Iancu v. Brunetti , 204 L. Ed. 2d 714 ( 2019 )


Menu:
  • (Slip Opinion)              OCTOBER TERM, 2018                                       1
    Syllabus
    NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is
    being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued.
    The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been
    prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader.
    See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 
    200 U.S. 321
    , 337.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    Syllabus
    IANCU, UNDER SECRETARY OF COMMERCE FOR
    INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND DIRECTOR, PATENT
    AND TRADEMARK OFFICE v. BRUNETTI
    CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR
    THE FEDERAL CIRCUIT
    No. 18–302.      Argued April 15, 2019—Decided June 24, 2019
    Respondent Erik Brunetti sought federal registration of the trademark
    FUCT. The Patent and Trademark Office (PTO) denied his applica-
    tion under a provision of the Lanham Act that prohibits registration
    of trademarks that “[c]onsist[ ] of or comprise[ ] immoral[ ] or scan-
    dalous matter,” 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a). Brunetti brought a First
    Amendment challenge to the “immoral or scandalous” bar in the Fed-
    eral Circuit, which invalidated the provision.
    Held: The Lanham Act’s prohibition on registration of “immoral[ ] or
    scandalous” trademarks violates the First Amendment.
    In Matal v. Tam, 582 U. S. ___, this Court declared unconstitution-
    al the Lanham Act’s ban on registering marks that “disparage” any
    “person[ ], living or dead.” §1052(a). A divided Court agreed on two
    propositions. First, if a trademark registration bar is viewpoint
    based, it is unconstitutional. And second, the disparagement bar was
    viewpoint based.
    The “immoral or scandalous” bar similarly discriminates on the
    basis of viewpoint and so collides with this Court’s First Amendment
    doctrine. Expressive material is “immoral” when it is “inconsistent
    with rectitude, purity, or good morals”; “wicked”; or “vicious.” So the
    Lanham Act permits registration of marks that champion society’s
    sense of rectitude and morality, but not marks that denigrate those
    concepts. And material is “scandalous” when it “giv[es] offense to the
    conscience or moral feelings”; “excite[s] reprobation”; or “call[s] out
    condemnation.” So the Lanham Act allows registration of marks
    when their messages accord with, but not when their messages defy,
    2                         IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Syllabus
    society’s sense of decency or propriety. The statute, on its face, dis-
    tinguishes between two opposed sets of ideas: those aligned with con-
    ventional moral standards and those hostile to them; those inducing
    societal nods of approval and those provoking offense and condemna-
    tion. This facial viewpoint bias in the law results in viewpoint-
    discriminatory application. The PTO has refused to register marks
    communicating “immoral” or “scandalous” views about (among other
    things) drug use, religion, and terrorism. But all the while, it has
    approved registration of marks expressing more accepted views on
    the same topics.
    The Government says the statute is susceptible of a limiting con-
    struction that would remove its viewpoint bias. The Government’s
    idea is to narrow the statutory bar to “marks that are offensive [or]
    shocking[ ] because of their mode of expression, independent of any
    views that they may express,” which would mostly restrict the PTO
    to refusing marks that are lewd, sexually explicit, or profane. But
    this Court cannot accept the Government’s proposal, because the
    statute says something markedly different. The “immoral or scan-
    dalous” bar does not draw the line at lewd, sexually explicit, or pro-
    fane marks. Nor does it refer only to marks whose “mode of expres-
    sion,” independent of viewpoint, is particularly offensive. To cut the
    statute off where the Government urges is not to interpret the stat-
    ute Congress enacted, but to fashion a new one. And once the “im-
    moral or scandalous” bar is interpreted fairly, it must be invalidated.
    Pp. 4–11.
    
    877 F.3d 1330
    , affirmed.
    KAGAN, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which THOMAS,
    GINSBURG, ALITO, GORSUCH and KAVANAUGH, JJ., joined. ALITO, J.,
    filed a concurring opinion. ROBERTS, C. J., and BREYER, J., filed opin-
    ions concurring in part and dissenting in part. SOTOMAYOR, J., filed an
    opinion concurring in part and dissenting in part, in which BREYER, J.,
    joined.
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)                              1
    Opinion of the Court
    NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the
    preliminary print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested to
    notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Wash-
    ington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order
    that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 18–302
    _________________
    ANDREI IANCU, UNDER SECRETARY OF COMMERCE
    FOR INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND DIRECTOR,
    PATENT AND TRADEMARK OFFICE,
    PETITIONER v. ERIK BRUNETTI
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FEDERAL CIRCUIT
    [June 24, 2019]
    JUSTICE KAGAN delivered the opinion of the Court.
    Two Terms ago, in Matal v. Tam, 582 U. S. ___ (2017),
    this Court invalidated the Lanham Act’s bar on the regis-
    tration of “disparag[ing]” trademarks.          
    15 U.S. C
    .
    §1052(a). Although split between two non-majority opin-
    ions, all Members of the Court agreed that the provision
    violated the First Amendment because it discriminated on
    the basis of viewpoint.      Today we consider a First
    Amendment challenge to a neighboring provision of the
    Act, prohibiting the registration of “immoral[ ] or scandal-
    ous” trademarks. 
    Ibid. We hold that
    this provision in-
    fringes the First Amendment for the same reason: It too
    disfavors certain ideas.
    I
    Respondent Erik Brunetti is an artist and entrepreneur
    who founded a clothing line that uses the trademark
    FUCT. According to Brunetti, the mark (which functions
    as the clothing’s brand name) is pronounced as four let-
    ters, one after the other: F-U-C-T. See Brief for Respond-
    2                   IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of the Court
    ent 1. But you might read it differently and, if so, you
    would hardly be alone. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 5 (describing
    the brand name as “the equivalent of [the] past participle
    form of a well-known word of profanity”). That common
    perception caused difficulties for Brunetti when he tried to
    register his mark with the U. S. Patent and Trademark
    Office (PTO).
    Under the Lanham Act, the PTO administers a federal
    registration system for trademarks.           See 
    15 U.S. C
    .
    §§1051, 1052. Registration of a mark is not mandatory.
    The owner of an unregistered mark may still use it in
    commerce and enforce it against infringers. See Tam, 582
    U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 4). But registration gives trade-
    mark owners valuable benefits. For example, registration
    constitutes “prima facie evidence” of the mark’s validity.
    §1115(a). And registration serves as “constructive notice
    of the registrant’s claim of ownership,” which forecloses
    some defenses in infringement actions. §1072. Generally,
    a trademark is eligible for registration, and receipt of such
    benefits, if it is “used in commerce.” §1051(a)(1). But the
    Act directs the PTO to “refuse[ ] registration” of certain
    marks. §1052. For instance, the PTO cannot register a
    mark that “so resembles” another mark as to create a
    likelihood of confusion. §1052(d). It cannot register a
    mark that is “merely descriptive” of the goods on which it
    is used. §1052(e). It cannot register a mark containing
    the flag or insignia of any nation or State. See §1052(b).
    There are five or ten more (depending on how you count).
    And until we invalidated the criterion two years ago, the
    PTO could not register a mark that “disparage[d]” a “per-
    son[ ], living or dead.” §1052(a); see Tam, 582 U. S. ___.
    This case involves another of the Lanham Act’s prohibi-
    tions on registration—one applying to marks that
    “[c]onsist[ ] of or comprise[ ] immoral[ ] or scandalous mat-
    ter.” §1052(a). The PTO applies that bar as a “unitary
    provision,” rather than treating the two adjectives in it
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)           3
    Opinion of the Court
    separately. In re Brunetti, 
    877 F.3d 1330
    , 1336 (CA Fed.
    2017); Brief for Petitioner 6 (stating that the PTO “has
    long treated the two terms as composing a single category”).
    To determine whether a mark fits in the category, the
    PTO asks whether a “substantial composite of the general
    public” would find the mark “shocking to the sense of
    truth, decency, or propriety”; “giving offense to the con-
    science or moral feelings”; “calling out for condemnation”;
    “disgraceful”; “offensive”; “disreputable”; or 
    “vulgar.” 877 F.3d, at 1336
    (internal quotation marks omitted); see
    Brief for Petitioner 6 (agreeing that the PTO “generally
    defines” the category in that way).
    Both a PTO examining attorney and the PTO’s Trade-
    mark Trial and Appeal Board decided that Brunetti’s
    mark flunked that test. The attorney determined that
    FUCT was “a total vulgar” and “therefore[ ] unregistrable.”
    App. 27–28. On review, the Board stated that the mark
    was “highly offensive” and “vulgar,” and that it had “de-
    cidedly negative sexual connotations.” App. to Pet. for
    Cert. 59a, 64a–65a. As part of its review, the Board also
    considered evidence of how Brunetti used the mark. It
    found that Brunetti’s website and products contained
    imagery, near the mark, of “extreme nihilism” and “anti-
    social” behavior. 
    Id., at 64a.
    In that context, the Board
    thought, the mark communicated “misogyny, depravity,
    [and] violence.” 
    Ibid. The Board concluded:
    “Whether one
    considers [the mark] as a sexual term, or finds that [Bru-
    netti] has used [the mark] in the context of extreme mi-
    sogyny, nihilism or violence, we have no question but that
    [the term is] extremely offensive.” 
    Id., at 65a.
      Brunetti then brought a facial challenge to the “immoral
    or scandalous” bar in the Court of Appeals for the Federal
    Circuit. That court found the prohibition to violate the
    First Amendment. As usual when a lower court has inval-
    idated a federal statute, we granted certiorari. 586 U. S.
    ___ (2019).
    4                    IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of the Court
    II
    This Court first considered a First Amendment chal-
    lenge to a trademark registration restriction in Tam, just
    two Terms ago. There, the Court declared unconstitutional
    the Lanham Act’s ban on registering marks that “dispar-
    age” any “person[ ], living or dead.” §1052(a). The eight-
    Justice Court divided evenly between two opinions and
    could not agree on the overall framework for deciding the
    case. (In particular, no majority emerged to resolve
    whether a Lanham Act bar is a condition on a government
    benefit or a simple restriction on speech.) But all the
    Justices agreed on two propositions. First, if a trademark
    registration bar is viewpoint-based, it is unconstitutional.
    See 582 U. S., at ___–___, ___–___ (opinion of ALITO, J.)
    (slip op., at 1–2, 22–23); id., at ___–___, ___ (opinion of
    Kennedy, J.) (slip op., at 1–2, 5). And second, the dispar-
    agement bar was viewpoint-based. See id., at ___–___,
    ___–___ (opinion of ALITO, J.) (slip op., at 1–2, 22–23); id.,
    at ___–___ (opinion of Kennedy, J.) (slip op., at 2–5).
    The Justices thus found common ground in a core postu-
    late of free speech law: The government may not discrimi-
    nate against speech based on the ideas or opinions it
    conveys. See Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of
    Va., 
    515 U.S. 819
    , 829–830 (1995) (explaining that view-
    point discrimination is an “egregious form of content
    discrimination” and is “presumptively unconstitutional”).
    In Justice Kennedy’s explanation, the disparagement bar
    allowed a trademark owner to register a mark if it was
    “positive” about a person, but not if it was “derogatory.”
    Tam, 582 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 2). That was the “es-
    sence of viewpoint discrimination,” he continued, because
    “[t]he law thus reflects the Government’s disapproval of a
    subset of messages it finds offensive.” Id., at ___–___ (slip
    op., at 2–3). JUSTICE ALITO emphasized that the statute
    “denie[d] registration to any mark” whose disparaging
    message was “offensive to a substantial percentage of the
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)            5
    Opinion of the Court
    members of any group.” Id., at ___ (slip op., at 22). The
    bar thus violated the “bedrock First Amendment principle”
    that the government cannot discriminate against “ideas
    that offend.” Id., at ___–___ (slip op., at 1–2). Slightly
    different explanations, then, but a shared conclusion:
    Viewpoint discrimination doomed the disparagement bar.
    If the “immoral or scandalous” bar similarly discrimi-
    nates on the basis of viewpoint, it must also collide with
    our First Amendment doctrine. The Government does not
    argue otherwise. In briefs and oral argument, the Gov-
    ernment offers a theory for upholding the bar if it is
    viewpoint-neutral (essentially, that the bar would then be
    a reasonable condition on a government benefit). See
    Brief for Petitioner 14–26. But the Government agrees
    that under Tam it may not “deny registration based on the
    views expressed” by a mark. Tr. of Oral Arg. 24. “As the
    Court’s Tam decision establishes,” the Government says,
    “the criteria for federal trademark registration” must be
    “viewpoint-neutral to survive Free Speech Clause review.”
    Pet. for Cert. 19. So the key question becomes: Is the
    “immoral or scandalous” criterion in the Lanham Act
    viewpoint-neutral or viewpoint-based?
    It is viewpoint-based. The meanings of “immoral” and
    “scandalous” are not mysterious, but resort to some dic-
    tionaries still helps to lay bare the problem. When is
    expressive material “immoral”? According to a standard
    definition, when it is “inconsistent with rectitude, purity,
    or good morals”; “wicked”; or “vicious.” Webster’s New
    International Dictionary 1246 (2d ed. 1949). Or again,
    when it is “opposed to or violating morality”; or “morally
    evil.” Shorter Oxford English Dictionary 961 (3d ed.
    1947). So the Lanham Act permits registration of marks
    that champion society’s sense of rectitude and morality,
    but not marks that denigrate those concepts. And when is
    such material “scandalous”? Says a typical definition,
    when it “giv[es] offense to the conscience or moral feel-
    6                    IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of the Court
    ings”; “excite[s] reprobation”; or “call[s] out condemna-
    tion.” Webster’s New International Dictionary, at 2229.
    Or again, when it is “shocking to the sense of truth, decency,
    or propriety”; “disgraceful”; “offensive”; or “disreputable.”
    Funk & Wagnalls New Standard Dictionary 2186 (1944).
    So the Lanham Act allows registration of marks when
    their messages accord with, but not when their messages
    defy, society’s sense of decency or propriety. Put the pair
    of overlapping terms together and the statute, on its face,
    distinguishes between two opposed sets of ideas: those
    aligned with conventional moral standards and those
    hostile to them; those inducing societal nods of approval
    and those provoking offense and condemnation. The
    statute favors the former, and disfavors the latter. “Love
    rules”? “Always be good”? Registration follows. “Hate
    rules”? “Always be cruel”? Not according to the Lanham
    Act’s “immoral or scandalous” bar.
    The facial viewpoint bias in the law results in
    viewpoint-discriminatory application. Recall that the PTO
    itself describes the “immoral or scandalous” criterion
    using much the same language as in the dictionary defini-
    tions recited above. 
    See supra, at 3
    . The PTO, for exam-
    ple, asks whether the public would view the mark as
    “shocking to the sense of truth, decency, or propriety”;
    “calling out for condemnation”; “offensive”; or “disrepu-
    table.” Brief for Petitioner 6 (internal quotation marks
    omitted). Using those guideposts, the PTO has refused to
    register marks communicating “immoral” or “scandalous”
    views about (among other things) drug use, religion, and
    terrorism. But all the while, it has approved registration
    of marks expressing more accepted views on the same
    topics. See generally Gilson & LaLonde, Trademarks Laid
    Bare, 101 Trademark Reporter 1476, 1510–1513, 1518–
    1522 (2011); Brief for Barton Beebe et al. as Amici Curiae
    28–29.
    Here are some samples. The PTO rejected marks con-
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)            7
    Opinion of the Court
    veying approval of drug use (YOU CAN’T SPELL
    HEALTHCARE WITHOUT THC for pain-relief medica-
    tion, MARIJUANA COLA and KO KANE for beverages)
    because it is scandalous to “inappropriately glamoriz[e]
    drug abuse.” PTO, Office Action of Aug. 28, 2010, Serial
    No. 85038867; see Office Action of Dec. 24, 2009, Serial
    No. 77833964; Office Action of Nov. 17, 2009, Serial No.
    77671304. But at the same time, the PTO registered
    marks with such sayings as D.A.R.E. TO RESIST DRUGS
    AND VIOLENCE and SAY NO TO DRUGS—REALITY IS
    THE BEST TRIP IN LIFE. See PTO, Reg. No. 2975163
    (July 26, 2005); Reg. No. 2966019 (July 12, 2005). Simi-
    larly, the PTO disapproved registration for the mark
    BONG HITS 4 JESUS because it “suggests that people
    should engage in an illegal activity [in connection with]
    worship” and because “Christians would be morally out-
    raged by a statement that connects Jesus Christ with
    illegal drug use.” Office Action of Mar. 15, 2008, Serial
    No. 77305946. And the PTO refused to register trade-
    marks associating religious references with products
    (AGNUS DEI for safes and MADONNA for wine) because
    they would be “offensive to most individuals of the Chris-
    tian faith” and “shocking to the sense of propriety.” Ex
    parte Summit Brass & Bronze Works, 
    59 U.S.P.Q. (BNA) 22
    , 23
    (Dec. Com. Pat. 1943); In re Riverbank Canning Co., 
    95 F. 2d
    327, 329 (CCPA 1938). But once again, the PTO ap-
    proved marks—PRAISE THE LORD for a game and
    JESUS DIED FOR YOU on clothing—whose message
    suggested religious faith rather than blasphemy or irrev-
    erence. See Reg. No. 5265121 (Aug. 15, 2017); Reg. No.
    3187985 (Dec. 19, 2006). Finally, the PTO rejected marks
    reflecting support for al-Qaeda (BABY AL QAEDA and
    AL-QAEDA on t-shirts) “because the bombing of civilians
    and other terrorist acts are shocking to the sense of decency
    and call out for condemnation.” Office Action of Nov. 22,
    2004, Serial No. 78444968; see Office Action of Feb. 23,
    8                    IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of the Court
    2005, Serial No. 78400213. Yet it approved registration of
    a mark with the words WAR ON TERROR MEMORIAL.
    Reg. No. 5495362 (Jun. 19, 2018). Of course, all these
    decisions are understandable. The rejected marks express
    opinions that are, at the least, offensive to many Ameri-
    cans. But as the Court made clear in Tam, a law disfavor-
    ing “ideas that offend” discriminates based on viewpoint,
    in violation of the First Amendment. 582 U. S., at ___
    (opinion of ALITO, J.) (slip op., at 2); see id., at ___–___
    (slip op., at 22–23); id., at ___–___ (opinion of Kennedy, J.)
    (slip op., at 2–3).
    How, then, can the Government claim that the “immoral
    or scandalous” bar is viewpoint-neutral? The Government
    basically asks us to treat decisions like those described
    above as PTO examiners’ mistakes. See Brief for Petitioner
    46. Still more, the Government tells us to ignore how
    the Lanham Act’s language, on its face, disfavors some
    ideas. In urging that course, the Government does not
    dispute that the statutory language—and words used to
    define it—have just that effect. At oral argument, the
    Government conceded: “[I]f you just looked at the words
    like ‘shocking’ and ‘offensive’ on their face and gave them
    their ordinary meanings[,] they could easily encompass
    material that was shocking [or offensive] because it ex-
    pressed an outrageous point of view or a point of view that
    most members” of society reject. Tr. of Oral Arg. 6. But
    no matter, says the Government, because the statute is
    “susceptible of” a limiting construction that would remove
    this viewpoint bias. 
    Id., at 7
    (arguing that the Court
    should “attempt to construe [the] statute in a way that
    would render it constitutional”). The Government’s idea,
    abstractly phrased, is to narrow the statutory bar to
    “marks that are offensive [or] shocking to a substantial
    segment of the public because of their mode of expression,
    independent of any views that they may express.” 
    Id., at 11
    (emphasis added); see Brief for Petitioner 27–28. More
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)                 9
    Opinion of the Court
    concretely, the Government explains that this reinterpre-
    tation would mostly restrict the PTO to refusing marks
    that are “vulgar”—meaning “lewd,” “sexually explicit or
    profane.” 
    Id., at 27,
    30. Such a reconfigured bar, the
    Government says, would not turn on viewpoint, and so we
    could uphold it.
    But we cannot accept the Government’s proposal, be-
    cause the statute says something markedly different. This
    Court, of course, may interpret “ambiguous statutory
    language” to “avoid serious constitutional doubts.” FCC v.
    Fox Television Stations, Inc., 
    556 U.S. 502
    , 516 (2009).
    But that canon of construction applies only when ambiguity
    exists. “We will not rewrite a law to conform it to consti-
    tutional requirements.” United States v. Stevens, 
    559 U.S. 460
    , 481 (2010) (internal quotation marks and alter-
    ation omitted). So even assuming the Government’s read-
    ing would eliminate First Amendment problems, we may
    adopt it only if we can see it in the statutory language.
    And we cannot. The “immoral or scandalous” bar stretches
    far beyond the Government’s proposed construction.
    The statute as written does not draw the line at lewd,
    sexually explicit, or profane marks. Nor does it refer only
    to marks whose “mode of expression,” independent of
    viewpoint, is particularly offensive. Brief for Petitioner 28
    (internal quotation marks omitted). It covers the universe
    of immoral or scandalous—or (to use some PTO synonyms)
    offensive or disreputable—material. Whether or not lewd
    or profane. Whether the scandal and immorality comes
    from mode or instead from viewpoint. To cut the statute
    off where the Government urges is not to interpret the
    statute Congress enacted, but to fashion a new one.*
    ——————
    *We reject the dissent’s statutory surgery for the same reason. Al-
    though conceding that the term “immoral” cannot be saved, the dissent
    thinks that the term “scandalous” can be read as the Government
    proposes. See post, at 1–2 (SOTOMAYOR, J., concurring in part and
    dissenting in part). But that term is not “ambiguous,” as the dissent
    10                       IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of the Court
    And once the “immoral or scandalous” bar is interpreted
    fairly, it must be invalidated. The Government just barely
    argues otherwise. In the last paragraph of its brief, the
    Government gestures toward the idea that the provision is
    salvageable by virtue of its constitutionally permissible
    applications (in the Government’s view, its applications to
    lewd, sexually explicit, or profane marks). See 
    id., at 47.
    In other words, the Government invokes our First
    Amendment overbreadth doctrine, and asks us to uphold
    the statute against facial attack because its unconstitu-
    tional applications are not “substantial” relative to “the
    statute’s plainly legitimate sweep.” 
    Stevens, 559 U.S., at 473
    (internal quotation marks omitted). But to begin
    with, this Court has never applied that kind of analysis to
    a viewpoint-discriminatory law. In Tam, for example, we
    did not pause to consider whether the disparagement
    clause might admit some permissible applications (say, to
    certain libelous speech) before striking it down. The
    Court’s finding of viewpoint bias ended the matter. And
    similarly, it seems unlikely we would compare permissible
    and impermissible applications if Congress outright
    banned “offensive” (or to use some other examples, “divi-
    sive” or “subversive”) speech. Once we have found that a
    law “aim[s] at the suppression of ” views, why would it
    ——————
    argues, post, at 3; it is just broad. Remember that the dictionaries
    define it to mean offensive, disreputable, exciting reprobation, and so
    forth. 
    See supra, at 5
    –6; post, at 3 (accepting those definitions). Even if
    hived off from “immoral” marks, the category of scandalous marks thus
    includes both marks that offend by the ideas they convey and marks
    that offend by their mode of expression. And its coverage of the former
    means that it discriminates based on viewpoint. We say nothing at all
    about a statute that covers only the latter—or, in the Government’s
    more concrete description, a statute limited to lewd, sexually explicit,
    and profane marks. Nor do we say anything about how to evaluate
    viewpoint-neutral restrictions on trademark registration, see post, at
    14–17—because the “scandalous” bar (whether or not attached to the
    “immoral” bar) is not one.
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)          11
    Opinion of the Court
    matter that Congress could have captured some of the
    same speech through a viewpoint-neutral statute? Tam,
    582 U. S., at ___ (opinion of Kennedy, J.) (slip op., at 2).
    But in any event, the “immoral or scandalous” bar is sub-
    stantially overbroad. There are a great many immoral and
    scandalous ideas in the world (even more than there are
    swearwords), and the Lanham Act covers them all. It
    therefore violates the First Amendment.
    We accordingly affirm the judgment of the Court of
    Appeals.
    It is so ordered.
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)            1
    ALITO, J., concurring
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 18–302
    _________________
    ANDREI IANCU, UNDER SECRETARY OF COMMERCE
    FOR INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND DIRECTOR,
    PATENT AND TRADEMARK OFFICE,
    PETITIONER v. ERIK BRUNETTI
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FEDERAL CIRCUIT
    [June 24, 2019]
    JUSTICE ALITO, concurring.
    For the reasons explained in the opinion of the Court,
    the provision of the Lanham Act at issue in this case
    violates the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment
    because it discriminates on the basis of viewpoint and
    cannot be fixed without rewriting the statute. Viewpoint
    discrimination is poison to a free society. But in many
    countries with constitutions or legal traditions that claim
    to protect freedom of speech, serious viewpoint discrimina-
    tion is now tolerated, and such discrimination has become
    increasingly prevalent in this country. At a time when
    free speech is under attack, it is especially important for
    this Court to remain firm on the principle that the First
    Amendment does not tolerate viewpoint discrimination.
    We reaffirm that principle today.
    Our decision is not based on moral relativism but on the
    recognition that a law banning speech deemed by govern-
    ment officials to be “immoral” or “scandalous” can easily
    be exploited for illegitimate ends. Our decision does not
    prevent Congress from adopting a more carefully focused
    statute that precludes the registration of marks contain-
    ing vulgar terms that play no real part in the expression of
    ideas. The particular mark in question in this case could
    2                  IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    ALITO, J., concurring
    be denied registration under such a statute. The term
    suggested by that mark is not needed to express any idea
    and, in fact, as commonly used today, generally signifies
    nothing except emotion and a severely limited vocabulary.
    The registration of such marks serves only to further
    coarsen our popular culture. But we are not legislators
    and cannot substitute a new statute for the one now in
    force.
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)                   1
    ROBERTS, C. J., concurring inOBERTS
    Opinion of R  part and
    , C. dissenting
    J.         in part
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 18–302
    _________________
    ANDREI IANCU, UNDER SECRETARY OF COMMERCE
    FOR INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND DIRECTOR,
    PATENT AND TRADEMARK OFFICE,
    PETITIONER v. ERIK BRUNETTI
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FEDERAL CIRCUIT
    [June 24, 2019]
    CHIEF JUSTICE ROBERTS, concurring in part and dissent-
    ing in part.
    The Lanham Act directs the Patent and Trademark
    Office to refuse registration to marks that consist of or
    comprise “immoral, deceptive, or scandalous matter.” 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a). Although the statute lists “immoral”
    and “scandalous” separately, the PTO has long read those
    terms together to constitute a unitary bar on “immoral or
    scandalous” marks.
    The Government concedes that the provision so read is
    broad enough to reach not only marks that offend because
    of their mode of expression (such as vulgarity and profanity)
    but also marks that offend because of the ideas they con-
    vey. The Government urges, however, that the provision
    can be given a narrowing construction—it can be under-
    stood to cover only marks that offend because of their
    mode of expression.
    The Court rejects that proposal on the ground that it
    would in effect rewrite the statute. I agree with the ma-
    jority that the “immoral” portion of the provision is not
    susceptible of a narrowing construction that would elimi-
    nate its viewpoint bias. As JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR explains,
    however, the “scandalous” portion of the provision is sus-
    2                      IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    ROBERTS, C. J., concurring inOBERTS
    Opinion of R  part and
    , C. dissenting
    J.         in part
    ceptible of such a narrowing construction. Standing alone,
    the term “scandalous” need not be understood to reach
    marks that offend because of the ideas they convey; it can
    be read more narrowly to bar only marks that offend
    because of their mode of expression—marks that are
    obscene, vulgar, or profane. That is how the PTO now
    understands the term, in light of our decision in Matal v.
    Tam, 582 U. S. ___ (2017). See Tr. of Oral Arg. 4–5. I
    agree with JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR that such a narrowing
    construction is appropriate in this context.
    I also agree that, regardless of how exactly the trade-
    mark registration system is best conceived under our
    precedents—a question we left open in Tam—refusing
    registration to obscene, vulgar, or profane marks does not
    offend the First Amendment. Whether such marks can be
    registered does not affect the extent to which their owners
    may use them in commerce to identify goods. No speech is
    being restricted; no one is being punished. The owners of
    such marks are merely denied certain additional benefits
    associated with federal trademark registration. The Gov-
    ernment, meanwhile, has an interest in not associating
    itself with trademarks whose content is obscene, vulgar, or
    profane. The First Amendment protects the freedom of
    speech; it does not require the Government to give aid and
    comfort to those using obscene, vulgar, and profane modes
    of expression. For those reasons, I concur in part and
    dissent in part.
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)            1
    Opinion of BREYER, J.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 18–302
    _________________
    ANDREI IANCU, UNDER SECRETARY OF COMMERCE
    FOR INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND DIRECTOR,
    PATENT AND TRADEMARK OFFICE,
    PETITIONER v. ERIK BRUNETTI
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FEDERAL CIRCUIT
    [June 24, 2019]
    JUSTICE BREYER, concurring in part and dissenting in
    part.
    Our precedents warn us against interpreting statutes in
    ways that would likely render them unconstitutional.
    Virginia v. American Booksellers Assn., Inc., 
    484 U.S. 383
    ,
    397 (1988) (noting that a law “will be upheld” if it is
    “ ‘readily susceptible’ to a narrowing construction that
    would make it constitutional”); United States v. 12 200-ft.
    Reels of Super 8MM. Film, 
    413 U.S. 123
    , 130, n. 7 (1973)
    (noting our “duty” to adopt a “ ‘fairly possible’ ” construc-
    tion by which constitutional doubts “ ‘may be avoided’ ”
    (quoting United States v. Thirty-seven Photographs, 
    402 U.S. 363
    , 369 (1971))). Following these precedents, I
    agree with JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR that, for the reasons she
    gives, we should interpret the word “scandalous” in the
    present statute to refer only to certain highly “vulgar” or
    “obscene” modes of expression. See post, at 6–7 (opinion
    concurring in part and dissenting in part).
    The question, then, is whether the First Amendment
    permits the Government to rely on this statute, as nar-
    rowly construed, to deny the benefits of federal trademark
    registration to marks like the one at issue here, which
    involves the use of the term “FUCT” in connection with a
    2                    IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of BREYER, J.
    clothing line that includes apparel for children and in-
    fants. Like JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR, I believe the answer is
    “yes,” though my reasons differ slightly from hers.
    I
    A
    In my view, a category-based approach to the First
    Amendment cannot adequately resolve the problem before
    us. I would place less emphasis on trying to decide whether
    the statute at issue should be categorized as an exam-
    ple of “viewpoint discrimination,” “content discrimination,”
    “commercial speech,” “government speech,” or the like.
    Rather, as I have written before, I believe we would do
    better to treat this Court’s speech-related categories not as
    outcome-determinative rules, but instead as rules of
    thumb. See Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 576 U. S. ___, ___
    (2015) (opinion concurring in judgment) (slip op., at 1).
    After all, these rules are not absolute. The First
    Amendment is not the Tax Code. Indeed, even when we
    consider a regulation that is ostensibly “viewpoint discrim-
    inatory” or that is subject to “strict scrutiny,” we some-
    times find the regulation to be constitutional after weigh-
    ing the competing interests involved. See, e.g., Morse v.
    Frederick, 
    551 U.S. 393
    , 397 (2007) (“[S]chools may take
    steps to safeguard those entrusted to their care from
    speech that can reasonably be regarded as encouraging
    illegal drug use”); Williams-Yulee v. Florida Bar, 
    575 U.S. 433
    , ___ (2015) (slip op., at 8) (explaining that although
    “ ‘it is the rare case’ ” when a statute satisfies strict scru-
    tiny, “those cases do arise” (quoting Burson v. Freeman, 
    504 U.S. 191
    , 211 (1992) (plurality opinion))).
    Unfortunately, the Court has sometimes applied these
    rules—especially the category of “content discrimina-
    tion”—too rigidly. In a number of cases, the Court has
    struck down what I believe are ordinary, valid regulations
    that pose little or no threat to the speech interests that the
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)            3
    Opinion of BREYER, J.
    First Amendment protects. See Janus v. State, County,
    and Municipal Employees, 585 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2018)
    (KAGAN, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 27–28); Sorrell v. IMS
    Health Inc., 
    564 U.S. 552
    , 589–592 (2011) (BREYER, J.,
    dissenting); see generally Reed, 576 U. S., at ___–___
    (opinion of BREYER, J.) (slip op., at 2–4).
    Rather than deducing the answers to First Amendment
    questions strictly from categories, as the Court often does,
    I would appeal more often and more directly to the values
    the First Amendment seeks to protect. As I have previ-
    ously written, I would ask whether the regulation at issue
    “works speech-related harm that is out of proportion to its
    justifications.” United States v. Alvarez, 
    567 U.S. 709
    ,
    730 (2012) (opinion concurring in judgment); see Reed, 576
    U. S., at ___ (opinion concurring in judgment) (slip op., at
    4) (discussing the matter further, particularly in respect to
    the category of content discrimination).
    B
    This case illustrates the limits of relying on rigid First
    Amendment categories, for the statute at issue does not fit
    easily into any of these categories.
    The Court has not decided whether the trademark
    statute is simply a method of regulating pure “commercial
    speech.” See Matal v. Tam, 582 U. S. ___, ___ (2017)
    (opinion of ALITO, J.) (slip op., at 24) (leaving open the
    question whether trademarks are commercial speech); id.,
    at ___ (opinion of Kennedy, J.) (slip op., at 5) (same).
    There may be reasons for doubt on that score. Trade-
    marks, after all, have an expressive component in addition
    to a commercial one, and the statute does not bar anyone
    from speaking. To be sure, the statute does regulate the
    commercial function of trademarks. But it does so in a
    limited way designed primarily to ensure that a mark
    identifies the product’s source. See Wal-Mart Stores, Inc.
    v. Samara Brothers, Inc., 
    529 U.S. 205
    , 212 (2000).
    4                   IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of BREYER, J.
    The trademark statute cannot easily be described as a
    regulation of “government speech,” either. Tam, 582 U. S.,
    at ___–___ (slip op., at 12–18). The Government, however,
    may be loosely associated with the mark because it regis-
    ters the mark and confers certain benefits upon the owner.
    What about the concept of a “public forum”? Trademark
    registration has little in common with a traditional public
    forum, as the register of trademarks is not a public park, a
    street, or a similar forum for public debate. See Perry Ed.
    Assn. v. Perry Local Educators’ Assn., 
    460 U.S. 37
    , 45
    (1983). But one can find some vague resemblance between
    trademark registration and what this Court refers to as a
    “limited public forum” created by the government for
    private speech. See post, at 15 (opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.);
    Christian Legal Soc. Chapter of Univ. of Cal., Hastings
    College of Law v. Martinez, 
    561 U.S. 661
    , 679, n. 11
    (2010). The trademark registration system also bears
    some resemblance to cases involving government subsidies
    for private speech, as such programs—like trademark
    registration—may grant a benefit to some forms of speech
    without prohibiting other forms of speech. See post, at 15
    (opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.); Legal Services Corporation v.
    Velazquez, 
    531 U.S. 533
    , 543–544 (2001) (noting that the
    First Amendment rules applicable to limited public forums
    may be “instruc[tive]” “when the government establishes a
    subsidy for specified ends”).
    As for the concepts of “viewpoint discrimination” and
    “content discrimination,” I agree with JUSTICE
    SOTOMAYOR that the boundaries between them may be
    difficult to discern. Post, at 10; see Rosenberger v. Rector
    and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 
    515 U.S. 819
    , 831 (1995)
    (“[T]he distinction is not a precise one”). Even so, it is
    hard to see how a statute prohibiting the registration of
    only highly vulgar or obscene words discriminates based
    on “viewpoint.” Of course, such words often evoke power-
    ful emotions. Standing by themselves, however, these
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)            5
    Opinion of BREYER, J.
    words do not typically convey any particular viewpoint.
    See FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, 
    438 U.S. 726
    , 746, n. 22
    (1978) (noting that the Government’s regulation of vulgar
    words was based not on “point of view,” but on “the way in
    which [speech] is expressed”). Moreover, while a re-
    striction on the registration of highly vulgar words argu-
    ably places a content-based limit on trademark registration,
    it is hard to see why that label should be outcome-
    determinative here, for regulations governing trademark
    registration “inevitably involve content discrimination.”
    Reed, 576 U. S., at ___ (opinion of BREYER, J.) (slip op., at
    3); see Tam, 582 U. S., at ___ (opinion of Kennedy, J.)
    (slip op., at 6) (noting that the constitutionality of some
    content-based trademark restrictions is “well settled”);
    Katyal, Trademark Intersectionality, 57 UCLA L. Rev.
    1601, 1602 (2010) (noting that trademark law is “indelibly
    rooted in content-based considerations”).
    In short, the trademark statute does not clearly fit
    within any of the existing outcome-determinative catego-
    ries. Why, then, should we rigidly adhere to these catego-
    ries? Rather than puzzling over categorization, I believe
    we should focus on the interests the First Amendment
    protects and ask a more basic proportionality question:
    Does “the regulation at issue wor[k] harm to First
    Amendment interests that is disproportionate in light of
    the relevant regulatory objectives”? Reed, 576 U. S., at ___
    (opinion of BREYER, J.) (slip op., at 4).
    II
    Based on this proportionality analysis, I would conclude
    that the statute at issue here, as interpreted by JUSTICE
    SOTOMAYOR, does not violate the First Amendment.
    How much harm to First Amendment interests does a
    bar on registering highly vulgar or obscene trademarks
    work? Not much. The statute leaves businesses free to
    use highly vulgar or obscene words on their products, and
    6                   IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of BREYER, J.
    even to use such words directly next to other registered
    marks. Indeed, a business owner might even use a vulgar
    word as a trademark, provided that he or she is willing to
    forgo the benefits of registration. See post, at 2 (opinion
    of SOTOMAYOR, J.); Tam, 582 U. S., at ___–___ (slip op.,
    at 4–5).
    Moreover, the field at issue here, trademark law, is a
    highly regulated one with a specialized mission: to “hel[p]
    consumers identify goods and services that they wish to
    purchase, as well as those they want to avoid.” Id., at ___
    (slip op., at 2). As I have noted, that mission, by its very
    nature, requires the Government to impose limitations on
    speech. Supra, at 5. Trademark law therefore forbids the
    registration of certain types of words—for example, those
    that will likely “cause confusion,” or those that are “merely
    descriptive.” 
    15 U.S. C
    . §§1052(d), (e). For that reason,
    an applicant who seeks to register a mark should not
    expect complete freedom to say what she wishes, but
    should instead expect linguistic regulation.
    Now consider, by way of contrast, the Government’s
    interests in barring the registration of highly vulgar or
    obscene trademarks. For one thing, when the Government
    registers a mark, it is necessarily “involv[ed] in promot-
    ing” that mark. Post, at 18 (opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.).
    The Government has at least a reasonable interest in
    ensuring that it is not involved in promoting highly vulgar
    or obscene speech, and that it will not be associated with
    such speech.
    For another, scientific evidence suggests that certain
    highly vulgar words have a physiological and emotional
    impact that makes them different in kind from most other
    words. See M. Mohr, Holy S***: A Brief History of Swear-
    ing 252 (2013) (Mohr) (noting the “emotional impact” of
    certain profane words that “excite the lower-brain circuitry
    responsible for emotion,” resulting in “electrical impulses
    that can be measured in the skin”). These vulgar words
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)           7
    Opinion of BREYER, J.
    originate in a different part of our brains than most other
    words. 
    Id., at 250.
    And these types of swear words tend
    to attract more attention and are harder to forget than
    other words. See Jay, Caldwell-Harris, & King, Recalling
    Taboo and Nontaboo Words, 121 Am. J. Psych. 83, 83–86
    (2008) (collecting research). Notably, that has remained
    true even as the list of offensive swear words has changed
    over time: In the last few centuries, the list has evolved
    away from words of religious disrespect and toward words
    that are sexually explicit or that crudely describe bodily
    functions. Mohr 253. And the list of swear words may be
    evolving yet again, perhaps in the direction of including
    race-based epithets. 
    Id., at 254,
    256.
    These attention-grabbing words, though financially
    valuable to some businesses that seek to attract interest in
    their products, threaten to distract consumers and disrupt
    commerce. And they may lead to the creation of public
    spaces that many will find repellant, perhaps on occasion
    creating the risk of verbal altercations or even physical
    confrontations. (Just think about how you might react if
    you saw someone wearing a t-shirt or using a product
    emblazoned with an odious racial epithet.) The Govern-
    ment thus has an interest in seeking to disincentivize the
    use of such words in commerce by denying the benefit of
    trademark registration. Cf. Brandenburg v. Ohio, 
    395 U.S. 444
    , 447 (1969) (per curiam) (permitting regulation
    of words “directed to inciting or producing imminent law-
    less action” and “likely to incite or produce such action”).
    Finally, although some consumers may be attracted to
    products labeled with highly vulgar or obscene words,
    others may believe that such words should not be dis-
    played in public spaces where goods are sold and where
    children are likely to be present. They may believe that
    trademark registration of such words could make it more
    likely that children will be exposed to public displays
    involving such words. To that end, the Government may
    8                   IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of BREYER, J.
    have an interest in protecting the sensibilities of children
    by barring the registration of such words. See Denver
    Area Ed. Telecommunications Consortium, Inc. v. FCC,
    
    518 U.S. 727
    , 743 (1996) (plurality opinion) (noting the
    Government’s interest in “protec[ting] children from expo-
    sure to patently offensive sex-related material”); Ginsberg
    v. New York, 
    390 U.S. 629
    , 640 (1968) (noting the gov-
    ernment’s “interest in the well-being of its youth”).
    The upshot of this analysis is that the narrowing con-
    struction articulated by JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR risks some
    harm to First Amendment interests, but not very much.
    And applying that interpretation seems a reasonable
    way—perhaps the only way—to further legitimate gov-
    ernment interests. Of course, there is a risk that the
    statute might be applied in a manner that stretches it
    beyond the few vulgar words that are encompassed by the
    narrow interpretation JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR sets forth.
    That risk, however, could be mitigated by internal agency
    review to ensure that agency officials do not stray beyond
    their mandate. In any event, I do not believe that this risk
    alone warrants the facial invalidation of this statute.
    I would conclude that the prohibition on registering
    “scandalous” marks does not “wor[k] harm to First
    Amendment interests that is disproportionate in light of
    the relevant regulatory objectives.” Reed, 576 U. S., at ___
    (opinion of BREYER, J.) (slip op., at 4). I would therefore
    uphold this part of the statute. I agree with the Court,
    however, that the bar on registering “immoral” marks
    violates the First Amendment.             Because JUSTICE
    SOTOMAYOR reaches the same conclusions, using roughly
    similar reasoning, I join her opinion insofar as it is con-
    sistent with the views set forth here.
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)           1
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 18–302
    _________________
    ANDREI IANCU, UNDER SECRETARY OF COMMERCE
    FOR INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND DIRECTOR,
    PATENT AND TRADEMARK OFFICE,
    PETITIONER v. ERIK BRUNETTI
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FEDERAL CIRCUIT
    [June 24, 2019]
    JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR, with whom JUSTICE BREYER joins,
    concurring in part and dissenting in part.
    The Court’s decision today will beget unfortunate re-
    sults. With the Lanham Act’s scandalous-marks provi-
    sion, 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1052(a), struck down as unconstitutional
    viewpoint discrimination, the Government will have no
    statutory basis to refuse (and thus no choice but to begin)
    registering marks containing the most vulgar, profane, or
    obscene words and images imaginable.
    The coming rush to register such trademarks—and the
    Government’s immediate powerlessness to say no—is
    eminently avoidable. Rather than read the relevant text
    as the majority does, it is equally possible to read that
    provision’s bar on the registration of “scandalous” marks
    to address only obscenity, vulgarity, and profanity. Such a
    narrowing construction would save that duly enacted
    legislative text by rendering it a reasonable, viewpoint-
    neutral restriction on speech that is permissible in the
    context of a beneficial governmental initiative like the
    trademark-registration system. I would apply that nar-
    rowing construction to the term “scandalous” and accord-
    ingly reject petitioner Erik Brunetti’s facial challenge.
    2                    IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    I
    Trademark registration, as the majority notes, is not
    required for using, owning, or suing others for infringing a
    trademark. Rather, the trademark-registration system is
    an ancillary system set up by the Government that confers
    a small number of noncash benefits on trademark-holders
    who register their marks. See ante, at 2.
    The Government need not provide this largely commer-
    cial benefit at all. Once the Government does provide the
    benefit, however, it may not restrict access on the basis of
    the viewpoint expressed by the relevant mark. See ante,
    at 4–5. For that reason, the Court concluded in Matal v.
    Tam, 582 U. S. ___ (2017), that §1052(a)’s provision direct-
    ing the U. S. Patent and Trademark Office (PTO) to deny
    registration to “disparag[ing]” trademarks was unconstitu-
    tional. This case centers on a neighboring set of re-
    strictions: §1052(a)’s provision barring registration of
    marks featuring “immoral . . . or scandalous matter.”
    The majority finds viewpoint discrimination here by
    treating the terms “scandalous” and “immoral” as compris-
    ing a unified standard that allows messages “aligned with
    conventional moral standards” but forbids messages “hos-
    tile to” such standards. See ante, at 6. While the major-
    ity’s interpretation of the statute is a reasonable one, it is
    not the only reasonable one.
    A
    As the majority notes, there are dictionary definitions
    for both “immoral” and “scandalous” that do suggest a
    viewpoint-discriminatory meaning. See ante, at 5–6. And
    as for the word “immoral,” I agree with the majority that
    there is no tenable way to read it that would ameliorate
    the problem. The word clearly connotes a preference for
    “rectitude and morality” over its opposite. See ante, at 5.
    It is with regard to the word “scandalous” that I part
    ways with the majority. Unquestionably, “scandalous” can
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)           3
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    mean something similar to “immoral” and thus favor some
    viewpoints over others. See ante, at 6. But it does not
    have to be read that way. To say that a word or image is
    “scandalous” can instead mean that it is simply indecent,
    shocking, or generally offensive. See Funk & Wagnalls
    New Standard Dictionary 2186 (1944) (Funk & Wagnalls)
    (“shocking to the sense of truth, decency, or propriety;
    disgraceful, offensive” (emphasis added)); Webster’s New
    International Dictionary 2229 (1942) (“exciting reproba-
    tion; calling out condemnation”); 9 Oxford English Diction-
    ary 175 (1933) (“Of the nature of, or causing, a ‘stumbling-
    block’ or occasion of offence”); 8 Century Dictionary
    and Cyclopedia 5374 (1911) (Century Dictionary) (“Caus-
    ing scandal or offense; exciting reproach or reprobation;
    extremely offensive to the sense of duty or propriety;
    shameful; shocking”); see also Webster’s New College
    Dictionary 1008 (3d ed. 2005) (“shocking or offensive”).
    That offensiveness could result from the views expressed,
    but it could also result from the way in which those views
    are expressed: using a manner of expression that is
    “shocking to [one’s] sense of . . . decency,” Funk & Wag-
    nalls 2186, or “extremely offensive to the sense of . . .
    propriety,” 8 Century Dictionary 5374.
    The word “scandalous” on its own, then, is ambiguous:
    It can be read broadly (to cover both offensive ideas and
    offensive manners of expressing ideas), or it can be read
    narrowly (to cover only offensive modes of expression).
    That alone raises the possibility that a limiting construc-
    tion might be appropriate. But the broader text confirms
    the reasonableness of the narrower reading, because the
    word “scandalous” appears in the statute alongside other
    words that can, and should, be read to constrain its scope.
    It is foundational “that a statute is to be read as a
    whole, since the meaning of statutory language, plain or
    not, depends on context.” King v. St. Vincent’s Hospital,
    
    502 U.S. 215
    , 221 (1991) (citation omitted). “ ‘Words are
    4                         IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    not pebbles in alien juxtaposition; they have only a com-
    munal existence; and not only does the meaning of each
    interpenetrate the other, but all in their aggregate take
    their purport from the setting in which they are used.’ ”
    
    Ibid. (quoting NLRB v.
    Federbush Co., 
    121 F.2d 954
    , 957
    (CA2 1941) (L. Hand, J.)). Accordingly, and relatedly,
    courts should, to the extent possible, read statutes so that
    “ ‘no clause, sentence, or word shall be superfluous, void, or
    insignificant.’ ” TRW Inc. v. Andrews, 
    534 U.S. 19
    , 31
    (2001).1
    Here, Congress used not only the word “scandalous,” but
    also the words “immoral” and “disparage,” in the same
    block of statutory text—each as a separate feature that
    could render a mark unregistrable. See §1052(a). Tam
    already decided that “disparage” served to prohibit marks
    that were offensive because they derided a particular
    person or group. See 582 U. S., at ___ (opinion of ALITO,
    J.) (slip op., at 22) (“It denies registration to any mark that
    is offensive to a substantial percentage of the members of
    any group”); id., at ___ (opinion of Kennedy, J.) (slip op., at
    2) (“[A]n applicant may register a positive or benign mark
    but not a derogatory one”). That defines one of the three
    words. Meanwhile, as the majority explains, the word
    “immoral” prohibits marks that are offensive because they
    transgress widely held moral beliefs. See ante, at 5. That
    defines a second of the three words.
    With marks that are offensive because they are dispar-
    aging and marks that are offensive because they are im-
    moral already covered, what work did Congress intend for
    ——————
    1 For example, McDonnell v. United States, 579 U. S. ___ (2016), in-
    volved a statute that defined an “ ‘official act’ ” as “ ‘any decision or
    action on any question, matter, cause, suit, proceeding or controversy.’ ”
    Id., at ___ (slip op., at 13). The Court declined to read “ ‘question’ ” and
    “ ‘matter’ ” as covering “a typical meeting, call, or event arranged by a
    public official” because doing so would deprive the words “ ‘cause, suit,
    proceeding or controversy’ ” of meaning. Id., at ___ (slip op., at 16).
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)                 5
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    “scandalous” to do? A logical answer is that Congress
    meant for “scandalous” to target a third and distinct type
    of offensiveness: offensiveness in the mode of communica-
    tion rather than the idea. The other two words cover
    marks that are offensive because of the ideas they express;
    the “scandalous” clause covers marks that are offensive
    because of the mode of expression, apart from any particu-
    lar message or idea.
    To be sure, there are situations in which it makes sense
    to treat adjoining words as expressing the same or highly
    similar concepts (even at the risk of some redundancy).
    Cf. Swearingen v. United States, 
    161 U.S. 446
    , 450 (1896)
    (construing “ ‘obscene, lewd or lascivious’ ” to have a uni-
    fied meaning). That is essentially the approach that the
    majority takes. See ante, at 6.2 But that is not the ap-
    proach that Congress appears to have intended here. For
    example, “scandalous” does not serve as a broader catchall
    at the end of a list of similar words that all point in one
    direction. E.g., Washington State Dept. of Social and
    Health Servs. v. Guardianship Estate of Keffeler, 
    537 U.S. 371
    , 384 (2003). Nor is “scandalous” simply grouped
    among a number of closely related terms that help define
    its meaning. E.g., Gustafson v. Alloyd Co., 
    513 U.S. 561
    ,
    575 (1995).
    The text of §1052, instead, is a grab bag: It bars the
    registration of marks featuring “immoral, deceptive, or
    scandalous matter,” as well as, inter alia, disparaging
    marks, flags, insignias, mislabeled wines, and deceased
    Presidents. See §§1052(a)–(e). This is not, in other words,
    a situation in which Congress was simply being “verbos[e]
    ——————
    2 That interpretive move appears to accord with the Federal Circuit
    and the PTO’s past practice. Ante, at 2–3. Nevertheless, it is by no
    means the only reasonable way to read this text, and indeed some
    courts have suggested that “scandalous” can and should be applied
    independently of “immoral,” see, e.g., In re McGinley, 
    660 F.2d 481
    ,
    485, n. 6 (CCPA 1981).
    6                        IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    and proli[x],” Bruesewitz v. Wyeth LLC, 
    562 U.S. 223
    , 236
    (2011), using two synonyms in rapid-fire succession when
    one would have done fine. Instead, “scandalous” and
    “immoral” are separated by an unrelated word (“decep-
    tive”) and mixed in with a lengthy series of other, unre-
    lated concepts. The two therefore need not be interpreted as
    mutually reinforcing under the Court’s precedents. See
    Graham County Soil and Water Conservation Dist. v.
    United States ex rel. Wilson, 
    559 U.S. 280
    , 288 (2010).
    For that reason, while the majority offers a reasonable
    reading of “scandalous,” it also unnecessarily and ill-
    advisedly collapses the words “scandalous” and “immoral.”
    Instead, it should treat them as each holding a distinct,
    nonredundant meaning, with “immoral” covering marks
    that are offensive because they transgress social norms,
    and “scandalous” covering marks that are offensive be-
    cause of the mode in which they are expressed.
    What would it mean for “scandalous” in §1052(a) to
    cover only offensive modes of expression? The most obvi-
    ous ways—indeed, perhaps the only conceivable ways—in
    which a trademark can be expressed in a shocking or
    offensive manner are when the speaker employs obscenity,
    vulgarity, or profanity.3 Obscenity has long been defined
    by this Court’s decision in Miller v. California, 
    413 U.S. 15
    (1973). See 
    id., at 24–26.
    As for what constitutes
    “scandalous” vulgarity or profanity, I do not offer a list,
    but I do interpret the term to allow the PTO to restrict
    (and potentially promulgate guidance to clarify) the small
    group of lewd words or “swear” words that cause a visceral
    reaction, that are not commonly used around children, and
    that are prohibited in comparable settings.4 Cf. 18
    ——————
    3 Other modes of expression, such as fighting words or extremely loud
    noises, could also be called shocking or offensive in certain contexts, see
    R. A. V. v. St. Paul, 
    505 U.S. 377
    , 386 (1992), but it is hard to see how
    they would apply in the context of a trademark.
    4 Although the Government represents, and case law and scholarship
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)                     7
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    U. S. C. §1464 (prohibiting “obscene, indecent, or profane
    language” in radio communications); FCC v. Pacifica
    Foundation, 
    438 U.S. 726
    , 746, and n. 22 (1978) (opinion
    of Stevens, J.) (regulator’s objection to a monologue con-
    taining various “four-letter words” was not to its “point of
    view, but to the way in which it [wa]s expressed”); 46 CFR
    §67.117(b)(3) (2018) (Coast Guard regulation prohibiting
    vessel names that “contain” or are “phonetically identical
    to obscene, indecent, or profane language, or to racial or
    ethnic epithets”); see also Jacobs, The Public Sensibilities
    Forum, 95 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1357, 1416–1417, and n. 432
    (2001) (noting that “swear words” are “perhaps more than
    any other categor[y] capable of specific articulation” and
    citing one state agency’s list). Of course, “scandalous”
    offers its own limiting principle: if a word, though not
    exactly polite, cannot be said to be “scandalous”—e.g.,
    “shocking” or “extremely offensive,” 8 Century Dictionary
    5374—it is clearly not the kind of vulgarity or profanity
    that Congress intended to target. Everyone can think of a
    small number of words (including the apparent homonym
    of Brunetti’s mark) that would, however, plainly qualify.5
    ——————
    appear to confirm, that “scandalous” in §1052(a) has often been applied
    to cover this kind of content, see Brief for United States 27; In re
    Boulevard Entertainment, Inc., 
    334 F.3d 1336
    , 1340 (CA Fed. 2003);
    Snow, Denying Trademark for Scandalous Speech, 51 U. C. D. L. Rev.
    2331, 2339 (2018) (Snow), the majority notes that the PTO has hardly
    amassed a perfect track record of consistency, see ante, at 6–8. Be that
    as it may, the Government undeniably receives a large volume of
    trademark applications that easily would fit under this rubric (exam-
    ples of which I will spare the reader). See In re Brunetti, 
    877 F.3d 1330
    , 1355 (CA Fed. 2017) (noting an appendix containing marks
    denied registration “whose offensiveness cannot be reasonably ques-
    tioned”). As a result of today’s ruling, all of those marks will now
    presumably have to be registered.
    5 There is at least one particularly egregious racial epithet that would
    fit this description as well. While Matal v. Tam, 582 U. S. ___ (2017),
    removed a statutory basis to deny the registration of racial epithets in
    general, the Government represented at oral argument that it is
    8                        IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    B
    A limiting construction like the one just discussed is
    both appropriate in this context and consistent with past
    precedent. First, while a limiting construction must al-
    ways be at least reasonable, there are contexts in which
    imposing such a construction is more appropriate than
    others. The most obvious example of a setting where more
    caution is required is in the realm of criminal statutes,
    where considerations such as the prohibition against
    vagueness and the rule of lenity come into play. See Reno
    v. American Civil Liberties Union, 
    521 U.S. 844
    , 872
    (1997) (noting that “[t]he severity of criminal sanctions”
    can increase First Amendment concerns); Board of Airport
    Comm’rs of Los Angeles v. Jews for Jesus, Inc., 
    482 U.S. 569
    , 575–576 (1987) (declining to apply a limiting con-
    struction to a provision that banned “ ‘First Amendment
    activities’ ” from an airport and noting that the limiting
    construction proposed would “ ‘confe[r] on police a virtually
    unrestrained power to arrest and charge persons with a
    violation,’ ” leading to “ ‘self-evident’ ” “ ‘opportunity for
    abuse’ ”). Here, however, the question is only whether the
    Government must be forced to provide the ancillary bene-
    fit of trademark registration to pre-existing trademarks
    that use even the most extreme obscenity, vulgarity, or
    profanity. The stakes are far removed from a situation in
    which, say, Brunetti was facing a threat to his liberty, or
    even his right to use and enforce his trademark in
    commerce.
    Second, the Court has in the past accepted or applied
    similarly narrow constructions to avoid constitutional
    ——————
    holding in abeyance trademark applications that use that particular
    epithet. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 61. As a result of today’s ruling, the
    Government will now presumably be compelled to register marks
    containing that epithet as well rather than treating it as a “scandalous”
    form of profanity under §1052(a).
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)            9
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    infirmities. In Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 
    315 U.S. 568
    (1942), for example, the Court accepted the New
    Hampshire Supreme Court’s narrowing of a state statute
    covering “ ‘any offensive, derisive or annoying word,’ ” 
    id., at 569,
    to reach only those words that would strike the
    average person as being “plainly likely to cause a breach of
    the peace by the addressee,” 
    id., at 573.
    “[T]hus con-
    strued,” this Court decided, the statute did not violate the
    right to free speech. Ibid.; see also Boos v. Barry, 
    485 U.S. 312
    , 329–330 (1988) (accepting Court of Appeals’
    construction of a statute making it illegal “ ‘to congregate
    within 500 feet of any [embassy, legation, or consulate]
    and refuse to disperse after having been ordered so to do
    by the police’ ” to reach only “congregations that are di-
    rected at an embassy” and “ ‘only when the police reason-
    ably believe that a threat to the security or peace of the
    embassy is present’ ”).
    In Frisby v. Schultz, 
    487 U.S. 474
    (1988), the Court
    addressed an ordinance that prohibited “ ‘picketing before
    or about the residence or dwelling of any individual.’ ” 
    Id., at 477.
    The Court construed the statute to reach only
    “focused picketing taking place solely in front of a particu-
    lar residence.” 
    Id., at 483.
    Given that “narrow scope,” the
    statute was not facially unconstitutional. 
    Id., at 488;
    see
    also In re Brunetti, 
    877 F.3d 1330
    , 1358 (CA Fed. 2017)
    (Dyk, J., concurring in judgment) (noting this Court’s
    narrow constructions of federal obscenity statutes).
    Taking the word “scandalous” to target only those
    marks that employ an offensive mode of expression follows
    a similar practice. To be sure, the word could be read
    more broadly, thereby sweeping unconstitutionally into
    viewpoint discrimination. And imposing a limiting con-
    struction is, of course, “not a license for the judiciary to
    rewrite language enacted by the legislature.” United
    States v. Albertini, 
    472 U.S. 675
    , 680 (1985). But where
    the Court can reasonably read a statute like this one to
    10                   IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    save it, the Court should do so. See Stern v. Marshall, 
    564 U.S. 462
    , 477–478 (2011); NLRB v. Jones & Laughlin
    Steel Corp., 
    301 U.S. 1
    , 30 (1937).
    II
    Adopting a narrow construction for the word “scandal-
    ous”—interpreting it to regulate only obscenity, vulgarity,
    and profanity—would save it from unconstitutionality.
    Properly narrowed, “scandalous” is a viewpoint-neutral
    form of content discrimination that is permissible in the
    kind of discretionary governmental program or limited
    forum typified by the trademark-registration system.
    A
    Content discrimination occurs whenever a government
    regulates “particular speech because of the topic discussed
    or the idea or message expressed.” Reed v. Town of Gil-
    bert, 576 U. S. ___, ___ (2015) (slip op., at 6); see also Ward
    v. Rock Against Racism, 
    491 U.S. 781
    , 791 (1989) (“Gov-
    ernment regulation of expressive activity is content neu-
    tral so long as it is ‘justified without reference to the con-
    tent of the regulated speech’ ”). Viewpoint discrimination
    is “an egregious form of content discrimination” in which
    “the government targets not subject matter, but particular
    views taken by speakers on a subject.” Rosenberger v.
    Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 
    515 U.S. 819
    , 829
    (1995).
    While the line between viewpoint-based and viewpoint-
    neutral content discrimination can be “slippery,” see
    Corbin, Mixed Speech: When Speech Is Both Private and
    Governmental, 83 N. Y. U. L. Rev. 605, 651 (2008), it is in
    any event clear that a regulation is not viewpoint discrim-
    inatory (or even content discriminatory) simply because it
    has an “incidental effect” on a certain subset of views.
    
    Ward, 491 U.S., at 791
    . Some people, for example, may
    have the viewpoint that society should be more sexually
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)                   11
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    liberated and feel that they cannot express that view
    sufficiently without the use of pornographic words or
    images. That does not automatically make a restriction on
    pornography into viewpoint discrimination, despite the
    fact that such a restriction limits communicating one’s
    views on sexual liberation in that way. See ibid.; Renton
    v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 
    475 U.S. 41
    , 48 (1986).
    Restrictions on particular modes of expression do not
    inherently qualify as viewpoint discrimination; they are
    not by nature examples of “the government target[ing] . . .
    particular views taken by speakers on a subject.” Rosen-
    
    berger, 515 U.S., at 829
    . For example, a ban on lighting
    fires in the town square does not facially violate the First
    Amendment simply because it makes it marginally harder
    for would-be flag-burners to express their views in that
    place. See R. A. V. v. St. Paul, 
    505 U.S. 377
    , 385 (1992).
    By the same token, “fighting words are categorically ex-
    cluded from the protection of the First Amendment” not
    because they have no content or express no viewpoint
    (often quite the opposite), but because “their content em-
    bodies a particularly intolerable (and socially unnecessary)
    mode of expressing whatever idea the speaker wishes to
    convey.” 
    Id., at 393;
    see 
    id., at 385–386;
    cf. Bolger v.
    Youngs Drug Products Corp., 
    463 U.S. 60
    , 84 (1983) (Ste-
    vens, J., concurring in judgment) (“It matters whether a
    law regulates communications for their ideas or for their
    style”).
    A restriction on trademarks featuring obscenity, vulgar-
    ity, or profanity is similarly viewpoint neutral, though it is
    naturally content-based.6 See R. A. 
    V., 505 U.S., at 383
    ——————
    6 Of course, obscenity itself is subject to a longstanding exception to
    First Amendment protection, see Brown v. Entertainment Merchants
    Assn., 
    564 U.S. 786
    , 791 (2011), so it is proscribable in any event. As
    for vulgarity and profanity, however, they are not subject to any such
    exception, and a regulation like §1052(a)’s ban on the registration of
    scandalous marks is not “ ‘justified without reference to the content of
    12                       IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    (kinds of speech like “obscenity, defamation, etc.” may “be
    regulated because of their constitutionally proscribable
    content” (emphasis deleted)); see also Bethel School Dist.
    No. 403 v. Fraser, 
    478 U.S. 675
    , 685 (1986) (treating
    punishment of “offensively lewd and indecent speech” as
    viewpoint neutral); 
    Pacifica, 438 U.S., at 745
    –746, and
    n. 22 (treating regulation of profane monologue as view-
    point neutral). Indeed, the statute that the Court upheld
    in Chaplinsky itself had been construed to cover, among
    other kinds of “disorderly words,” “profanity, obscenity
    and 
    threats,” 315 U.S., at 573
    , despite the fact that such
    words had been used in that case to communicate an
    expressive message, 
    id., at 574.
    To treat a restriction on
    vulgarity, profanity, or obscenity as viewpoint discrimina-
    tion would upend decades of precedent.7
    Brunetti invokes Cohen v. California, 
    403 U.S. 15
    (1971), to argue that the restriction at issue here is view-
    point discriminatory. But Cohen—which did not employ
    the precise taxonomy that is more common today—does
    not reach as far as Brunetti wants. Cohen arose in the
    criminal context: Cohen had been arrested and imprisoned
    under a California criminal statute targeting disturbances
    of the peace because he was “wearing a jacket bearing the
    words ‘F[***] the Draft.’ ” 
    Id., at 16.
    The Court held that
    applying that statute to Cohen because of his jacket vio-
    lated the First Amendment. 
    Id., at 26.
    But the Court did
    ——————
    the regulated speech’ ” in the way that a simple regulation of time,
    place, or manner is. Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 
    491 U.S. 781
    , 791
    (1989) (emphasis deleted).
    7 It would also risk destabilizing government practice in a number of
    other contexts. Governments regulate vulgarity and profanity, for
    example, on city-owned buses and billboards, e.g., American Freedom
    Defense Initiative v. Massachusetts Bay Transp. Auth., 
    989 F. Supp. 2d 182
    , 183 (Mass. 2013) (noting such a prohibition), on registered vessels,
    46 CFR §67.117(b)(3) (Coast Guard regulations), and at school events,
    e.g., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 
    478 U.S. 675
    , 677–678, 685
    (1986) (upholding discipline of high school student).
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)                13
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    not suggest that the State had targeted Cohen to suppress
    his view itself (i.e., his sharp distaste for the draft), such
    that it would have accepted an equally colorful statement
    of praise for the draft (or hostility toward war protesters).
    Rather, the Court suggested that the State had simply
    engaged in what later courts would more precisely call
    viewpoint-neutral content discrimination—it had regu-
    lated “the form or content of individual expression.” 
    Id., at 24;
    see 
    id., at 25–26.
       Cohen also famously recognized that “words are often
    chosen as much for their emotive as their cognitive force,”
    
    id., at 26,
    and that “one man’s vulgarity is another’s lyric,”
    
    id., at 25.
    That is all consistent with observing that a
    plain, blanket restriction on profanity (regardless of the
    idea to which it is attached) is a viewpoint-neutral form of
    content discrimination. The essence of Cohen’s discussion
    is that profanity can serve to tweak (or amplify) the view-
    point that a message expresses, such that it can be hard to
    disentangle the profanity from the underlying message—
    without the profanity, the message is not quite the same.
    See 
    id., at 25–26.
    But those statements merely reinforce
    that profanity is still properly understood as protected
    First Amendment content. See also R. A. 
    V., 505 U.S., at 384
    –385. Cohen’s discussion does not also go further to
    declare, as Brunetti suggests, that a provision that treats
    all instances of profanity equally is nevertheless by nature
    an instance of “the government target[ing] . . . particular
    views taken by speakers on a subject.” Rosen
    berger, 515 U.S., at 829
    . To be sure, such a restriction could have the
    incidental effect of tamping down the overall volume of
    debate on all sides. But differential effects alone, as ex-
    plained above, do not render a restriction viewpoint (or
    even content) discriminatory. See 
    Ward, 491 U.S., at 791
    –792.8
    ——————
    8 That   does not mean, of course, that a government may elude harsher
    14                       IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    Cohen therefore does not resolve this case in Brunetti’s
    favor. Yes, Brunetti has been, as Cohen was, subject to
    content discrimination, but that content discrimination is
    properly understood as viewpoint neutral. And whereas
    even viewpoint-neutral content discrimination is (in all
    but the most compelling cases, such as threats) impermis-
    sible in the context of a criminal prosecution like the one
    that Cohen faced, Brunetti is subject to such regulation
    only in the context of the federal trademark-registration
    system. I discuss next why that distinction matters.
    B
    While the Court has often subjected even viewpoint-
    neutral content discrimination to strict constitutional
    scrutiny, see, e.g., Reed, 576 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 6),
    there are contexts in which it does not, see, e.g., Rosen-
    
    berger, 515 U.S., at 829
    –830. When that is the case, the
    difference between viewpoint-based and viewpoint-neutral
    content discrimination can be decisive.           The federal
    trademark-registration system is such a context.
    Rights to a trademark itself arise through use, not
    registration. Regardless of whether a trademark is regis-
    tered, it can be used, owned, and enforced against would-
    be infringers. See B&B Hardware, Inc. v. Hargis Indus-
    tries, Inc., 575 U. S. ___, ___, ___ (2015) (slip op., at 3, 5).
    Trademark registration, meanwhile, confers several ancil-
    ——————
    scrutiny or invalidation of a regulation by simply claiming disinter-
    est in a speaker’s message, see United States v. Eichman, 
    496 U.S. 310
    , 315–317 (1990), or by concealing an attempt to favor some views
    over others in superficially neutral garb, see Renton v. Playtime Thea-
    tres, Inc., 
    475 U.S. 41
    , 46–49 (1986); cf. Church of Lukumi Babalu Aye,
    Inc. v. Hialeah, 
    508 U.S. 520
    , 533–534 (1993). But there is no evidence
    in the record from which to conclude that Congress enacted the scandalous-
    marks provision in order to advantage certain views over others.
    And where a denial of trademark registration by the PTO raises such a
    concern, it would be proper for an applicant to bring an as-applied
    challenge. See infra, at 18–19.
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)              15
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    lary benefits on trademark-holders who meet Congress’
    specifications, including for example, additional protec-
    tions against infringers. See ante, at 2; Tam, 582 U. S., at
    ___ (slip op., at 5). Registering a mark in the Govern-
    ment’s searchable register puts the world on notice
    (whether actual or constructive) that a party is asserting
    ownership of that mark.9 Registration, in short, is a help-
    ful system, but it is one that the Government is under no
    obligation to establish and that is collateral to the exist-
    ence and use of trademarks themselves. There is no evi-
    dence that speech or commerce would be endangered if the
    Government were not to provide it at all.
    When the Court has talked about governmental initia-
    tives like this one before, it has usually used one of two
    general labels. In several cases, the Court has treated
    such initiatives as a limited public (or nonpublic) forum.
    See, e.g., Christian Legal Soc. Chapter of Univ. of Cal.,
    Hastings College of Law v. Martinez, 
    561 U.S. 661
    , 669–
    670, 682 (2010) (“ ‘Registered Student Organization’ ”
    program providing various financial and nonfinancial
    benefits to recognized law-school student groups); Rosen-
    
    berger, 515 U.S., at 823
    –824, 829–830 (“Student Activities
    Fund” for registered campus student groups); Cornelius v.
    NAACP Legal Defense & Ed. Fund, Inc., 
    473 U.S. 788
    ,
    790–791, 799–801, 806 (1985) (“Combined Federal Cam-
    paign” literature enabling approved charitable organiza-
    tions to solicit donations from federal employees). In other
    situations, the Court has discussed similar initiatives as
    government programs or subsidies. See, e.g., Legal Ser-
    vices Corporation v. Velazquez, 
    531 U.S. 533
    , 536, 543–
    544 (2001) (government program distributing funds to
    legal-services organizations); National Endowment for
    ——————
    9 See 
    15 U.S. C
    . §1072; U. S. Patent & Trademark Office, Search
    Trademark Database, https://www.uspto.gov/trademarks-application-
    process/search-trademark-database (as last visited June 20, 2019).
    16                       IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    Arts v. Finley, 
    524 U.S. 569
    , 573, 585–587 (1998) (compet-
    itive government grant-making program to support the
    arts).10 In each of these situations, a governmental body
    established an initiative that supported some forms of
    expression without restricting others. Some speakers
    were better off, but no speakers were worse off.
    Regardless of the finer distinctions between these labels,
    reasonable, viewpoint-neutral content discrimination is
    generally permissible under either framework. See Chris-
    tian Legal 
    Soc., 561 U.S., at 679
    (“Any access barrier
    must be reasonable and viewpoint neutral”); 
    Velazquez, 531 U.S., at 543
    –544, 548–549 (analogizing to limited-
    forum cases and explaining that “[w]here private speech is
    involved, even Congress’ antecedent funding decision
    cannot be aimed at the suppression of ideas thought inim-
    ical to the Government’s own interest”); see also Ysursa v.
    Pocatello Ed. Assn., 
    555 U.S. 353
    , 355 (2009) (finding
    government conduct that did not restrict speech but sim-
    ply “decline[d] to promote” it valid where it was “reasonable
    in light of the State’s interest”). Perhaps for that reason,
    the Court has often discussed the two frameworks as at
    least closely related. See, e.g., Christian Legal 
    Society, 561 U.S., at 682
    (“[T]his case fits comfortably within the
    limited-public forum category, for [the plaintiff], in seek-
    ——————
    10 In Tam, four Justices concluded that cash-subsidy programs like
    the one in Finley were “not instructive in analyzing” trademark regis-
    tration. 582 U. S., at ___ (opinion of ALITO, J.) (slip op., at 20). Trade-
    mark registration differs, of course, because any “subsidy” comes in the
    form of a noncash benefit, but that difference does not foreclose under-
    standing the registration system as a beneficial, noncash governmental
    program. No Justice, meanwhile, rejected the limited-public-forum
    analogy, see id., at ___–___, and n. 16 (slip op., at 22–23, and n. 16)
    (calling such cases “[p]otentially more analogous” and reserving the
    question), and scholars have noted arguments for adopting it. See Snow
    2364–2366; Katyal, Trademark Intersectionality, 57 UCLA L. Rev.
    1601, 1676–1681 (2010); Lefstin, Note, Does the First Amendment Bar
    Cancellation of REDSKINS? 52 Stan. L. Rev. 665, 706–707 (2000).
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)                  17
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    ing what is effectively a state subsidy, faces only indirect
    pressure . . . ”); 
    Velazquez, 531 U.S., at 544
    (“As this suit
    involves a subsidy, limited forum cases . . . may not be
    controlling in a strict sense, yet they do provide some
    instruction”).
    Whichever label one chooses here, the federal system of
    trademark registration fits: It is, in essence, an opportun-
    ity to include one’s trademark on a list and thereby secure
    the ancillary benefits that come with registration.11 Just
    as in the limited-forum and government-program cases,
    some speakers benefit, but no speakers are harmed.
    Brunetti, for example, can use, own, and enforce his mark
    regardless of whether it has been registered. Whether he
    may register his mark can therefore turn on reasonable,
    viewpoint-neutral content regulations.12
    C
    Prohibiting the registration of obscene, profane, or
    vulgar marks qualifies as reasonable, viewpoint-neutral,
    content-based regulation. Apart from any interest in
    regulating commerce itself, the Government has an inter-
    est in not promoting certain kinds of speech, whether
    because such speech could be perceived as suggesting
    governmental favoritism or simply because the Govern-
    ment does not wish to involve itself with that kind of
    speech. See, e.g., 
    Ysursa, 555 U.S., at 359
    –360; 
    Cornelius, 473 U.S., at 809
    . While “there is no evidence that the
    ——————
    11 Not every registration system would necessarily fit the same bill,
    whether because not every such system invites expressive content like
    trademarks or simply because other forms of registration may not be so
    ancillary as to qualify solely as a “benefit.”
    12 Though I do not address the constitutionality of provisions not be-
    fore the Court, I note as well that the “scandalous” bar in §1052(a) is
    hardly the only provision in §1052 that could be characterized as
    content discriminatory. See, e.g., §1052(b) (no flags or insignias);
    §1052(c) (no unapproved markers of deceased U. S. Presidents during
    the lives of their spouses).
    18                       IANCU v. BRUNETTI
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    public associates the contents of trademarks with the
    Federal Government,” Tam, 582 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at
    17), registration nevertheless entails Government in-
    volvement in promoting a particular mark. Registration
    requires the Government to publish the mark, as well as
    to take steps to combat international infringement. See 
    15 U.S. C
    . §§1062, 1124; see also Brief for United States 35.
    The Government has a reasonable interest in refraining
    from lending its ancillary support to marks that are ob-
    scene, vulgar, or profane. Cf. Hustler Magazine, Inc. v.
    Falwell, 
    485 U.S. 46
    , 56 (1988) (“[S]peech that is vulgar,
    offensive, and shocking is not entitled to absolute constitu-
    tional protection under all circumstances” (internal quota-
    tion marks omitted)).
    III
    “The cardinal principle of statutory construction is to
    save and not to destroy.” Jones & Laughlin Steel 
    Corp., 301 U.S., at 30
    ; see also Hooper v. California, 
    155 U.S. 648
    , 657 (1895) (“The elementary rule is that every rea-
    sonable construction must be resorted to, in order to save
    a statute from unconstitutionality”). In directing the PTO
    to deny the ancillary benefit of registration to trademarks
    featuring “scandalous” content, Congress used a word that
    is susceptible of different meanings. The majority’s read-
    ing would render the provision unconstitutional; mine
    would save it. Under these circumstances, the Court
    ought to adopt the narrower construction, rather than
    permit a rush to register trademarks for even the most
    viscerally offensive words and images that one can
    imagine.13
    ——————
    13 As noted above, I agree with the majority that §1052(a)’s bar on the
    registration of “immoral” marks is unconstitutional viewpoint discrimi-
    nation. 
    See supra, at 2
    . I would simply sever that provision and
    uphold the bar on “scandalous” marks. See Reno v. American Civil
    Liberties Union, 
    521 U.S. 844
    , 882–883 (1997); Brockett v. Spokane
    Cite as: 588 U. S. ____ (2019)                   19
    Opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.
    That said, I emphasize that Brunetti’s challenge is a
    facial one. That means that he must show that “ ‘a sub-
    stantial number of [the scandalous-marks provision’s]
    applications are unconstitutional, judged in relation to the
    [provision’s] plainly legitimate sweep.’ ” United States v.
    Stevens, 
    559 U.S. 460
    , 473 (2010). With “scandalous”
    narrowed to reach only obscene, profane, and vulgar con-
    tent, the provision would not be overly broad. Cf. 
    Frisby, 487 U.S., at 488
    (rejecting a facial challenge after adopt-
    ing a limiting construction); 
    Boos, 485 U.S., at 331
    (same).
    Even so, hard cases would remain, and I would expect
    courts to take seriously as-applied challenges demonstrat-
    ing a danger that the provision had been used to restrict
    speech based on the views expressed rather than the mode
    of expression.14 Cf. 
    Finley, 524 U.S., at 587
    (reserving the
    possibility of as-applied challenges).
    Freedom of speech is a cornerstone of our society, and
    the First Amendment protects Brunetti’s right to use
    words like the one at issue here. The Government need
    not, however, be forced to confer on Brunetti’s trademark
    (and some more extreme) the ancillary benefit of trade-
    mark registration, when “scandalous” in §1052(a) can
    reasonably be read to bar the registration of only those
    marks that are obscene, vulgar, or profane. Though I
    concur as to the unconstitutionality of the term “immoral”
    in §1052(a), I respectfully dissent as to the term “scandal-
    ous” in the same statute and would instead uphold it
    under the narrow construction discussed here.
    ——————
    Arcades, Inc., 
    472 U.S. 491
    , 504–507 (1985); see also Tam, 582 U. S., at
    ___ (slip op., at 26) (striking down only the disparagement clause).
    14 The majority adverts to details in the record that could call into
    question whether the PTO engaged in viewpoint discrimination in this
    very case. See ante, at 3. Because a facial challenge is the only chal-
    lenge before the Court, I do not address whether an as-applied chal-
    lenge could have merit here.
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 18-302

Citation Numbers: 139 S. Ct. 2294, 204 L. Ed. 2d 714, 2019 U.S. LEXIS 4201

Judges: Elana Kagan

Filed Date: 6/24/2019

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 1/13/2023

Authorities (52)

National Labor Relations Board v. Federbush Co. , 121 F.2d 954 ( 1941 )

In Re the Boulevard Entertainment, Inc , 334 F.3d 1336 ( 2003 )

In Re Riverbank Canning Co. , 95 F.2d 327 ( 1938 )

Hooper v. California , 15 S. Ct. 207 ( 1895 )

United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co. , 26 S. Ct. 282 ( 1906 )

National Labor Relations Board v. Jones & Laughlin Steel ... , 57 S. Ct. 615 ( 1937 )

Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire , 62 S. Ct. 766 ( 1942 )

Swearingen v. United States , 16 S. Ct. 562 ( 1896 )

Federal Communications Commission v. Pacifica Foundation , 98 S. Ct. 3026 ( 1978 )

Christian Legal Soc. Chapter of Univ. of Cal., Hastings ... , 130 S. Ct. 2971 ( 2010 )

Bruesewitz v. Wyeth LLC , 131 S. Ct. 1068 ( 2011 )

Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. , 131 S. Ct. 2653 ( 2011 )

Stern v. Marshall , 131 S. Ct. 2594 ( 2011 )

Bolger v. Youngs Drug Products Corp. , 103 S. Ct. 2875 ( 1983 )

Washington State Department of Social & Health Services v. ... , 123 S. Ct. 1017 ( 2003 )

Morse v. Frederick , 127 S. Ct. 2618 ( 2007 )

Ysursa v. Pocatello Education Ass'n , 129 S. Ct. 1093 ( 2009 )

Federal Communications Commission v. Fox Television ... , 129 S. Ct. 1800 ( 2009 )

Brown v. Entertainment Merchants Assn. , 131 S. Ct. 2729 ( 2011 )

Perry Education Ass'n v. Perry Local Educators' Ass'n , 103 S. Ct. 948 ( 1983 )

View All Authorities »

Cited By (23)

United States v. Reyes-Valdivia ( 2022 )

Speech First, Inc. v. Alexander Cartwright ( 2022 )

Speech First, Inc. v. Alexander Cartwright ( 2022 )

Collins v. Putt ( 2020 )

Center for Investigative Repor v. SEPTA ( 2020 )

Northeastern Pennsylvania v. County of Lackawanna Transit ( 2019 )

Billy Ison v. Madison Local Sch. Dist. Bd. of Educ. ( 2021 )

Preterm-Cleveland v. Stephanie McCloud ( 2021 )

United States v. Robert Rundo ( 2021 )

Carrie Davis v. Colerain Twp., Ohio ( 2022 )

Am. Freedom Defense v. Suburban Mobility Auth. ( 2020 )

In Re ELSTER ( 2022 )

United States v. Eric Stagno ( 2020 )

In Re ELSTER ( 2022 )

Preterm-Cleveland v. Stephanie McCloud ( 2021 )

Lodestar Anstalt v. Bacardi & Company Ltd. ( 2022 )

Carrie Davis v. Colerain Twp., Ohio ( 2022 )

Speech First, Inc. v. Timothy Sands ( 2023 )

Zukerman v. United States Postal Service ( 2021 )

Mashaud v. Boone ( 2023 )

View All Citing Opinions »