or “#F5”—yielded a partial male profile. The lab noted
    that “[f]ewer than one in one hundred billion unrelated individuals would” match
    the profile discovered at stain #F5. The lab also determined that the male
    contributor to stain #F5 “could also be the donor of the minor male contribution”
    found in the gearshift lever sample.
    So police focused their efforts on finding the male contributor to stain #F5.
    Police submitted the #F5 profile to the FBI’s CODIS1 database, which consists of
    millions of known DNA profiles. No matches were found.
    Police also compiled a list of potential suspects from police reports and
    other sources. More than 100 individuals were cleared from suspicion by
    collecting their DNA through buccal swabs and then comparing their DNA
    profiles against the #F5 profile. Other possible suspects were cleared on other
    grounds, such as being in custody at the time of the murder.
    1CODIS   refers to Combined DNA Index System.
    7
    In 2018, police used the services of a private lab called Parabon to perform
    kinship analysis and genetic genealogy. This work included running the #F5
    profile through a public database called GEDmatch. Based on this analysis,
    Parabon directed police to investigate the descendants of four sets of great-great-
    grandparents. Police did so.
    As part of this work, police contacted Janice Burns of Linn County, Iowa.
    Janice agreed to provide her DNA through a buccal swab. Parabon was then able
    to report that the contributor of the #F5 profile was probably a first cousin of
    Janice Burns. Janice has three first cousins: defendant Burns and his two
    brothers Donald and Kenneth.
    Police then began surveilling the three brothers. The plan was to collect
    discarded items that could contain the men’s DNA. Police collected a straw from
    Kenneth and a toothbrush from Donald’s trash. Lab analysis of these items
    eliminated Donald and Kenneth as possible contributors to stain #F5.
    Police followed Jerry Burns and his son to a Pizza Ranch in Manchester.
    Investigators sat down in the booth next to Burns. They saw Burns drink several
    sodas using a clear drinking straw. When Burns and his son finished eating,
    they got up and walked out of the restaurant.2 Police then grabbed Burns’s soda
    cup, packaged up the straw, and sent it to the DCI lab for analysis. The lab
    extracted DNA from the straw, analyzed it, and created a report. The report said:
    The weak DNA profile developed from the ends of the straw indicated
    a male source. The DNA donor could NOT be eliminated as the major
    2At   Pizza Ranch, you pay before you eat.
    8
    contributor to the DNA profile previously developed from stain #F5
    . . . from the black dress . . . .
    Further interpretation may be attempted if a KNOWN DNA
    sample from a potential source is submitted.
    In light of this report, police sought and obtained a search warrant to swab
    Burns’s mouth directly. The DCI lab then confirmed that Burns’s DNA profile
    matched the stain #F5 profile. The report went on to say: “The probability of
    finding this profile in a population of unrelated individuals, chosen at random,
    would be less than 1 out of 100 billion.” And a private lab—Bode Technology—
    found that Burns’s DNA was consistent with DNA extracted from the gearshift
    lever in Martinko’s Buick. One in 1,700 males would match the DNA profile from
    the gearshift lever sample. This match was close enough to eliminate about
    99.94% of all males in the United States.
    Police interviewed Burns at his office in Manchester. Burns denied any
    firsthand knowledge of the murder. When police confronted Burns, he repeatedly
    told police to “test the DNA.”
    On January 24, 2019, police charged Burns with murder in the first
    degree. Prior to trial, Burns filed a motion to suppress. Burns argued that the
    warrantless search of his DNA from the Pizza Ranch straw violated the Fourth
    Amendment to the United States Constitution as well as article I, section 8 of the
    Iowa Constitution. The court disagreed. The court believed that a person does
    not maintain a reasonable expectation of privacy in property that has been
    abandoned. And “[w]hen he exited the restaurant without the straw,” the court
    9
    believed, Burns “relinquished any expectation of privacy in the drinking straw,
    the saliva left on it and the DNA contained within the saliva.”
    The case went to trial. Among other evidence, the jury heard the testimony
    of Michael Allison, a federal detainee. When Burns was in jail awaiting trial, he
    bunked near Allison. At Burns’s trial, Allison testified about incriminating
    statements that Burns had made. According to Allison, Burns said that “he
    wished he had listened to his dad and cleaned up after himself” but that “no one
    was thinking about DNA as far as it being a possibility” in 1979. Burns also
    threatened to take Allison “to the mall” after Allison beat him in a game of cards.
    And Burns told Allison that “[h]e feels like no matter what happens in this case,
    that he wins, because he had the opportunity to be out there with his family all
    these years.” Plus, Burns autographed a news story about the murder for Allison.
    Burns wrote, “[T]o my favorite son Michael” and signed it “Jerry Burns.”
    A jury found Burns guilty of murder in the first degree. The court
    sentenced Burns to prison. Burns now appeals.
    II. Analysis.
    A. Did Police Need a Warrant to Collect the Straw that Burns
    Discarded or to Analyze DNA Attached to the Straw? Burns contends that
    the district court should have suppressed evidence about the DNA that police
    found on the straw that Burns discarded at the Pizza Ranch. He argues
    suppression was required by the Fourth Amendment to the United States
    Constitution and article I, section 8 of the Iowa Constitution. Following our de
    novo review, we conclude that the district court was right to deny suppression.
    10
    See State v. Brown, 
    930 N.W.2d 840
    , 844 (Iowa 2019) (“When a defendant
    challenges a district court’s denial of a motion to suppress based upon the
    deprivation of a state or federal constitutional right, our standard of review is
    de novo.” (quoting State v. Brown, 
    890 N.W.2d 315
    , 321 (Iowa 2017))).
    1. General principles. The United States Constitution is a written
    document. Marbury v. Madison, 
    5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137
    , 176–78 (1803). So is the
    Iowa Constitution. See Stewart v. Bd. of Supervisors, 
    30 Iowa 9
    , 18–19 (1870).
    They both consist of words.
    Here are the words of the Fourth Amendment to the United States
    Constitution side-by-side with the words of article I, section 8 of the Iowa
    Constitution:
    Fourth Amendment to the United               Article I, section 8 of the Iowa
    States Constitution                            Constitution
    The right of the people to be secure in    The right of the people to be secure in
    their persons, houses, papers, and         their persons, houses, papers and
    effects,     against      unreasonable     effects, against unreasonable seizures
    searches and seizures, shall not be        and searches shall not be violated;
    violated, and no Warrants shall issue,     and no warrant shall issue but on
    but upon probable cause, supported         probable cause, supported by oath or
    by    Oath     or   affirmation,   and     affirmation, particularly describing
    particularly describing the place to be    the place to be searched, and the
    searched, and the persons or things to     persons and things to be seized.
    be seized.
    Comparison shows that the words of the Fourth Amendment are
    essentially identical to the words of section 8. See State ex rel. Kuble v. Bisignano,
    
    28 N.W.2d 504
    , 508 (Iowa 1947). And we have recognized that section 8 “as
    originally understood, was meant to provide the same protections as the Fourth
    Amendment, as originally understood.” State v. Wright, 
    961 N.W.2d 396
    , 411–12
    (Iowa 2021).
    11
    It is perhaps unsurprising, then, that this court’s interpretations of section
    8 have often “tracked with prevailing federal interpretations” of the Fourth
    Amendment. Kain v. State, 
    378 N.W.2d 900
    , 902 (Iowa 1985). But we are not
    “compel[led]” to follow that path. Bisignano, 
    28 N.W.2d at 508
     (noting that,
    although section 8 “is identical in language with the Fourth Amendment,” this
    “does not compel us to follow the construction placed on the language by the
    United States Supreme Court”). While the United States Supreme Court is the
    final arbiter of the Federal Constitution’s meaning, the same is not true of the
    Iowa Constitution. McClure v. Owen, 
    26 Iowa 243
    , 248–50 (1868) (noting the
    United States Supreme Court “is required to look to the courts of the States for
    the rules of construction of their respective laws and Constitutions”). Rather, the
    Iowa Supreme Court “is the final arbiter” of what the Iowa Constitution means.
    West v. Am. Tel. & Tel. Co., 
    311 U.S. 223
    , 236 (1940) (“[T]he highest court of the
    state is the final arbiter of what is state law.”). And we recognize our “duty to
    interpret” the Iowa Constitution “independently.” Brown, 
    930 N.W.2d at 847
    .
    Indeed, “[w]e jealously guard our right to construe a provision of our state
    constitution differently than its federal counterpart.” 
    Id.
     (quoting State v. Brooks,
    
    888 N.W.2d 406
    , 410–11 (Iowa 2016)). We also recognize our duty to “interpret
    our constitution consistent with the text given to us by our founders,” State v.
    Green, 
    896 N.W.2d 770
    , 778 (Iowa 2017), and to “give the words used by the
    framers their natural and commonly-understood meaning” in light of the
    “circumstances at the time of adoption,” State v. Senn, 
    882 N.W.2d 1
    , 8 (Iowa
    2016) (quoting Star Equip., Ltd. v. State, 
    843 N.W.2d 446
    , 457–58 (Iowa 2014)).
    12
    It follows that if a federal interpretation of the Fourth Amendment is not
    consistent with the text and history of section 8, we may conclude that the
    federal interpretation should not govern our interpretation of section 8.
    With this background in mind, we turn to Burns’s arguments about the
    Fourth Amendment and section 8. He addresses the two provisions separately.
    We follow his lead.
    2. Fourth Amendment analysis. According to its text, the Fourth
    Amendment protects “the people” from “unreasonable searches and seizures” of
    “their persons, houses, papers, and effects.” U.S. Const. amend. IV. It would
    seem, then, that the Fourth Amendment could apply if the discarded straw—or
    the DNA attached to it—were part of Burns’s “person,” Burns’s “house,” Burns’s
    “papers,” or Burns’s “effects.” Cf. Hester v. United States, 
    265 U.S. 57
    , 59 (1924)
    (“[T]he special protection accorded by the Fourth Amendment to the people in
    their ‘persons, houses, papers and effects,’ is not extended to the open fields.”).
    Burns’s brief recites the words of the Fourth Amendment. But his brief
    does not argue that the straw or the DNA would qualify as his “person,” his
    “house,” his “papers,” or his “effects” for purposes of the Fourth Amendment. 3
    Instead, Burns relies on cases that extend Fourth Amendment protections
    beyond those “places and things” that are “indicate[d] with some precision” in
    the Fourth Amendment’s text. Oliver v. United States, 
    466 U.S. 170
    , 176 (1984)
    3At   oral argument, Burns and the amicus’s counsel suggested that Burns’s straw-
    attached DNA might qualify as a “person.” We generally decline to “decide or consider arguments
    raised for the first time during oral argument.” State v. Warren, 
    955 N.W.2d 848
    , 860 (Iowa 2021).
    In any event, the parties have not cited—and we have not found—authority for the proposition
    that discarded DNA counts as a Fourth Amendment “person.”
    13
    (citing Hester, 
    265 U.S. at 59
    ). These cases tie Fourth Amendment protections
    to “reasonable expectation[s] of privacy.” Katz v. United States, 
    389 U.S. 347
    , 360
    (1967) (Harlan, J., concurring); see Kyllo v. United States, 
    533 U.S. 27
    , 33 (2001)
    (noting that, under modern jurisprudence “a Fourth Amendment search does not
    occur—even when the explicitly protected location of a house is concerned—
    unless” the reasonable expectation of privacy test is met). Under these cases, a
    reasonable expectation of privacy exists if two criteria are met. Smith v.
    Maryland, 
    442 U.S. 735
    , 740 (1979) (“This inquiry . . . normally embraces two
    discrete questions.”). First, the defendant must have sought to “preserve
    something as private.” Carpenter v. United States, 
    138 S. Ct. 2206
    , 2213 (2018)
    (quoting Smith, 
    442 U.S. at 740
    ). Second, the defendant’s expectation of privacy
    must be “one that society is prepared to recognize as reasonable.” 
    Id.
     (quoting
    Smith, 
    442 U.S. at 740
    ); see also Skinner v. Ry. Lab. Execs.’, 
    489 U.S. 602
    , 616–
    17 (1989) (analyzing whether society had recognized certain expectations of
    privacy). Unless both criteria are met, there is no reasonable expectation of
    privacy, and the Fourth Amendment does not apply.
    These criteria are not met here. Burns made no effort to “preserve” the
    straw “as private.” He left it on the table at a Pizza Ranch. It was open to
    collection by Pizza Ranch employees or fellow diners—whether those diners were
    civilians or, as happened, officers of the law. Burns could hardly have retained
    any subjective expectation of privacy in the straw.
    And even if Burns somehow expected privacy, his expectation was not the
    kind that society is prepared to recognize as reasonable. “When a person
    14
    voluntarily abandons his privacy interest in property, his subjective expectation
    of privacy becomes unreasonable . . . .” United States v. Stevenson, 
    396 F.3d 538
    ,
    546 (4th Cir. 2005). “There can be nothing unlawful in the Government’s
    appropriation of such abandoned property.” Abel v. United States, 
    362 U.S. 217
    ,
    241 (1960). And we agree with the State that Burns voluntarily abandoned the
    straw. Intent to abandon “may be inferred from words, acts, and other objective
    facts.” State v. Bumpus, 
    459 N.W.2d 619
    , 625 (Iowa 1990). Burns left the straw
    behind in a restaurant. He exposed it for collection by anyone who passed by.
    These acts and objective facts show voluntary abandonment. And, again, “[t]he
    Fourth Amendment does not protect voluntarily abandoned property.” State v.
    Grant, 
    614 N.W.2d 848
    , 855 (Iowa Ct. App. 2000) (en banc); cf. California v.
    Greenwood, 
    486 U.S. 35
    , 40–41 (1988) (concluding that defendants who
    “deposited their garbage ‘in an area particularly suited for public inspection and,
    in a manner of speaking, public consumption, for the express purpose of having
    strangers take it’ . . . could have had no reasonable expectation of privacy in the
    inculpatory items that they discarded” (citation omitted) (quoting United States
    v. Reicherter, 
    647 F.2d 397
    , 399 (3d Cir. 1981))).
    To his credit, Burns seems to concede that he abandoned any Fourth
    Amendment privacy interest in the straw. In Burns’s view, though, we should
    treat the DNA on the straw as different from the straw itself.
    Even if we accept this distinction, though, the two-part “reasonableness
    test” still leads to the same result. The DNA was on the straw. So when Burns
    failed to “preserve” the straw “as private,” he also failed to “preserve” the straw-
    15
    bound DNA “as private,” either. Carpenter, 
    138 S. Ct. at 2213
     (quoting Smith,
    442 N.W.2d at 740). Again, he did not take the DNA-laced straw home or to his
    car, or even to a trash can. Instead, he left the straw—and the DNA—on the Pizza
    Ranch table so that anyone passing by could collect both the DNA and the straw.
    In short, just as Burns voluntarily abandoned the straw, he also voluntarily
    abandoned any DNA attached to the straw. Burns “could have had no reasonable
    expectation of privacy” in either. Greenwood, 
    486 U.S. at
    40–41.
    But Burns points out that, unlike the straw, his DNA was not visible to
    staff or patrons at the restaurant. Plus, his DNA profile—the information that
    permits identification of the donor—couldn’t be obtained without lab analysis
    involving specialized equipment and technical expertise. So, Burns argues that
    even after he abandoned the straw, he could still expect his DNA profile to remain
    private.
    We disagree. In State v. Christian, the court of appeals concluded that a
    defendant who voluntarily abandoned a water bottle and fork also abandoned
    any “objective expectation of privacy in the DNA shed on the items.” No. 04–0900,
    
    2006 WL 2419031
    , at *4 (Iowa Ct. App. Aug. 23, 2006). We think this is the right
    approach—and we think it applies equally to a profile created from the DNA that
    Burns abandoned at the Pizza Ranch. Indeed, like the State, we see no practical
    difference between (1) DNA that a rapist leaves behind at a crime scene and (2)
    the DNA that Burns left on the straw at the Pizza Ranch. In both situations, a
    casual observer would not be able to see any DNA, much less any DNA profile.
    Rather, in both cases, DNA profiles would have to be developed using technical
    16
    expertise and equipment. In our view, though, neither situation involves an
    expectation of privacy that society would be prepared to recognize as reasonable.
    See Wilson v. State, 
    752 A.2d 1250
    , 1272 (Md. Ct. Spec. App. 2000) (“Once an
    individual’s fingerprints and/or his blood sample for DNA testing are in lawful
    police possession, that individual is no more immune from being caught by the
    DNA sample he leaves on the body of his rape victim than he is from being caught
    by the fingerprint he leaves on the window of the burglarized house or the
    steering wheel of the stolen car.”).
    Other courts have reasoned similarly. See, e.g., State v. Emerson, 
    981 N.E.2d 787
    , 792 (Ohio 2012) (noting that “numerous courts around the country”
    have concluded “a person has no reasonable expectation of privacy in his or her
    DNA profile extracted from a lawfully obtained DNA sample”). As one
    commentator summarized, “Courts have uniformly rejected Fourth Amendment
    protection against surreptitious harvesting of out-of-body DNA by the police.”
    Albert E. Scherr, Genetic Privacy & the Fourth Amendment: Unregulated
    Surreptitious DNA Harvesting, 
    47 Ga. L. Rev. 445
    , 454 (2013). “By and large,
    [courts] have found (1) that the putative suspect abandoned the item upon or in
    which the DNA-laden cells were found and (2) as a result, there was no
    expectation of privacy in the item or that which it was in or on.” 
    Id.
    In Burns’s view, though, DNA isn’t voluntarily abandoned because
    humans are constantly and involuntarily shedding DNA through hair loss, skin
    flakes, sneezes, and so on. For purposes of this case, though, we don’t need to
    consider every possible form of DNA loss or DNA collection. See Book v.
    17
    Doublestar Dongfeng Tyre Co., 
    860 N.W.2d 576
    , 596 (Iowa 2015) (“We decide only
    the case before us.”). Rather, we only have to consider whether the Fourth
    Amendment protects the DNA that Burns left on one clearly identifiable item: the
    drinking straw that Burns voluntarily placed in his own mouth, and then
    voluntarily left on the Pizza Ranch table even though Burns could have instead
    chosen to keep the straw (and its DNA) private by taking them to his car or home.
    We think it does not.
    Even if we lump Burns’s situation in with less voluntary forms of DNA loss,
    the same outcome might still hold. Although it is true that humans distribute
    DNA continually and unconsciously, the same is true of latent fingerprints (not
    to mention footwear impressions, tire tracks, and other impression evidence).
    Like our DNA, we leave fingerprints everywhere—and generally without volition.
    Thomas D. Holland, Novel Features of Considerable Biologic Interest the Fourth
    Amendment and the Admissibility of Abandoned DNA Evidence, 
    20 Colum. Sci. & Tech. L. Rev. 271
    , 310 (2019) [hereinafter Holland] (“[F]ingerprints, like DNA, are
    involuntarily ‘abandoned’ in prodigious amounts on the items that we touch.”).
    Fingerprints share other features with DNA as well. Of course, “[b]oth
    fingerprints and DNA are powerful means of individual identification.” 
    Id.
     Also,
    just as DNA is not visible to the unaided eye, that’s ordinarily true of latent
    fingerprints as well. Dactyloscopy, Britannica, https://www.britannica.com/
    topic/dactyloscopy#ref1231149      [https://perma.cc/M9KK-HRHD].         And—like
    DNA profiles—latent fingerprints are developed with the aid of specialized
    technology. See Div. Crim. Investigation, Criminalistics Laboratory - Latent Print
    18
    &       Identification        Section,        https://dps.iowa.gov/divisions/criminal-
    investigation/criminalistics-laboratory/latent-print-identification-section
    [https://perma.cc/8F2E-S6NM] (“The techniques used in the development of
    latent prints range from traditional fingerprint powdering techniques and
    superglue fuming, to advanced techniques such as fluorescent dye stains and
    alternate light sources.”). Even so, the time-honored process of collecting latent
    fingerprints—and then using them to identify perpetrators—seems to raise no
    Fourth Amendment concerns. Certainly, no one suggests that police would have
    needed a warrant to collect fingerprints from the cup that Burns left behind at
    the Pizza Ranch—or to use those fingerprints to determine whether Burns was
    in Martinko’s car on the night of her murder.4 We think the same is true of the
    DNA that Burns left on the straw—and that ultimately connected him with
    Martinko’s dress. See Maryland v. King, 
    569 U.S. 435
    , 458 (2013) (drawing
    analogy between fingerprinting and DNA technology).
    But Burns claims DNA is different from fingerprints because—although
    fingerprints can only be used for identification5—DNA analysis reveals vast
    amounts of private information, like “genetic defects, predispositions to
    diseases,” and perhaps even genetic likelihood for noncriminal behaviors that
    are, nevertheless, “socially disfavored.” United States v. Kincade, 
    379 F.3d 813
    ,
    4To be clear, police were unable to find human fingerprints in Martinko’s car. Rather, as
    mentioned, it appears that the murderer wore rubber gloves to prevent law enforcement from
    retrieving any fingerprints.
    5This may underestimate the usefulness of fingerprints. See Holland, 20 Colum. Sci. &
    Tech. L. Rev. at 315–17 (noting other possible information that can be determined through
    analysis of fingerprints).
    19
    850 (9th Cir. 2004) (Reinhardt, J., dissenting). In Burns’s view, then, DNA
    analysis is more like the cell phone site location information (CSLI) records at
    issue in Carpenter v. United States, 
    138 S. Ct. at 2211
    . Those “detailed,
    encyclopedic” records—which provided an “all-encompassing record” of the
    Carpenter suspect’s location over a course of 127 consecutive days—can give law
    enforcement “an intimate window into a person’s life, revealing not only his
    particular movements, but through them his ‘familial, political, professional,
    religious, and sexual associations.’ ” 
    Id.
     at 2216–17 (quoting United States v.
    Jones, 
    565 U.S. 400
    , 415 (2012) (Sotomayor, J., concurring)). So, the Court
    believed, “These location records ‘hold for many Americans the “privacies of
    life.” ’ ” Id. at 2217 (quoting Riley v. California, 
    573 U.S. 373
    , 403 (2014)). For
    this and other reasons, the Carpenter Court held that “when the Government
    accessed CSLI from [a suspect’s] wireless carriers, it invaded [the suspect’s]
    reasonable expectation of privacy in the whole of his physical movements.” Id. at
    2219.
    We think Carpenter is distinguishable on two grounds. First, the Carpenter
    Court said that its decision “is a narrow one.” Id. at 2220. “We do not express a
    view on matters not before us,” the Court said. Id. We take the Court at its word.
    So, as a technical matter, we read Carpenter as limited to CSLI or very similar
    technologies that can provide police with comprehensive surveillance of a
    person’s physical movements. And that is not the kind of information that police
    obtained through Burns’s DNA. The DNA from the Pizza Ranch straw helped
    police establish one fact, namely, that Burns’s DNA profile matched with DNA
    20
    found on Martinko’s dress. As far as location goes, the DNA provided almost no
    information. At most, it supported an inference that Burns was at one particular
    location (in Martinko’s car) at some point on one particular night (December 19,
    1979). That doesn’t approach the comprehensive surveillance described in
    Carpenter.
    Moreover, while we appreciate that some forms of DNA analysis may
    provide remarkable windows into deeply personal information, we remain
    focused on the facts of “the case before us.” Book, 
    860 N.W.2d at 596
    . And the
    case before us is about one particular instance of DNA analysis, namely, analysis
    of DNA from the straw that Burns left behind at the Pizza Ranch. That analysis
    did not reveal the kinds of personal information—like “genetic defects” or
    “predispositions to disease”—that free citizens might expect to keep private.
    Kincade, 
    379 F.3d at 850
    . Rather, according to the lab report, the straw analysis
    only revealed that “[t]he weak DNA profile developed from the ends of the straw
    indicated a male source,” and—most importantly—the “DNA donor could NOT
    be eliminated as the major contributor to the DNA profile previously developed”
    from a stain on Martinko’s dress.6 We see little difference between this report
    and, say, a lab report that connects fingerprints from a discarded cup with
    fingerprints found at a crime scene.7 Neither report could provide much insight
    6The full lab report is included in Appendix A. Note that the report includes analysis of
    the straw collected from the Pizza Ranch as well as some items collected from Donald’s trash.
    The Pizza Ranch straw is labeled as item 49.
    7It is true that the DNA report also gave the donor’s sex. But it appears fingerprint
    analysis can also be used to determine sex. Holland, 20 Colum. Sci. & Tech. L. Rev. at 315
    (“Studies by anthropologists and medical researchers suggest that both the size and density of
    fingerprint ridges are statistically linked to the sex of the individual, and scientists also have
    21
    into the “familial, political, professional, religious, [or] sexual associations”
    mentioned in Carpenter, 
    138 S. Ct. at 2217
     (quoting Jones, 
    565 U.S. at 415
    (Sotomayor,      J.,   concurring)).     Neither    situation     involves    technological
    encroachment into those “privacies of life” that Carpenter sought to protect. 
    Id.
    (quoting Riley, 573 U.S. at 403).
    By way of conscious repetition, though, “[w]e decide only the case before
    us.” Book, 
    860 N.W.2d at 596
    . We do not foreclose the possibility that other kinds
    of warrantless DNA analysis might require a different result. For instance, as the
    State notes, “[p]erhaps” if police had used different techniques to “catalogue[]
    numerous traits about” Burns’s “physiology and health conditions (like genetic
    predispositions to cancer or the like), there would be some merit to the . . .
    privacy complaints” raised by Burns and the amici. But that is not the case
    before us. And after careful consideration of the case before us, we conclude that
    the Fourth Amendment did not require police to obtain a warrant before
    collecting the straw or before analyzing DNA on the straw to determine whether
    it matched DNA found on Martinko’s dress. So the Fourth Amendment did not
    require suppression.
    3. Section 8. Burns also argues that even if the Fourth Amendment to the
    United States Constitution does not apply, suppression was still required by
    article I, section 8 of the Iowa Constitution. We disagree.
    shown that the amino acids left behind in sweat deposited with the fingerprint varies with sex
    as well.” (footnote omitted)).
    22
    a. Burns’s general argument. Burns’s state constitution analysis begins
    with the general premise that section 8 categorically “provides greater protection
    of individual privacy than the Fourth Amendment.” We reject this premise. See,
    e.g., State v. Beckett, 
    532 N.W.2d 751
    , 755 (Iowa 1995) (citing cases and stating,
    “We have consistently declined to provide greater protection under article I,
    section 8 of the Iowa Constitution than the United States Supreme Court has
    found in the Fourth Amendment.”). As explained, it is our duty to independently
    interpret section 8 based on its words and history. Depending on the issue, this
    inquiry may lead us to conclude that section 8 provides protections that are the
    same as, greater than, or less than the protections provided by the Fourth
    Amendment.
    b. Burns’s specific arguments. Burns also raises two specific arguments
    about section 8. First, Burns claims that analysis of his discarded DNA was a
    trespass and, therefore, the analysis violated section 8 as interpreted in State v.
    Wright, 
    961 N.W.2d 396
    . Second, and alternatively, Burns again claims a
    reasonable expectation of privacy in his discarded DNA. We address these
    arguments in turn.
    i. Trespass and Wright. We begin with Burns’s claim under Wright. In
    Wright we held that because a Clear Lake ordinance prohibited anyone except a
    “licensed collector” from collecting trash, and because police did not qualify as a
    “licensed collector” of trash, police lacked any legal right to dig around in trash
    that a homeowner had left out for collection. 
    Id.
     at 419–20. By doing so, police
    23
    had unlawfully trespassed on the homeowner’s “papers” and “effects” in violation
    of section 8. Id. at 417.
    Burns claims the same is true here because Iowa Code section 729.6(3)
    (2019) prohibited police from collecting his DNA and “performing genetic testing
    of him without his informed written consent.” We disagree for two reasons. First,
    we do not believe section 729.6(3) applies here. It states in pertinent part:
    3. a. A person shall not obtain genetic information or samples
    for genetic testing from an individual without first obtaining
    informed and written consent from the individual or the individual’s
    authorized representative.
    b. A person shall not perform genetic testing of an individual
    or collect, retain, transmit, or use genetic information without the
    informed and written consent of the individual or the individual’s
    authorized representative.
    c. The following exceptions apply to the prohibitions in
    paragraphs “a” and “b”:
    ....
    (2) To identify an individual in the course of a criminal
    investigation by a law enforcement agency.
    Id. (emphasis added).
    As its text makes clear, section 729.6(3) imposes limits on the collection
    and use of genetic information. But paragraph (c)(2) makes it equally clear that
    the statute’s prohibitions don’t apply to law enforcement’s efforts to “identify an
    individual in the course of a criminal investigation.” Id. § 729.6(3)(c)(2). That is
    what happened here: law enforcement collected and analyzed Burns’s DNA as
    part of their effort to “identify an individual”—the unidentified individual who left
    DNA on Martinko’s dress.
    24
    Burns responds that “[c]onsidering the rules of construction,” paragraph
    (c)(2) can only apply when law enforcement has a “warrant.” We disagree. “We
    must look to the statute as it is written.” Moss v. Williams, 
    133 N.W. 120
    , 121
    (Iowa 1911). As written, paragraph (c)(2) includes no mention of a “warrant.” If
    the legislature had intended it to require a warrant, the legislature “could easily
    have so stated.” Hansen v. Haugh, 
    149 N.W.2d 169
    , 172 (Iowa 1967). And we
    can’t create a new requirement that the legislature chose not to enact. See 
    id.
    (citing Iowa Const. art. III, § 1).
    We recognize that Burns’s statutory          argument is tied up with
    constitutional concerns. We also recognize that when there are “competing
    plausible interpretations of a statutory text,” we may rely on the presumption
    that our legislature “did not intend the alternative which raises serious
    constitutional doubts.” Clark v. Martinez, 
    543 U.S. 371
    , 381–82 (2005); see 
    Iowa Code § 4.4
    (1) (“In enacting a statute, it is presumed that . . . [c]ompliance with
    the Constitutions of the state and of the United States is intended.”). But here
    there are no “competing plausible interpretations of a statutory text.” Clark, 
    543 U.S. at 381
    ; see In re Guardianship of Kennedy, 
    845 N.W.2d 707
    , 714 (Iowa 2014)
    (“We have interpreted ambiguous statutes in the past to avoid constitutional
    problems.” (emphasis added)). There is no “plausible” interpretation that would
    require a warrant. The statute does not mention “warrants” or any synonym.
    Second, and in any event, the statute is not relevant under the trespass
    standard set forth in Wright. As mentioned above, and as the Wright court
    emphasized, “section 8 provides that people have the right to be secure in ‘their’
    25
    persons, houses, papers, and effects.” Wright, 961 N.W.2d at 415 (quoting Iowa
    Const. art. I, § 8). “Although phrased in the plural, ‘[t]he obvious meaning of
    [“their”] is that each person has the right to be secure against unreasonable
    searches and seizures in his own person, house, papers, and effects.’ ” Id.
    (alterations in original) (quoting Carpenter, 
    138 S. Ct. at
    2241–42 (Thomas, J.,
    dissenting)). In Wright, we explained that section 8 “precludes a peace officer
    from engaging in general criminal investigation that constitutes a trespass
    against a citizen’s house, papers, or effects.” Id. at 417. Here, however, the police
    did not trespass against or otherwise seize or search Burns’s person, his house,
    his papers, or his effects. So, Wright does not apply.
    ii. Reasonable expectation of privacy. Next Burns claims that—like the
    Fourth Amendment—section 8 also protects his reasonable expectation of
    privacy in the straw-bound DNA. Indeed, Burns claims his reasonable-
    expectation claim is even stronger under the Iowa Constitution because—as
    mentioned—Burns thinks that Iowa Code section 729.6(3) prohibited Iowa law
    enforcement officers from collecting or analyzing his DNA.
    We disagree. As a preliminary matter, we note that the text of section 8
    does not mention “expectations” or “privacy.” But the parties agree that, like the
    Fourth Amendment, section 8 protects “reasonable expectations of privacy.” Our
    cases offer support for this view. See, e.g., State v. Gaskins, 
    866 N.W.2d 1
    , 16
    (Iowa 2015) (“The protections of article I, section 8 against warrantless searches
    are not meant to benefit the public generally. They are meant to protect
    individual citizens and their reasonable expectations of privacy.”).
    26
    In any event, for the same reasons we discussed with regard to the Fourth
    Amendment, we conclude that the collection and analysis of Burns’s DNA did
    not invade any privacy expectations that are protected by section 8. We note also
    that, as discussed, Iowa Code section 729.6(3)(c)(2) plainly permits Iowa law
    enforcement to collect and analyze genetic material to “identify an individual in
    the course of a criminal investigation.” So Burns could have no reasonable
    expectation that Iowa law enforcement would refrain from using his DNA in their
    efforts to identify Martinko’s killer. On the contrary, given the “unparalleled
    ability” of DNA technology “to exonerate” the innocent and “to identify the guilty,”
    Iowans should fully expect that law enforcement agencies would use that
    technology to solve difficult cases like Martinko’s murder. King, 
    569 U.S. at 442
    (quoting Dist. Atty’s Off. for Third Jud. Dist. v. Osborne, 
    557 U.S. 52
    , 55 (2009))
    (“Since the first use of forensic DNA analysis to catch a rapist and murderer in
    England in 1986, law enforcement, the defense bar, and the courts have
    acknowledged DNA testing’s ‘unparalleled ability both to exonerate the wrongly
    convicted and to identify the guilty. It has the potential to significantly improve
    both the criminal justice system and police investigative practices.’ ” (citation
    omitted) (quoting Osborne, 
    557 U.S. at 55
    )).
    4. Conclusion. Police did not violate the Fourth Amendment to the United
    States Constitution or article I, section 8 of the Iowa Constitution by collecting
    the straw that Burns discarded at the Pizza Ranch, or by analyzing the DNA on
    the straw to determine whether it would match DNA found on Martinko’s dress.
    The district court did not err by declining to suppress the State’s DNA evidence.
    27
    B. Did the District Court Err by Refusing to Give a Requested Jury
    Instruction? Burns also argues that the district court abused its discretion by
    declining to give an instruction regarding federal sentencing law. We disagree.
    See State v. Williams, 
    929 N.W.2d 621
    , 628 (Iowa 2019) (“[W]e review the refusal
    to give a cautionary jury instruction for abuse of discretion.”).8
    As explained, Michael Allison was a federal detainee who bunked near
    Burns in the Cedar Rapids jail. At Burns’s trial, Allison testified about
    incriminating remarks Burns had made. For instance, according to Allison, “he
    had told me, if I keep beating him in pinochle, he was going to have to take me
    to the mall.” Pretty troubling—one might infer—since Burns was accused of
    murdering Martinko in a mall parking lot.
    On cross-examination, Allison conceded that he had a substantial criminal
    record. He had already been to federal prison on several occasions. And at the
    time of Burns’s trial, Allison was facing a new federal indictment for conspiracy
    to distribute methamphetamine, which carries a mandatory minimum prison
    sentence of fifteen years and a maximum sentence of life. Allison said that he
    had previously negotiated a deal to resolve the conspiracy charge—but then he
    later “pulled” the deal, apparently at his lawyer’s advice. So, by the time of
    Burns’s trial, he had no “active” plea agreement with the government. Allison
    said that he was waiting for a new deal, which—he hoped—would change his
    8The State suggests that the standard of review is for correction of errors at law. Under
    either standard, we find no grounds for reversal.
    28
    range of possible prison sentences “from 15 to life” to a range of “zero to 20”
    years.
    Allison admitted that he was “very familiar” with the federal sentencing
    guidelines, the “cookbook” that guides sentencing in the federal system. Allison
    acknowledged that the guidelines allow federal prosecutors “to ask” the court to
    impose “a lesser sentence” than what the guidelines would otherwise “call for” if
    Allison “cooperate[d] with the prosecution or investigation” of another suspect.
    And Allison acknowledged that he9 had gone to law enforcement with information
    about Burns, i.e., the incriminating remarks we have already discussed. Allison
    also acknowledged that—through his testimony in Burns’s murder trial—he was
    indeed cooperating with law enforcement. But, Allison explained, he had no
    “cooperation agreement” that would require federal prosecutors to make any
    request for leniency in return for his cooperation. According to Allison, he had
    not “received any kind of promise of a plea agreement or a deal to testify” against
    Burns.10 Indeed, Allison maintained that he had never talked to federal
    prosecutors about cooperation. When defense counsel asked Allison if he was
    “using Jerry Burns as a bargaining chip to try to get a better sentence” for his
    federal conspiracy case, Allison responded, “No, sir, not at all.”
    In response to Allison’s testimony, the defense asked for a jury instruction
    concerning federal sentencing law. Here is the text of the proposed instruction:
    9Allisonsaid he conveyed the information to his lawyer who then conveyed the
    information to law enforcement.
    10This   testimony was given on redirect.
    29
    You have heard that witness Michael Allison was earlier
    convicted of crimes. You may use that evidence only to help you
    decide whether to believe the witness and how much weight to give
    his testimony.
    You have also heard [evidence] that Michael Allison hopes to
    receive a reduced sentence on criminal charges pending against him
    in return for his cooperation with the prosecution in this case.
    Michael Allison entered into an agreement with the United States
    Attorney for the Northern District of Iowa which provides that in
    return for his assistance, the government may recommend a less
    severe sentence which could be less than the mandatory minimum
    sentence for the crime with which he is charged. Michael Allison is
    subject to a mandatory minimum sentence, that is, a sentence that
    the law provides must be of a certain minimum length. If the
    prosecutor handling this witness’s case believe[s] he provided
    substantial assistance, the prosecutor can file in the court in which
    the charges are pending against the witness a motion to reduce his
    sentence below the statutory minimum. The judge has no power to
    reduce the sentence for substantial assistance unless the
    government, acting through the United States Attorney, files such a
    motion. If such a motion for reduction of sentence for substantial
    assistance is filed by the prosecution, then it is up to the judge to
    decide whether to reduce the sentence at all, and if so, how much to
    reduce it.
    You may give testimony of this witness such weight as you
    think it deserves. Whether or not testimony of a witness may have
    been influenced by his hope of receiving a reduced sentence is for
    you to decide.
    Burns’s counsel explained that “this is a standard instruction given in the
    Eighth Circuit district courts, and it gives guidance to the jury to view the
    testimony of a witness for whom some consideration is being given in exchange
    for the witness’ cooperation or testimony on behalf of the prosecution.” Counsel
    acknowledged that because Allison had been less than “forthright about why he’s
    testifying against” Burns, the instruction “could be modified” to say that “if you
    find that Michael Allison hopes to receive a reduced sentence on criminal charges
    pending against him, et cetera, you can then consider that in giving the weight
    30
    to his evidence.” Otherwise, though, counsel believed the “factual predicates for
    th[e] instruction were admitted by” Allison.
    The district court declined to give the instruction. Instead, the court gave
    “stock” state-court instructions to guide the jury’s consideration of Allison’s
    testimony. Specifically, Jury Instruction No. 11 listed factors the jury may
    consider when deciding what testimony to believe, including “[t]he witness’s
    interest in the trial, their motive, candor, bias and prejudice.” And Jury
    Instruction No. 15 stated, “The witness Michael Allison has admitted he was
    convicted of a crime. You may use that evidence only to help you decide whether
    to believe the witness and how much weight to give his testimony.”
    On appeal, Burns claims that the district court erred by giving these
    instructions instead of his proposal. Burns argues that because the proposed
    instruction correctly reflected federal sentencing law, the court had no choice
    but to give the instruction. We disagree. Burns does not cite, and we have not
    found, any authority that requires Iowa trial courts to instruct jurors about state
    or federal sentencing law simply because a witness’s testimony may be
    influenced by pending charges or—more to the point—the possibility that the
    witness may receive a lighter sentence because of their testimony. And although
    the trial court must “instruct a jury on all legal issues presented in a case,” we
    don’t think an instruction on federal sentencing would have addressed any legal
    issues that the jury had to decide. Anderson v. Webster City Cmty. Sch. Dist., 
    620 N.W.2d 263
    , 265–66 (Iowa 2000) (en banc); see State v. Davis, 
    951 N.W.2d 8
    , 17
    (Iowa 2020) (noting instructions must give the jury “a clear understanding of the
    31
    issues it must decide” (quoting Thompson v. City of Des Moines, 
    564 N.W.2d 839
    ,
    846 (Iowa 1997) (emphasis added))). Rather, we agree with the State that an
    instruction about federal sentencing would have been about facts. It would have
    given the jury facts about how the sentencing process works and, particularly,
    how Allison could receive a lesser sentence through cooperation. These are the
    same kind of facts that Burns’s counsel successfully obtained from Allison on
    cross-examination. And we aren’t sure that any more facts were required: Allison
    made it clear to the jury that—if he cooperated—prosecutors could ask the court
    to impose “a lesser sentence.” If additional facts were needed, though, they
    should have come in through additional evidence—from Allison or another
    witness—not a jury instruction.
    In any event, when we read the jury instructions as a whole, we find no
    prejudicial error. The instructions listed factors the jury may consider when
    deciding what testimony to believe, including “[t]he witness’s interest in the trial,
    their motive, candor, bias and prejudice.” And the instructions said that “[t]he
    witness Michael Allison has admitted he was convicted of a crime. You may use
    that evidence only to help you decide whether to believe the witness and how
    much weight to give his testimony.” These instructions adequately guided the
    jury’s consideration of Allison’s testimony.
    Burns has shown no reversible error in the jury instructions.
    C. Was the Evidence Sufficient to Support Burns’s Conviction?
    Finally, Burns argues that there was not sufficient evidence to support the
    murder verdict. We disagree.
    32
    “We review sufficiency-of-evidence claims for correction of errors at law.”
    State v. Cahill, 
    972 N.W.2d 19
    , 27 (Iowa 2022). “[W]e are highly deferential to the
    jury’s verdict. The jury’s verdict binds this court if the verdict is supported by
    substantial evidence.” 
    Id.
     (alteration in original) (quoting State v. Jones, 
    967 N.W.2d 336
    , 339 (Iowa 2021)).
    Martinko was brutally murdered during a vicious struggle in her Buick.
    Burns does not dispute this. Instead, Burns only raises an identity issue, a claim
    that he wasn’t the murderer. But there was ample evidence from which a jury
    could conclude that he was. The DNA from Burns’s buccal swab was consistent
    with the DNA found on Martinko’s dress to a probability of 1 out of 100 billion
    unrelated persons.
    Plus, Burns’s DNA matched the profile obtained from the Buick’s gearshift
    lever. This match was close enough to eliminate about 99.94% of all males in the
    United States.
    Also, law enforcement observed “noticeable” scars on both of Burns’s
    hands and arms. He could have received the cuts during a bloody struggle with
    Martinko.
    Finally, a jury could reasonably conclude that Burns’s statements to
    Allison were oblique admissions of guilt. Burns even autographed a news story
    about Martinko’s murder.
    Viewing the evidence “in the light most favorable to the State, including all
    ‘legitimate inferences and presumptions that may fairly and reasonably be
    deduced from the record evidence,’ ” we conclude the verdict was adequately
    33
    supported. Jones, 967 N.W.2d at 339 (quoting State v. Tipton, 
    897 N.W.2d 653
    ,
    692 (Iowa 2017)).
    III. Conclusion.
    Burns has not shown reversible error. We affirm the judgment of the
    district court.
    AFFIRMED.
    Christensen, C.J., and Waterman, Mansfield, and McDonald, JJ., join this
    opinion. McDonald, J., files a concurring opinion. Oxley, J., files a dissenting
    opinion. McDermott, J., files a dissenting opinion, in which Oxley, J., joins
    except as to part I.B.
    34
    Appendix A
    E-FILED 2020 FEB 07 1:50 PM LINN - CLERK OF DISTRICT COURT
    Cross-reference DCI Case 1971-703, 1972-635, 1972-885, 1980-6274, 2006-13798 and 2007-733
    Official Report Of                                     1985-6117 Report 39
    Iowa Department of Public Safety                                  LAB CASE NUMBER
    DCI Criminalistics Laboratory
    2240 South Ankeny Boulevard                                           11/05/2018
    Ankeny, Iowa 50023-9093                                           REPORT DATE
    (515) 725-1500
    DNA Report
    See Code of Iowa Section 691.2 Presumption of qualification - evidence – testimony. “It shall be presumed that any employee
    or technician of the criminalistics laboratory is qualified or possesses the required expertise to accomplish any analysis, comparison,
    or identification done by the employee’s employment in the criminalistics laboratory. Any report, or copy of a report, or the
    findings of the criminalistics laboratory shall be received in evidence, if determined to be relevant, in any court, preliminary hearing,
    grand jury proceeding, civil proceeding, administrative hearing, and forfeiture proceeding in the same manner and with the same
    force and effect as if the employee or technician of the criminalistics laboratory who accomplished the requested analysis,
    comparison, or identification had testified in person...”
    AGENCY:                                      Cedar Rapids Police                         CASE TYPE:                    Death Investigation
    Department
    AGENCY CASE NUMBER:                          1979-25441                                  OFFENSE DATE:                 December 19, 1979
    CASE OFFICER:                                David Zahn                                  REPORT OF:                    Michael Schmit
    SUSPECT(S):                                                                              VICTIM(S):                    Michelle Marie
    Suspect Names                                                       Martinko
    Redacted
    ITEMS AS DESCRIBED BY SUBMITTING AGENCY:
    On October 30, 2018, Kraig Kruger with Cedar Rapids Police Department submitted the following item(s) to
    Stacie Prall (DCI Lab):
    Lab #       Agency #       Description
    49          JB1            Straw. Collected immediately after being used by Jerry Burns.
    50          DB1A           Straw w/ lid. Collected from garbage of Donald Burns.
    51          DB1B           Drinking glass. Collected after being used by Donald Burns.
    52          DB1C           Bandage w/ blood. Collected from garbage of Donald Burns.
    53          DB1D           Toothbrush. Collected from garbage of Donald Burns.
    EXPLANATION
    The polymerase chain reaction (PCR) was used to amplify twenty-one (21) short tandem repeat (STR)
    loci and 3 sexing loci. The loci targeted and amplified are D3S1358, vWA, D16S539, CSF1PO, TPOX,
    Y-Indel, Amelogenin, D8S1179, D21S11, D18S51, DYS391, D2S441, D19S433, TH01, FGA,
    D22S1045, D5S818, D13S317, D7S820, SE33, D10S1248, D1S1656, D12S391, and D2S1338. The
    composite result of testing at each locus is termed an individual’s DNA profile.
    The STR kit that the Iowa DCI Crime Lab uses to process DNA samples was changed in January 2017
    and now includes 21 STR loci per the requirements of the FBI. The questioned profiles from Items 49
    through 53 were developed using the current 21 STR loci. The questioned profile from Item F was
    previously developed using 15 STR loci. Comparisons were made using the 13 STR loci that are
    common to both kits.
    35
    RESULTS OF EXAMINATION
    49         The weak DNA profile developed from the ends of the straw indicated a male source. The
    DNA donor could NOT be eliminated as the major contributor to the DNA profile previously
    developed from stain #F5 (see DNA report dated 12/5/2005) from the black dress
    (described as “Item F1” on DNA report dated 9/8/2003).
    Further interpretation may be attempted if a KNOWN DNA sample from a potential source is submitted.
    Linn
    Page 1 of 2
    E-FILED 2020 FEB 07 1:50 PM LINN - CLERK OF
    DISTRICT COURT Lab Case#: 1985-6117 Report#: 39 Agency Case#:
    1979-25441 Michael Schmit
    50         The DNA profile developed from the mouth end of the straw indicated a mixture of at least
    two individuals that was too weak for conclusive interpretation. The lid was not examined.
    51         The DNA profile developed from the mouth area of the drinking glass indicated a
    mixture of at least four individuals. No further conclusions could be made.
    52         The DNA profile developed from the stained area on the gauze indicated a female source.
    The DNA donor was eliminated as the major contributor to the DNA profile previously
    developed from stain
    #F5.
    53         The DNA profile developed from the toothbrush bristles indicated a male source.
    The DNA donor was eliminated as the major contributor to the DNA profile previously
    developed from stain
    #F5.
    DISPOSITION OF EVIDENCE
    The evidence will be returned to the DCI laboratory evidence room.
    This report may contain opinions, conclusions or interpretations of the examiner whose signature
    appears below.
    Michael Schmit, Criminalist
    Page 2 of 2
    36
    #20–1150, State v. Burns
    McDONALD, Justice (concurring).
    The words of the Fourth Amendment really do mean what they
    say. They do not require warrants, even presumptively, for searches
    and seizures. They do not require probable cause for all searches
    and seizures without warrants. They do not require—or even invite—
    exclusions of evidence, contraband, or stolen goods. All this is
    relatively obvious if only we read the Amendment’s words carefully
    and take them seriously . . . .
    Akhil Reed Amar, Fourth Amendment First Principles, 
    107 Harv. L. Rev. 757
    , 761
    (1994) [hereinafter Amar].
    Modern search and seizure doctrine does not take the words of the federal
    or state constitutions seriously. As a result, search and seizure doctrine “today
    is an embarrassment.” Id. at 757; see State v. Wright, 
    961 N.W.2d 396
    , 410 (Iowa
    2021) (stating “[c]urrent Fourth Amendment jurisprudence is a mess” and
    collecting authorities). The three pillars of modern search and seizure doctrine—
    the warrant requirement, the probable cause requirement, and the exclusionary
    rule—are “initially plausible but ultimately misguided. As a matter of text,
    history, and plain old common sense, these three pillars of modern Fourth
    Amendment case law are hard to support.” Amar, 107 Harv. L. Rev. at 757
    (footnote omitted). I join the court’s well-reasoned opinion because it correctly
    resolves Burns’s federal and state constitutional claims under the controlling
    precedents. I write separately to address the third pillar of modern search and
    seizure doctrine—the exclusionary rule—under federal and state law.
    37
    I.
    The federal exclusionary rule, as applied in state courts, is of relatively
    recent origin. In Boyd v. United States and Weeks v. United States, the United
    States Supreme Court held evidence obtained in violation of the Federal
    Constitution was inadmissible in federal criminal proceedings. Boyd, 
    116 U.S. 616
    , 638 (1886), abrogated as recognized by Fisher v. United States, 
    425 U.S. 391
     (1976); Weeks, 
    232 U.S. 383
    , 398 (1914), overruled on other grounds by
    Mapp v. Ohio, 
    367 U.S. 643
     (1961). In Wolf v. Colorado, the Supreme Court held
    the principles underlying the Fourth Amendment were “enforceable against the
    States through the Due Process Clause.” Wolf, 
    338 U.S. 25
    , 27–28 (1949),
    overruled on other grounds by Mapp, 
    367 U.S. 643
    . Wolf specifically declined,
    however, to require state courts to adopt the exclusionary rule as a remedy. Id.
    at 33. In Mapp v. Ohio, the Supreme Court overruled Wolf, in part, and held state
    courts were required to apply the exclusionary rule for violations of the right
    recognized in Wolf. Mapp, 
    367 U.S. at
    654–57; see United States v. Janis, 
    428 U.S. 433
    , 443–47 (1976) (discussing history of exclusionary rule).
    The conclusion that the Fourth Amendment requires the exclusion of
    relevant and reliable evidence in state court criminal proceedings “could not
    withstand even the slightest scrutiny.” Collins v. Virginia, 
    138 S. Ct. 1663
    , 1677
    (2018) (Thomas, J., concurring). “The exclusionary rule appears nowhere in the
    Constitution, postdates the founding by more than a century, and contradicts
    several longstanding principles of the common law.” 
    Id.
     “Supporters of the
    exclusionary rule [could not and] cannot point to a single major statement from
    38
    the Founding—or even the antebellum or Reconstruction eras—supporting
    Fourth Amendment exclusion of evidence in a criminal trial.” Amar, 107 Harv. L.
    Rev. at 786. “Indeed, the idea of exclusion was so implausible that it seems
    almost never to have been urged by criminal defendants . . . in the vast number
    of criminal cases litigated in the century after Independence.” Id.
    Dean Wigmore was particularly critical of the Court’s new exclusionary
    rule jurisprudence. He explained that “it has long been established that the
    admissibility of evidence is not affected by the illegality of the means through
    which the party has been enabled to obtain the evidence.” John H. Wigmore,
    Using Evidence Obtained by Illegal Search and Seizure, 
    8 A.B.A. J. 479
    , 479
    (1922). He explained the exclusionary rule misapprehended the nature of the
    right. Id. at 482. The Fourth Amendment “implies both a civil action by the citizen
    thus disturbed and a process of criminal contempt against the offending
    officials.” Id. at 481. It was fallacious to conclude the Fourth Amendment
    required “a novel exception . . . to the fundamental principle that an illegality in
    the mode of procuring evidence is no ground for excluding it.” Id. at 482
    (emphasis omitted) (citation omitted).
    In two memorable passages, Dean Wigmore explained the exclusionary
    rule actually perverts the administration of justice. See id. at 482, 484. In the
    first passage, he explained the exclusionary rule undermines the foundations of
    justice:
    All this is misguided sentimentality. For the sake of indirectly
    and contingently protecting the Fourth Amendment, a Court
    appears indifferent to what is the direct and immediate result, viz.,
    39
    of making Justice inefficient, and of coddling the criminal classes of
    the population. It puts Supreme Courts in the position of assisting
    to undermine the foundations of the very institutions they are set
    there to protect. It regards the over-zealous officer of the law as a
    greater danger to the community than the unpunished murderer or
    embezzler or panderer.
    Id. at 482. In the second passage Wigmore explained the exclusionary rule
    commits two separate wrongs: it excuses the criminal conduct of the defendant,
    and it excuses the unlawful conduct of the offending officer.
    “Titus, you have been found guilty of conducting a lottery;
    Flavius, you have confessedly violated the constitution. Titus ought
    to suffer imprisonment for crime, and Flavius for contempt. But no!
    We shall let you both go free. We shall not punish Flavius directly,
    but shall do so by reversing Titus’ conviction. This is our way of
    teaching people like Flavius to behave, and of teaching people like
    Titus to behave, and incidentally of securing respect for the
    Constitution. Our way of upholding the Constitution is not to strike
    at the man who breaks it, but to let off somebody else who broke
    something else.”
    Id. at 484.
    Given the lack of historical or doctrinal support for the rule, the Court has
    walked back the notion that the admission of evidence obtained by way of
    unlawful search and seizure violates the Fourth Amendment. The Court has
    “emphasized repeatedly that the governments’ use of evidence obtained in
    violation of the Fourth Amendment does not itself violate the Constitution.” Pa.
    Bd. of Prob. & Parole v. Scott, 
    524 U.S. 357
    , 362 (1998). Instead, the exclusionary
    rule is a “judicial remedy to deter Fourth Amendment violations.” Utah v. Strieff,
    
    579 U.S. 232
    , 237 (2016); see Herring v. United States, 
    555 U.S. 135
    , 141 (2009)
    (“We have repeatedly rejected the argument that exclusion is a necessary
    consequence of a Fourth Amendment violation”); Scott, 
    524 U.S. at 363
     (“The
    40
    exclusionary rule is instead a judicially created means of deterring illegal
    searches and seizures.”); United States v. Calandra, 
    414 U.S. 338
    , 348 (1974)
    (“[T]he [exclusionary] rule is a judicially created remedy designed to safeguard
    Fourth Amendment rights generally through its deterrent effect, rather than a
    personal constitutional right of the party aggrieved.”).
    As a judicially created remedy and not a constitutional right in and of itself,
    the Court has decided the exclusionary “does not ‘proscribe the introduction of
    illegally seized evidence in all proceedings or against all persons.’ ” Scott, 
    524 U.S. at 363
     (quoting Stone v. Powell, 
    428 U.S. 465
    , 486 (1976)). It is inapplicable
    in habeas proceedings. Powell, 
    428 U.S. at
    493–96. It is inapplicable in federal
    civil tax proceedings. Janis, 
    428 U.S. at
    459–460. It is inapplicable in federal
    civil deportation proceedings. INS v. Lopez–Mendoza, 
    468 U.S. 1032
    , 1050–51
    (1984). It is inapplicable in parole revocation proceedings. Scott, 
    524 U.S. at 369
    .
    It is inapplicable in grand jury proceedings. Calandra, 
    414 U.S. at
    353–55. Even
    in criminal proceedings, the exclusionary rule is no longer automatic. Lange v.
    California, 
    141 S. Ct. 2011
    , 2026 (2021) (Thomas J., concurring) (“Establishing
    a violation of the Fourth Amendment, though, does not automatically entitle a
    criminal defendant to exclusion of evidence. Far from it.”). The “significant costs
    of this rule” make it applicable only where its “deterrence benefits outweigh its
    substantial social costs.” Strieff, 579 U.S. at 237–38 (quoting Hudson v.
    Michigan, 
    547 U.S. 586
    , 591 (2006)). “To trigger the exclusionary rule, police
    conduct must be sufficiently deliberate that exclusion can meaningfully deter it,
    and sufficiently culpable that such deterrence is worth the price paid by the
    41
    justice system. As laid out in [the Court’s] cases, the exclusionary rule serves to
    deter deliberate, reckless, or grossly negligent conduct, or in some circumstances
    recurring or systemic negligence.” Herring, 
    555 U.S. at 144
    .
    The officers’ conduct here is not sufficiently culpable such that the cost of
    deterrence is worth the price paid by the justice system. Here, in obtaining the
    saliva sample from the discarded straw, the officers did not trespass upon
    Burns’s person, house, papers, or effects. See Carpenter v. United States, 
    138 S. Ct. 2206
    , 2241–42 (2018) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (“[T]he obvious meaning of
    [‘their’] is that each person has the right to be secure against unreasonable
    searches and seizures in his own person, house, papers, and effects” (second
    alteration in original) (quoting Minnesota v. Carter, 
    525 U.S. 83
    , 92 (1998)
    (Scalia, J., concurring))). Further, the officers collected the straw pursuant to a
    statute authorizing the collection and use of DNA for the purposes of criminal
    investigation. See 
    Iowa Code § 729.6
    (3)(c)(2) (2019). “It is one thing for the
    criminal ‘to go free because the constable has blundered.’ It is quite another to
    set the criminal free because the constable has scrupulously adhered to
    governing law.” Davis v. United States, 
    564 U.S. 229
    , 249–50 (2011) (citation
    omitted) (quoting People v. Defore, 
    150 N.E. 585
    , 587 (N.Y. 1926)). In addition,
    the officers did not obtain “deeply revealing” information about Burns. Carpenter,
    
    138 S. Ct. at 2223
     (majority opinion). In short, there is nothing in the Fourth
    Amendment, as originally understood or under current doctrine, that requires a
    state court to exclude from evidence a relevant and reliable lab report confirming
    42
    a single, discrete fact where the investigating officers obtained the biological
    sample analyzed in the report pursuant to a state statute.
    II.
    Under the Iowa Constitution, the exclusion of relevant and reliable
    evidence as a judicially-created penalty for an unlawful search or seizure is legal
    fiction contrary to the constitutional text, constitutional design, and more than
    a century’s worth of precedents faithfully applying and implementing the same.
    The fundamental defect of the exclusionary rule, as it relates to seizures and
    searches under article I, section 8 of the Iowa Constitution, is not that it is a bad
    remedy, it is that it is no remedy at all given the nature of the constitutional right
    as expressed in the constitutional text and design as originally understood and
    implemented. See State v. Nelson, 
    300 N.W. 685
    , 688 (Iowa 1941) (explaining the
    exclusionary rule “has a strange sound” for a remedy when the constitutional
    prohibition is “viewed in the light of its origin and history”).
    A.
    In 1857, the people of this state did “ordain and establish a free and
    independent government, by the name of the State of Iowa.” Iowa Const. pmbl.
    The constituted government has almost plenary power to protect the “lives,
    limbs, health, comfort, and quiet of all persons” within its borders, to protect “all
    property within the state,” and, more generally, to promote “domestic order,
    morals, health, and safety.” State v. Schlenker, 
    84 N.W. 698
    , 699 (Iowa 1900)
    (quoting R.R. Co. v. Husen, 
    95 U.S. 465
    , 471 (1877)); see Fuller v. Chi. & N.W.R.R.
    Co., 
    31 Iowa 187
    , 209 (1871) (stating the government may act “to preserve the
    43
    peace, health, morals and property of its people, and to protect them from
    imposition and injustice”). Of course, “[t]he police power of the state . . . is
    subject to the constitution, and cannot be used as a cloak under which to
    disregard constitutional rights or restrictions.” Schlenker, 84 N.W. at 699.
    The judicial department is vested with the final authority to determine the
    meaning of the constitution. See, e.g., Junkins v. Branstad, 
    421 N.W.2d 130
    , 135
    (Iowa 1988) (en banc) (stating a constitutional “determination, notwithstanding
    the legislative definition, is for the courts”); see also Marbury v. Madison, 
    5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137
    , 177 (1803) (“It is emphatically the province and duty of the
    judicial department to say what the law is.”). In determining the meaning of the
    constitution, the judicial department is bound to interpret and apply the
    document as it was understood at the time of its enactment. See Lennette v.
    State, 
    975 N.W.2d 380
    , 403 (Iowa 2022) (McDonald, J., concurring); State v.
    
    Thompson, 954
     N.W.2d 402, 415 (Iowa 2021) (examining historical practice to
    resolve constitutional questions). “The age of the Constitution may develop
    conditions which make it desirable to amend it; until amended, it is a holy
    covenant.” Hunter v. Colfax Consol. Coal Co., 
    154 N.W. 1037
    , 1047 (Iowa 1915).
    A judge’s oath to uphold the constitution contains “neither an express nor
    implied exception that the oath shall not be binding after the Constitution has
    been in existence for a stated, or any, length of time. Unless amended, it will be
    the duty of the judges who serve a hundred years from now to obey this
    Constitution.” 
    Id.
     A judge cannot “disregard the Constitution because it was
    created in the eighteenth or nineteenth century.” 
    Id.
    44
    Nothing in the text of the Iowa Constitution, as understood at the time of
    its enactment, requires, or even supports, the exclusion of relevant and reliable
    evidence in criminal proceedings as a judicially-created penalty for an unlawful
    search and seizure. Article I, section 8 of the Iowa Constitution provides:
    The right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses,
    papers and effects, against unreasonable seizures and searches
    shall not be violated; and no warrant shall issue but on probable
    cause, supported by oath or affirmation, particularly describing the
    place to be searched, and the persons and things to be seized.
    This constitutional provision says nothing about excluding evidence from
    criminal trials. C.f. Davis, 
    564 U.S. at 236
     (“The [Fourth] Amendment says
    nothing about suppressing evidence obtained in violation of this command.”). As
    Judge Richard Posner explained with respect to the parallel Fourth Amendment,
    the Constitution does not protect “the criminal’s interest in not being punished.”
    Richard A. Posner, Rethinking the Fourth Amendment, 
    1981 Sup. Ct. Rev. 49
    , 64
    (1981) [hereinafter Posner]. “Sometimes it is argued that there is a . . . right to
    exclude, but the argument has no support in the text or history or nearly two
    centuries of judicial interpretation . . . .” Id. at 53 (footnote omitted). Quite
    simply, the textual prohibition against unreasonable searches and seizures “was
    not intended to give criminals a right to conceal evidence of their crimes.” Id.
    Doctrinally, the exclusionary rule would have been incomprehensible to
    the founders of our government. “At the time of Iowa’s founding, article I,
    section 8 could not have been understood to establish a substantive standard of
    ‘reasonableness’ that regulated the conduct of executive branch officials
    conducting seizures or searches because there was no conception that such
    45
    officials” could violate, or were even subject to, direct regulation under article I,
    section 8. Lennette, 975 N.W.2d at 411. “The modern conception that article I,
    section 8 created a substantive standard of ‘reasonableness’ governing seizures
    and searches is a prochronistic error that imposes, post hoc, principles of state
    action, agency law, and vicarious liability that run directly counter to the law at
    the time of Iowa’s founding.” Id. at 412. The founders would thus not have
    understood suppression as a remedy for an official’s violation of article I,
    section 8 because there was no conception that an official could even violate the
    constitution. See Thomas Y. Davies, Recovering the Original Fourth Amendment,
    
    98 Mich. L. Rev. 547
    , 554 (1999) [hereinafter Davies] (“Likewise, because
    unlawful acts by officers were only personal, it never occurred to the Framers to
    apply an exclusionary principle to such misconduct.”).
    If article I, section 8 did not set forth a substantive standard that directly
    regulates the conduct of government officials, then what did and does it do? As
    explained in State v. Wright, the constitutional prohibition against search and
    seizures “is little more than the affirmance of a great constitutional doctrine of
    the common law.” 961 N.W.2d at 404 (quoting 3 Joseph Story, Commentaries on
    the Constitution of the United States §§ 1894–1895, at 748 (1833)). Article I,
    section 8 secures “the right to bring nonconstitutional causes of action against
    government officials for seizures and searches conducted in violation of the law.”
    Lennette, 975 N.W.2d at 409 (collecting cases); see Amar, 107 Harv. L. Rev. at
    786 (“Tort law remedies were thus clearly the ones presupposed by the Framers
    of the Fourth Amendment and counterpart state constitutional provisions.”). It
    46
    is a constitutional “injunction against lawmakers,” and it prohibits them “from
    abrogating the preexisting common law regime of rights and remedies.” Lennette,
    975 N.W.2d at 409–10 (collecting cases).11
    More specifically, article I, section 8 prohibits lawmakers from creating for
    government officials’ special justification defenses to or immunities from
    common law suits arising out of searches and seizures. See id. at 404 (“The
    authentic historical context in which this right was codified reveals that the
    nature and scope of the right was to fix in place the common law regime of rights
    and remedies governing seizures and searches and to prohibit legislative
    abrogation of the same.”); Wright, 961 N.W.2d at 400 (“Decency, security, and
    liberty alike demand that government officials shall be subjected to the same
    rules of conduct that are commands to the citizen.” (quoting Olmstead v. United
    11See     Carpenter, 
    138 S. Ct. at 2243
     (Thomas, J., dissenting) (“[B]y prohibiting
    ‘unreasonable’ searches and seizures in the Fourth Amendment, the Founders ensured that the
    newly created Congress could not use legislation to abolish the established common-law rules of
    search and seizure.”); Adams v. New York, 
    192 U.S. 585
    , 598 (1904) (“The security intended to
    be guaranteed by the 4th Amendment against wrongful search and seizures is designed to
    prevent violations of private security in person and property and unlawful invasion of the sanctity
    of the home of the citizen by officers of the law, acting under legislative or judicial sanction, and
    to give remedy against such usurpations when attempted.”); State v. Griswold, 
    34 A. 1046
    , 1047
    (Conn. 1896) (explaining the Connecticut Constitution “forbids the legislature to enact any
    statute, and the courts from passing any rule, which would authorize any unreasonable search
    or seizure of the goods of a citizen” and stating trespassing officers “would be liable, in a proper
    action, to pay to the defendant all damage they had done him”); Williams v. State, 
    28 S.E. 624
    ,
    627–28 (Ga. 1897) (“That is to say, we believe the framers of the constitutions of the United
    States and of this and other states merely sought to provide against any attempt, by legislation
    or otherwise, to authorize, justify, or declare lawful, any unreasonable search or seizure. This
    wise restriction was intended to operate upon legislative bodies, so as to render ineffectual any
    effort to legalize by statute what the people expressly stipulated could in no event be made lawful
    . . . .”), abrogated by Mobley v. State, 
    834 S.E.2d 785
     (Ga. 2019); State v. Fuller, 
    85 P. 369
    , 373
    (Mont. 1906) (“The provision in the state and federal Constitutions is therefore a limitation upon
    the powers of the respective governments declaring all searches and seizures unlawful and
    forbidding the Legislature and the Congress to authorize them . . . and the redress for the wrong
    therein denounced is an appropriate action directly against those who have been guilty of
    trespass.”).
    47
    States, 
    277 U.S. 438
    , 485 (1928) (Brandeis, J., dissenting), overruled by Katz v.
    United States, 
    389 U.S. 347
     (1967), and Berger v. New York, 
    388 U.S. 41
     (1967)));
    see Posner, 1981 Sup. Ct. Rev. at 61 (“The Fourth Amendment was intended to
    limit the defense of legal process in tort suits against public officers or agencies
    . . . .”). As Judge Posner explained, any effort to immunize officers beyond that
    allowed at common law “would violate the Fourth Amendment, the central
    purpose of which was to ensure the availability of state remedies for
    unreasonable searches and seizures.” Id. at 69.
    The understanding that article I, section 8 is a constitutional injunction
    against lawmakers and not a direct, substantive limitation on the conduct of
    peace officers is dictated by another provision of the Iowa Constitution. Unlike
    the Federal Constitution, the Iowa Constitution explicitly sets forth its scope and
    remedy. Article XII, section 1 of the Iowa Constitution provides, “This
    Constitution shall be the supreme law of the State, and any law inconsistent
    there with, shall be void.” By its own terms, the Iowa Constitution applies only
    to   laws—whether     originating   in   the   legislative,   executive,   or   judicial
    departments—and provides as a remedy that “any law” inconsistent with the
    constitution “shall be void.” Id. It says nothing about the regulation of peace
    officer conduct. It says nothing about the exclusion of relevant and reliable
    evidence in criminal proceedings.
    Not only is the exclusionary rule not supported or invited by the state
    constitution, the exclusionary rule is contra-constitutional in numerous
    respects, two of which I will mention here. First, the exclusionary rule frames
    48
    article I, section 8 as a rule of criminal procedure contrary to the constitution’s
    design. Article I, section 8 protects “[t]he right of the people” and not merely the
    right of the criminally accused. Id. art. I, § 8. In contrast, article I, section 10
    sets forth the rights of “the accused” in “all criminal prosecutions.” Id. art. I,
    § 10. But these rights do not include the exclusion of relevant and reliable
    evidence as a judicially-created penalty for a peace officer’s breach of the law in
    conducting a search or seizure.
    Second,    the   exclusionary   rule   is   wholly   inconsistent   with   the
    constitutional criminal jury system. Citizen jurors are called to serve to decide
    the factual guilt of a criminal defendant. Modern search and seizure doctrine
    hides relevant and reliable evidence from these citizen servants, interferes with
    their accurate determination of guilt, and uses citizen jurors as mere
    instrumentalities to advance other public policy purposes unrelated to their
    service in the particular case. Lange, 141 S. Ct. at 2207 (“One cost is especially
    salient: excluding evidence under the Fourth Amendment always obstructs the
    ‘truth-finding functions of judge and jury.’ ” (quoting United States v. Leon, 
    468 U.S. 897
    , 907 (1984))); Todd E. Pettys, Instrumentalizing Jurors: An Argument
    Against the Fourth Amendment Exclusionary Rule, 
    37 Fordham Urb. L.J. 837
    ,
    871–72 (2010). The judiciary’s intentional deception of and instrumentalization
    of citizen jurors is fundamentally contra-constitutional and wrongheaded. The
    exclusionary rule subverts the very foundation of the constitution that courts
    are supposed to protect.
    49
    B.
    The preceding interpretation of article I, section 8 of the Iowa Constitution
    is not novel; it is supported by “the contemporaneously expressed understanding
    of ratified text.” Amy Coney Barrett, Originalism and Stare Decisis, 
    92 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1921
    , 1924 (2017). “By the time the citizens of Iowa ratified the
    Iowa Constitution in 1857, it was well established throughout the country” that
    the legality of searches and seizures were nonconstitutional civil matters in
    which government officials could assert a defense of justification in response to
    a tort claim. Lennette, 975 N.W.2d at 405–06 (collecting cases). “Iowa’s earliest
    precedents were in accord with the national consensus. Iowa law allowed
    ‘traditional common law tort claims, such as trespass, conversion, malicious
    prosecution, and abuse of process’ to be asserted against government officials.”
    Id. at 405–08 (quoting Godfrey v. State, 
    898 N.W.2d 844
    , 887 (Iowa 2017)
    (Mansfield, J., dissenting)) (collecting cases). A peace officer’s means and
    methods of search and seizure were not of constitutional concern. See, e.g.,
    State v. Ward, 
    36 N.W. 765
    , 767 (Iowa 1888) (rejecting constitutional argument
    despite recognizing that the “officer in this case may have been guilty of a
    trespass”).
    This court thus explicitly considered and rejected the exclusionary rule for
    more than a century after Iowa’s founding. See State ex rel. Hanrahan v. Miller,
    
    98 N.W.2d 859
    , 860–61 (Iowa 1959); State v. Smith, 
    73 N.W.2d 189
    , 190 (Iowa
    1955); State ex rel. Kuble v. Bisignano, 
    28 N.W.2d 504
    , 507–08 (Iowa 1947);
    State v. Bradley, 
    3 N.W.2d 133
    , 134–35 (Iowa 1942); State v. Gillam, 
    300 N.W. 50
    567, 568 (Iowa 1941); State v. Rowley, 
    248 N.W. 340
    , 342–43 (Iowa 1933);
    State v. Bourgeois, 
    229 N.W. 231
    , 232 (Iowa 1930); State v. Rollinger, 
    225 N.W. 841
    , 841 (Iowa 1929); State v. Bamsey, 
    223 N.W. 873
    , 874 (Iowa 1929); State v.
    Lambertti, 
    215 N.W. 752
    , 753 (Iowa 1927); State v. Korth, 
    215 N.W. 706
    , 707
    (Iowa 1927); State v. Wenks, 
    202 N.W. 753
    , 753 (Iowa 1925); McNamara v.
    Utterback, 
    200 N.W. 699
    , 700 (Iowa 1924); Lucia v. Utterback, 
    198 N.W. 626
    , 628
    (Iowa 1924); State v. Rowley, 
    195 N.W. 881
    , 881–82 (Iowa 1923); Foley v.
    Utterback, 
    195 N.W. 721
    , 722 (Iowa 1923) (per curiam); Joyner v. Utterback, 
    195 N.W. 594
    , 596 (Iowa 1923). The rejection of the exclusionary rule did “not detract
    one iota from the full protection vouchsafed to the citizen by the constitutional
    provisions . . . [because a] trespassing officer [was] liable for all wrong done in
    an illegal search or seizure.” State v. Tonn, 
    191 N.W. 530
    , 535 (Iowa 1923),
    abrogated by State v. Hagen, 
    137 N.W.2d 895
     (Iowa 1965).
    C.
    Contrary to the text of the constitution and the original precedents
    interpreting the same, this court ultimately adopted the exclusionary rule as a
    remedy for purported violations of article I, section 8 of the Iowa Constitution.
    See Hagen, 
    137 N.W.2d at 900
    . However, this court did so on belief that it was
    “compelled to do so by the United States Supreme Court’s decision in Mapp.”
    State v. Cline, 
    617 N.W.2d 277
    , 286–87 (Iowa 2000) (en banc), abrogated on other
    grounds by State v. Turner, 
    630 N.W.2d 601
     (Iowa 2001). The “conclusion that
    Mapp required this court to adopt the exclusionary rule as a remedy for a
    51
    violation of state constitutional law was incorrect.” State v. Brown, 
    930 N.W.2d 840
    , 862 (Iowa 2019) (McDonald, J., concurring specially).
    While this court mistakenly believed that Mapp required states to adopt
    the exclusionary rule with respect to parallel provisions of their respective
    constitutions, the mistake was understandable. The Supreme Court was rapidly
    changing federal constitutional law and applying it to the states under the
    Fourteenth Amendment incorporation doctrine. See Henry J. Friendly, The Bill
    of Rights as a Code of Criminal Procedure, 
    53 Cal. L. Rev. 929
    , 930 (1965)
    (“[A]lthough the Court has been inspired by the highest of motives, it ought to
    realize there is danger in moving too far too fast . . . .”). At the time, there was a
    belief that the Federal Constitution set the floor with respect to parallel
    provisions of state constitutions. In particular, as relevant here, there was a
    belief that states were required to adopt the exclusionary rule as a remedy for
    purported violations of their respective state constitutional search and seizure
    provisions. See, e.g., State v. Lindquist, 
    869 N.W.2d 863
    , 874 (Minn. 2015) (“The
    exclusionary rule has no basis in the U.S. and Minnesota Constitutions.
    Moreover, the exclusionary rule was wholly unknown as a remedy for
    unreasonable searches and seizures when our state constitution came into force
    in 1858, and was not adopted in Minnesota for over a century until the Supreme
    Court    mandated     its   application   to    the    states.”    (citations    omitted));
    Commonwealth v.      Russo,    
    934 A.2d 1199
    ,   1207       (Pa.   2007)   (“Indeed,
    notwithstanding that the federal exclusionary rule had been in existence since
    the 1914 decision in Weeks, this Court . . . repeatedly refused to find a similar
    52
    remedy encompassed in Article I, Section 8. . . . The exclusionary rule itself,
    then, was not an organic part of Article I, Section 8; it was a federal imposition,
    made applicable against the states for Fourth Amendment purposes by Mapp v.
    Ohio.” (citations omitted)).
    Subsequent research and reflection have shown this floor-ceiling
    metaphor to be incorrect. “Incorporation did not change the substantive content
    of state constitutional law; it changed the substantive content of federal
    constitutional law.” Brown, 
    930 N.W.2d at 858
    . “The Supreme Court’s
    Fourteenth Amendment jurisprudence does not dictate the substance of the
    state law or the remedy for any violation of the same.” 
    Id.
     State courts were not
    compelled and are not compelled to continue to adhere to the federal
    exclusionary rule in interpreting a parallel provision of their respective state
    constitutions. See Collins, 
    138 S. Ct. at
    1680 n.6 (“[T]he States are free to adopt
    their own exclusionary rules as a matter of state law. But nothing in the Federal
    Constitution requires them to do so.”); see, e.g., People v. Lance W. (In re Lance
    W.), 
    694 P.2d 744
    , 752–53 (Cal. 1985) (en banc) (recognizing proposition repealed
    exclusionary rule for violations of California’s constitutional prohibition against
    unreasonable searches and seizures). The states can “permissibly conclude that
    the benefits of excluding relevant evidence of criminal activity do not outweigh
    the costs when the police conduct at issue does not violate federal law.”
    California v. Greenwood, 
    486 U.S. 35
    , 44–45 (1988). States are thus allowed to
    “eliminate the exclusionary rule as a remedy for violations” of state law. 
    Id. at 44
    .
    53
    D.
    Given the more recent research in this area and the understanding that
    this court is not bound to follow federal precedents interpreting the Fourth
    Amendment, this court should reconsider the state exclusionary rule under
    article I, section 8 of the Iowa Constitution in the appropriate case. See
    William J. Stuntz, The Political Constitution of Criminal Justice, 
    119 Harv. L. Rev. 780
    , 832 (2006) (“[T]he best thing to do with the massive body of Fourth
    Amendment privacy regulation, together with the equally massive body of law on
    the scope and limits of the exclusionary rule, is to wipe it off the books. Let states
    experiment with different regulatory regimes.”). “[S]tare decisis does not prevent
    the court from reconsidering, repairing, correcting or abandoning past judicial
    announcements when error is manifest . . . .” Garrison v. New Fashion Pork LLP,
    
    977 N.W.2d 67
    , 83 (Iowa 2022) (alteration and omission in original) (quoting
    McElroy v. State, 
    703 N.W.2d 385
    , 395 (Iowa 2005)). Error is manifest here. By
    ignoring the text of the constitution as it was understood at the time of its
    enactment and by ignoring the one hundred years of original precedents
    interpreting the same, modern search and seizure doctrine, including the
    exclusionary rule, has risen “into the thin atmosphere of sheer fiction.” Robert H.
    Jackson, The Struggle for Judicial Supremacy: A Study of a Crisis in American
    Power Politics 292 (1941).
    The nonfiction is the state constitution is silent on many matters. The Iowa
    Constitution creates a government. It sets forth the core powers of the
    government, divides the powers of the government among different departments,
    54
    and sets forth the outer bounds of the government’s powers. It necessarily
    speaks in broad terms. It is inconceivable that the founders of our government
    believed the great charter of government directly regulated the conduct of every
    petty officer in every county, city, town, and village across the state and made
    every action of every government employee into a constitutional question. C.f.
    Davies, 98 Mich. L. Rev. at 663 (“Even so, there is no reason to think the Framers
    perceived an ordinary officer’s misconduct to be a form of governmental action.
    Thus, they had neither a motive nor a basis for addressing the conduct of
    ordinary officers in constitutional provisions.”). Indeed, this court explicitly
    rejected that interpretation of the constitution for more than a century after
    Iowa’s founding despite repeated entreaties.
    In accord with the text of the constitution and the original precedents
    interpreting and applying the same, we must admit the state constitution, as
    originally understood, has nothing intelligible to say about the minutiae of peace
    officer conduct and the admissibility of evidence in criminal proceedings
    depending upon how the peace officer obtained the evidence. How long can a
    roadside detention last? Can an officer manipulate a packet of foil in someone’s
    pocket during a stop and frisk? Can the police collect discarded DNA for the
    purpose of determining identity? The constitution is silent on these questions.
    The contrary conclusion invites judges to write their own personal predilections
    and normative judgments into the constitution as caselaw. But that is not
    constitutional law; it is a legal fiction, and a dangerous one at that.
    55
    Because the exclusionary rule “is not constitutionally required, . . . [we]
    must rescind the exclusionary rule and leave it to the policy-making branches of
    government to develop policies to deter future police misconduct.” Eugene
    Milhizer, The Exclusionary Rule Lottery, 
    39 U. Tol. L. Rev. 755
    , 767 (2008).
    Rescinding the exclusionary rule would afford the appropriate
    authorities the chance to fashion public policy based on moral
    values informed by practical experience. . . . It would unburden
    society from the consequences of an immoral and unwise rule,
    imposed by an illegitimate authority, designed to minimize one evil
    by threatening a different and often greater evil. We can and should
    do better than the current version of the exclusionary rule, and we
    would all be better for it if we did.
    
    Id.
     at 767–68.
    III.
    I join in full the court’s well-reasoned opinion. For the reasons set forth in
    the court’s opinion and the reasons set forth in this separate opinion, I conclude
    the defendant’s conviction should be affirmed.
    56
    #20–1150, State v. Burns
    OXLEY, Justice (dissenting).
    I cannot join the majority’s Fourth Amendment analysis, which
    simplistically concludes that because Burns left behind his straw in a Pizza
    Ranch, he abandoned the information contained in his DNA embedded in the
    saliva left on the straw. Justice McDermott convincingly explains the problems
    with the majority’s abandonment theory in parts II.A and II.B of his dissent. I
    agree with his analysis and repeat only his conclusions. First, extraction of
    information from DNA is a distinct act12 from collecting the straw on which the
    DNA is left and must be analyzed separately. Second, the abandonment doctrine
    does not apply to DNA involuntarily and unavoidably shed in everyday life. And
    as Justice McDermott explains in part II.C, the majority’s attempt to minimize
    the consequences of its reasoning is internally inconsistent. If abandonment of
    the straw means abandonment of the DNA—and the information contained in
    the DNA—then it matters not what the police do with any information extracted
    from that DNA.
    Concluding that the DNA on the straw was not abandoned, however, only
    opens the inquiry. We must still apply United States Supreme Court precedent
    to determine whether the officers’ processing of Burns’s DNA was a search in the
    constitutional sense, and therefore entitled to Fourth Amendment protection. On
    12Justice   McDermott calls the DNA analysis a distinct “search.” Where the DNA was not
    taken directly from Burns in the traditional sense of a search, whether the DNA analysis is a
    “search” is yet to be determined. It is, however, a distinct act from collecting the discarded straw,
    and with that qualification, I otherwise agree with Justice McDermott’s analysis in parts II.A and
    II.B.
    57
    this issue, although I ultimately arrive at the same conclusion, I part ways with
    Justice McDermott’s analysis in part I.B of his dissent. Under my interpretation
    of current Supreme Court precedent, Justice McDermott’s attempt to categorize
    DNA as a “person” or “paper” so as to make its analysis a constitutional search
    is an unnecessary effort to fit a square peg into a round hole.
    I believe Carpenter v. United States, 
    138 S. Ct. 2206 (2018)
    , controls the
    Fourth Amendment analysis in this case. In Carpenter, the United States
    Supreme Court recognized that Katz v. United States, 
    389 U.S. 347
     (1967),
    “expanded our conception of the [Fourth] Amendment to protect certain
    expectations of privacy as well” as the traditional property rights enumerated in
    the Amendment’s text—“persons, houses, papers, and effects.” Carpenter,
    
    138 S. Ct. at 2213
     (emphasis added) (quoting U.S. Const. amend. IV). Under that
    expanded view, the Fourth Amendment’s protection applies essentially to
    anything (“something,” in the Court’s words) as long as someone “ ‘seeks to
    preserve [it] as private,’ and his expectation of privacy is ‘one that society is
    prepared to recognize as reasonable.’ ” 
    Id.
     (quoting Smith v. Maryland, 
    442 U.S. 735
    , 740 (1979)). If it is, “official intrusion into that private sphere generally
    qualifies as a search.” 
    Id.
     (emphasis added); see also Wong Sun v. United States,
    
    371 U.S. 471
    , 485 (1963) (“It follows from our holding in Silverman v. United
    States, [
    365 U.S. 505
     (1961)], that the Fourth Amendment may protect against
    the overhearing of verbal statements as well as against the more traditional
    seizure of ‘papers and effects.’ ”).
    58
    Indeed, that the Katz test applies beyond the Fourth Amendment’s textual
    limitation to “persons, houses, papers, and effects” is fully illustrated by
    Carpenter itself. There, the “something” at issue was “digital data,” more
    specifically, “cell-site location information,” or CSLI, about the person’s physical
    movements, that was actually collected and owned by a third-party cellular
    service provider based on the person’s use of a cell phone. Carpenter, 138 S. Ct.
    at 2211–12, 2214. Even though the information was actually owned by a third
    party and was merely about the person, the Supreme Court made no attempt to
    determine whether that information was that individual’s person, house, paper,
    or effect. See id. at 2216–20. In doing so, the Supreme Court unmoored an
    individual’s Fourth Amendment protections against unreasonable searches from
    the textual limitations in the Amendment. See id. at 2224 (Kennedy, J.,
    dissenting) (“In concluding that the Government engaged in a search, the Court
    unhinges Fourth Amendment doctrine from the property-based concepts that
    have long grounded the analytic framework that pertains in these cases.”).
    Agree with that underlying premise or not, that is the precedent from the
    Supreme Court that should guide our analysis of Burns’s Fourth Amendment
    challenge. The majority is correct that the Supreme Court described its decision
    as “a narrow one.” Id. at 2220 (majority opinion). That means we should tread
    carefully in applying it, but it does not mean we can ignore it. Under Katz and
    Carpenter, we should be asking: (1) is the information contained in Burns’s DNA
    something he sought to protect as private? And (2) is Burns’s expectation of
    privacy in the information gathered from his DNA and used by officers an
    59
    expectation that society is prepared to recognize as reasonable? I agree with
    Justice McDermott that surreptitious collection of DNA is analogous to the third-
    party collection of the CSLI in Carpenter. But that only addresses the first part
    of the Katz-Carpenter test—whether Burns’s DNA was something he sought to
    protect as private. We still must decide whether Burns’s expectation is one
    society would recognize as reasonable.
    As to the second part: The State argues, and the majority agrees, that
    using DNA to gather only identification information isn’t really that invasive, as
    many courts have concluded. See, e.g., People v. Mendez, 
    155 N.Y.S.3d 534
    ,
    536–37 (Sup. Ct. 2021) (“[T]he extraction and analysis of DNA for the sole
    purpose of developing a profile is not, like the cell-cite location information at
    issue [in Carpenter], ‘deeply revealing’ or of substantial ‘depth, breadth, and
    comprehensive reach,’ since the genetic information obtainable from DNA that is
    deeply revealing and comprehensive is neither sought nor revealed in the
    process.”). If we glean from Carpenter that the important distinction is the extent
    of information gathered, one could argue, as the People v. Mendez court found,
    that the limited use of DNA to only gather identifying information is minimal as
    compared to the extensive amount of information that could have been obtained
    from the DNA, a point the Supreme Court relied on in Maryland v. King to hold
    that analysis of an individual’s DNA for identification purposes was not an
    unconstitutional search. 
    569 U.S. 435
    , 464 (2013) (“In addition the processing
    of respondent’s DNA sample’s 13 CODIS loci did not intrude on respondent’s
    privacy in a way that would make his DNA identification unconstitutional.”). But
    60
    that comparison is incomplete when King is considered more closely, and indeed,
    in light of Carpenter, is the wrong comparison.
    To begin with, comparing the limited identification information actually
    collected to the wealth of information available, but not taken, from Burns’s DNA
    is not the right comparison. Remember, we are determining whether the officers’
    actions—processing the DNA to collect unique identification information to use
    in a criminal investigation—violated an expectation of privacy society is prepared
    to recognize as reasonable. If we were assessing only whether police conduct was
    reasonable here, it is certainly important that officers only requested a report on
    whether Burns’s DNA matched the blood sample from the crime scene—they did
    not request, or even receive, anything else. But in assessing whether individuals
    have a reasonable expectation that their DNA will remain private and not be
    tested without their consent or without a warrant, we should not blind ourselves
    to the vast scope of information police can gain access to when they “peek behind
    the curtain” of DNA.13 Allowing the police’s conduct to limit the scope of the
    allegedly protected privacy interest turns the Fourth Amendment analysis on its
    head.14 See Carpenter, 
    138 S. Ct. at
    2215 n.2 (“Justice Kennedy argues that this
    13As amici American Civil Liberties Union and Electronic Frontier Foundation set out in
    their brief, that scope “includ[es] our propensities for certain medical conditions, such as
    Alzheimer’s, cystic fibrosis, breast cancer, and addiction; our ancestry; and our biological familial
    relationships, which can reveal previously unknown parentage, among other things.”
    14If police invade the curtilage of a home, is it any less an invasion of an expectation of
    privacy in that curtilage if the police justify the act by saying they only wanted to get a better
    look into the open window that anyone passing by on the street could have looked through? Cf.
    King, 
    569 U.S. at 469
     (Scalia, J., dissenting) (“And could the police engage, without any suspicion
    of wrongdoing, in a ‘brief and . . . minimal’ intrusion into the home of an arrestee—perhaps just
    peeking around the curtilage a bit? Obviously not.” (alteration in original) (citation omitted)).
    61
    case is in a different category from Jones and the dragnet-type practices posited
    in Knotts because the disclosure of the cell-site records was subject to ‘judicial
    authorization.’ That line of argument conflates the threshold question whether a
    ‘search’ has occurred with the separate matter of whether the search was
    reasonable. The subpoena process set forth in the Stored Communications Act
    does not determine a target’s expectation of privacy.” (citation omitted)). Rather,
    we should first determine whether an expectation of privacy exists here and, if
    so, what it looks like, before we ask whether police “intrusion into that private
    sphere” qualifies as a search. Id. at 2213 (emphasis added).
    For example, in Carpenter, it was not just that officials learned information
    from the third-party service provider about the individual’s movements. Rather,
    the Court focused on the individual’s “expectation of privacy in the record of his
    physical movements” over an extended period of time to determine whether the
    officers’ use of the information was in fact a search. Id. at 2217. The Court thus
    began with the premise “that individuals have a reasonable expectation of
    privacy in the whole of their physical movements,” before proceeding to
    determine whether “[a]llowing government access to cell-site records contravenes
    that expectation.” Id. Only in then determining if the officers’ use of the CSLI
    records “impinge[d] on expectations of privacy” did the Court analyze the extent
    of information gathered and the officers’ use of that information. Id. at 2215,
    2217–19 (quoting United States v. Jones, 
    565 U.S. 400
    , 430 (Alito, J., concurring
    in judgment) (2012)). To that end, the Carpenter Court compared United States
    v. Knotts, 
    460 U.S. 276
     (1983), where it had concluded that intermittent tracking
    62
    of a planted beeper did not violate expectations of privacy because the travelling
    public can expect to be followed, with United States v. Jones, 
    565 U.S. 400
    , where
    five members of the Court agreed that “longer term GPS monitoring in
    investigations of most offenses impinges on expectations of privacy,” regardless
    of whether those movements were disclosed to the public at large. Carpenter,
    
    138 S. Ct. at
    2215–17 (quoting Jones, 
    565 U.S. at 430
     (Alito, J., concurring in
    judgment)) (citing Jones, 
    565 U.S. at 415
     (Sotomayor, J., concurring)). From
    these cases, the Court concluded that use of the CSLI to track virtually all of
    Carpenter’s physical movements over a period of seven days “invaded
    Carpenter’s reasonable expectation of privacy.” 
    Id.
     at 2217–19. Therefore, only
    once we’ve determined whether an expectation of privacy exists here and what it
    looks like should we then look to the information received from Burns’s DNA and
    how officers used it to analyze whether that use violated any reasonable
    expectation of privacy. At this threshold step, King is not only instructive, but,
    in my view, controlling.
    The question in King was whether a Maryland statute, which allowed
    officers to collect DNA from arrestees of certain serious offenses to put into the
    CODIS database,15 violated the Fourth Amendment where the DNA collection
    was unrelated to the charge of arrest and the arrestee had only been charged,
    not convicted. 
    569 U.S. at
    443–46. The King majority went out of its way to first
    15“CODIS   is the acronym for the Combined DNA Index System and is the generic term
    used to describe the FBI’s program of support for criminal justice DNA databases as well as the
    software used to run these databases.” Fed. Bureau of Investigation, Frequently Asked Questions
    on CODIS and NDIS, https://www.fbi.gov/how-we-can-help-you/dna-fingerprint-act-of-
    2005-expungement-policy/codis-and-ndis-fact-sheet [https://perma.cc/JHR2-2ABE].
    63
    distinguish the lessened privacy expectations for an arrestee, explaining that
    while the
    Court has insisted on some purpose other than “to detect evidence
    of ordinary criminal wrongdoing” to justify these searches [of
    members of the general public] in the absence of individualized
    suspicion[,] . . . [o]nce an individual has been arrested on probable
    cause for a dangerous offense that may require detention before
    trial, however, his or her expectations of privacy and freedom from
    police scrutiny are reduced.
    
    Id.
     at 462–63 (citation omitted) (quoting City of Indianapolis v. Edmund, 
    531 U.S. 32
    , 38 (2000)) (noting that “special needs” were required to justify searching an
    average citizen in cases like Chandler v. Miller, 
    520 U.S. 305
    , 314 (1997),
    involving drug testing of a political candidate, and Indianapolis v. Edmond,
    
    531 U.S. at
    40–41, 47–48, involving police stops at a checkpoint). Yet even then,
    the Court still identified a noncriminal-investigation purpose for collecting and
    analyzing the arrestee’s DNA. The Court concluded that “the context of a valid
    arrest supported by probable cause . . . gives rise to significant state interests in
    identifying respondent not only so that the proper name can be attached to his
    charges but also so that the criminal justice system can make informed decisions
    concerning pretrial custody.” Id. at 465. In other words, the majority said
    gathering DNA following an arrest was important to ensure that the officers knew
    who they had arrested for booking purposes and could accurately check his
    criminal history so they knew if he was dangerous for purposes of housing him
    in jail while he awaited trial.
    Whether that justification is convincing or not (Justice Scalia certainly
    found it not to be, see id. at 466 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (“The Court’s assertion
    64
    that DNA is being taken, not to solve crimes, but to identify those in the State’s
    custody, taxes the credulity of the credulous.”)), the relevant lesson from King is
    that even the majority recognized that the Fourth Amendment protects against
    a person’s DNA being used to match that person to a general criminal
    investigation; the DNA analysis there was permissible only because it was being
    used for identification purposes in the booking process of an arrestee. See id. at
    449, 460–63 (majority opinion). If an arrestee—whose expectations of privacy are
    already diminished—is still protected against use of identification information
    from his DNA for general criminal investigation purposes unrelated to the offense
    of his arrest, how can we say an unsuspecting member of the general public is
    not? The lengths to which the King majority went to justify using the arrestee’s
    DNA for a purpose other than criminal investigation solidifies this point. The
    expectation that police will not warrantlessly analyze an individual’s DNA is one
    that society is prepared to recognize as reasonable—at least where, as here, that
    person does not have a diminished expectation of privacy from already being in
    police custody.
    Now we must analyze whether the actual intrusion police made into
    Burns’s expectation of privacy here was constitutionally significant. Again, King
    is controlling. Analyzing King’s DNA was constitutionally sound only because
    police had a noncriminal-investigation use for the DNA—identifying him for
    booking purposes and determining whether he might be dangerous while
    detaining him by ensuring the officers knew his criminal history. See id. at 450–
    53. Here, even though officers only received relatively minimal information from
    65
    the lab report about Burns, it is the specific information they received that
    matters. And here, the DNA information they received revealed that Burns was
    a match to the major contributor of DNA in the Martinko investigation16—critical
    information they could not have otherwise obtained. When police used
    sophisticated technology to obtain unique identifying information from Burns’s
    DNA to compare it to the unidentified blood left in Martinko’s car all those years
    ago, Carpenter, read in light of King, says they intruded into Burns’s private
    sphere, making that a search under the Fourth Amendment that required a
    warrant. Cf. Carpenter, 138 S. Ct. at 2213 (“[O]fficial intrusion into that private
    sphere [(i.e., intrusion upon a reasonable expectation of privacy)] generally
    qualifies as a search and requires a warrant supported by probable cause.”).
    Indeed, once you strip away the technological aspects of this action, not
    only does it begin to look like what we would traditionally classify as a “search”
    (e.g., reading through someone’s “papers” to determine where they were and
    what they did on a specific date), but it in fact looks like precisely the type of
    generalized, suspicionless search that the Framers sought to guard against. If
    the Fourth Amendment has nothing to say on this matter, there is no reason
    police could not have done the same thing to everyone in the Pizza Ranch, or
    16The  majority is correct that the lab report confirmed only that Burns’s DNA revealed
    that he was male and “could NOT be eliminated as the major contributor to the DNA profile
    previously developed from” the Martinko crime scene. But the officer’s affidavit to support the
    subsequent search warrant for a buccal swab from Burns to create a complete DNA profile
    explained that the officer “spoke with the analyst who explained that this finding mean[t] that
    the DNA collected from a drinking straw used by Jerry Burns was found [to] be a match for our
    suspect sample by the DCI Crime Lab.” So the “could NOT be eliminated” language from the lab
    report is not as innocuous as it might appear.
    66
    everyone who lived in Cedar Rapids in 1979, or everyone, period. As Justice
    McDermott states in his dissent, “If we have no legitimate expectation of privacy
    in the ‘bread-crumb trail of identifying DNA matter’ we leave behind, ‘what
    possible impediment can there be to having the government collect what we leave
    behind, extract its DNA signature and enhance CODIS’ . . . ‘to include
    everyone?’ ” (Quoting United States v. Kincade, 
    379 F.3d 813
    , 873 (9th Cir. 2004)
    (Kozinski, J., dissenting).) The lengths to which the majority in King went to find
    a justification for collecting King’s DNA reveals otherwise.
    That is not to say DNA is off-limits to police investigations. The warrant
    application affidavit ultimately used to properly obtain Burns’s DNA reveals the
    impressive techniques officers used to crack this cold case. Through genealogy
    databases and cooperating individuals identified through that process, officers
    narrowed the suspects down to Burns and his two brothers. The problem arose
    when officers searched Burns’s DNA without a warrant.
    While my underlying analysis differs from Justice McDermott’s in part I.B
    of his dissent, rather than reiterate the additional points he persuasively makes,
    I join the remainder of his opinion.
    67
    #20–1150, State v. Burns
    McDERMOTT, Justice (dissenting).
    The majority’s holding hinges on the idea that the drinking straw and the
    DNA specimen on it were “abandoned property,” and since people have no
    reasonable   expectation   of privacy in abandoned       property, the    Fourth
    Amendment is not even implicated here. But to call microscopic strands of DNA
    in human cells that we involuntarily leave wherever we go “abandoned” doesn’t
    fit either a common or legal conception. The majority’s attempt to buttress its
    holding with a false analogy between fingerprints and DNA, and an empty
    limitation that permits DNA analysis only for identification purposes, serves to
    highlight—not    abate—the   majority    opinion’s   weaknesses.   Because   the
    warrantless search of the DNA specimen in this case violated Jerry Burns’s
    Fourth Amendment protections against unreasonable searches and seizures, I
    respectfully dissent.
    I. The Constitution.
    A. Text and Technology.
    The Fourth Amendment to the United States Constitution doesn’t lay down
    an aspiration or suggestion. It embodies a protection as powerful and firmly-held
    as any other in the Bill of Rights. The limitations that it imposes on the
    government, informed by the Framers’ lived history of abuse and subjection
    under a system of general warrants and writs of assistance, are “not mere
    second-class rights but belong in the catalog of indispensable freedoms.”
    Brinegar v. United States, 
    338 U.S. 160
    , 180 (1949) (Jackson, J., dissenting).
    68
    Contempt for unrestrained searches for evidence of criminal activity was “one of
    the driving forces” that sparked the American Revolution itself. Riley v.
    California, 
    573 U.S. 373
    , 403 (2014). As Justice Robert Jackson warned, “Among
    deprivations of rights, none is so effective in cowing a population, crushing the
    spirit of the individual and putting terror in every heart. Uncontrolled search and
    seizure is one of the first and most effective weapons in the arsenal of every
    arbitrary government.” Brinegar, 338 U.S. at 180.
    The Fourth Amendment states in relevant part that “[t]he right of the
    people to be secure in their persons, houses, papers, and effects, against
    unreasonable searches and seizures, shall not be violated, and no Warrants shall
    issue, but upon probable cause.” U.S. Const. amend. IV. The amendment
    presents one long sentence with two parts. The text of the first part divides into
    four questions: (1) Is the subject of the alleged intrusion a person, house, paper,
    or effect? (2) If so, was it searched or seized? (3) If so, was it the defendant’s
    (“their”) person, house, paper, or effect? (4) If so, was the search or seizure
    unreasonable? Orin S. Kerr, Katz as Originalism, 
    71 Duke L.J. 1047
    , 1052 (2022)
    [hereinafter Kerr, Katz as Originalism].
    The parties do not parse the text of the Fourth Amendment but focus
    instead on the familiar “reasonable expectation of privacy” test that derives from
    Justice Harlan’s concurring opinion in Katz v. United States, 
    389 U.S. 347
    , 360–
    61 (1967) (Harlan, J., concurring). Under the Katz test, the government action is
    a search if it violates an actual (subjective) expectation of privacy and society is
    prepared to recognize that expectation as objectively reasonable. 
    Id. at 361
    . The
    69
    United States Supreme Court, in the decades since Katz, has often used this
    two-step test to determine whether a Fourth Amendment search has occurred.
    See, e.g., Carpenter v. United States, 
    138 S. Ct. 2206
    , 2213 (2018); Smith v.
    Maryland, 
    442 U.S. 735
    , 740 (1979). The Katz test has been described “as a
    means of identifying modern equivalents to the physical-entry invasions that
    occurred in 1791,” and thus a way “to ensure technology-neutrality in the Fourth
    Amendment’s coverage of what is a search.” Kerr, Katz as Originalism, 71 Duke
    L.J. at 1050.
    The majority finds that Burns fails both parts of the Katz test. First, the
    majority finds that Burns made no effort to preserve the drinking straw or the
    DNA on it, and thus “could hardly have retained any subjective expectation of
    privacy in the straw.” Second, even if Burns had a subjective expectation of
    privacy in the straw or his DNA specimen, the majority finds that it wasn’t a
    reasonable expectation because he abandoned the straw and the law generally
    permits no reasonable expectation of privacy in abandoned property.
    In analyzing these issues, we must distinguish between the drinking straw
    and the DNA specimen on the straw. A straw, of course, is a hollow tube (typically
    plastic) commonly provided to diners to facilitate drinking. A DNA specimen,
    conversely, is a molecule found within the nucleus of a cell that carries the
    genetic instructions for a particular person’s entire biological development and
    function. A straw and a DNA specimen are capable of physical separation—a fact
    made obvious in this case by the DNA specimen’s extraction from the straw for
    analysis. The straw itself was of no investigatory use separate from Burns’s DNA
    70
    specimen. Thus the pertinent questions in this case surround whether the DNA
    specimen, not the straw, was protected from a warrantless search.
    Burns raises his unlawful-search challenge under both the Fourth
    Amendment to the United States Constitution and article I, section 8 of the Iowa
    Constitution. We independently interpret Iowa constitutional provisions even
    when the Federal Constitution contains nearly identical language. State v.
    Wright, 
    961 N.W.2d 396
    , 402–03 (Iowa 2021). Because Burns’s challenge under
    the Federal Constitution resolves this appeal, I focus only on the Fourth
    Amendment claim and forego separate analysis under the Iowa Constitution.
    B. Analysis of the Text.
    Whether an expectation of privacy is one that “society is prepared to
    recognize as ‘reasonable,’ ” as the Katz test asks, necessarily brings us back to
    the Fourth Amendment’s text. 
    389 U.S. at 361
    . The protection only applies to a
    “person,” “house,” “paper,” or “effect” under the Fourth Amendment. U.S. Const.
    amend. IV. Which of these categories, if any, does a DNA specimen fall under?
    No Supreme Court case to date directly addresses this question.
    But we know that these categories must bear the same meaning—to have
    all the same dimensions and coverage—that they had when the Fourth
    Amendment was enacted. Kyllo v. United States, 
    533 U.S. 27
    , 34 (2001) (per
    Scalia, J.). We’re required, in other words, to apply the Constitution to current
    circumstances even when, as in this case, technological change presents a
    circumstance that people living when the Fourth Amendment was enacted
    71
    wouldn’t fathom.17 Interpreting the words in this way “assure[] preservation of
    that degree of privacy against government that existed when the Fourth
    Amendment was adopted.” Carpenter, 138 S. Ct. at 2214 (alteration in original)
    (quoting Kyllo, 
    533 U.S. at 34
    ). As originalist scholar William Baude explains:
    At a most basic level, it does not take any fancy theoretical footwork
    to see that fixed texts can harness what seem to be changing
    meanings. Though the text may have originally been expected to
    apply in a particular way to a particular circumstance, that does not
    mean that its original meaning always must apply in the same way.
    Similarly, originalists can sensibly apply legal texts to
    circumstances unforeseeable at the time of enactment. This is
    because a word can have a fixed abstract meaning even if the specific
    facts that meaning points to change over time.
    William Baude, Is Originalism Our Law?, 
    115 Colum. L. Rev. 2349
    , 2356 (2015).
    To give an example, the noun “shields” could encompass a meaning that includes
    both a medieval piece of personal armor, or a futuristic technology that protects
    a starship. In searching for meaning, we focus on the function and not any
    particular form.
    1. “Person.” Human genetic material created by and within a person—
    matter that, though microscopic, once formed a body part—certainly bears
    strong connection to a “person.” Each of us has a meter of DNA “packed into
    every cell, and so many cells that if you formed all the DNA in your body into a
    single strand, it would stretch ten billion miles, to beyond Pluto. Think of it: there
    17DNA   was still scores of years from its discovery when the Bill of Rights was ratified.
    Even as late as the 1930s, the idea that you could pluck a gene and the DNA that composed it
    “from your body and take it away for study was as absurd to many [scientists] as the idea that
    scientists today might capture a stray thought and examine it under a microscope.” Bill Bryson,
    A Short History of Nearly Everything 402 (2003).
    72
    is enough of you to leave the solar system. You are in the most literal sense
    cosmic.” Bill Bryson, The Body 5 (2019) [hereinafter Bryson, The Body].
    The Supreme Court’s treatment of blood in its cases is illuminating. In
    Birchfield v. North Dakota, the Court determined that using a person’s breath for
    a warrantless alcohol test in a drunk driving investigation didn’t violate the
    Fourth Amendment. 
    579 U.S. 438
    , 479–79 (2016). Testing exhaled air for its
    alcohol concentration, the Court reasoned, involves no meaningful physical
    intrusion and is only a “negligible” invasion of privacy. Id. at 461. But blood tests
    are “a different matter,” the Court further reasoned, because they “ ‘require
    piercing the skin’ and extract a part of the subject’s body.” Id. at 463 (quoting
    Skinner v. North Dakota, 
    489 U.S. 438
    , 625 (2016)). Perhaps with a direct nod to
    DNA evidence, the Court noted that expelled air used in a preliminary breath
    test was not a specimen “from which a wealth of additional, highly personal
    information could potentially be obtained.” 
    Id.
     A DNA specimen, of course, is.
    The more analogous case might be Kyllo v. United States, in which a federal
    agent, while parked in his vehicle on the street, used thermal imaging technology
    to measure heat emanating from inside a home to investigate whether the
    homeowner was growing marijuana. 
    533 U.S. at
    29–30. The Court held that the
    thermal imaging was a search under the Fourth Amendment because it gave the
    government private information that otherwise would have required a physical
    invasion of the home. 
    Id. at 34, 40
    . The holding in Kyllo demonstrates that
    Fourth Amendment searches can occur without any physical intrusion. See Kerr,
    Katz as Originalism, 71 Duke L.J. at 1054 (citing the holding in Katz). In this
    73
    case, similar to Kyllo, the extraction and analysis of Burns’s DNA provided the
    State private information that otherwise would have required a physical invasion
    of Burns’s person.
    2. “Papers.” The nature of the information revealed in a DNA specimen also
    suggests a fit within the meaning of a “paper.” DNA carries a person’s private
    genetic information, identical in material respects to the types of sensitive
    information generally protected in one’s “papers.” It’s not a “paper” in the form
    that someone in 1791 would have recognized it, of course; but then again,
    neither is electronic information stored on a computer hard drive or smartphone.
    See Riley, 573 U.S. at 403.
    Phones and computers use a skeuomorphic design—a digital interface in
    which electronic elements resemble real-world objects, such as a “document,” or
    “file folder,” or “trash bin.” In reality, the digital device simply stores a series of
    ones and zeroes; everyone knows there are no physical documents, folders, or
    trash bins found within. But information stored in digital form, based on its use
    and function, nonetheless warrants Fourth Amendment protection as “papers.”
    See, e.g., United States v. Warshak, 
    631 F.3d 266
    , 285–86 (6th Cir. 2010) (“Given
    the   fundamental       similarities   between   email   and   traditional   forms   of
    communication, it would defy common sense to afford emails lesser Fourth
    Amendment protection. Email is the technological scion of tangible mail.”
    (citations omitted)).
    It stands to reason that if a string of binary digits encoded onto a miniscule
    spinning magnetic disk to record private information is a “paper,” then a string
    74
    of DNA codons stored in the nucleus of human cells could similarly be considered
    a “paper.” The information encoded in our DNA ranges from biological familial
    relationships and ancestral origins to our predisposition to suffering from certain
    genetically-determined diseases. Researchers have linked DNA to our behavioral
    traits, our preferences and aversions, and our physical appearance. Given the
    intensely private nature of the information, an actual printout of someone’s DNA
    analysis could certainly constitute “papers” protected under the Fourth
    Amendment. There’s no reason it should lack similar protection as a “paper” in
    its molecular form.
    The Supreme Court’s holding in Skinner v. Railway Labor Executives’
    Assoc., a case addressing the Fourth Amendment’s application to a law
    mandating employee blood testing, generally supports the notion that a DNA
    specimen could constitute a “person” or “paper.” 
    489 U.S. 602
    , 617–18. Although
    the opinion doesn’t include discussion parsing the particular categories listed in
    the Fourth Amendment’s text, the Court nonetheless concluded that “collection
    and subsequent analysis of . . . biological samples must be deemed Fourth
    Amendment searches.” 
    Id. at 618
    .
    There’s perhaps some overlap between “person” and “papers” in play here.
    Other cases applying the Fourth Amendment to new technologies suggest some
    category straddling at work. This seems permissible considering that the Fourth
    Amendment’s list (“persons, houses, papers, and effects”) is joined by the
    inclusive connector “and.” U.S. Const. amend. IV. In Katz, for instance, the Court
    found a Fourth Amendment violation when the FBI installed a hidden
    75
    microphone to record conversations in a public phone booth. Katz, 
    389 U.S. at
    348–49, 359 (majority opinion). Neither the majority opinion nor Justice Harlan’s
    concurrence specified whether the Fourth Amendment applied because the
    phone booth was a type of “house” or “effect.” See 
    id. at 347
    ; Kerr, Katz as
    Originalism, 71 Duke L.J. at 1054. Spoken words don’t neatly fall into the
    categories of “papers” or “effects,” but the Court has said that conversations
    heard through wireless eavesdropping nonetheless constitute unlawful seizures.
    See Wong Sun v. United States, 
    371 U.S. 471
    , 485 (1963) (citing Silverman v.
    United States, 
    365 U.S. 505
     (1961)).
    Similarly, although the postal system is obviously not a house, the
    Supreme Court long ago held that a piece of mail in a sealed envelope was
    entitled to house-like protection. Ex parte Jackson, 
    96 U.S. 727
    , 732–33 (1877);
    see Kerr, Katz as Originalism, 71 Duke L.J. at 1082. “Whilst in the mail,” sealed
    letters are afforded the same protection against searches as “papers [that] are
    subjected to search in one’s own household.” Jackson, 96 U.S. at 733.
    II. The Majority’s Abandonment Holding Is Wrong.
    A. The “abandonment” doctrine does not apply to the DNA specimen
    on the straw.
    In this case, the State didn’t get a warrant before it seized the straw and
    extracted and analyzed the DNA specimen on it. The State makes no claim that
    any exception to the warrant requirement applies. Instead, the State argues—
    and the majority holds—that people have no constitutional search-and-seizure
    protections in property they abandon and, thus, that the Fourth Amendment
    has no application in this case because Burns abandoned the straw and the DNA
    76
    specimen on it. The majority finds, in other words, that by abandoning the straw
    Burns cannot establish that the straw or the DNA specimen on it was his person,
    house, paper, or effect.
    The majority’s conclusion relies on a false premise. Even if we accept that
    Burns abandoned the straw, this does not mean that he also abandoned his DNA
    specimen on the straw. And as a result, the State could not extract and search
    the DNA specimen without a warrant.
    There are two reasons for this. First, the extraction and analysis of Burns’s
    DNA is a search separate and apart from the seizure of the straw, with distinct
    Fourth Amendment considerations that go with it. There’s a fundamental
    difference between seizing an object and extracting private information contained
    on or within that object. Fourth Amendment interests are invaded by depriving
    a person of the right to exclude others from information. People have the right,
    in other words, “to be secure” in their person and papers, as opposed to simply
    the right not to be deprived of their person or papers. U.S. Const., amend. IV.
    In Riley v. California, the Supreme Court unanimously held that even
    though police could lawfully seize a person’s cell phone incident to the person’s
    arrest, police generally could not search the digital information stored on the cell
    phone. 573 U.S. at 403. “Our answer to the question of what police must do
    before searching a cell phone seized incident to an arrest is accordingly simple—
    get a warrant.” Id. The Court’s holding rested on clear lines of distinction it drew
    between cell phones as “physical objects,” on the one hand, and “data stored on
    a cell phone,” on the other. Id. at 386–87 (emphasis added). The Court recognized
    77
    the strong privacy interests at stake because people’s cell phones contain “a
    digital record of nearly every aspect of their lives—from the mundane to the
    intimate.” Id. at 395. Applying the same principle in this case, even if we accept
    that the police may lawfully seize a used drinking straw, police cannot parlay
    that right into a right to search the DNA on it.
    Second, the doctrine of abandonment doesn’t apply to DNA that a person
    involuntarily and unavoidably sheds in the course of daily life. The abandoned
    property doctrine hinges on whether a person “voluntarily” abandons the thing
    in question. State v. Bumpus, 
    459 N.W.2d 619
    , 625 (Iowa 1990). “Under Iowa
    law, ‘[a]bandonment is shown by proof that the owner intends to abandon the
    property and has voluntarily relinquished all right, title and interest in the
    property.’ ” Wright, 961 N.W.2d at 415 (alteration in original) (quoting Benjamin
    v. Lindner Aviation, Inc., 
    534 N.W.2d 400
    , 406 (Iowa 1995) (en banc)).
    Determining “whether a person has voluntarily abandoned property” is thus a
    question of intent, and intent “may be inferred from words, acts, and other
    objective facts.” Bumpus, 
    459 N.W.2d at 625
    ; see also Abel v. United States, 
    362 U.S. 217
    , 239 (1960) (explaining that a warrantless seizure of items was
    permitted only because the suspect “chose to leave some things behind in his
    [hotel] room, which he voluntarily relinquished” (emphasis added)).
    The Supreme Court’s holding in Carpenter v. United States illuminates how
    involuntary disclosure plays into the reasonable expectation of privacy analysis.
    
    138 S. Ct. 2206
    . In Carpenter, the Court rejected the notion that people
    voluntarily expose their cell phone location information and thus have no Fourth
    78
    Amendment protection in location data collected by cell phone companies. 
    Id. at 2220
    . The location information, the Court reasoned, “is not truly ‘shared’ as one
    normally understands the term.” 
    Id.
    The reasons are interconnected. First, “cell phones and the services they
    provide are ‘such a pervasive and insistent part of daily life’ that carrying one is
    indispensable to participation in modern society.” 
    Id.
     (quoting Riley, 573 U.S. at
    385). This “indispensability” principle holds truer still, of course, with the
    omnipresence of human DNA. Every human cell contains a copy of our DNA.
    Our physical participation in society—social presence itself—requires us to bring
    our DNA to public spaces.
    The Court’s second reason is rooted in the automatic nature of the
    disclosure. In the case of a cell phone, the device “logs a cell-site record by dint
    of its operation, without any affirmative act on the part of the user beyond
    powering up.” Id. Disclosure of location information to the cell phone company
    arises from “[v]irtually any activity on the phone,” including various automated
    phone operations. Id. The Court noted that, short of “disconnecting the phone
    from the network, there is no way to avoid leaving behind a trail of location data.”
    Id.
    The automatic-disclosure principle discussed in Carpenter applies with
    even more force to DNA evidence. A DNA specimen can come from the shedding
    of any human cells—skin, blood, saliva, sweat, hair, and on and on. DNA is
    released when someone sneezes, speaks, or touches something. The natural
    release of a person’s DNA into their environment—skin cells left by resting an
    79
    elbow on an armchair,18 an eyelash lost with a blink,19 a droplet of sweat on a
    bicycle handle,20 a trace of saliva on a drinking straw,21 and so on—doesn’t have
    the element of voluntary relinquishment necessary for an act to constitute
    abandonment. See Elizabeth E. Joh, Reclaiming “Abandoned” DNA: The Fourth
    Amendment And Genetic Privacy, 
    100 Nw. U. L. Rev. 857
    , 867 (2006) (explaining
    how, with involuntarily shed DNA, “[t]he volition that is implied in abandonment
    is simply unrealistic”).
    DNA, like cell phone data, is left “without any affirmative act” of the person.
    Carpenter, 
    138 S. Ct. at 2220
    . Indeed, as long as one lives, “there is no way to
    avoid leaving behind a trail of” DNA in the places and spaces that a person
    inhabits. 
    Id.
     A human can turn off a cell phone; a human cannot turn off one’s
    own automatic, continuous life cycle of creating and casting off DNA. If we
    possess a reasonable expectation of privacy in sensitive digital information that
    we unavoidably leave behind, we likewise possess a reasonable expectation of
    privacy in the sensitive genetic information we unavoidably leave behind.
    B. By leaving the straw, Burns did not “assume the risk” of
    abandoning his DNA for the government’s criminal investigation.
    Nor can we conclude that a person lacks a reasonable expectation of
    privacy in shed DNA under an “assumption of risk” theory. The Court in
    18Expert testimony in this case indicates that the average human sheds approximately
    two million skin cells per minute.
    19You   blink about 14,000 times a day. Bill Bryson, The Body 4.
    20“Even at rest we sweat steadily, if inconspicuously, but if you add in vigorous activity
    and challenging conditions, we drain off our water supplies very quickly.” Id. at 23.
    21A   typical adult secretes a little less than a quart and a half of saliva a day. Id. at 98.
    80
    Carpenter, having already observed the cell phone’s indispensability to modern
    life, determined that “in no meaningful sense does the user voluntarily ‘assume[]
    the risk’ of turning over a comprehensive dossier of his physical movements” to
    others. Id. (alteration in original) (quoting Smith, 
    442 U.S. at 745
    ). What’s true
    in Carpenter is truer here: “in no meaningful sense” do people “voluntarily
    ‘assume[] the risk’ of turning over a comprehensive dossier” of sensitive biological
    information simply through the involuntary shedding of DNA. 
    Id.
     (alteration in
    original) (quoting Smith, 
    442 U.S. at 745
    ).
    Justice Gorsuch’s dissent in Carpenter examined the limitations of an
    assumption-of-risk theory when someone reveals private information to third
    parties knowing there’s a possibility that the third party could reveal it. 
    Id.
     at
    2262–63 (Gorsuch, J., dissenting). He distinguished knowledge of a possibility
    that information could be revealed from legal responsibility for its revelation. Id.
    at 2263. “[K]nowing about a risk doesn’t mean you assume responsibility for it.”
    Id.
    On this point, Professor Richard Epstein (in an article cited in Justice
    Gorsuch’s dissent) warns that we must “guard against the undue extension of
    the notion of voluntary consent” in Fourth Amendment cases through “the false
    equation of knowledge of a risk with the assumption of the risk.” Richard A.
    Epstein, Privacy and the Third Hand: Lessons from the Common Law of
    Reasonable Expectations, 
    24 Berkeley Tech. L.J. 1199
    , 1204 (2009) [hereinafter
    Epstein]. “Whenever you walk down the sidewalk you know a car may negligently
    or recklessly veer off and hit you, but that hardly means you accept the
    81
    consequences and absolve the driver of any damage he may do to you.”
    Carpenter, 
    138 S. Ct. at
    2263 (citing Epstein, 24 Berkeley Tech. L.J. at 1204).
    “The requirement of waiver is critical,” Epstein explains, “because it suggests
    that there is some quid pro quo in the relationship. Knowledge in the absence of
    consent precludes that possibility, because all the gain goes on one side and all
    the costs go on the other.” Epstein, 24 Berkeley Tech. L.J. at 1204.
    Short of some hermitic existence in which a person somehow never leaves
    the confines of home, there’s no reliable way to protect against exposing your
    DNA to the government. Participating in life (setting aside, I suppose, some
    virtual reality sphere) is pretty much impossible without exposing yourself to the
    risk that the government could collect and analyze your DNA as you unavoidably
    and unconsciously discard it. The trap is always set and inescapable. Walking
    into the trap happens autonomically and at the microscopic level, in such a way
    that we come to it with a lowered guard and leading chin. The Supreme Court
    has cautioned us to be wary of the “power of technology to shrink the realm of
    guaranteed privacy.” Kyllo, 
    533 U.S. at 34
    . By declaring involuntary shedding of
    our DNA “abandonment,” the majority ushers the way for an unconstitutional
    constriction of privacy rights.
    C. The majority’s claim that analyzing Burns’s DNA was
    constitutional because it was limited to identification cannot be
    reconciled with the majority’s other analysis.
    The majority determines that using DNA only for identification purposes,
    as the police did in this case, doesn’t “foreclose the possibility that other kinds
    of warrantless DNA analysis might require a different result.” The majority seeks
    82
    to present its holding as a wooden matchstick, good for one light only. But in so
    doing, the majority fails to own up to the consequence of its own reasoning and
    instead “disguises the vast (and scary) scope of its holding by promising a
    limitation it cannot deliver.” Maryland v. King, 
    569 U.S. 435
    , 481 (2013) (Scalia,
    J., dissenting).
    Today’s decision commits to a governing principle with unconstitutional
    moorings that the majority itself appears unable to reconcile. It can’t square an
    identity-only limitation on DNA analysis with its own earlier holding that the
    constitution doesn’t protect abandoned DNA at all. Again, the majority’s holding
    is premised on the notion that Burns had no reasonable expectation of privacy
    in his DNA specimen on the straw. And without a reasonable expectation of
    privacy, there is no “search” for Fourth Amendment purposes. “Trash is trash,”
    after all, as the State repeatedly said at oral argument.
    Either the DNA is abandoned, or it isn’t. The majority makes clear that
    “just as Burns voluntarily abandoned the straw, he also voluntarily abandoned
    any DNA attached to the straw” and thus “ ‘could have had no reasonable
    expectation of privacy’ in either.” (Quoting California v. Greenwood, 
    486 U.S. 35
    ,
    40–41 (1988).) The conditional proposition the majority lays down—if DNA is
    abandoned, then police may do with it as they wish without Fourth Amendment
    imposition—offers no room for a different result in a future case involving
    abandoned DNA. The majority’s reasoning burns the ship after disembarking.
    “The line it is drawn. The curse it is cast.” Bob Dylan, The Times They Are A-
    Changin’ (Warner Bros., Inc. 1963). The suggestion that in the future we might
    83
    decide other challenges to warrantless DNA analysis differently is empty
    consolation.
    III. The False Analogy Between DNA and Fingerprints.
    Much of the majority’s holding hinges on our acceptance that DNA is more
    or less analogous to a fingerprint. In his stinging dissent in Maryland v. King—
    the same case today’s majority cites for its fingerprint-to-DNA analogy—Justice
    Scalia responded to the analogy this way: “[T]he Court’s comparison of
    Maryland’s DNA searches to other techniques, such as fingerprinting, can seem
    apt only to those who know no more than today’s opinion has chosen to tell them
    about how those DNA searches actually work.” 
    569 U.S. at 466
    .
    A fingerprint reveals—with existing technology, at least—only identity, and
    reveals that only by comparing one fingerprint against a known sample. A
    fingerprint itself stores no private information. To the extent a fingerprint has
    any communicative application at all, it derives merely from the fact of its
    existence (“someone was here”) or from comparing it to another known
    fingerprint exemplar (“Brooks was here”).
    DNA, on the other hand, arms those with the ability to analyze it with a
    vast trove of private details about a person. The informational superabundance
    of DNA and its ever-expanding uses have sparked a scientific revolution. No less
    than a dozen Nobel Prizes have been awarded for research involving DNA.22 DNA
    22See     Helix, The Nobel Prize: Winners Who’ve Advanced the Study of Genetics,
    https://blog.helix.com/2017/10/nobel-prize-winners-genetics/ [https://perma.cc/FAD8-SNUZ]; The
    Nobel Prize, All Nobel Prizes, https://www.nobelprize.org/prizes/lists/all-nobel-prizes/
    [https://perma.cc/MM9Z-3Y5N].
    84
    has been called “the most extraordinary molecule on Earth.” Bill Bryson, A Short
    History of Nearly Everything 399 (2003). It is considered among history’s greatest
    scientific breakthroughs. Gareth Williams, Unraveling the Double Helix 203
    (2019). DNA has not received these accolades because of its mere capacity to
    verify identity against an exemplar.
    The reasonable expectation of privacy test applied in Carpenter “focuse[d]
    on how much the government can learn about a person regardless of the place
    or thing from which the information came.” Orin S. Kerr, Implementing
    Carpenter, in The Digital Fourth Amendment 6 (USC L. Legal Stud. Working Paper
    No. 18–29, (Oxford Univ. Press, forthcoming)). People do not forfeit to the
    government a reasonable expectation of privacy in the contents of their entire
    genetic code—and all that it reveals about them—merely by leaving a drinking
    straw at a restaurant.
    DNA is that much richer, that much more laden with information, by
    orders of magnitude, than fingerprints. And DNA is that much more sensitive to
    privacy concerns than fingerprint impressions left on a surface. Like fingerprints,
    the analogy exists on the surface only. The comparison between fingerprints and
    DNA denotes, it seems to me, rationalization rather than reasoning.
    IV. The Crime-Solving Potential of Warrantless DNA Searches Does
    Not Trump Our Fourth Amendment Protections.
    The majority suggests that we should expect and even welcome the
    benefits of warrantless DNA analysis because of “DNA testing’s ‘unparalleled
    ability both to exonerate the wrongly convicted and to identify the guilty’ ” and
    its “potential to significantly improve both the criminal justice system and police
    85
    investigative practices.” (Quoting King, 
    569 U.S. at 442
     (majority opinion).) You
    can count me among those dazzled by the crime-solving capabilities of DNA
    analysis. If the constitutional test for an investigation technique turned on that
    technique’s capacity to aid the government in solving crimes, DNA analysis
    would doubtless sail past the bar with such vertical velocity as to escape Earth’s
    gravity.
    Yet the mere capacity to enable easier or faster crime detection does not—
    and cannot—determine whether an action violates constitutional safeguards.
    “Solving unsolved crimes is a noble objective,” in the words of Justice Scalia,
    “but it occupies a lower place in the American pantheon of noble objectives than
    the protection of our people from suspicionless law-enforcement searches. The
    Fourth Amendment must prevail.” King, 
    569 U.S. at 481
     (Scalia, J., dissenting).
    The Supreme Court has declared many warrantless investigatory practices
    unconstitutional notwithstanding a particular technique’s formidable potency
    for crime-solving. See, e.g., Carpenter, 
    138 S. Ct. at
    2220–21 (majority opinion)
    (cell phone location data); United States v. Jones, 
    565 U.S. 400
    , 410 (2012) (GPS
    tracking device on a vehicle); Kyllo, 
    533 U.S. at 40
     (heat-sensing technology
    aimed at a home). Warrantless entry by kicking in the doors of homes might well
    result in solving more crimes, but that doesn’t mean the Fourth Amendment
    sanctions it. See Florida v. Jardines, 
    569 U.S. 1
    , 11–12 (2013) (finding even the
    government’s use of trained police dogs to sniff the immediate surroundings of a
    home constitutes a “search” within the meaning of the Fourth Amendment).
    86
    Courts have no license to aid the government in solving crimes through judicial
    revision of constitutional protections.
    Justice Brandeis’s warning about state action is well heeded here:
    “Experience should teach us to be most on our guard to protect liberty when the
    government’s purposes are beneficent.” Olmstead v. United States, 
    277 U.S. 438
    ,
    479, (1928) (Brandeis, J., dissenting) (overruled by Katz, 
    389 U.S. 347
    , and
    Berger v. New York, 
    388 U.S. 41
     (1967)). The potential power to assemble a DNA
    database of all Americans using “abandoned” DNA (in which the majority says
    you have no rights) to “improve both the criminal justice system and police
    investigative practices” should bring a shudder to the reader. (Quoting King, 
    569 U.S. at 442
     (majority opinion).) If we have no legitimate expectation of privacy in
    the “bread-crumb trail of identifying DNA matter” we leave behind, “what
    possible impediment can there be to having the government collect what we leave
    behind, extract its DNA signature and enhance CODIS”—the national repository
    of criminal offenders’ DNA profiles—“to include everyone?” United States v.
    Kincade, 
    379 F.3d 813
    , 873 (9th Cir. 2004) (Kozinski, J. dissenting).
    “[P]laced in the hands of an administration that chooses to ‘exalt order at
    the cost of liberty,’ Whitney v. California, 
    274 U.S. 357
    , 374 (1927) (Brandeis, J.
    dissenting), the database could be used to repress dissent or, quite literally, to
    eliminate political opposition.” Id. at 847 (Reinhardt, J., dissenting). Searching
    the database for behavioral or psychological markers conceivably becomes a
    means to generate criminal suspects by identifying people with, for instance,
    predispositions to aggressive behavior or mental health disorders. On the whole,
    87
    I much prefer Thomas Jefferson’s approach: “The time to guard against
    corruption and tyranny, is before they shall have gotten hold on us. It is better
    to keep the wolf out of the fold, than to trust to drawing his teeth and talons after
    he shall have entered.” Thomas Jefferson, Notes on Virginia (1787), in Notes on
    the State of Virginia 125 (Boston, Lilly and Wait, 1832).
    The majority’s attempt to analogize a rapist’s DNA left at a crime scene and
    abandoned DNA left on a straw at a pizza restaurant confuses the analysis. A
    warrant to gather and analyze crime-scene evidence is uncontroversial. The
    government is permitted to use DNA evidence to solve crimes; the constitutional
    violation in this case involves only the warrantless collection and analysis of
    Burns’s DNA. DNA evidence remains available to use in criminal investigations
    with a warrant supported by probable cause. No party suggests that obtaining a
    warrant to gather and analyze DNA left at a crime scene poses an unreasonable
    burden on law enforcement.
    As explained in Entick v. Carrington—a case “ ‘undoubtedly familiar’ to
    ‘every American statesman’ at the time the Constitution was adopted,” Jones,
    
    565 U.S. at 405
     (quoting Brower v. County of Inyo, 
    489 U.S. 593
    , 598 (1989))—
    even for “murder, rape, robbery, and housebreaking . . . our law has provided no
    paper search in these cases to help forward the convictions.” Entick, (1765) 19
    How. St. Tr. 1029, 1073 (C.P.). We should not let DNA’s efficacy override core
    constitutional protections.
    88
    V. The Benefit of the Law.
    I recognize that had my view prevailed today, Burns’s murder conviction
    would be reversed, and the prosecution would be left to pursue a conviction in a
    new trial without the same DNA evidence. But that is the very essence of how
    the exclusionary rule operates, and no party in this case asks us to cast the rule
    aside. Courts cannot carry out their duty to uphold constitutional rights only
    when doing so will mean the reversal of misdemeanor convictions. Warrantless
    searches of DNA should not be permitted simply because we’ve decided that the
    cost of enforcing the Fourth Amendment’s promise is too high.
    Even murder suspects receive the benefit of constitutional protections.
    Law enforcement has no license to suspend these protections to get its man,
    even to solve a crime as heinous as the one in this case. The lines ascribed to Sir
    Thomas More and William Roper by the playwright Robert Bolt are not without
    relevance here:
    Roper[:] So now you’d give the Devil the benefit of the law!
    More[:] Yes. What would you do? Cut a great road through the
    law to get after the Devil?
    Roper[:] I’d cut down every law in England to do that!
    More[:] Oh? And when the last law was down, and the Devil
    turned round on you—where would you hide, Roper, the laws all
    being flat? This country’s planted thick with laws from coast to
    coast—man’s laws, not God’s—and if you cut them down . . . d’you
    really think you could stand upright in the winds that would blow
    then? Yes, I’d give the Devil benefit of law, for my own safety’s sake.
    Robert Bolt, A Man For All Seasons: A Play in Two Acts 66 (1990) (stage directions
    omitted).
    89
    The Fourth Amendment protects “that degree of respect for the privacy of
    persons and the inviolability of their property that existed when the provision
    was adopted—even if a later, less virtuous age should become accustomed to
    considering all sorts of intrusion ‘reasonable.’ ” Minnesota v. Dickerson, 
    508 U.S. 366
    , 380 (1993) (Scalia, J., concurring). We can anticipate, in light of today’s
    ruling, that the public will come to accept that they have no reasonable
    expectation of privacy in DNA that they involuntarily and unavoidably leave
    behind. As Judge Kozinski warned in his dissent about the perils of government
    DNA collection, a court opinion that “revels in the boon that new technology will
    provide to law enforcement[] is an engraved invitation to future expansion. And
    when that inevitable expansion comes, we will look to the regime we approved
    today as the new baseline and say, this too must be OK because it’s just one
    small step beyond the last thing we approved.” Kinkade, 
    379 F.3d at 873
    (Kozinski, J., dissenting).
    Today’s opinion might not bring Fourth Amendment protections “tumbling
    down all at once like the walls of Jericho at Joshua’s trumpet-blast.” Grant
    Gilmore, The Ages of American Law 68 (1977). But it brings to bear violations of
    individual privacy against government intrusion from which, in my view, the
    Framers sought—indeed, fought—to protect us. I would reverse the trial court’s
    ruling denying the motion to suppress and remand the case for a new trial.
    Oxley, J., joins this dissent except as to part I.B.