Manning v. Caldwell for City of Roanoke ( 2019 )


Menu:
  •                                           PUBLISHED
    UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
    FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT
    No. 17-1320
    BRYAN MANNING; RYAN                       WILLIAMS;      RICHARD   DECKERHOFF;
    RICHARD EUGENE WALLS,
    Plaintiffs - Appellants,
    v.
    DONALD CALDWELL, Commonwealth’s Attorney for the City of Roanoke;
    MICHAEL NEHEMIAH HERRING, Commonwealth’s Attorney for the City of
    Richmond,
    Defendants - Appellees.
    ---------------------------------------
    NATIONAL LAW CENTER ON HOMELESSNESS & POVERTY,
    Amicus Supporting Appellant.
    Appeal from the United States District Court for the Western District of Virginia, at
    Roanoke. Glen E. Conrad, District Judge. (7:16-cv-00095-GEC)
    Argued: January 30, 2019                                           Decided: July 16, 2019
    Before GREGORY, Chief Judge, and WILKINSON, NIEMEYER, MOTZ, KING,
    AGEE, KEENAN, WYNN, DIAZ, FLOYD, THACKER, HARRIS, RICHARDSON, and
    QUATTLEBAUM, Circuit Judges, and DUNCAN, Senior Circuit Judge.
    Reversed and remanded by published opinion. Judges Motz and Keenan wrote the
    majority opinion, in which Chief Judge Gregory, and Judges King, Wynn, Floyd,
    Thacker, and Harris joined. Judge Keenan wrote a concurring opinion, in which Judges
    Motz and Thacker joined. Judge Wilkinson wrote a dissenting opinion, in which Judges
    Niemeyer, Agee, Richardson, Quattlebaum, and Senior Judge Duncan joined. Judge
    Wilkinson wrote a specially dissenting opinion. Judge Diaz wrote a dissenting opinion.
    ARGUED: Jonathan Lee Marcus, SKADDEN, ARPS, SLATE, MEAGHER & FLOM,
    LLP, Washington, D.C., for Appellants. Matthew Robert McGuire, OFFICE OF THE
    ATTORNEY GENERAL OF VIRGINIA, Richmond, Virginia, for Appellees. ON
    BRIEF: Mark D. Young, Maureen A. Donley, Donald P. Salzman, Theodore M.
    Kneller, Shekida A. Smith, Daniel B. O’Connell, SKADDEN, ARPS, SLATE,
    MEAGHER & FLOM, LLP, Washington, D.C.; Mary Frances Charlton, Angela Ciolfi,
    Elaine Poon, LEGAL AID JUSTICE CENTER, Charlottesville, Virginia, for Appellants.
    Mark R. Herring, Attorney General, Trevor S. Cox, Deputy Solicitor General, OFFICE
    OF THE ATTORNEY GENERAL, Richmond, Virginia, for Appellees. Eric S. Tars,
    NATIONAL LAW CENTER ON HOMELESSNESS & POVERTY, Washington, D.C.;
    Richard P. Bress, Andrew D. Prins, George C. Chipev, Ryan C. Grover, LATHAM &
    WATKINS LLP, Washington, D.C.; Douglas N. Letter, Nicolas Y. Riley, Seth Wayne,
    Institute for Constitutional Advocacy and Protection, GEORGETOWN UNIVERSITY
    LAW CENTER, Washington, D.C., for Amicus Curiae.
    2
    DIANA GRIBBON MOTZ and BARBARA MILANO KEENAN, Circuit Judges, with
    whom Chief Judge GREGORY, and Judges KING, WYNN, FLOYD, THACKER and
    HARRIS join:
    Homeless alcoholics brought this action challenging a Virginia statutory scheme
    that makes it a criminal offense for those whom the Commonwealth has labelled
    “habitual drunkards” to possess, consume, or purchase alcohol. The scheme authorizes
    Virginia to obtain, in absentia, a civil interdiction order against persons it deems
    “habitual drunkards,” and then permits Virginia to rely on the interdiction order to
    criminally prosecute conduct permitted for all others of legal drinking age. Plaintiffs
    allege that this scheme, which has resulted in their repeated arrest and imprisonment,
    violates the Constitution. The district court dismissed their complaint, holding that they
    failed to state a claim upon which relief could be granted. After a panel of this Court
    affirmed, we agreed to rehear the case en banc. For the reasons that follow, we now
    reverse.
    I.
    Because the district court dismissed Plaintiffs’ complaint under Federal Rule of
    Civil Procedure 12(b)(6), we accept as true the factual allegations set forth in the
    complaint and draw all reasonable inferences in their favor. See Ashcroft v. Iqbal, 
    556 U.S. 662
    , 678 (2009).
    A.
    The challenged policy rests on a series of interrelated statutes that operate as a
    single scheme. Virginia Code § 4.1-333(A) permits a Virginia circuit court to enter a
    3
    civil interdiction order “prohibiting the sale of alcoholic beverages . . . until further
    ordered” to a person who “has been convicted of driving . . . while intoxicated or has
    shown himself to be an habitual drunkard.” The Virginia statutory scheme does not
    include a definition of the term “habitual drunkard,” nor does it set forth any elements or
    standards governing the determination whether a defendant qualifies as an “habitual
    drunkard.” Va. Code § 4.1-333. Instead, it relegates those matters “to the satisfaction of
    the circuit court.” Id. And although Virginia Code § 4.1-333 requires that any individual
    potentially subject to interdiction be permitted a “hearing upon due notice,” the record
    shows that such hearings often are conducted without the defendant being present.
    Once declared an “habitual drunkard,” an interdicted person is subject to
    incarceration for the mere possession of or attempt to possess alcohol, or for being drunk
    in public. Virginia Code § 4.1-322 establishes a Class 1 misdemeanor for an interdicted
    person to “possess any alcoholic beverages,” or to be “drunk in public” in violation of
    Virginia Code § 18.2-388. Similarly, Virginia Code § 4.1-305 establishes a Class 1
    misdemeanor prohibiting an interdicted person from “consum[ing], purchas[ing], or
    possess[ing], or attempt[ing] to consume, purchase or possess, any alcoholic beverage,”
    except in certain statutorily exempt circumstances, such as the use of medicines
    containing alcohol. 1 The punishment for these crimes is “confinement in jail for not
    more than twelve months and a fine of not more than $2,500, either or both.” Va. Code
    1
    Plaintiffs do not challenge the constitutionality of the portion of the Virginia
    scheme addressing driving while intoxicated. When bringing a constitutional challenge,
    a party may contest certain parts of a statute without challenging the whole of the statute.
    See Reno v. Am. Civil Liberties Union, 
    521 U.S. 844
    , 862–63 (1997).
    4
    § 18.2-11(a). Individuals who have not been interdicted are subject only to a “fine of not
    more than $250” for public intoxication. See Va. Code §§ 18.2-388, 18.2-11(d).
    B.
    Each of the named Plaintiffs in this case, Bryan Manning, Ryan Williams, Richard
    Deckerhoff, and Richard Eugene Walls, alleges that he has been interdicted as an
    “habitual drunkard” pursuant to this statutory scheme. Each alleges that he suffers from
    alcohol use disorder, commonly called alcoholism, which causes him a “profound drive
    or craving to use alcohol” that is “compulsive or non-volitional.” Each further alleges
    that he is homeless and that his homelessness exacerbates his addiction, “mak[ing] it
    nearly impossible . . . to cease or mitigate alcohol consumption.” Notably, however,
    nothing in the complaint or elsewhere in the record indicates that any Plaintiff was
    convicted of any alcohol-related offenses before being interdicted. 2
    Plaintiffs allege that, although by its terms the challenged scheme is not limited to
    the homeless, in practice it functions as a tool to rid the streets of particularly vulnerable,
    unwanted alcoholics like themselves. In support of this claim, they allege that although
    there were 4,743 prosecutions for the crime of “possession or consumption of alcoholic
    beverages by interdicted persons” during the decade preceding 2015, only 1,220 distinct
    individuals were interdicted between 2007 and 2015.
    2
    Although the civil orders of interdiction for Manning and Williams state that
    certified abstracts or copies of convictions were submitted to the state court as part of the
    interdiction proceedings, the record does not show the offense underlying those
    convictions, nor does the record reveal how many times Manning or Williams had been
    convicted before being interdicted. The record does not contain the interdiction orders
    for Deckerhoff or Walls.
    5
    Each of the named Plaintiffs asserts that he has been repeatedly criminally
    prosecuted after interdiction, often on dubious grounds.       Some say they have been
    prosecuted as many as 25 to 30 times. In each instance, Plaintiffs faced (and allege they
    will again face) arrest, prosecution, and incarceration for up to a year in prison, all for
    conduct permitted for all others of legal drinking age. They allege that the “habitual
    drunkard” label also has adversely affected their ability to maintain employment and
    secure long-term housing, and has subjected them to continual harassment and
    embarrassment. 3
    C.
    In March 2016, the named Plaintiffs filed this putative class action alleging that
    the Virginia scheme (1) constituted cruel and unusual punishment outlawed by the Eighth
    Amendment, (2) deprived them of due process of the law in violation of the Fourteenth
    Amendment, (3) denied them the equal protection guarantees of the Fourteenth
    Amendment, and (4) was unconstitutionally vague in violation of the Fourteenth
    3
    The challenged Virginia scheme dates to the late nineteenth century. See Va.
    Code Ch. 83 § 5 (1873). Then, it had a rehabilitative purpose. A family member or
    friend could file a written complaint asserting that a person was “an habitual drunkard,”
    which authorized a justice of the peace to issue a warrant ordering a hearing. Id. If three
    justices of the peace found, in consultation with a physician, that home confinement
    would “possibly restore” the person “to sobriety and self-control,” they could impose
    home confinement. Id. The law permitted a person so confined to demand a jury trial as
    to his condition at any time after an order was sought. Id.; see also Maria Slater, Note, Is
    Powell Still Valid? The Supreme Court’s Changing Stance on Cruel and Unusual
    Punishment, 
    104 Va. L
    . Rev. 547, 582–83 (2018). In 1934, Virginia abandoned this
    rehabilitative approach and adopted the punitive scheme that it retains today.
    6
    Amendment. The district court considered and rejected all four claims and so dismissed
    the complaint.
    In rejecting Plaintiffs’ vagueness and Eighth Amendment claims, the district court
    relied largely on a 1979 district court opinion, which this Court summarily affirmed.
    Fisher v. Coleman, 
    486 F. Supp. 311
     (W.D. Va. 1979), aff’d, 
    639 F.2d 191
     (4th Cir.
    1981) (per curiam). After a panel of this Court affirmed the district court in this case, we
    voted to rehear the case en banc, and so vacated the panel opinion. See Manning v.
    Caldwell, 
    900 F.3d 139
     (4th Cir.), reh’g en banc granted, 741 F. App’x 937 (4th Cir.
    2018).
    We now consider the case anew, reviewing de novo the district court’s grant of a
    motion to dismiss for failure to state a claim. Stewart v. Iancu, 
    912 F.3d 693
    , 702 (4th
    Cir. 2019). 4 We hold that the challenged scheme is unconstitutionally vague, and that
    4
    The Commonwealth poses several preliminary challenges to our jurisdiction —
    namely, the Rooker-Feldman doctrine and asserted lack of standing and ripeness. The
    panel correctly and unanimously, albeit sub silentio, rejected all of these challenges. The
    Rooker-Feldman doctrine provides no bar because Plaintiffs do not seek redress for an
    injury caused by a state court judgment. See Thana v. Bd. of License Comm’rs for
    Charles Cty., 
    827 F.3d 314
    , 318–20 (4th Cir. 2016); see also Rooker v. Fid. Trust Co.,
    
    263 U.S. 413
     (1923); D.C. Ct. of App. v. Feldman, 
    460 U.S. 462
     (1983). That is,
    Plaintiffs do not challenge their specific interdiction orders; they challenge only the
    Virginia scheme’s application to them in the future. Nor do standing and ripeness
    doctrines pose obstacles to Plaintiffs’ suit. Plaintiffs allege that they have been
    repeatedly arrested, charged, and prosecuted with violating Virginia Code § 4.1-322.
    They further allege that because they are homeless, their possession and consumption of
    alcohol is necessarily in the public view. Plaintiffs have thus plausibly alleged a real and
    immediate threat of future injury. See City of Los Angeles v. Lyons, 
    461 U.S. 95
    , 101–07
    (1983).
    7
    even if it could be narrowed to apply only to similarly situated alcoholics, Plaintiffs have
    stated a claim that it violates the Eighth Amendment as applied to them. 5
    II.
    We first consider Plaintiffs’ vagueness challenge.
    A.
    Before reaching the merits of that challenge, we must address the question
    whether this issue is properly before the en banc Court. Although the question of
    vagueness was fully litigated and decided in the district court, Plaintiffs expressly
    declined to “press this claim” before the original three-judge panel.              Thus, the
    Commonwealth now contends that the issue has been waived before the en banc Court. 6
    Mindful of our role as a neutral arbiter, this Court typically does not “ventur[e]
    beyond the confines of the case on appeal to address arguments the parties have deemed
    unworthy of orderly mention.” United States v. Holness, 
    706 F.3d 579
    , 591–92 (4th Cir.
    2013). Nonetheless, “[t]he matter of what questions may be taken up and resolved for the
    5
    For the reasons set forth in the panel opinion, Plaintiffs’ other claims fail. See
    Manning, 900 F.3d at 151–53.
    6
    The Commonwealth frames Plaintiffs’ decision as a “waiver,” which is the
    “intentional relinquishment . . . of a known right” that leaves no error for the Court to
    review. See United States v. Olano, 
    507 U.S. 725
    , 733 (1993). However, we recently
    explained that “waiver, in a technical sense, concerns a party’s relinquishment of rights
    before a district court.” United States v. Simms, 
    914 F.3d 229
    , 238 n.4 (4th Cir. 2019)
    (en banc). Because Plaintiffs properly raised and litigated their vagueness claim before
    the district court, their decision not to advance that argument on appeal is better treated as
    abandonment or forfeiture, pursuant to which we retain the discretion to review the
    particular issue in question. See id.
    8
    first time on appeal is one left primarily to the discretion of the courts of appeals, to be
    exercised on the facts of individual cases.” Singleton v. Wulff, 
    428 U.S. 106
    , 121 (1976).
    We regularly exercise our discretion to excuse a party’s abandonment of an issue
    when the record provides an adequate basis to consider an alternative legal theory and
    when neither party is prejudiced by such consideration. See, e.g., Simms, 914 F.3d at
    238; Holness, 706 F.3d at 592; United States v. Ramos-Cruz, 
    667 F.3d 487
    , 496 n.5 (4th
    Cir. 2012); Rice v. Rivera, 
    617 F.3d 802
    , 808 n.4 (4th Cir. 2010); A Helping Hand, LLC
    v. Baltimore County, 
    515 F.3d 356
    , 369 (4th Cir. 2008). Indeed, we have recognized that
    when “deemed necessary to reach the correct result” on matters of public importance, we
    may “sua sponte consider points not presented to the district court and not even raised on
    appeal by any party.” Wash. Gas Light Co. v. Va. Elec. & Power Co., 
    438 F.2d 248
    , 251
    (4th Cir. 1971) (second emphasis added); see also Hormel v. Helvering, 
    312 U.S. 552
    ,
    557 (1941) (“Rules of practice and procedure are devised to promote the ends of justice,
    not to defeat them.”); Curry v. Beatrice Pocahontas Coal Co., 
    67 F.3d 517
    , 522 n.8 (4th
    Cir. 1995) (“The normal rule of course is that failure to raise an issue for review in the
    prescribed manner constitutes a waiver. But the rule is not an absolute one and review
    may proceed (even completely sua sponte) when the equities require.” (internal citation
    omitted)).
    We considered an abandoned issue less than a year ago in United States v. Simms,
    
    914 F.3d 229
    .      In that case, the en banc Court addressed whether 18 U.S.C.
    § 924(c)(3)(B) was susceptible to a conduct-specific approach, notwithstanding that the
    government had expressly abandoned that argument before the original three-judge panel.
    9
    See id. at 237–39. 7 Given the “exceptional importance” of the question presented, in
    Simms every member of the Court, the majority and the dissenters alike, unanimously
    agreed to consider the merits of the government’s abandoned arguments. See id. at 239–
    52; see also id. at 253–60 (Wynn, J., concurring); id. at 260–63 (Wilkinson, J.,
    dissenting); id. at 264–72 (Niemeyer, J., dissenting); id. at 272–80 (Richardson, J.,
    dissenting).
    The circumstances before us here merit a similar exercise of discretion. As noted
    above, the issue of vagueness was litigated fully and was decided in the district court.
    And the question of a statute’s vagueness is a purely legal issue that does not require
    additional fact-finding. See United States v. Picardi, 
    739 F.3d 1118
    , 1126 (8th Cir.
    2014); United States v. Paradies, 
    98 F.3d 1266
    , 1284 (11th Cir. 1996); United States v.
    Mallas, 
    762 F.2d 361
    , 364 n.4 (4th Cir. 1985).         Thus, the present record “readily
    permit[s] evaluation” of Plaintiffs’ vagueness theory. Holness, 706 F.3d at 592.
    Additionally, neither party will be prejudiced by consideration of the vagueness
    issue. Both parties were questioned about the vagueness of the statutory scheme during
    oral argument before the en banc Court, and both submitted supplemental briefs on the
    subject. Moreover, the crux of Plaintiffs’ appeal concerns an issue of “exceptional
    importance” to the Commonwealth of Virginia, namely, whether a statutory scheme
    7
    Thus, Plaintiffs’ failure to raise their vagueness claim before the original three-
    judge panel in this case clearly does not preclude the en banc Court from considering the
    issue. The grant of rehearing en banc vacated the original panel opinion. See 4th Cir.
    Local R. 35(c). And, as we concluded in Simms, 914 F.3d at 237–39, it is well within the
    authority of the en banc Court to decide a case on grounds not relied upon, or even
    considered, by the original panel.
    10
    imposing criminal penalties on an untold number of chronically ill citizens is
    unconstitutionally vague.   Accordingly, we are persuaded that there are compelling
    reasons in this case to justify excusing Plaintiffs’ initial abandonment of their vagueness
    claim on appeal.
    B.
    1.
    The void for vagueness doctrine is rooted in the Due Process Clause of the Fifth
    and Fourteenth Amendments. See Doe v. Cooper, 
    842 F.3d 833
    , 842 (4th Cir. 2016). To
    survive a vagueness challenge, a statute must give a person of ordinary intelligence
    adequate notice of what conduct is prohibited and must include sufficient standards to
    prevent arbitrary and discriminatory enforcement.         See Papachristou v. City of
    Jacksonville, 
    405 U.S. 156
    , 160 (1972); Martin v. Lloyd, 
    700 F.3d 132
    , 135 (4th Cir.
    2012); see also Kolender v. Lawson, 
    461 U.S. 352
    , 358 (1983) (requiring that criminal
    statutes contain “minimal guidelines to govern law enforcement” (citation omitted)).
    This test is not applied mechanically. The degree of vagueness tolerated in a law
    depends in part on the type of statute. Less clarity is required in purely civil statutes
    because the “consequences of imprecision are qualitatively less severe.” Vill. of Hoffman
    Estates v. Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc., 
    455 U.S. 489
    , 499 (1982). But see Sessions v.
    Dimaya, 
    138 S. Ct. 1204
    , 1225–31 (2018) (Gorsuch, J., concurring in part and concurring
    in the judgment) (noting that “today’s civil laws regularly impose penalties far more
    severe than those found in many criminal statutes”). However, if criminal penalties may
    be imposed for violations of a law, a stricter standard is applied in reviewing the statute
    11
    for vagueness. Hoffman, 455 U.S. at 498–99. Similarly, the void-for-vagueness doctrine
    applies to “laws that fix the permissible sentences for criminal offenses.” Beckles v.
    United States, 
    137 S. Ct. 886
    , 892 (2017); accord Cross v. United States, 
    892 F.3d 288
    ,
    304–06 (7th Cir. 2018). And even laws that nominally impose only civil consequences
    warrant a “relatively strict test” for vagueness if the law is “quasi-criminal” and has a
    stigmatizing effect. Hoffman, 455 U.S. at 498–500; see also Dimaya, 138 S. Ct. at 1212–
    13 (applying the most exacting vagueness standard to a civil statute authorizing a
    respondent’s removal from the United States).
    In this case, the challenged Virginia scheme plainly has criminal consequences.
    An individual adjudicated to be an “habitual drunkard” faces an enhanced penalty for
    public intoxication. Compare Va. Code § 4.1-322, with id. § 18.2-388. And, unlike all
    others of legal drinking age, interdicted persons commit a crime punishable by up to
    twelve months’ incarceration merely for possessing alcohol. See id. §§ 4.1-305; -322.
    Because the interrelated provisions operate together to “fix the permissible sentences” for
    those labelled “habitual drunkards,” the statutes, at a minimum, are quasi-criminal in
    nature. Beckles, 137 S. Ct. at 892; Hoffman, 455 U.S. at 498–500.
    The integrated structure of the challenged scheme reinforces this conclusion.
    “[W]ords of a statute must be read in their context and with a view to their place in the
    overall statutory scheme.” Davis v. Mich. Dep’t of Treasury, 
    489 U.S. 803
    , 809 (1989);
    In re Consol. Freightways Corp. of Del., 
    564 F.3d 1161
    , 1165 (9th Cir. 2009)
    (recognizing that courts must “construe th[e] provision [at issue] with the statutory
    scheme in which it is embedded”). A civil interdiction order issued under Virginia Code
    12
    § 4.1-333 is a necessary predicate for imposing the increased criminal penalties set forth
    in the other statutes addressing interdiction. Indeed, such an interdiction order would be
    meaningless without the conditions and criminal consequences that follow from a
    violation of that order. And although the portions of the scheme that impose those
    conditions and consequences do not use the term “habitual drunkard,” that term is
    incorporated by reference.    See, e.g., Va. Code §§ 4.1-304 (prohibiting the sale of
    alcoholic beverages to “interdicted person”), 4.1-322 (prohibiting “person[s] who [have]
    been interdicted pursuant to § 4.1-333” from possessing alcoholic beverages), 4.1-100
    (defining “interdicted person” to mean “a person to whom the sale of alcoholic beverages
    is prohibited by order pursuant to this title”). Thus, these interrelated statutes must be
    construed together to give effect to their various provisions and, because they are quasi-
    criminal in nature, a “relatively strict” test for vagueness applies here. Hoffman, 455 U.S.
    at 498–99.
    2.
    Plaintiffs contend that the term “habitual drunkard” did not provide fair notice to
    them about what conduct is targeted by Virginia’s statutory interdiction scheme. The
    Commonwealth, however, responds that the term “habitual drunkard” has a readily
    ascertainable meaning. It argues that a person of ordinary intelligence can understand
    what is meant by the term “habitual drunkard,” because Virginia Code § 4.1-333 requires
    that a person has “shown himself” to be an “habitual drunkard.” Va. Code § 4.1-333. In
    the Commonwealth’s view, Plaintiffs’ allegations that they often had difficulty
    maintaining sobriety in public places due to their alcoholism demonstrate that their
    13
    conduct falls within any definition of “habitual drunkard,” and, thus, that the statute is not
    impermissibly vague as applied to them.
    The purpose of the fair notice requirement is to enable citizens to conform their
    conduct to the proscriptions of the law. See City of Chicago v. Morales, 
    527 U.S. 41
    , 58
    (1999) (“No one may be required at peril of life, liberty or property to speculate as to the
    meaning of penal statutes.” (quoting Lanzetta v. New Jersey, 
    306 U.S. 451
    , 453 (1939)));
    Kolender, 461 U.S. at 357. If a statute fails to provide any standard of conduct by which
    persons can determine whether they are violating the statute or does not provide
    “minimal guidelines to govern law enforcement,” the statute is unconstitutionally vague.
    See Kolender, 461 U.S. at 358; Cooper, 842 F.3d at 842.
    In the present case, the lack of any guidelines or standards regarding who qualifies
    as an “habitual drunkard” compels the conclusion that use of the term in the challenged
    scheme is unconstitutionally vague.      Virginia’s Alcoholic Beverage Control Act, of
    which this scheme is a part, does not define the term “habitual drunkard.” See Va. Code
    § 4.1-100. And the few Virginia cases applying the challenged scheme have not provided
    a limiting construction of the phrase to satisfy the fair notice requirement. See Hoffman,
    455 U.S. at 494 n.5 (explaining that when considering a void-for-vagueness challenge, a
    federal court must “consider any limiting construction that a state court or enforcement
    agency has proffered” (citation omitted)). Thus, the statutes and case law fail to provide
    any standards of what is meant by the term “habitual drunkard.” Cf. Capital Assoc.
    Indus., Inc. v. Stein, 
    922 F.3d 198
    , 210–11 (4th Cir. 2019) (concluding that the statute
    prohibiting unauthorized practice of law was not impermissibly vague because “[t]he
    14
    statutes and state case law collectively provide an extensive definition of what it means to
    practice law”).
    Our principal dissenting colleague maintains that the “sole purpose” of interdiction
    proceedings under Virginia Code § 4.1-333 is “to provide notice” to high-risk persons
    about the type of conduct Virginia prohibits. Dissent at 70 (Wilkinson, J.). In doing so,
    however, he inverts Virginia’s statutory scheme. Once labelled an “habitual drunkard,” a
    person may be on notice about the conduct prohibited, but it does not follow that the
    person was also on notice that he or she could be interdicted. Stated differently, persons
    informed that they can no longer possess alcohol because they are an “habitual drunkard”
    are not thereby put on notice about what conduct led to that adjudication in the first place.
    And, plainly, the term “habitual drunkard” itself does not “assist in clearly
    articulating the proscriptions of the ordinance.” Morales, 527 U.S. at 51. To begin, the
    word “habitual” is itself susceptible to numerous interpretations. “Habitual” means “of
    the nature of a habit . . . customarily doing a certain thing.”        Habitual, Webster’s
    International Dictionary (3d ed. 2002). But a habit can also be a “custom,” a “nearly
    involuntary” practice, a “normal manner of procedure,” or something done with “frequent
    repetition.” Id. Thus, on its own, the word “habitual” does not provide any principles or
    standards for determining how often or regularly an act must be performed to constitute
    “habitual” behavior. See Cooper, 842 F.3d at 843 (concluding that the term “regularly
    scheduled” was unconstitutionally vague because the statute at issue did not explain what
    “regular” meant in context); Lytle v. Doyle, 
    326 F.3d 463
    , 469 (4th Cir. 2003) (“[T]he
    vagueness that dooms this ordinance is not the product of uncertainty about the normal
    15
    meaning of [the term at issue], but rather about what specific conduct is covered by the
    statute and what is not.” (internal quotation marks and citation omitted)).
    In the context of the present case, therefore, several questions immediately arise
    concerning who may be adjudicated an “habitual” drunkard. For example, must a person
    engage in a pattern of drinking over time that establishes a “normal manner of
    procedure,” or is it enough that the person drinks many alcoholic beverages over an
    extended period? Or is a “habit” established if the person drinks numerous alcoholic
    beverages only every Friday and Saturday night? The language of the challenged scheme
    does not provide any guidance to answer these or a myriad of other questions.
    Likewise, the term “drunkard” does not provide any meaningful guidance
    regarding proscribed conduct. In Hancock v. Cox, the Supreme Court of Virginia held
    that a civil statute providing for the commitment of “alcoholics” was unconstitutionally
    vague, because the statute lacked any definition to determine “when a person is an
    alcoholic.” 
    183 S.E.2d 149
    , 151–52 (Va. 1971). Similarly, in Booth v. Commonwealth,
    the court held an earlier version of this scheme, which provided for the interdiction of any
    person who has “shown himself to be an improper person to be allowed to purchase
    alcoholic beverages,” to be impermissibly vague, because the term “improper person”
    allowed “arbitrary interpretation” and enforcement. 
    88 S.E.2d 916
    , 917–18 (Va. 1955)
    (emphasis added).
    The same is true here. Black’s Law Dictionary defines “drunkard” as “[s]omeone
    who habitually consumes intoxicating substances excessively” or “[an] alcoholic.”
    Drunkard, Black’s Law Dictionary (10th ed. 2014). To our dissenting colleagues, this
    16
    type of general definition is the end of the matter. Dissent at 72 (Wilkinson, J.); Dissent
    at 82 (Diaz, J.). But such a conclusion relies entirely on a tautology: a person who
    drinks alcoholic beverages excessively is a drunkard and, therefore, a person would easily
    understand that a person is an “habitual drunkard” if they regularly drink alcohol to
    excess. This definition entirely fails to answer the question of what the Virginia’s
    interdiction scheme meant by “drunkard.” General definitions of the term “drunkard” do
    not identify how much alcohol a person must consume before such consumption is
    considered “excessive” or, as noted above, what frequency of behavior constitutes a
    “habit.” Thus, such definitions fail to impart any standards for determining whether a
    given individual is a “drunkard.” 8
    This absence of meaningful guidance is further illustrated when the term “habitual
    drunkard” is compared with the word “intoxicated” as used in Virginia’s public
    intoxication statute. A conviction for public intoxication requires proof that a person is
    “intoxicated.” See Va. Code § 18.2-388. “Intoxication” in turn is expressly defined as “a
    condition in which a person has drunk enough alcoholic beverages to observably affect
    his manner, disposition, speech, muscular movement, general appearance or behavior.”
    Id. § 4.1-100. Thus, a person in a public place who has consumed enough alcohol to
    8
    Although the district court in Fisher, 486 F. Supp. at 315, and the Court of
    Appeals of Virginia in Jackson v. Commonwealth, 
    604 S.E.2d 122
    , 125 (Va. Ct. App.
    2004), proposed a definition of the term “habitual drunkard” which states that the term
    “encompasses one who, like the plaintiff, is admittedly in the continual habit of being
    intoxicated from alcohol,” for the reasons just explained, we conclude that that definition
    does not provide any meaningful guidance about how to decide whether an individual
    should be considered an “habitual drunkard.”
    17
    impair his physical movement or speech is notified by the language and definitions in
    Virginia Code § 18.2-388 of the conditions under which he may be charged with public
    intoxication. See United States v. Brown, 
    401 F.3d 588
    , 597 (4th Cir. 2005). In contrast,
    this scheme lacks any substantive guidance regarding what is required to establish that a
    person is an “habitual drunkard.” Indeed, the fact that Virginia’s Alcoholic Beverage
    Control Act specified what behavior constitutes being “intoxicated” with respect to the
    state’s public intoxication offense, Va. Code § 4.1-100, but left undefined the term
    “habitual drunkard” in its interdiction scheme, id. § 4-1.333, demonstrates that the
    legislature intended each term to target different behavior, Forst v. Rockingham Poultry
    Marketing Coop., Inc., 
    279 S.E.2d 400
    , 404 (Va. 1981) (“When the General Assembly
    uses . . . different terms in the same act, it is presumed to mean . . . different things.”).
    Counsel for the Commonwealth stated at oral argument that an “habitual
    drunkard” is someone who “causes harm to other persons or their community” as a result
    of his or her repeated drunkenness. But this “harm” requirement is not found in the
    challenged scheme, nor does the concept appear in any Virginia or federal case
    interpreting it. 9   Thus, the determination whether a certain person qualifies as an
    “habitual drunkard” is left to the subjective view of judges and law enforcement officials.
    See Kolender, 461 U.S. at 358 (“[W]here the legislature fails to provide . . . minimal
    guidelines, a criminal statute may permit a standardless sweep [that] allows policemen,
    prosecutors, and juries to pursue their personal predilections.”); Papachristou, 
    405 U.S. 9
    Indeed, the word “harm” does not appear a single time in Fisher v. Coleman, 
    486 F. Supp. 311
    , or Jackson v. Commonwealth, 
    604 S.E.2d 122
    .
    18
    at 170 (“Where, as here, there are no standards governing the exercise of the discretion
    granted by the ordinance, the scheme permits and encourages an arbitrary and
    discriminatory enforcement of the law.”); see also Booth, 88 S.E.2d at 918 (“On the basis
    of such a portmanteau word . . . the judiciary has no standards with which to judge the
    validity of . . . action which necessarily involves, at least in large measure, subjective
    determination.” (citation omitted)).
    Determinations of this nature invite arbitrary enforcement.          Police officers,
    prosecutors, and even state circuit court judges likely will have differing perceptions
    regarding what frequency of drunkenness exceeds the necessary threshold for a person to
    be considered an “habitual drunkard.” The interpretation of the phrase therefore leaves
    open the widest conceivable inquiry about a person’s behavior and depends “entirely
    upon the prohibition philosophy of the particular” individual enforcing the scheme at that
    moment. Booth, 88 S.E.2d at 917. Indeed, the absence of any standards or limiting
    language to assist in the interpretation of the term “habitual drunkard” supports Plaintiffs’
    assertion that the law was designed to target persons, including the homeless, that state
    officials deem undesirable.      See Papachristou, 405 U.S. at 166 (observing that
    “[d]efiniteness is designedly avoided [in vagrancy laws] so as to allow the net to be cast
    at large, to enable men to be caught who are vaguely undesirable in the eyes of police and
    prosecution, although not chargeable with any particular offense”). The imposition of
    significant criminal penalties cannot rest on the use of such subjective standards, nor may
    a statute consign a person to the risk of significant penal consequences without first
    providing sufficiently definite notice of prohibited activities. See Tanner v. City of
    19
    Virginia Beach, 
    674 S.E.2d 848
    , 853 (Va. 2009). Because the determinations required by
    the Virginia scheme are not meaningfully constrained by the text of the statutes, those
    statutes plainly fail to give fair notice of the conduct to be avoided. See Papachristou,
    405 U.S. at 166. 10
    The decisions of courts in other jurisdictions likewise fail to provide any aid in
    resolving this definitional quandary. There are almost as many definitions for terms such
    as “common drunk” or “habitual drunkard” as there are courts that have attempted to
    formulate them. See, e.g., Ledezma-Cosino v. Sessions, 
    857 F.3d 1042
    , 1046 (9th Cir.
    2017) (en banc) (“The ordinary meaning of ‘habitual drunkard’ is a person who regularly
    drinks alcoholic beverages to excess.”); Tatum v. State, 
    22 So. 2d 350
    , 351 (Ala. Ct. App.
    1945) (“A common drunkard is a person whose general rule of life is that of drunkenness
    . . . sobriety being the exception.”); Sowder v. Commonwealth, 
    88 S.W.2d 274
    , 275 (Ky.
    1935) (approving a jury instruction that defined “habitual drunkard” as a person who “has
    a fixed habit of frequently getting drunk, though not oftener drunk than sober, and though
    sober for weeks at a time”); Commonwealth v. Whitney, 
    71 Mass. 85
    , 87–88 (1855)
    (defining “common drunk” as a person who is “an habitual drunkard [and] is so to the
    disturbance of the public peace and good order”).        Moreover, several courts have
    concluded that such terms simply are not amenable to any meaningful definition, given
    10
    Additionally, because the Virginia scheme does not distinguish between private
    and public conduct, the term “habitual drunkard” lends itself to arbitrary enforcement of
    the interdiction process against homeless individuals in particular. See Brief of National
    Law Center on Homelessness & Poverty as Amicus Curiae in Support of Plaintiffs-
    Appellants, Manning v. Caldwell (No. 17-1320), at 13–14 (explaining that the term
    “habitual drunkard” has historically been used as a euphemism for the homeless).
    20
    the variety of differing definitions assigned to common terms of this nature. See, e.g.,
    State v. Pugh, 
    369 So. 2d 1308
    , 1309–10 (La. 1979); Ex Parte Newbern, 
    350 P.2d 116
    ,
    123 (Cal. 1960) (en banc).
    We do not require statutes to be models of “perfect clarity.” Ward v. Rock Against
    Racism, 
    491 U.S. 781
    , 794 (1989). But even acceptably imprecise language must specify
    some standard of conduct both to guide the actions of individuals and to govern law
    enforcement. See Cooper, 842 F.3d at 842; Lytle, 326 F.3d at 469. Without the addition
    of some defining standards, members of both groups are left without any understanding
    of how the scheme should be applied.
    The Commonwealth nevertheless contends that Plaintiffs’ admitted difficulty in
    maintaining sobriety proves that, whatever the definition of “habitual drunkard,” the term
    was meant to prohibit Plaintiffs’ conduct. The first problem with this argument is that the
    record lacks any indication of the conduct that led to Plaintiffs’ interdictions. Each of the
    named Plaintiffs were interdicted in absentia, and so have no knowledge of the evidence
    that was relied upon by the court in determining that they are “habitual drunkards.”
    Although the interdiction orders for Manning and Williams state that the court considered
    “abstract[s] of conviction” as part of the evidence submitted in those plaintiffs’ respective
    hearings, the interdiction orders consist entirely of boilerplate language that does not
    identify any offense on which those convictions were based, or the number of such
    convictions. And, as counsel for the Commonwealth admitted during oral argument,
    there is no requirement that a person be convicted of any offense to be interdicted as an
    21
    “habitual drunkard.” Thus, the interdiction orders, without more, do not establish that
    Plaintiffs’ conduct clearly was encompassed by Virginia’s scheme. 11
    Moreover, Plaintiffs’ acknowledgement that they have difficulty maintaining
    sobriety due to alcoholism does not establish that they are “habitual drunkards.”
    Plaintiffs are not charged with the responsibility of defining statutory terms, and their
    acknowledgement of illness says nothing about the sweep of the statutory scheme.
    Supreme Court precedent requires that statutes be based on objectively discernable
    standards. See, e.g., Johnson v. United States, 
    135 S. Ct. 2251
    , 2558 (2015); Kolender,
    461 U.S. at 357; Grayned v. City of Rockford, 
    408 U.S. 104
    , 108–09 (1972). And here,
    there is no basis on which to conclude that Plaintiffs’ conduct was clearly prohibited by
    the challenged scheme.
    In sum, the term “habitual drunkard” specifies no standard of conduct. It is thus
    unconstitutionally vague, 12 because the term invites the very type of arbitrary
    11
    The district court appears to have relied incorrectly on Plaintiffs’ post-
    interdiction arrests to conclude that these plaintiffs were sufficiently on notice of what
    conduct the scheme proscribed. But the fact that a person is arrested after being
    interdicted is irrelevant to the issue whether he or she should have been adjudicated an
    “habitual drunkard” in the first place. Indeed, an interdicted person is subject to arrest for
    merely possessing alcohol. Va. Code § 4.1-322. And it does not follow that mere
    possession of alcohol will inevitably lead to “habitual drunkenness.” Otherwise, an
    overwhelming number of adults in the Commonwealth of Virginia likely would be
    considered “habitual drunkards.”
    12
    For this reason, the Commonwealth’s attempt to frame this argument as a
    challenge to Plaintiffs’ standing to bring a facial vagueness claim is unpersuasive. The
    question whether Plaintiffs’ conduct clearly falls within the grasp of Virginia’s scheme
    necessarily requires an evaluation of the merits of that vagueness challenge as applied to
    these plaintiffs. See Holder v. Humanitarian Law Project, 
    561 U.S. 1
    , 18–19 (2010).
    And we have recognized that if a statute specifies “no standard of conduct,” the statute is
    (Continued)
    22
    enforcement that the Constitution’s prohibition against vague statutes is designed to
    prevent. See Cooper, 842 F.3d at 842–43. Accordingly, the challenged scheme’s current
    use of the term “habitual drunkard” is unconstitutionally vague even as applied to these
    Plaintiffs, and we conclude that the district court thus erred in dismissing Plaintiffs’
    vagueness challenge under Rule 12(b)(6).
    III.
    As we have explained, the term “habitual drunkard” as used in Virginia law is so
    vague as to offer no meaningful standard of conduct. But even if this term could be
    narrowed to apply only to those individuals who, like Plaintiffs, suffer from alcoholism,
    such a construction would raise independent Eighth Amendment concerns.               See
    Appellees’ Supp. Br. at 7 (“Whatever construction is given to the phrase . . . it surely
    applies to individuals who . . . ‘pathologically pursue alcohol use’ because they ‘have a
    profound drive or craving to use alcohol’ that ‘is largely uncontrollable and inevitable
    . . . .’” (quoting Plaintiffs’ complaint)). We now turn to those concerns.
    A.
    The Eighth Amendment’s Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause “circumscribes
    the criminal process in three ways.” Ingraham v. Wright, 
    430 U.S. 651
    , 667 (1977). The
    Clause operates to (1) “limit[] the kinds of punishment that can be imposed on those
    unconstitutionally vague notwithstanding the fact that some conduct may fall within the
    provision’s grasp. Cooper, 842 F.3d at 842–43; see also Johnson, 135 S. Ct. at 2560–61.
    23
    convicted of crimes,” (2) “proscribe[] punishment grossly disproportionate to the severity
    of the crime,” and (3) “impose[] substantive limits on what can be made criminal and
    punished as such.” Id.
    Plaintiffs’ Eighth Amendment challenge rests on the third limitation.              This
    restriction is “one to be applied sparingly,” id., for a state of course has broad authority to
    define and prosecute criminal offenses. But a state’s power to punish is not boundless, as
    the Supreme Court made clear more than fifty years ago.
    The Court then held that a California statute that criminalized addiction “to the use
    of narcotics” violated the third limitation. See Robinson v. California, 
    370 U.S. 660
    , 660,
    667 (1962); see also Ingraham, 430 U.S. at 667. Rejecting the state’s contention that this
    prohibition constituted a valid exercise of its police power, the Court reasoned that a
    narcotics addiction was an illness, and “a state law which imprison[ed] a person thus
    afflicted as a criminal” constituted cruel and unusual punishment. Robinson, 370 U.S. at
    666–67.
    1.
    In Robinson, the Supreme Court held that a state may not, consistent with the
    Eighth Amendment, punish an individual for being addicted to narcotics. Speaking for
    the Court, Justice Stewart explained that “at th[at] moment in history” no state would
    “attempt to make it a criminal offense for a person to be mentally ill, or a leper, or to be
    afflicted with a venereal disease.” Id. at 666. Rather, “a law which [would make] a
    criminal offense of such a disease would doubtless be universally thought to be an
    infliction of cruel and unusual punishment in violation of the Eighth and Fourteenth
    24
    Amendments.” Id. This was so, the Court held, because a state could not, consistent
    with the Constitution, punish a person for an illness. See id. at 667. In so holding, the
    Robinson Court expressly noted, as the state there recognized, that just as a “narcotic
    addict” is “in a state of mental and physical illness[,] [s]o is an alcoholic.” See id. at 667
    n.8.
    Six years after the Supreme Court decided Robinson, the Court considered a
    challenge to a Texas statute that criminalized public intoxication. Powell v. Texas, 
    392 U.S. 514
     (1968). The defendant, an alcoholic individual who was not homeless, argued
    that the Texas statute, like the statute in Robinson, punished an illness over which he had
    no control and so violated the Eighth Amendment. In a fractured decision (4–1–4), the
    Supreme Court affirmed Powell’s conviction.
    Four Justices in Powell interpreted Robinson to prohibit only the criminalization
    of “mere status.” Id. at 532 (Marshall, J.) (plurality opinion). In their view, the Texas
    statute withstood constitutional challenge because it criminalized the act of being
    intoxicated in public rather than the status of alcohol addiction. These Justices did not
    suggest that alcoholism was not an illness.        Nor did they contend that the Eighth
    Amendment allowed a state to prosecute an individual merely for being an alcoholic.
    Rather, they concluded that the Texas statute, unlike the law at issue in Robinson, did not
    criminalize “being an addict” or “being a chronic alcoholic.” Id.
    Four Justices voted to reverse Powell’s conviction. Writing for the dissent, Justice
    Fortas explained that Robinson compelled this result because it stood for a principle at
    “the foundation of individual liberty and the cornerstone of the relations between a
    25
    civilized state and its citizens”: the principle that “[c]riminal penalties may not be
    inflicted upon a person for being in a condition he is powerless to change.” Id. at 567
    (Fortas, J., dissenting, joined by Douglas, Brennan, & Stewart, JJ.). Because Powell —
    an alcoholic — “was powerless to avoid drinking” and “once intoxicated, he could not
    prevent himself from appearing in public places,” these Justices would have found
    Powell’s conviction violated the Eighth Amendment. Id. at 568–70. The dissenters
    believed that “the essential constitutional defect . . . [was] the same as in Robinson, for in
    both cases the particular defendant was accused of being in a condition which he had no
    capacity to change or avoid.” Id. at 567–68.
    Justice White provided the decisive fifth vote to uphold Powell’s conviction. In
    doing so, however, Justice White expressly rejected the act-status rationale adopted by
    the plurality and advocated by our dissenting colleagues. See id. at 548–49 (White, J.,
    concurring in the result). 13 As Justice White explained:
    Unless Robinson is to be abandoned, the use of narcotics by an addict must
    be beyond the reach of the criminal law. Similarly, the chronic alcoholic
    with an irresistible urge to consume alcohol should not be punishable for
    drinking or for being drunk.
    13
    Under the rule set forth in Marks v. United States, 
    430 U.S. 188
     (1977), Justice
    White’s opinion constitutes the holding of the Court. The Marks rule teaches that
    “[w]hen a fragmented Court decides a case and no single rationale explaining the result
    enjoys the assent of five Justices, the holding of the Court may be viewed as that position
    taken by those Members who concurred in the judgments on the narrowest grounds.” Id.
    at 193 (internal quotation marks and alterations omitted); cf. Hughes v. United States, 
    138 S. Ct. 1765
    , 1771–72 (2018). As the parties agree, see Reh’g Petition at 15; Reh’g Opp.
    at 10, this rule requires us to treat Justice White’s concurrence, the narrowest ground
    supporting the Court’s judgment, as “the holding of the Court.” Marks, 430 U.S. at 193.
    26
    Id. Agreeing with the four dissenters, Justice White concluded that the critical question
    was not whether the state statute punished an “act” or a “status,” but rather “whether
    volitional acts brought about the ‘condition’” of public intoxication and “whether those
    [volitional] acts [were] sufficiently proximate to the ‘condition.’” Id. at 550 n.2. Finding
    that Powell had not made the necessary evidentiary showing, Justice White voted to
    narrowly affirm his public intoxication conviction. Id. at 554.
    In reaching this conclusion, Justice White specifically contemplated a case, like
    the one at hand, in which no volitional act was required for conviction. In the context of
    the public intoxication statute at issue there, he explained that “chronic alcoholics must
    drink and hence must drink somewhere,” and while many chronic alcoholics “ha[d]
    homes, many others [did] not.” Id. at 551 (emphasis added). Thus, if individuals could
    show both “that resisting drunkenness [was] impossible and that avoiding public places
    when intoxicated [was] also impossible,” a statute banning public drunkenness would be
    unconstitutional as applied to them. Id. (emphasis added). In those circumstances, the
    statute would, in effect, “ban[] a single act for which [homeless alcoholics] may not be
    convicted under the Eighth Amendment — the act of getting drunk.” Id. To do so,
    Justice White concluded, would punish “addiction under a different name.” Id. at 548.
    2.
    Applying the teachings of Robinson and Powell to the factual allegations in
    Plaintiffs’ complaint, we can only conclude that — even assuming the term “habitual
    drunkard,” as used in Virginia law, could be limited to alcoholics — Plaintiffs have
    alleged a viable claim for relief under the Eighth Amendment. Plaintiffs allege they are
    27
    addicted to alcohol and that this addiction, like narcotics addiction, is an illness. They
    allege that their addiction causes them to “pathologically pursue alcohol use,” without
    any volitional control over their drinking.
    Plaintiffs thus allege that the challenged Virginia scheme targets them for special
    punishment for conduct that is both compelled by their illness and is otherwise lawful for
    all those of legal drinking age. 14 If true, the challenged scheme indeed violates the
    Eighth Amendment as applied to Plaintiffs. See Powell, 392 U.S. at 551 (White, J.,
    concurring in the result) (where “resisting drunkenness [was] impossible and . . . avoiding
    public places when intoxicated [was] also impossible,” conviction for being drunk in
    public would violate Eighth Amendment); Robinson, 370 U.S. at 666 (“[A] law which
    made a criminal offense of . . . a disease would doubtless be universally thought to be an
    infliction of cruel and unusual punishment . . . .”).
    To avoid this straightforward result, Virginia argues that its statutory scheme is
    consistent with both Powell and Robinson. In doing so, the Commonwealth primarily
    seeks to narrow the scope of Powell, and secondarily asserts that its interdiction scheme
    punishes actions rather than “being” and so comports with Robinson. Both efforts fail.
    14
    As noted above, Plaintiffs allege that the Virginia statute targets homeless
    alcoholics, rather than all alcoholics. See supra note 10. But this allegation is immaterial
    to Plaintiffs’ Eighth Amendment challenge because, as the Commonwealth explains, its
    statutory scheme, unlike that at issue in Powell, is not limited to outdoor or public
    conduct. Reh’g Opp. at 5–6. What matters under the Eighth Amendment is that
    Plaintiffs allege that the Commonwealth has singled them out for special punishment for
    otherwise lawful conduct that is compelled by their illness.
    28
    As to Powell, the Commonwealth concedes that Justice White’s concurrence
    “offers the narrowest basis for the Court’s fractured decision,” and so is controlling under
    the Marks rule. Reh’g Opp. at 10; see Marks, 430 U.S. at 193. The Commonwealth
    contends, however, that most of Justice White’s opinion is “dicta.” Reh’g Opp. at 11–12.
    According to the Commonwealth, the Marks rule only requires us to adhere to Justice
    White’s concurrence to the extent that when an “offense involves at least one volitional
    element, the Eighth Amendment does not bar criminal prosecution.” Id. at 12. In
    Virginia’s view, we are free to ignore the rest. Id.
    Even if we were to accept the Commonwealth’s characterization that Justice
    White’s controlling analysis — including his rejection of the act-status distinction on
    which the Commonwealth and our dissenting colleagues now rely — constitutes “dicta,”
    we cannot agree that we are free to ignore it. To the contrary, we routinely afford
    substantial, if not controlling deference to dicta from the Supreme Court. See, e.g., NLRB
    v. Bluefield Hosp. Co., LLC, 
    821 F.3d 534
    , 541 n.6 (4th Cir. 2016); McCravy v. Metro.
    Life Ins. Co., 
    690 F.3d 176
    , 181 n.2 (4th Cir. 2012). Respect for the rule of law demands
    nothing less: lower courts grappling with complex legal questions of first impression
    must give due weight to guidance from the Supreme Court, so as to ensure the consistent
    and uniform development and application of the law.
    Such deference seems particularly warranted here, given that the “dicta” the
    Commonwealth urges us to disregard was so central to Justice White’s result. This is not
    a case where a single jurist offered his unsolicited views on a tangential issue in passing.
    To the contrary, Justice White made clear that he voted to affirm Powell’s conviction not
    29
    because of the act-status theory relied on by the plurality, but solely because Powell had
    not produced facts establishing the involuntariness of his public alcoholism. See Powell,
    392 U.S. at 549 n.1 (White, J., concurring in the result). 15 And Justice White’s view as to
    the crucial importance of this fact was shared by four other Justices. 16 Particularly under
    these circumstances, we cannot accept the Commonwealth’s invitation to cast aside the
    reasoning underlying what it concedes is the controlling opinion in Powell.
    Moreover, even if we were free to narrow Powell to the one-sentence holding that
    the Commonwealth advances, Robinson would require the same result. Plaintiffs allege
    that their drinking is not “voluntary” and, thus, this case does not “involve[] at least one
    volitional element.” Reh’g Opp. at 12. At the motion to dismiss stage, we must take
    Plaintiffs’ allegations as true, and these allegations place us squarely within the holding
    15
    Justice White’s disagreement with the dissenters thus turned on whether Powell
    had made a sufficient showing in his case to challenge his conviction. Compare id. at
    568 & n.31 (Fortas, J., dissenting, joined by Douglas, Brennan, & Stewart, JJ.) (adopting
    trial judge’s findings), with id. at 549 (White, J., concurring in the result) (reasoning
    “[n]othing in the record before the trial court supports the” conclusion that “Powell was a
    chronic alcoholic with a compulsion . . . to frequent public places when intoxicated”),
    and id. at 521 (plurality op.) (“Whatever else may be said of them, those are not ‘findings
    of fact’ in any recognizable, traditional sense in which that term has been used . . . .”).
    As to the substantive limits imposed by the Eighth Amendment, Justice White’s views
    aligned far more with the dissent than the plurality.
    16
    We note that Justice (then-Judge) Kavanaugh has suggested that under a faithful
    application of the Marks rule, such views, if shared by five Justices, are binding on lower
    courts. See United States v. Duvall, 
    740 F.3d 604
    , 616 (D.C. Cir. 2013) (Kavanaugh, J.,
    concurring in the denial of rehearing en banc) (arguing “lower court[s] . . . must strive to
    reach the result that a majority of the Supreme Court would have reached in the current
    case” by “run[ning] the facts and circumstances of the current case through the various
    tests articulated by the Supreme Court in the binding case”). We need not determine
    today whether this is the proper reading of Marks, as our result would be the same in any
    event.
    30
    of Robinson, which bars Virginia from criminalizing Plaintiffs’ illness. 17 In fact, four
    years after Robinson, this Court applied that case to hold that “punish[ing] an involuntary
    symptom of a status” — namely, enforcing a criminal “public intoxication” statute
    against a “chronic alcoholic” — was unconstitutional. Driver v. Hinnant, 
    356 F.2d 761
    ,
    765 (4th Cir. 1966). 18 That principle applies in equal force today.
    In arguing to the contrary, the Commonwealth heavily relies on the fact that the
    challenged Virginia scheme operates in two steps. Recall that Virginia law first permits a
    court to enter a civil interdiction order “prohibiting the sale of alcoholic beverages . . .
    until further ordered” to a person who “has shown himself to be an habitual drunkard.”
    Va. Code § 4.1-333(A). Then state law makes it a Class 1 misdemeanor — punishable
    by up to a year in jail, see Va. Code § 18.2-11(a) — for an interdicted person to “possess
    any alcoholic beverages” or to “consume, purchase or possess, or attempt to consume,
    purchase or possess, any alcoholic beverage,” Va. Code §§ 4.1-322, 4.1-305.
    17
    The principal dissent suggests that our interpretation of this precedent “runs
    headlong into a large chorus of circuit court opinions” holding to the contrary. Far from
    it. Of the four cases the principal dissent cites in support of this assertion, two
    erroneously treated the plurality opinion in Powell as the holding of the Court, see Fisher,
    639 F.2d at 192; United States v. Stenson, 475 F. App’x 630, 631 (7th Cir. 2012), and two
    are cursory and unpersuasive decisions from the same circuit, see Joel v. City of Orlando,
    
    232 F.3d 1353
    , 1362 (11th Cir. 2000); United States v. Benefield, 
    889 F.2d 1061
    , 1064
    (11th Cir. 1989). In fact, the only other circuit to squarely confront the issue has arrived
    at the same conclusion we reach here. See Martin v. City of Boise, 
    920 F.3d 584
    , 616–17
    (9th Cir. 2019).
    18
    After affirming the constitutionality of this Virginia statute on vagueness and
    Eighth Amendment grounds, the Fisher court compounded its error by adopting the
    district court’s suggestion that Powell “overruled and made inapplicable the holding[] . . .
    of Driver.” Fisher, 486 F. Supp. at 316. As we have explained, Justice White’s
    controlling opinion in Powell did no such thing.
    31
    Virginia’s two-pronged statutory scheme may be less direct than the statute at
    issue in Robinson, but it yields the same result: it effectively criminalizes an illness.
    Robinson, 370 U.S. at 667–68. If the statute challenged in Robinson had instead allowed
    California to “interdict” prescription drug addicts and then arrest interdicted addicts for
    filling those prescriptions, the statute effectively would also have criminalized “being
    addicted to narcotics” even if it nominally punished only filling prescriptions. Such a
    statute would surely be just as unconstitutional as the statute in Robinson, and for
    precisely the same reasons.
    Similarly, although Virginia’s statutory scheme may nominally penalize
    “possession” or “consumption,” even a sufficiently definite construction limited to
    alcoholics effectively targets and punishes Plaintiffs based on their illness, which
    Robinson holds violates the Eighth Amendment. 19 As Justice White explained, the thin
    distinction between “hav[ing] an irresistible compulsion” and “yield[ing] to such a
    compulsion” is not one of constitutional magnitude under Robinson. See Powell, 392
    U.S. at 548 (White, J., concurring in the result). That the Commonwealth civilly brands
    19
    The dissents fundamentally err by presuming that the Robinson Court somehow
    embraced the act-status distinction on which the Commonwealth now relies. To do so,
    the dissents must ignore Robinson’s core holding: that a state may not, consistent with
    the Eighth Amendment, target a person for punishment based on an illness. Robinson,
    370 U.S. at 666–67 (holding “a state law which imprisons a person” afflicted with an
    illness “inflicts a cruel and unusual punishment”). In his controlling opinion in Powell,
    Justice White recognized that the act-status distinction could not be squared with this
    core holding. 392 U.S. at 548–49 (White, J., concurring in the result) (“Unless Robinson
    is to be abandoned, . . . the chronic alcoholic with an irresistible urge to consume alcohol
    should not be punishable for drinking or for being drunk.”). Thus, Justice White simply
    applied the Court’s holding in Robinson; he did not alter that holding in Powell and
    neither do we.
    32
    alcoholics   as   “habitual   drunkards”    before   prosecuting    them    for   involuntary
    manifestations of their illness does nothing to cure the unconstitutionality of this statutory
    scheme. 20
    We therefore conclude that, even if the term “habitual drunkard” could be
    construed to apply only to those who suffer from alcoholism, Plaintiffs have stated an
    independent claim that the challenged statute violates the Eighth Amendment.
    B.
    Our Eighth Amendment holding is narrow. Consistent with Robinson and Powell,
    Plaintiffs have limited their Eighth Amendment challenge to what they allege is targeted
    criminalization, in the first instance, of conduct that is an involuntary manifestation of
    their illness, and that is otherwise legal for the general population. Put differently,
    Plaintiffs allege that, as applied to them, the challenged statutory scheme threatens them
    with arrest and incarceration for conduct that is not proscribed as a consequence of a
    prior criminal conviction, does not rest on even a single volitional element, and is lawful
    for all others of legal drinking age.
    Plaintiffs do not challenge the constitutionality of any restrictions imposed after
    conviction of a crime, and our holding does not prevent the government from utilizing
    20
    Only Virginia and Utah retain interdiction laws today, and it is unclear how one
    is interdicted under Utah law and to what extent the Utah statute is applied in practice.
    Utah Code § 32B-1-102. That the vast majority of states eschew interdiction schemes
    suggests another reason to doubt their constitutionality. See Trop v. Dulles, 
    356 U.S. 86
    ,
    100–01 (1958) (explaining that because “the words of the [Eighth] Amendment are not
    precise” and “their scope is not static[,] [t]he Amendment must draw its meaning from
    the evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society”).
    33
    such prophylactic measures to thwart criminal misconduct. Unquestionably, courts may
    restrict an individual’s liberty pursuant to a criminal sentence, and (in some cases) may
    continue to do so after his formal sentence has concluded. Courts are thus entitled in
    appropriate cases to impose and enforce targeted restrictions as conditions of supervised
    release, probation, parole, or release from criminal custody, even on persons who suffer
    from certain illnesses. See, e.g., 18 U.S.C. § 3583(d) (permitting district courts to order
    conditions of supervised release that, among other things, “involve[] no greater
    deprivation of liberty than is reasonably necessary for the purposes set forth in”
    18 U.S.C. §§ 3553(a)(2)(B)–(D)); 34 U.S.C. § 20913 (establishing sex offender registry);
    id. § 20911(1) (defining “sex offender” as “an individual who was convicted of a sex
    offense”).    Plaintiffs’ limited challenge does not implicate such post-conviction
    restrictions, nor does our holding cast any doubt on their continued viability.
    Plaintiffs also wisely confine their Eighth Amendment challenge to conduct that is
    an involuntary manifestation of the very illness that triggers the Commonwealth’s
    scheme. Robinson, Powell, and our holding here are so cabined. Thus, our analysis does
    not call into question substantive criminal laws, like penalties for underage drinking and
    prohibitions against driving while intoxicated, that do not involve conduct that is an
    involuntary manifestation of an illness. 21
    21
    As noted above, the plaintiffs have not challenged the portion of the Virginia
    statutory scheme providing for the interdiction of individuals who have been convicted of
    driving while intoxicated. See supra note 1.
    34
    Moreover, Plaintiffs do not seek an exemption from generally applicable criminal
    laws, and our reasoning does not offer them one. A state undoubtedly has the power to
    prosecute individuals, even those suffering from illnesses, for breaking laws that apply to
    the general population. That is so because such laws — even when enforced against sick
    people — reflect a state’s considered judgment that some actions are so dangerous or
    contrary to the public welfare that they should lead to criminal liability for everyone who
    commits them. Faithfully following Robinson and Powell, as we do, does not provide an
    alcoholic escape from prosecution for such behavior. See Powell, 392 U.S. at 552 n.4
    (White, J., concurring) (emphasizing that the Eighth Amendment does not bar a state
    from convicting “the heavily intoxicated, compulsive alcoholic . . . for committing crimes
    involving much greater risk to society”).         Thus, contrary to the principal dissent’s
    suggestion, our holding neither creates nor supports the notion of a nonvolitional defense
    against generally applicable crimes.
    Finally, our holding does not unduly restrict “[t]he broad power of a State to
    regulate” alcohol within its borders. Robinson, 370 U.S. at 664. As the Court explained
    in Robinson, “[t]here can be no question of the authority of the state in the exercise of its
    police power to regulate the administration, sale, prescription and use of dangerous and
    habitforming drugs.”     Id. (internal quotation marks omitted).      Nor does the Eighth
    Amendment tie the hands of state officials seeking to address the ill effects of alcoholism.
    “[T]he range of valid choice[s] which a State might make in this area is undoubtedly a
    wide one, and the wisdom of any particular choice within the allowable spectrum is not
    for us to decide.” Id. at 665.
    35
    What the Eighth Amendment cannot tolerate is the targeted criminalization of
    otherwise legal behavior that is an involuntary manifestation of an illness. Imprisonment
    for a short time — here, for not more than twelve months — does not, in the abstract,
    seem to be cruel or unusual punishment.            But, as the Supreme Court in Robinson
    recognized, “[e]ven one day in prison would be a cruel and unusual punishment for the
    ‘crime’ of having a common cold.” 370 U.S. at 667. If, as Plaintiffs allege, Virginia has
    in the challenged statutory scheme criminalized and punished otherwise legal behavior by
    them, and that behavior is an involuntary manifestation of their illness, then Virginia has
    imposed cruel and unusual punishment just as surely as California did in Robinson.
    IV.
    In sum, we hold that the challenged Virginia statutory scheme is unconstitutionally
    vague, and that even assuming it could be limited to those suffering from alcoholism,
    Plaintiffs have stated an Eighth Amendment claim under both Robinson and Powell. In
    so holding, we expressly take the step the panel could not: we overrule our flawed
    decision in Fisher, 
    639 F.2d 191
    , which bound the district court in this case as to both
    claims.
    In Fisher, we affirmed the constitutionality of the Virginia scheme “for reasons
    sufficiently stated by” the district court, id. at 192, thus adopting reasoning that rejected a
    vagueness challenge and incorrectly treated the plurality opinion in Powell as the holding
    of the Court without deference to, or even acknowledgment of, Justice White’s
    36
    controlling concurrence, see Fisher, 486 F. Supp. at 316. Fisher was wrong when
    decided, and we explicitly overrule it today.
    Without question, the many homeless citizens of Virginia who struggle with the
    effects of alcohol on their mental and physical health are entitled to guidance and fair
    notice under the law. They have not been given such direction in the current version of
    this statutory scheme. While necessary changes in the law may not alter the choices that
    they make or enhance the quality of their life, at least the government will not be
    compounding their problems by subjecting them to incarceration based on the arbitrary
    enforcement of ambiguous laws or, at best, the targeted criminalization of their illnesses.
    Accordingly, the judgment of the district court is reversed and the case is
    remanded for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
    REVERSED AND REMANDED
    37
    BARBARA MILANO KEENAN, Circuit Judge, with whom Judge MOTZ and Judge
    THACKER join, concurring:
    In my view, the alarmist tone of the principal dissent warrants separate comment.
    Among other salvos, the principal dissent characterizes the majority opinion as “an
    assault upon the constitutional, democratic, and common law foundations of American
    civil and criminal law.” Additional remarks include likening the members of the majority
    to “Caesar Augustus,” accusing the majority of “usurp[ing] the American Constitution,”
    and alleging that our decision today will exacerbate the abuse of women.
    What were the principal dissenters reading when they reached these conclusions?
    Surely not the majority’s opinion, addressing arguments that a Virginia statutory scheme
    is vague and targets homeless alcoholics based on their compulsion to consume alcohol.
    I make these observations because I worry about the message that we convey to
    the public when we attempt to bolster a legal analysis by making assertions suggesting
    malfeasance by judges who disagree with our position. And what message do we send to
    trial judges and lawyers who know that such assertions are false? Will they view these
    broadsides as evidence of institutional disharmony?      Such attacks are not part of a
    “vigorous exchange of views,” but instead detract from any substantive analysis.
    As judges, we all take our duty to faithfully interpret the law as a solemn
    obligation. That we reach different conclusions in applying the law to a given case
    should be of no moment. What is truly important is that we have a legal system that
    allows for good-faith disagreements and provides for further review by a higher court.
    38
    Our Court has a cherished tradition of civility. In that spirit, I express hope that
    we will turn away from the use of inflammatory language, which diminishes the value of
    our work.
    39
    WILKINSON, Circuit Judge, with whom Judges NIEMEYER, AGEE, RICHARDSON,
    QUATTLEBAUM, and Senior Judge DUNCAN join, dissenting:
    This ought to be a straightforward case. But the majority asks this court to take
    two unprecedented steps. First, it asks that we find—as no court previously has―that
    addiction gives rise to an Eighth Amendment right to abuse dangerous substances without
    the imposition of any criminal sanctions. Second, it insists that we expand vagueness
    doctrine to invalidate a civil statute that clearly delineates the conduct within its ambit.
    The Eighth Amendment leaves to the states the decision as to which acts are
    worthy of the community’s opprobrium. And so long as the state’s proscriptions give
    sufficient notice of what acts are culpable, the vagueness doctrine does not stand in the
    way. The Virginia statutes at issue here prohibit specific acts regarding alcohol and do so
    for a variety of legitimate reasons. That should be all that is required.
    Instead of simply applying the law as it is, my colleagues strive for something
    new; thrusting our court into not one, but two, jurisprudential quagmires. First, the
    majority has found—in the Eighth Amendment’s prohibition on “cruel and unusual”
    punishments, of all places―constitutional protection for any act that is alleged to be
    “non-volitional,” i.e. the result of some compulsion. Maj. Op. at 5. In doing so, it has
    discarded any pretense of a workable limiting principle, expanded the Eighth Amendment
    beyond any discernible limits, and overturned sixty years of controlling Supreme Court
    precedent (Part I).
    Unfortunately, Supreme Court precedent will not be the only victim of this
    decision. The majority’s new theory of the Eighth Amendment will foreclose a state’s
    40
    ability to take reasonable steps to protect its citizens from serious and long recognized
    harms. The consequences will fall on the most vulnerable, especially the victims of
    domestic abuse and sexual assault. How ironic that the majority would stand on the cusp
    of the centennial of women’s suffrage and deal a setback not only to the physical safety
    of women, but to their basic right to peace of mind (Part II). Its decision will also
    interject the federal courts into areas traditionally and wisely reserved for the states,
    subverting both the democratic process and dual sovereignty (Part III.A). The majority,
    moreover, has converted the Eighth Amendment into a constitutional provision for all
    seasons, designed to do what other constitutional provisions manifestly cannot (Part
    III.B).
    It is hard to believe a single decision could inflict more damage, but this one
    proceeds to do just that. The majority, in an alternative holding, invokes the Due Process
    Clause to contort vagueness doctrine beyond recognition. It takes what has heretofore
    been a limited principle and extends it to a civil statute that is not only clear on its face,
    but exists solely for the purpose of giving fair notice of what the law requires. The
    majority’s notion of civil vagueness imperils a whole range of previously uncontroversial
    statutes (Part IV).
    My colleagues in the majority strain to present this case as “narrow” and
    inconsequential; a judicial ticket good for one train only. Maj. Op. at 33. I am not
    comforted. There is nothing “narrow” about the majority’s holding or its reasoning. This
    case is an assault upon the constitutional, democratic, and common law foundations of
    American civil and criminal law, and most importantly, to the judge’s place within it. I
    41
    cannot join journeys whose destinations are so shrouded in uncertainty. One day the last
    dolorous rays of sun will set upon the majority’s approach. Sooner rather than later, I
    hope. But in all events, eventually, at the United States Supreme Court.
    I.
    I begin with the Eighth Amendment question, for which we granted en banc
    review in the first place. * The majority professes to believe that states have “broad
    authority to define and prosecute criminal offenses,” Maj. Op. at 24, but proceeds to hold
    that the Eighth Amendment nonetheless imposes a limit on a state’s ability to proscribe
    specific conduct in its criminal law. For the nearly six decades since the decision in
    Robinson v. California, 
    370 U.S. 660
     (1962), courts have consistently and emphatically
    rejected that view. Resolving this case requires nothing more than the straightforward
    application of settled constitutional law.
    A.
    The Eighth Amendment states that “[e]xcessive bail shall not be required, nor
    excessive fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments inflicted.” U.S. Const.
    amend. VIII. In Robinson v. California, the Supreme Court held that this constitutional
    guarantee prevented a state from making it a crime “to be addicted to the use of
    narcotics.” 
    370 U.S. 660
     (1962). Unlike laws that “punish[] a person for the use of
    narcotics, for their purchase, sale or possession, or for antisocial or disorderly behavior
    *
    This dissent draws in part from the now vacated panel opinion in Manning v.
    Caldwell, 
    900 F.3d 139
     (4th Cir. 2018).
    42
    resulting from their administration,” id. at 666, the statute before the Court in Robinson
    punished the mere “status” of narcotics addiction, untethered from any particular
    conduct. Id. Faced with a criminal sanction that so clearly departed from the traditional
    foundations of the criminal law, the Court held that the Eighth Amendment had been
    violated. As the Court reasoned, “[e]ven one day in prison would be cruel and unusual
    punishment for the ‘crime’ of having a common cold.” Id. at 667.
    The Robinson Court was careful to note the “broad power of the State to regulate
    the narcotic drugs traffic within its borders.” Id. at 664. Indeed, a “State might impose
    criminal sanctions, for example, against the unauthorized manufacture, prescription, sale,
    purchase, or possession of narcotics” because those things constitute punishable conduct,
    not status. Id. The Court in Robinson thus considered and rejected precisely what the
    majority has now done, and that is to read its holding to prevent states from criminalizing
    any particular act associated with dangerous and addictive substances. Because the
    holding of Robinson is so emphatic on this point, it is worth quoting the relevant
    paragraph in full:
    The broad power of a State to regulate the narcotic drugs traffic within its
    borders is not here in issue. More than forty years ago . . . this Court
    explicitly recognized the validity of that power: ‘There can be no question
    of the authority of the state in the exercise of its police power to regulate
    the administration, sale, prescription and use of dangerous and
    habitforming drugs . . . . The right to exercise this power is so manifest in
    the interest of the public health and welfare, that it is unnecessary to enter
    upon a discussion of it beyond saying that it is too firmly established to be
    successfully called in question.’
    Id. at 664 (quotations and alterations omitted). The holding of Robinson is clear: the
    criminal law cannot punish who you are; it can only punish what you do. That simple
    43
    command has given rise to the “status-act distinction” or, if you will, “illness-act
    distinction” in our Eighth Amendment jurisprudence, a distinction that has remained
    untouched since Robinson, and respected until the majority’s effort to unravel it today.
    The Supreme Court has never wavered from the decision in Robinson and the
    status-act distinction that it articulated. In Powell v. Texas, 
    392 U.S. 514
     (1968), decided
    only a few years after Robinson, a defendant challenged a Texas law that prohibited
    public drunkenness on the ground that his status as an alcoholic compelled him to violate
    the statute. In a divided opinion, the Supreme Court upheld the statute. Id. A four-justice
    plurality, authored by Justice Marshall, found that it was not the lack of volition on the
    part of the offender, but the lack of any conduct whatsoever, that had created a
    constitutional infirmity in Robinson, and that no such defect existed in the Texas statute.
    Id. at 533 (“[C]riminal penalties may be inflicted only if the accused has committed some
    act, has engaged in some behavior, which society has an interest in preventing, or perhaps
    in historical common law terms, has committed some actus reus.”).
    Justice White, who cast the decisive fifth vote, left open the question of whether
    conduct compelled by addiction might be protected under Robinson. But because Powell
    “made no showing that he was unable to stay off the streets on the night in question,”
    Justice White voted to uphold the conviction on the ground that Powell’s behavior
    involved a volitional act. Id. at 553-54. Justice White wrote that it was “unnecessary to
    pursue at this point the further definition of the circumstances or the state of intoxication
    which might bar conviction of a chronic alcoholic for being drunk in a public place.” Id.
    at 553. Because Justice White chose to resolve the case without reaching the broader
    44
    question of compulsion, the judgment in Powell neither extended or contracted Robinson,
    which was left undisturbed.
    This has been the consensus view of the Supreme Court and our sister circuits ever
    since. Astonishingly, the majority has focused on what is at best an ambiguous opinion
    by a single justice, and has completely ignored the entirety of the legal landscape since
    Powell was handed down. Maj. Op. at 26-36. Worst of all, the majority has not even
    bothered to look at the approval of Robinson signaled by the Supreme Court itself.
    To repeat, the Supreme Court has not walked away from Robinson. It has not
    embraced the majority’s whole notion of nonvolitional conduct, which under Robinson
    would plainly constitute a proscribable act. Instead, long after the decision in Powell, the
    Supreme Court has routinely looked to Robinson as providing the applicable law for the
    Eighth Amendment. See, e.g., Atkins v. Virginia, 
    536 U.S. 304
    , 311 (2002); Solem v.
    Helm, 
    463 U.S. 277
    , 287 (1983); Rummel v. Estelle, 
    445 U.S. 263
    , 268 (1980). When the
    Supreme Court has cited to Powell, it has been to the four-justice plurality, which
    explicitly adopted the status-act distinction. See, e.g., Clark v. Arizona, 
    548 U.S. 735
    ,
    774-75 (2006); Montana v. Egelhoff, 
    518 U.S. 37
    , 56 (1996) (plurality); Medina v.
    California, 
    505 U.S. 437
    , 449 (1992); Ingraham v. Wright, 
    430 U.S. 651
    , 667 (1977);
    Marshall v. United States, 
    414 U.S. 417
    , 426-27 (1974). Moreover, Eighth Amendment
    cases involving issues of mental capacity have been concerned with modes of
    punishment, which is the primary focus of the Amendment, rather than the substance of
    state criminal laws. See Atkins v. Virginia, 
    536 U.S. 304
     (2002).
    45
    The majority now puts us at odds with the Supreme Court’s understanding of its
    own decision. It also runs headlong into a large chorus of circuit court
    opinions―including from this court, see Fisher v. Coleman, 
    639 F.2d 191
     (4th Cir.
    1981)―which have upheld state laws criminalizing acts that were allegedly compelled.
    For instance, the Seventh Circuit held that an alcoholic who violated the terms of his
    parole by consuming alcohol “was not punished for his status as an alcoholic but for his
    conduct. Therefore, his claim for cruel and unusual punishment fails.” United States v.
    Stenson, 475 F. App’x 630, 631 (7th Cir. 2012) (“Under Powell, punishment for unlawful
    conduct resulting from alcoholism is permissible.”); see also Joel v. City of Orlando, 
    232 F.3d 1353
    , 1361 (11th Cir. 2000) (“A distinction exists between applying criminal laws
    to punish conduct, which is constitutionally permissible, and applying them to punish
    status, which is not.”); United States v. Benefield, 
    889 F.2d 1061
    , 1064 (11th Cir. 1989)
    (“The considerations that make any incarceration unconstitutional when a statute
    punishes a defendant for his status are not applicable when the government seeks to
    punish a person’s actions.”). In the rare case where the Eighth Amendment was found to
    invalidate a criminal law, the law in question sought to punish persons merely for their
    need to eat or sleep, which are essential bodily functions. See Pottinger v. City of Miami,
    
    810 F. Supp. 1551
    , 1565 (S.D. Fla. 1992) (“For plaintiffs, resisting the need to eat, sleep
    or engage in other life-sustaining activities is impossible.”). This is simply a variation of
    Robinson’s command that the state identify conduct in crafting its laws, rather than
    punish a person’s mere existence.
    46
    My colleagues in the majority disagree, and instead tease their preferred reading
    from the dicta of a single justice. Maj. Op. at 26-36. By venturing so far from the
    Supreme Court’s guidance, the majority has adopted a view of the Eighth Amendment
    that has never been necessary to the Supreme Court’s resolution of any single case. The
    Powell decision, as earlier noted, was a 4-1-4 decision. Faced with a such a decision,
    which lacks a clear majority rationale for the judgment, federal courts are instructed that
    the “holding of the Court may be viewed as that position taken by those Members who
    concurred in the judgments on the narrowest ground.” Marks v. United States, 
    430 U.S. 188
    , 193 (1977) (quotations omitted). There may well be difficult cases concerning how
    best to apply Marks, but this is not one of them. As mentioned above, Justice Marshall’s
    decision for four justices in Powell upheld the statute on the basis of the status-act
    distinction. Justice White concurred in this judgment because the statute in question
    involved an act that was clearly volitional, forestalling the need to examine whether and
    under what conditions nonvolitional conduct might be constitutionally shielded from
    criminal sanctions. The majority improperly pulls from this concurrence, which took
    pains not to decide a constitutional question, a new constitutional rule: that states may not
    criminalize conduct “compelled by [a person’s] illness.” Maj. Op. at 28. The problem, of
    course, is that this new rule is found nowhere in the Court’s holding. The majority’s
    quotation of selected sentences from the concurring opinion fails to recognize the
    ultimate point that Justice White never purported to reach the central question.
    Because Justice White took a narrow view of the case, leaving the broader issues
    to the side, the Powell decision does not overturn or in any way disrupt Robinson. There
    47
    has never been any holding that Robinson’s status-act distinction has yielded to a new test
    focused on compulsion. As Judge Wilkey noted shortly after Powell, “the interpretation
    that Robinson held that it was not criminal to give in to the irresistible compulsion of a
    ‘disease[]’ weaves in and out of the Powell opinions, but there [was] definitely no
    Supreme Court holding to this effect.” United States v. Moore, 
    486 F.2d 1139
    , 1150
    (D.C. Cir. 1973) (en banc) (plurality opinion). The absence of such a holding, as well as
    the Supreme Court’s repeated references to the status-act distinction as the law, means
    that we are bound to respect Robinson until some clearer and more definitive guidance
    emerges. Those who see in the Powell decision a repudiation of Robinson are mistaking
    themselves for occupants of a higher bench.
    What we are left with, then, is simply a matter of fact. And as a matter of fact, for
    nearly sixty years courts at all levels have consistently affirmed Robinson’s basic
    holding: although states may not criminalize status, they may criminalize actual behavior
    even when the individual alleges that addiction created a strong urge to engage in a
    particular act.
    The status-act distinction has endured because it works. States are given a clear
    constitutional line to respect in crafting their criminal laws. Lower courts are given a
    simple and principled directive to apply when assessing those laws in subsequent
    proceedings. By contrast, the majority’s alternative “afford[s] substantial, if not
    controlling deference to dicta.” Maj. Op. at 29. But the majority’s approach utterly fails
    to provide a workable test for defining compulsion, which is the predictable result of
    relying on guidance divorced from what was necessary to resolve a concrete dispute. Nor
    48
    does the majority explain why such a test, whatever it is, applies to alcohol consumption,
    but is not equally applicable to narcotics use, sexual molestations, or other allegedly
    compelled acts. If the Supreme Court had ever rested an Eighth Amendment decision on
    the compelled nature of an act, there would likely be an answer to these questions. But
    because the majority has ventured far beyond the Court’s actual judgments, it strands the
    doctrine at sea. Much better for us, in assessing an Eighth Amendment challenge, to limit
    our review to whether the law at issue has proscribed specific conduct, or in common law
    terms, an actus reus. If yes, our task comes to an end.
    So yet again, the question for us is whether we should permit a 4-1-4 opinion that
    is at most ambiguous to overturn or greatly extend a longstanding and widely recognized
    Supreme Court opinion that the Court itself has repeatedly referenced and has never once
    seen fit to repudiate or otherwise disavow. It is in the end a matter of respecting both the
    Supreme Court’s authority to overturn its own decisions, and the limits of a circuit
    court’s authority to find circuitous routes around higher controlling precedent. The
    principle embodied in that precedent is plain. The vitality of Robinson is simply not an
    open question.
    B.
    Under the status-act distinction, which must govern our consideration of this case,
    the Virginia statutes pose no defect whatsoever. Virginia has been careful to draft a
    statutory scheme that falls on the constitutional side of the line drawn in Robinson. This
    scheme is comprised of two parts: one civil and one criminal. The interdiction provision
    set forth in § 4.1-333 is a civil enactment. Under that provision, a person can be
    49
    interdicted, and therefore subject to specific alcohol-related prohibitions, on the basis of
    either a drunk driving conviction or designation as a “habitual drunkard.” An interdiction
    order is not accompanied by imprisonment or a punitive fine. The Eighth Amendment’s
    prohibition on “cruel and unusual punishment” has obvious criminal purposes. See
    Ingraham v. Wright, 
    430 U.S. 651
    , 664 (1977). A provision that puts a person on notice
    that future acts may result in criminal sanctions does not criminalize status for the simple
    reason that it does not criminalize anything. It is the other Virginia provisions, not § 4.1-
    333, that impose criminal sanctions.
    While criminal prohibitions do come into play in §§ 4.1-322 and 4.1-305, those
    prohibitions apply only to affirmative acts: to “possess any alcoholic beverages” or to “be
    drunk in public,” and to “consume, purchase or possess, or attempt to consume, purchase
    or possess, any alcoholic beverage.” The whole world, apart from the majority, knows
    these things are acts. Appellants were arrested on the basis of committing these acts. That
    stands in stark contrast to the statute at issue in Robinson, under which a defendant could
    be charged even if the state never showed that he “used or possessed any narcotics.” 370
    U.S. at 666. The defendant’s alleged compulsion simply does not enter into this analysis.
    The majority implausibly claims that the plaintiffs’ “drinking is not ‘voluntary,’” and so,
    somehow, “Robinson would require the same result.” Maj. Op. at 30. But the problem in
    Robinson, as the Court explained, was not that the criminal sanction applied to
    “compelled,” “involuntary,” or “nonvolitional” acts; the problem was that the law applied
    to no act at all. The Virginia statutes do not “criminaliz[e] Plaintiffs’ illness,” Maj. Op. at
    50
    31; they criminalize specific acts. See Va. Code Ann., §§ 4.1-322, 4.1-305. They
    therefore lack the core defect of the law in Robinson.
    I emphasize what I hope would be obvious: it would be unlawful for the state to
    simply round up “undesirable” persons based on their perceived status as addicts or
    drunkards. Cf. Papachristou v. City of Jacksonville, 
    405 U.S. 156
     (1972). It is inimical to
    personal dignity and liberty to bring criminal charges on the basis of who someone is. To
    allow any sort of roundup exercise would not only grossly augment the power of the
    state, but put that power to the most pernicious use. For that reason, there must be some
    behavioral link set forth in the law. But Virginia has been careful to observe that line. It
    has prohibited individuals deemed at a higher risk of alcohol abuse from possessing or
    consuming alcohol. This category includes not only habitual drunkards, but also people
    who have been convicted of drunk driving offenses and those under twenty-one. See
    § 4.1-305.
    Perhaps aware that the status-act distinction is still operative, the majority strains
    to fit within the test, arguing that Virginia law “effectively criminalizes an illness.” Maj.
    Op. at 32 (emphasis added). That argument, however, again ignores the fact that the
    Virginia scheme actually bases criminal liability on specific acts. Robinson, 370 U.S. at
    662. Those acts can be done by any person subject to interdiction, regardless of their
    status as “homeless” or “alcoholic.” The majority’s claim that Virginia “nominally
    penalize[s] ‘possession’ or ‘consumption,’ . . . [but] effectively targets and punishes
    Plaintiffs based on their illness,” Maj. Op. at 32, not only mischaracterizes Virginia law,
    but threatens to change the character of criminal law as we have known it.
    51
    Which laws criminalize illness and which do not? In trying to cabin its new
    constitutional theory, the majority emphasizes time and again that its holding will only
    reach statutes that criminalize “otherwise legal behavior.” Maj. Op. at 36. My colleagues
    are silent, however, on just where this limit comes from. Surely not Robinson or Powell,
    both of which dealt with generally applicable criminal laws. Even Justice White’s
    opinion in Powell noted that a constitutional test based on volition would collapse into
    factual squabbles about what constitutes addiction, what constitutes compulsion, and
    what crimes are serious enough to, in the court’s view, overcome the nonvolitional claims
    of the accused. See Powell, 392 U.S. at 552, n.4. As the Justices themselves understood,
    such a position has no plain limiting principle.
    I do not state this lightly. It is wise not to accept casually every “slippery slope” or
    “open-the-floodgates” argument that comes along. But in this case the potential breadth
    of the principle espoused by the appellants and the majority is staggering. Many criminal
    acts can be alleged to “effectively” be the result of some compulsion. Many statutes can
    be alleged to punish someone’s illness. If human behavior is viewed as something over
    which human beings lack control, and for which they are not responsible, the
    implications are boundless. The examples extend beyond the discrete context of
    substance addiction. For instance, child molesters could challenge their convictions on
    the basis that their criminal acts were the product of uncontrollable pedophilic urges and
    therefore beyond the purview of criminal law. See Kansas v. Hendricks, 
    521 U.S. 346
    ,
    362 (1997) (upholding a sex offender statute where the law in question defined sex
    offenders as “suffering from a ‘mental abnormality’ or a ‘personality disorder’ that
    52
    prevents them from exercising adequate control over their behavior”). The same could be
    said not only of sex offenders, but of stalkers, domestic abusers, and others driven by
    impulses they were allegedly powerless to check. The Eighth Amendment has not, before
    today, been thought to absolve them of their wrongs. From this point on, however,
    “nonvolitional conduct” will enter the gallery of go-to phrases used to curtail the capacity
    of democratic governments to protect the people from a veritable slew of allegedly
    nonvolitional criminal acts.
    II.
    A.
    In its rush to condemn the Virginia statute, the majority makes no more than
    passing mention of “the ill effects of alcoholism,” Maj. Op. at 35, averting its eyes from
    the painful reasons why states regulate alcohol in the first place. Reading the majority’s
    opinion, one would be forgiven for thinking the majority was discussing soda pop. But
    decades of research show that “[a] large number of crimes, especially violent crimes, are
    committed by intoxicated offenders.” Montana v. Egelhoff, 
    518 U.S. 37
    , 49 (1996)
    (plurality) (citing Third Special Report to the U.S. Congress on Alcohol and Health from
    the Secretary of Health, Education, and Welfare 64 (1978)). The link between alcohol
    and violence has been well-documented for a century and motivated early efforts to limit
    alcohol consumption and intoxication. See generally John S. Billings et al., The Liquor
    Problem 10 (1905) (“[N]early fifty per cent[] of crime is referred to intemperance as one
    cause, and in thirty-one per cent[] it appears as a first cause.”). Let us stipulate that
    53
    Prohibition was a wildly impractical experiment. Let us stipulate also that alcohol use in
    moderation visits little or no social harm. The days of national Prohibition are fortunately
    behind us. See U.S. Const. amend. XXI. But the days of alcohol abuse and concomitant
    violence are unfortunately not.
    One particularly troubling example of violence driven by alcohol is domestic
    abuse. We all know the familiar story: a man pockets his Friday paycheck, heads off to
    the nearest bar, and stumbles home to commit what are too often unconscionable acts.
    The women’s groups who led the Temperance Movement understood this menace all too
    well, and made violence in the home a rallying cry for their cause. See Note, Bernadette
    Dunn Sewell, History of Abuse: Societal, Judicial, and Legislative Responses to the
    Problem of Wife Beating, 23 Suffolk L. Rev. 983, 991 (1989) (“Temperance campaigners
    viewed domestic violence as inextricably connected with the evils of alcohol, and thus
    sought abolition as a means of protecting abuse victims.”).
    The scourge of alcohol-related violence is with us still. Studies show that more
    than 90% of domestic violence offenders, for example, used alcohol or other drugs on the
    day of the attack. See Daniel Brookoff et al., Characteristics of Participants in Domestic
    Violence, 277 J. Am. Med. Ass’n 1369 (1997). While Virginia’s regulatory scheme
    applies to rich and poor alike, many crimes, fueled by alcohol, fall hardest on the most
    vulnerable. Women of limited means often lack the resources to engage counsel in cases
    of domestic abuse or to escape brutal treatment in what should be inviolate sanctuaries in
    their lives. Similarly, the sexual violence on American campuses is largely driven by
    “[m]en who reported heavy drinking.” Christopher P. Krebs et al., The Campus Sexual
    54
    Assault (CSA) Study, Nat’l Inst. of Just., at 2-11 (October 2007). These campus sexual
    offenses, which are finally starting to receive the attention they deserve, endanger a
    shocking number of young women. Id. at xiii (“Nineteen percent of the women reported
    experiencing completed or attempted sexual assault since entering college.”). Now we
    may expect that future attempts to impose even mild civil restrictions on heavy or
    habitual campus drinkers will be met with a nonvolitional conduct objection.
    The majority goes to great lengths to say that it is not creating a “nonvolitional
    defense against generally applicable crimes.” Maj. Op. at 35. It believes its opinion can
    somehow be confined to the context of this case, despite the undeniable breadth of its
    dual holdings. That is not how law’s progressions work. The very day that a doctrine of
    this nature is announced, a court relinquishes control over its course. Many insidious
    principles seek innocuous entries, and the majority has no control over how its new rule
    will be applied.
    It takes no great imagination to develop the nonvolitional possibilities. See supra,
    at 52-53. The severe “practical considerations” surrounding a new doctrine “serve to
    highlight the wisdom of the traditional limitations” on a court’s function and ought to
    prevent us from taking a first step when we do not know where the subsequent steps will
    lead. San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 
    411 U.S. 1
    , 58 (1973) (“[W]e do no
    violence to the values of federalism and separation of powers by staying our hand.”). I
    take no solace whatsoever in the majority’s assurance that its decision is a narrow one; it
    is but the momentary narrowness of a waxing quarter moon.
    
    55 Barb. I
     do not understand why the majority would go to such lengths to thwart attempts
    to ameliorate these conditions. Virginia has developed a comprehensive policy to
    confront the pervasive problem of alcohol abuse. But the majority, despite its protests to
    the contrary, would use “the Eighth Amendment [to] tie the hands of state officials.” Maj.
    Op. at 35. The interdiction statute at issue here is one part of Virginia’s larger scheme.
    The law sanctions relatively minor acts, like using and possessing alcohol, in order to
    forestall more serious criminal misconduct. The statute achieves this result through a
    two-step approach: first, a civil determination identifies people who are more likely to
    commit serial and grave offenses. Va. Code Ann. §§ 4.1-333, 4.1-334. Second, these
    individuals are then subject to milder criminal sanctions on relatively small acts to head
    off more heinous criminal misconduct. Id. §§ 4.1-322, 4.1-305. Any person who satisfies
    the criteria for the first step, whether because of drunk driving or habitual drinking, is
    subject to the criminal prohibitions of the second step. By establishing this framework,
    Virginia has made the judgment that the purchase or consumption of alcohol by persons
    with a history of heavy drinking could lead them to commit more dangerous acts, like
    drunk driving, domestic abuse, or sexual assault.
    States have always been entrusted with regulating addictive substances, most
    especially alcohol. See Cal. Retailer’s Liquor Dealers Ass’n v. Midcal Aluminum, Inc.,
    
    445 U.S. 97
    , 110 (1980) (“The Twenty-first Amendment grants the States virtually
    complete control over whether to permit importation or sale of liquor and how to
    structure the liquor distribution system.”). In exercising its broad powers in this area,
    56
    Virginia has chosen a prophylactic approach, focusing its resources on those who are
    most likely to present a heightened future risk. This includes those convicted of drunk
    driving offenses or prior alcohol-related offenses, as well as those who are designated
    “habitual drunkards,” which can follow from repeated misconduct while intoxicated. Va.
    Code Ann. §§ 4.1-333, 334; see Jackson v. Commonwealth, 
    604 S.E.2d 122
    , 124 (Va. Ct.
    App. 2004). In adopting this policy, the state legislature has applied its restrictions to
    those who have repeatedly failed to comply with alcohol laws in the past, concluding that
    they are more likely than others to do so in the future. Given that irresponsible alcohol
    consumption increases the likelihood of more grave offenses, the Commonwealth surely
    had good reason to think that the population of prior abusers posed a greater risk to the
    community than others who lack such a history.
    The use of such a prophylactic scheme is hardly uncommon. Many laws, state and
    federal, share the two-step structure adopted by Virginia, which imposes minor sanctions
    on those who present a heightened danger in order to lessen the risk that the danger will
    actually come to pass. For example, the Sex Offender Registration and Notification Act
    (SORNA) requires federal sex offenders to notify the states where they live and work of
    their prior conviction. See 34 U.S.C. § 20913 (2012). Once the prior conviction has
    established that a person poses a social risk, his mere failure to register can give rise to
    criminal liability. Id. In that way, SORNA uses criminal law to ensure that past sexual
    offenders cannot in the future fly under the radar.
    The majority casts SORNA aside by claiming that “post-conviction restrictions”
    are not implicated here. Maj. Op. at 33-34. The majority distinguishes post-conviction
    57
    restrictions, such as supervised release, noting that those remain acceptable. That
    distinction is, to say the least, awkward. The majority purports to hold that schemes such
    as Virginia’s constitute cruel and unusual punishments. Since when are cruel and unusual
    punishments on nonvolitional conduct suddenly permissible post-conviction? Post-
    conviction limits are based on the same calibration of restriction to risk as are the
    Virginia statutes here. The fact that Virginia has elected to fire a warning shot before
    imposing criminal sanctions is to its credit, not otherwise.
    Other analogies to Virginia’s prophylactic approach abound. Federal criminal law,
    for example, prohibits otherwise routine firearms purchases by individuals who have
    been found by a court in a civil proceeding to be mentally incompetent. Such restrictions
    reduce the risk those people pose to themselves and to others. See 18 U.S.C.
    §§ 922(g)(4); 924(a)(2). By the same token, a domestic abuser who violates a civil
    Temporary Restraining Order can be subject to criminal contempt proceedings. See, e.g.,
    Va. Code Ann. § 19.2-152.10, et seq. Once someone is found to pose a risk to his spouse
    or child, the simple act of coming within a certain distance of the protected persons or
    their home can give rise to criminal liability for “contempt of court.” Id.
    All of these laws have one thing in common: they apply milder sanctions to less
    serious infractions, such as the possession, use, or purchase of dangerous items and
    addictive substances or the failure to register, in order to reduce the risk of grave
    misconduct involving gun violence, sexual predation, or fatal accidents on the road.
    Virginia’s alcohol laws adopt precisely this approach and similarly present no
    constitutional infirmity.
    58
    The majority renders this approach unconstitutional when the criminal acts are
    “both compelled by [the defendant’s] illness and [are] otherwise lawful.” Maj. Op. at 28.
    The “otherwise lawful” limitation is both wholly lacking in authority and ignores the
    valid reasons why prohibitions apply to some population cohorts and not to others. The
    reason is simply this: past actions give rise to present and future risks. To say that a state
    acts impermissibly on this basis is an astonishing proposition, and one that prohibits
    legislative bodies from making the altogether practical assessments of risky behaviors
    that are entirely within the legislative prerogative.
    Legislatures, whether state or federal, commonly calibrate restrictions to risk in
    order to protect the public. The federal Bail Reform Act, for example, authorizes a judge
    to require pre-trial detention if he finds that “no condition or combination of conditions
    will reasonably assure . . . the safety of any other person and the community.” 18 U.S.C.
    § 3142(e)(1). The Supreme Court rejected a constitutional challenge to this statute,
    finding “there is no doubt that preventing danger to a community is a legitimate
    regulatory goal,” United States v. Salerno, 
    481 U.S. 739
    , 747 (1987), and that, to achieve
    this goal, Congress could focus “only on individuals who have been arrested for . . .
    extremely serious offenses.” Id. at 750. Contrary to the majority’s position that a selective
    statute is inherently problematic, e.g., Maj. Op. at 28, the Court instead saw this as a
    feature of the bail scheme, demonstrating a “narrow[] focus[] on a particularly acute
    problem . . . in which the Government interests are overwhelming.” Id. at 750. Virginia’s
    regulatory risk assessment here, like so many state laws that limit the use of automobiles,
    firearms, and alcohol, reflects the same approach.
    59
    The majority tries to frame its holding as “narrow,” Maj. Op. at 33, affecting only
    Virginia’s purportedly unique scheme. Id. at 33, n.20. To repeat, I cannot see how
    Virginia’s prophylactic structure differs from the many others that share its two-step
    approach. I am therefore left to conclude that the only distinctive feature of what Virginia
    has done lies in the nature of the offense. As my colleagues apparently see it, consuming
    alcohol, even by those with a documented history of alcohol abuse, is just not the sort of
    conduct that warrants criminal sanctions. Given the comprehensive body of research
    pointing to the harms of alcohol abuse, I cannot agree. More importantly though, I do not
    feel empowered to weigh in on such a question in the first place.
    There are many considerations that can and do inform legislative judgments
    regarding alcohol and addiction. There are many policy tools available to enforce these
    judgments once they have been made. Criminal law is but one of them, as are
    prophylactic laws that focus public resources on those most likely to cause harm. I would
    hope that settled law was enough to prevent the majority from second-guessing the
    Commonwealth’s judgment. But I find it particularly distressing that at a time when we
    are beginning to make some modest progress on often alcohol-related offenses such as
    domestic violence and sexual assault that the majority feels itself empowered to hinder
    that progress. In doing so, it thwarts the efforts of Virginia to assure that the future of its
    citizens, and particularly the future of women in the Commonwealth, is measurably more
    secure than it has been in times past.
    60
    III.
    It is well to take a brief, broader look. The majority decision aspires to rework our
    constitutional system. It erodes the states’ role as separate sovereigns entrusted to define
    the criminal law within their own borders. And it pushes the Eighth Amendment as a
    catch-all corrective for perceived ills that other constitutional provisions have left
    unredressed.
    A.
    The majority upends our system of dual sovereignty. It puts judges in
    policymaking roles reserved largely for legislatures and states. The reason for legislative
    responsibility over criminal law is fundamental: the criminal law exists to protect the
    safety of citizens, and ensuring the safety of the people is one of those things that popular
    government exists to do. State legislatures thus have considerable latitude to address
    social ills. What behavior to criminalize is not an exclusive state responsibility, but it is a
    core one: “Under our federal system, the ‘states possess primary authority for defining
    and enforcing the criminal law.’” United States v. Lopez, 
    514 U.S. 549
    , 561, n.3 (1995)
    (quoting Engle v. Isaac, 
    456 U.S. 107
    , 128 (1982)).
    That is no impediment to the majority, which rushes in where others fear to tread.
    The Supreme Court has repeatedly been asked to make broad psychological
    pronouncements regarding addiction and mental illness, and has consistently emphasized
    its own inability to do so. See Clark, 548 U.S. at 771; see also Powell, 392 U.S. at 537
    (plurality) (“It is simply not yet the time to write the Constitutional formulas cast in terms
    whose meaning, let alone relevance, is not yet clear either to doctors or to lawyers.”). As
    61
    the Supreme Court made clear decades ago, “[t]he lesson we have drawn is not that
    government may not act in the face of this uncertainty, but rather that courts should pay
    particular deference to reasonable legislative judgments.” Jones, 463 U.S. at 364, n.13.
    The Supreme Court should have saved its breath, so swiftly does the majority breeze by.
    In its lecture on psychology and sermon to the states, the majority does not even
    acknowledge the many features of state law that already address issues of volition and
    compulsion. The criminal justice system of every state has in place numerous features
    designed to address nonvolitional conduct, among them mens rea requirements (willfully,
    knowingly); affirmative defenses such as provocation, self-defense, and in extreme cases
    insanity; and of course, sentencing proceedings where any nonvolitional characteristic or
    circumstance can be appraised and applied by a sentencing judge. See, e.g., Egelhoff, 518
    U.S. at 56 (plurality opinion). Those approaches to nonvolitional conduct often rely upon
    democratic input, making them far more sensitive and balanced than the constitutional
    theory developed by the majority on the fly.
    Rather than focusing on what should matter, the majority thinks it is somehow
    relevant that Virginia’s approach is different from that of many other states. Maj. Op. at
    33, n.20 (“That the vast majority of states eschew interdiction schemes suggests another
    reason to doubt their constitutionality”). If sanctions are viewed by the majority as too
    stern, the appropriate course for mitigation is through reforms achieved through the states
    and in the legislative branch, not through the Eighth Amendment. It is inevitable that
    under federalism some states will develop policies that are more strict or lenient than
    others. Where the Virginia scheme falls on this spectrum is, as I have indicated, a matter
    62
    of debate. That variability, however, has always been thought to be a vibrant feature of
    our constitutional system: “Absent a constitutionally imposed uniformity inimical to
    traditional notions of federalism, some State will always bear the distinction of treating
    particular offenders more severely than any other state.” Rummel, 445 U.S. at 282. The
    rarity of a state’s chosen policy is not a sound basis for condemnation, just as “not every
    widespread experiment with a procedural rule favorable to criminal defendants
    establishes a fundamental principle of justice.” Egelhoff, 518 U.S. at 51 (plurality
    opinion).
    Under our system of governance, the states are the primary expositors of the
    common law. The risk of having our Constitution resemble more and more a common
    law document, where meaningful restraints on judicial preferences are minimal, is all too
    real. See Paul v. Davis, 
    424 U.S. 693
    , 701 (1976) (rejecting a reading that “would make
    of the Fourteenth Amendment a font of tort law to be superimposed upon whatever
    systems may already be administered by the States”). All the richness and diversity of our
    fifty state democracies is now swept aside for a single policy preference. The majority
    thinks that because it invokes the word “constitution” it is empowered through that
    incantation to displace other branches and other levels of government with its own
    transcendent views of how best to regulate a species of conduct with which it has no
    expertise and over which it has no authority. Such a malleable constitution; such
    adjudicative power: Caesar Augustus would be envious.
    63
    B.
    Apart from the damage to legislative judgments and federal-state relations, the
    majority also expands the Eighth Amendment to a place not heretofore envisioned.
    Since the Eighth Amendment does not generally limit which acts can be made
    criminal, challenges to the substance of criminal law are properly directed through those
    portions of the Constitution that speak to specific substantive rights, like the freedom of
    speech. See Texas v. Johnson, 
    491 U.S. 397
     (1989); Brandenburg v. Ohio, 
    395 U.S. 444
    (1969). The majority shatters this harmony. Its analysis seeks to protect a social group,
    homeless alcoholics, without reference to the Equal Protection Clause, enshrines alcohol
    consumption as a protected activity without reference to the Due Process Clause, and
    adopts a fulsome narrative of police harassment without reference to the Fourth
    Amendment. At bottom, it creates unprecedented protections for those with “a profound
    drive or craving to use alcohol” in the least likely of places, the Eighth Amendment, and
    in a manner that will erode the careful structure of the Constitution. Maj. Op. at 5.
    Usually when we speak of particular groups that share particular characteristics,
    we are assessing an equal protection challenge. The appellants here in fact brought such a
    challenge. My colleagues in the majority rightly recognize that this claim is barred by
    precedent. Maj. Op. at 8, n.5. Alcoholics are surely worthy of social care and solicitude,
    but they, like the homeless, are not a constitutionally protected class. See Mitchell v.
    Comm’r of the Soc. Sec. Admin., 
    182 F.3d 272
    , 274 (4th Cir. 1999) (“Alcoholics are
    neither a suspect nor a quasi-suspect class for purposes of equal protection analysis.”);
    Joel v. City of Orlando, 
    232 F.3d 1353
    , 1357 (11th Cir. 2000) (“Homeless persons are not
    64
    a suspect class.”). Nor is consuming alcohol a fundamental constitutional right. Cf. Saenz
    v. Roe, 
    526 U.S. 489
     (1999). The fact that many groups such as the homeless deserve
    civic charity, compassion, and respect does not mean they possess the immutable
    characteristics akin to race, gender, ethnicity, and the like that define a suspect class for
    equal protection purposes.
    This has not stopped the majority, however, from using the Eighth Amendment to
    carve out heightened protections manifestly unavailable under the Equal Protection
    Clause. See Maj. Op. at 36-37. At bottom, this bald circumvention of settled law amounts
    to nothing more than a new font of disparate impact liability. The majority overlooks the
    clear language of the Virginia law—which on its face applies to rich or poor, homeless or
    homeowner—and instead speculates and invalidates the interdiction statute for falling too
    harshly on homeless alcoholics. Maj. Op. at 32 (noting that “Virginia’s statutory scheme
    may nominally penalize ‘possession’ or ‘consumption,’ . . . [but] effectively targets and
    punishes Plaintiffs based on their illness”). This whole “targeting” concept is, to
    understate the matter, breathtaking. All laws have disparate impacts, falling more heavily
    on some groups than on others. Those impacts do not constitute unconstitutional
    targeting. The reality of uneven impact is inevitable in law, which, after all, is enacted to
    address specific social problems. Disparate impacts normally present no defect under the
    Equal Protection Clause. See Washington v. Davis, 
    426 U.S. 229
     (1976). But after
    today’s holding, many laws, both civil and criminal, will be vulnerable on an Eighth
    Amendment disparate impact theory.
    65
    This case is about a group, interdicted persons, that is not a protected class under
    the Equal Protection Clause. It is about an activity, consuming alcohol, that is not a
    fundamental right under the Due Process Clause. It is about police interactions, but no
    claim was brought under the Fourth Amendment. It seems that the Eighth Amendment is
    coming into fashion as a means for striking down both civil and criminal laws that
    display no constitutional defect but merely fail to comport with the majority’s sense of
    optimal public policy. I cannot see how a claim that fails on multiple other grounds, all of
    which are arguably more applicable to the case at hand, can prevail on this one. The
    result is that constitutional doctrine will become ever more sprawling, ever more
    confusing, and judges will seize upon that same confusion to further work their personal
    will.
    IV.
    I now turn to the majority’s vagueness theory. The majority has adopted an
    alternative rationale for striking down duly-enacted law, holding that the term “habitual
    drunkard” in the civil interdiction statute is unconstitutionally vague. It is difficult to
    know where to begin with such an unprecedented position. First, as a matter of this
    court’s settled procedures, the question should be unreviewable. Second, even if we could
    reach it, there is no basis whatsoever for invalidating Virginia’s law. The interdiction
    statute is a civil enactment, which exists solely to provide notice of what acts will trigger
    criminal sanctions. Vagueness doctrine simply has no place in this case, as the appellants
    themselves recognized before the panel. By nonetheless pushing forward, the majority
    66
    has launched a new theory of civil vagueness, a doctrine that will most assuredly become
    a favorite of litigants seeking to invalidate state laws.
    A.
    As an initial matter, the majority has no basis for reaching the vagueness
    challenge. The appellants, who were ably represented throughout this litigation, stated
    twice before the panel that they were not raising the issue. Accordingly, the panel did not
    consider it, and neither should the en banc court.
    We do not have here a simple failure to press a claim. The appellants instead
    expressly waived any appeal on their vagueness challenge. See Opening Br. at 12, n.8
    (“Count Five alleges that the Interdiction Statute as applied to Plaintiffs is
    unconstitutionally vague in violation of the Fourteenth Amendment. The district court
    dismissed this count, and Plaintiffs do not press this claim here.”); id. at 15, n.9 (“The
    district court additionally rejected Plaintiffs’ vagueness claim. As stated above, Plaintiffs
    do not press this claim here.”). Waiver and forfeiture are not the same, and the
    “intentional relinquishment or abandonment of a known right” has serious consequences.
    See United States v. Olano, 
    507 U.S. 725
    , 733 (1993) (“Waiver is different from
    forfeiture. Whereas forfeiture is the failure to make the timely assertion of a right, waiver
    is the ‘intentional relinquishment or abandonment of a known right.’” (quoting Johnson
    v. Zerbst, 
    304 U.S. 458
    , 464 (1938)). Accordingly, our circuit has, before today, been
    especially reluctant to consider waived arguments. See Porter v. Clarke, No. 18-6257, at
    24 (4th Cir. May 3, 2019) (citing United States v. Washington, 
    743 F.3d 938
    , 941, n.1
    67
    (4th Cir. 2014) (“Issues that [the appellant] failed to raise in his opening brief are
    waived.”)).
    Since the appellant’s vagueness claim was waived, and therefore uncontested, any
    consideration by the panel would have been an advisory opinion. See Wood v. Milyard,
    
    566 U.S. 463
    , 471, n.5 (2012). As such, the panel did not sua sponte resurrect it. The
    majority’s decision to nonetheless take up the vagueness claim en banc significantly
    degrades the place of panel process in federal appellate review. Of course en banc
    proceedings have their necessary place, but a panel of three remains our basic unit of
    decision, three being a more efficient and more collaborative number than a conclave of
    fifteen.
    The majority has provided no standard under which an en banc court can resolve a
    claim affirmatively waived before a panel, other than “whenever it suits us.” This open-
    endedness is said to be needed “to promote the ends of justice,” Maj. Op. at 9 (quoting
    Hormel v. Helvering, 
    312 U.S. 552
    , 557 (1941)). But the orderly progression of litigation
    provided by process and the ends of justice are not dichotomous, but complementary, as
    the neutrality of procedure protects litigants of all persuasions against arbitrary courts and
    ambush by adversaries. The Federal Rules of Appellate Procedure rightly and properly
    contemplate en banc proceedings for cases of “exceptional” importance. Fed. R. App. P.
    35. They do not contemplate them as the setting for “exceptional” procedural departures.
    It is not unfair to ask the majority to estimate the costs of allowing procedure to turn this
    flabby, but the majority has not so much as acknowledged the damage to panel
    deliberations it has wrought.
    68
    The majority contends that our recent decision in United States v. Simms, 
    914 F.3d 229
     (4th Cir. 2019), provides some license for its procedural departure. The differences
    between that case and the decision reached today ought to be obvious. In Simms, the
    government changed its views in response to intervening Supreme Court precedent and
    both parties argued the issue fully to the en banc court. In this case, the plaintiffs chose to
    abandon a weak claim on appeal and deliberately refrained from pressing that claim when
    seeking en banc review. When the issue did emerge during en banc argument, the state
    was afforded a limited opportunity through supplemental briefing to respond, without the
    benefit of any panel decision or adequate airing.
    By reviving the vagueness claim now, we are inviting litigants to take this court
    for a ride. We should not, for want of a better word, be such chumps. Future litigants will
    rely on this case endlessly to excuse inexcusable carelessness, or worse, calculated
    litigation strategy that in hindsight proved unsuccessful.
    B.
    The civil vagueness claim also fails on its merits. “The essential purpose of the
    ‘void for vagueness’ doctrine is to warn individuals of the criminal consequences of their
    conduct.” Jordan v. De George, 
    341 U.S. 223
    , 230 (1951). See Lanzetta v. New Jersey,
    
    306 U.S. 451
    , 453 (1939) (“All are entitled to be informed as to what the State commands
    or forbids.”). Fair notice both informs the public and constrains law enforcement.
    Vagueness doctrine protects a person’s right to be convicted only under laws that speak
    with some clarity.
    69
    It ought to be obvious that a statute whose sole purpose is to provide notice does
    not transgress this constitutional limit. Once again, Virginia’s interdiction law has two
    parts: one civil and one criminal. Under the scheme, a person can be convicted of a crime
    only after an interdiction hearing, which itself requires “due notice” and a determination
    by a neutral magistrate. See Va. Code Ann. § 4.1-333. The interdiction itself does not
    carry criminal consequences. There is no question that the subsequent prohibitions on
    consuming and possessing alcohol are not vague, and the majority has not argued that
    they are. Moreover, an interdicted person may never face criminal punishment at all,
    either because he refrains from drinking or has his interdiction cancelled. Id.
    At bottom then, Virginia’s statute works to address the very concerns that
    motivate vagueness doctrine in the first place. The two-step structure puts high-risk
    persons on notice of precisely what sort of acts will subject them to criminal sanctions
    and places the initial interdiction decision in the hands of a court, rather than law
    enforcement. The majority collapses these two steps into one for much of its analysis, but
    somehow still fails to appreciate that it is the statute’s prophylactic structure that provides
    notice before imposing criminal consequences. Put simply, this statute presents no
    problem that vagueness doctrine could possibly solve.
    The majority, however, is undeterred. According to my colleagues, the term
    “habitual drunkard,” which appears only in the civil interdiction statute, is
    unconstitutionally vague. This position suffers from two infirmities. First, the term is
    simply not vague under any conceivable standard, as other courts have found. See
    Ledezma-Cosino v. Sessions, 
    857 F.3d 1042
    , 1047 (9th Cir. 2017) (en banc) (“[T]he term
    70
    ‘habitual drunkard’ readily lends itself to an objective factual inquiry.”). “Many perfectly
    constitutional statutes use imprecise terms.” Sessions v. Dimaya, 
    138 S. Ct. 1204
    , 1214
    (2018). The Supreme Court has found that open-ended phrases, like “crime involving
    moral turpitude,” Jordan, 341 U.S. at 232, pose no difficulty, even under the most
    rigorous scrutiny. In its most recent vagueness decisions, Dimaya and Johnson, the Court
    noted that the imprecise statutory terms “serious potential risk” or “substantial risk” were
    not unconstitutional on their own. See Dimaya, 138 S. Ct. at 1213; Johnson v. United
    States, 
    135 S. Ct. 2551
    , 2557-58 (2015). The vagueness challenge in those cases only
    succeeded because of the specific problem that arose from assessing an earlier criminal
    offense, a problem that is obviously not implicated here.
    Each of the above phrases were far less precise than the Virginia statute. “Habitual
    drunkard,” by its own language, requires both a pattern of behavior and a certain form of
    conduct, both of which are familiar to the law. See Drunkard, Black’s Law Dictionary
    (10th ed. 2014) (“Someone who habitually consumes intoxicating substances
    excessively.”). The majority finds fault with Virginia’s statute on the grounds that
    Webster’s International Dictionary (3d ed. 2002) provides multiple definitions for the
    word “habit.” Maj. Op. at 15. If multiple dictionary definitions of a word are the new
    standard for toppling state statutes, few such civil enactments will be left standing. The
    majority prefers to treat “habit” as a noun in isolation, rather than a modifier for the noun
    that follows. But whatever form of the word is used, discerning its common meaning is
    really not all that hard. As the majority well knows, “habit” means doing something over
    71
    and over, in this case consuming alcohol to excess. Habits are something that all of us
    have as we go about our personal lives; none of us can fail to miss a habit’s meaning.
    By identifying specific and repeated conduct, the statute is nothing like those laws
    that have been found unconstitutionally vague in the past, such as those that proscribed
    passive acts like “loitering,” see Papachristou, 405 U.S. at 160, or targeted “improper
    persons,” see Booth v. Commonwealth, 
    88 S.E.2d 916
    , 918 (Va. 1955), without any
    conduct at all. To fall within the interdiction statute, moreover, a person must
    affirmatively “show[] himself to be” a habitual drunkard. See Va. Code Ann. § 4.1-333. It
    is simply not a statute that can sweep up the unwitting passerby.
    Were the text of the law not clear enough, the Virginia courts have provided even
    greater precision, holding that the term “habitual drunkard encompasses one who . . . is
    admittedly in the continual habit of being intoxicated from alcohol.” See Jackson v.
    Commonwealth, 
    604 S.E.2d 122
    , 125 (Va. Ct. App. 2004) (quoting Fisher v. Coleman,
    
    486 F. Supp. 311
    , 315 (W.D. Va. 1979)). While other courts have used slight variations
    on this definition, each of them has been driving at the same basic conduct: a repeated
    course of consuming alcohol to excess, excess being the impairment of judgment, the loss
    of motor function, the lessening of impulse control, and other commonly recognized
    effects. These interpretations, just like the statute’s plain text, clearly put citizens and
    officers on notice of the statute’s limited reach.
    In sum, the majority would outlaw “general definition[s]” and terms from many
    state enactments. See Maj. Op. at 17. It apparently believes that its semantic hair-splitting
    of the terms “habitual” and “drunkard” passes for some sort of textualism. It is the very
    72
    opposite of textualism. Properly understood, textualism seeks to apply the lawmaker’s
    words to a particular case, thereby respecting the lawmaker’s intent. The whole point of
    the majority’s faux textualism is not to respect the lawmaker’s intent but to undermine it,
    and in doing so to aggrandize the power of the judiciary vis-à-vis the legislative branch
    by picking critically and ceaselessly at enacted words. Only an approach as ad hoc and
    pliable as the majority’s could lead to the conclusion that “drunkard” is vague while
    “intoxicated” is not. Maj. Op. at 17-18. Yet that is where we are. An analogy to this sort
    of indiscriminate picking at verbiage took place with respect to jury instructions until the
    Supreme Court brought it up short. See Henderson v. Kibbe, 
    431 U.S. 145
     (1977). The
    approach to vagueness adopted by the majority transparently incentivizes the semantic
    destruction of many kinds of statutes of whose purpose a court does not approve.
    C.
    The majority’s extended discussion of civil vagueness shows no differentiation at
    all in the notice required or standards applied to civil and criminal enactments. See Maj.
    Op. at 15. The majority casually applies its pick to a civil law, showing an utter
    indifference to the consequences of its novel venture. The Supreme Court has spoken of
    vagueness in explicitly criminal terms for decades. See, e.g., Johnson, 135 S. Ct. at 2557
    (“[Vagueness] principles apply not only to statutes defining elements of a crime, but also
    to statutes fixing sentences.”); Kolender v. Lawson, 
    461 U.S. 352
    , 357 (1983). See also
    Papachristou, 405 U.S. at 162. The criminal nature of the doctrine is so prevalent that
    there was recently some debate about whether there could even be a proper standard for
    “civil vagueness.” Transcript of Oral Argument at 39-41, Dimaya, 
    138 S. Ct. 1204
    . One
    73
    need not have a view on that question to recognize that civil statutes are certainly not held
    to the same standard as criminal ones, a proposition richly supported in the U.S. Reports.
    See Vill. of Hoffman Estates v. Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc., 
    455 U.S. 489
    , 498-99
    (1982) (“The Court has also expressed greater tolerance of enactments with civil rather
    than criminal penalties because the consequences of imprecision are qualitatively less
    severe.”); Jordan, 341 U.S. at 231 (applying the criminal vagueness standard because of
    the “grave nature of deportation”); Winters v. New York, 
    333 U.S. 507
    , 515 (1948) (“The
    standards of certainty in statutes punishing for offenses is higher than in those depending
    primarily upon civil sanction for enforcement.”).
    The majority leaps casually from criminal to civil vagueness, not disputing that an
    interdiction order alone carries no criminal penalty whatsoever or seriously contending
    that an inability to drink alcohol is comparable to other serious consequences like
    deportation. Nonetheless, the majority charges forward and finds the purely civil part of
    the Virginia law warrants the most exacting scrutiny. See Maj. Op. at 12-13. The
    consequences of such a venture are boundless. Many civil statutes make use of imprecise
    phrases. Virginia, like all other states, attaches civil liability to broad concepts like “a
    public or common nuisance,” Va. Code Ann. § 48-1, or “reasonable care.” RGR, LLC v.
    Settle, 
    764 S.E.2d 8
    , 22 (Va. 2014). Federal civil laws are often just as open-ended. A
    person can be subjected to civil fines for “deceptive acts or practices” affecting
    consumers, Federal Trade Commission Act, 15 U.S.C. § 45, or may be liable in a public
    or private suit for “material misstatement[s] and omission[s]” involving securities.
    Halliburton Co. v. Erica P. John Fund, Inc., 
    573 U.S. 258
    , 267 (2014). A company’s
    74
    product can be banned by the Consumer Product Safety Commission if it “presents an
    unreasonable risk of injury” to consumers. 15 U.S.C. § 2057. If civil vagueness were to
    prevail, all these previously uncontroversial statutes and many more would suddenly be
    placed in doubt. See Transcript of Oral Argument at 35-36, Dimaya, 
    138 S. Ct. 1204
    (“We might do a wonderful job of pruning the United States Code if we said that every
    civil statute that is not written with the specificity that is required by criminal statute is
    unconstitutionally vague.” (Statement of Alito, J.)).
    The majority tries to evade the implications of its civil vagueness theory by
    pointing to “the integrated structure of the challenged scheme,” arguing that Virginia’s
    prophylactic approach justifies a “relatively strict test for vagueness.” Maj. Op. at 12-13.
    My colleagues cannot have it both ways. Either what matters here are the civil
    consequences of an interdiction order, in which case the strict standard is inapplicable, or
    what matters are the criminal consequences that can befall interdicted persons for
    subsequent acts, in which case prior notice and a determination by a neutral magistrate
    are an integral part of the scheme. The inconsistency of the majority’s view is the
    inevitable result of stretching vagueness doctrine to meet its preferences, without any
    regard to the vital purpose that doctrine serves in our constitutional law.
    As if this novel view of civil vagueness were not enough, the majority takes it one
    step further by tearing up state law, striking yet another blow to the state’s rightful place
    in our federal system. On the majority’s theory, states would be prevented from using a
    civil designation to ward off future criminal acts, lest the entire scheme be attacked as
    “quasi-criminal.” Maj. Op. at 13. There is no doubt that Virginia, as part of its efforts to
    75
    prevent alcohol-related violence, could impose increasingly severe sentences for each act
    of public intoxication or disorderly conduct. Instead, Virginia has opted for a less
    draconian approach, which uses a pattern of violations to put someone on notice, by civil
    means, of future acts that will lead to criminal punishment. Faced with the majority’s
    vagueness theory, however, it is easy to imagine the Commonwealth looking to other
    familiar means of deterring repeat offenders that would cause far more heartburn than its
    present scheme.
    The majority’s civil vagueness holding shares with its Eighth Amendment holding
    the same disregard for Supreme Court precedent, the same unwillingness to confront
    obvious implications, and the same failure to provide any workable limits. In the end, the
    only thing that ought to be void for vagueness here is the majority opinion, which gives
    the district court no guidance on remand. It tells everyone what is wrong, and no one
    what might be right. What it has created is a confusion which promotes judicial
    ascendency by inviting litigants to trek again to Delphi for yet another inscrutable judicial
    decree.
    V.
    It is hard to imagine a decision so infused with ruinous consequences or so
    insensitive to a judge’s inability to rework society from the bench. First, the desire to
    remove unspecified acts from the purview of criminal law flies in the face of the distinct
    and emphatic language of the Robinson opinion, which indicates that individual actions,
    as opposed to personal status, remain fair subjects for the legislative contemplation of
    76
    criminal sanctions. Not only are the words of the Supreme Court disregarded, but so too
    is the settled legal landscape that for more than half a century has reinforced their
    relevance. The clear and principled status-act distinction is now replaced with a nebulous
    “nonvolitional conduct” defense, a phrase that will surely metastasize and absolve
    individuals from personal responsibility for all forms and manners of criminal acts.
    This decision is an affront to our legal traditions. It leaves states less able to enact
    prophylactic civil laws and sanctions in order to forestall more serious crimes. It usurps
    the American Constitution in order to cement the states as subordinate entities in our
    federal structure, a result profoundly at odds with the vibrant federalism that was
    intended to define not only our young but our maturing Republic. What’s more, the
    majority adopts the Eighth Amendment as its amendment du jour, pushing it into a
    supervisory role over substantive criminal law and into territory heretofore inhabited by
    other constitutional provisions.
    Finally, the majority has, without even bothering to follow this court’s basic
    procedures, adopted a novel theory of civil vagueness, one that calls into question
    countless expressions in numerous civil laws. The effects of this position will long be
    felt, as all manner of words and phrases will be impugned for their alleged imprecision.
    It is not often that a decision operates to visit structural and institutional damage in
    so many respects. Any one of these flaws would be serious. Altogether, they are more
    than severe. I only wish that my colleagues, in their rush to condemn Virginia for a policy
    they don’t prefer, stopped to consider that perhaps this law has endured for the benefit of
    the many victims of alcohol-fueled violence; victims who cannot easily make their voices
    77
    heard, and who are all too often neglected in decisions like the one reached here. One
    may always hope, however. All pretensions to restraint have been abandoned. But may
    the first rays of sunrise light the return of the many clear principles that have so eluded
    the majority along the way.
    78
    WILKINSON, Circuit Judge, dissenting specially:
    I thank Judge Keenan for her concurring opinion. With all respect, the doctrinal
    march of the majority opinion is indeed “an assault upon the constitutional, democratic,
    and common law foundations of American civil and criminal law.” See Conc. Op. at 38.
    A decision impairing the ability of states to regulate purportedly nonvolitional conduct
    and alcohol under the authority of the Twenty-first Amendment absolutely carries somber
    implications for the abuse of women both on campus and in the home. See Diss. Op. at
    52-55. An en banc case with two novel and troubling constitutional holdings is hardly the
    unremarkable matter the concurrence seeks to portray.
    I shall not repeat the arguments in the principal dissenting opinion other than to
    say that the very purpose of a dissenting opinion is to illuminate difference, not to
    evidence disrespect. To my mind, mutual respect and collegiality are enhanced, not
    compromised, by a vigorous exchange of views over basic and fundamental principles of
    law. A robust exchange reveals judges who care, not out of self-interest, but about the
    lives of the litigants before them and, in a larger sense, about the capacity of law to bring
    great benefit to society or to inflict significant harm. That we discharge our oath of office
    with conviction and at times with passion is something I believe the public and the
    profession will respect. What I hope makes the judicial process unique is that the clash of
    views plays out under a transcendent canopy of mutual regard and affection. And so it is
    here.
    My concurring colleagues suggest I have attributed to them “malfeasance.” Conc.
    Op. at 38. Of course I have done no such thing. Being wrong, even woefully wrong, is in
    79
    no way malfeasance. I am reminded of the words of Justice Douglas that “[s]peech is
    often provocative and challenging” and that “a function of free speech under our system
    of government is to invite dispute.” Terminiello v. Chicago, 
    337 U.S. 1
    , 4 (1949). In
    positing that speech “may indeed best serve its high purpose when it . . . stirs people to
    anger,” id., Justice Douglas missed a point rightly grasped by my concurring
    colleagues—namely that civil discourse is often the best antidote to a coarsening culture.
    But one need not subscribe wholly to the Justice’s full-throated cry in order to recognize
    that civility, for all its value, may also be used as a censoring mechanism to drain and
    dilute dissenting voices. Flaws are not always best laid bare by pallid speech. Animation
    defines the First Amendment I was taught to revere.
    I thank the members of the majority not only for the sincere expression of their
    views but for affording me the opportunity to say that our Circuit is truly fortunate to
    have the services of such capable and dedicated jurists—and that I have been blessed
    beyond measure to have them as colleagues and friends.
    That having been said, we have in this case a deep and honest difference of
    opinion the importance of which can neither be brushed off nor wished away. It is after
    all a dissent to which my colleagues take exception. The very nature of the effort is one
    of contrast. And so it is here.
    80
    DIAZ, Circuit Judge, dissenting:
    I agree with the substance of Judge Wilkinson’s dissent regarding the merits of
    this case.    I write separately, however, because I think it well within this court’s
    discretion to consider Plaintiffs’ vagueness challenge, even as I would reject the
    challenge on its merits.     With respect to Plaintiffs’ Eighth Amendment claim, the
    majority ventures too far in extending the holding announced in Robinson v. California,
    
    370 U.S. 660
     (1962), so as to apply to criminal conduct compelled by addiction.
    Respectfully, that decision is not for us to make.
    A.
    When a party expressly waives an argument before a panel of this court, we
    usually decline, as a matter of discretion, to consider the argument on rehearing en banc.
    But as the majority explains, we may consider an abandoned argument in the rare case
    where the record enables us to do so, where doing so would not prejudice either party,
    and where the argument implicates an issue of great importance.
    This is such a case, for the reasons described by the majority. The basis for
    Plaintiffs’ vagueness challenge was adequately developed in the district court. We do not
    prejudice the Commonwealth by considering the challenge now, because it had a full
    opportunity to address the issue at en banc oral argument and through supplemental
    briefing. And although I cannot join in the majority’s analysis of the vagueness issue, I
    agree that we should consider it to ensure that we correctly decide a matter of public
    importance.    Enforcement of Virginia’s interdiction statute impacts the basic liberty
    interests of the Plaintiffs and many similarly situated persons throughout the
    81
    Commonwealth. Whether it does so within constitutional bounds is a question that
    touches on Eighth Amendment and vagueness concerns, which are closely related and
    have been applied in tandem in cases addressing similar types of statutes. See, e.g., Joel
    v. City of Orlando, 
    232 F.3d 1353
    , 1359–62 (11th Cir. 2000); Farber v. Rochford, 407 F.
    Supp. 529, 533–34 (1975); City of Chicago v. Youkhana, 
    660 N.E.2d 34
    , 39–42 (Ill. App.
    Ct. 1995), aff’d sub nom. City of Chicago v. Morales, 
    687 N.E.2d 53
     (Ill. 1997), aff’d 
    527 U.S. 41
     (1999).
    Nonetheless, I part company with my colleagues in the majority on whether
    Virginia’s interdiction statute is void for vagueness. As Judge Wilkinson notes, the law
    is rife with open-ended terms, from “reasonable doubt” to “moral turpitude.” These
    terms generally don’t present constitutional vagueness issues, except where they invite
    arbitrary or discriminatory enforcement or fail to fairly notify those who are subject to a
    law of what conduct will constitute a violation. The term “habitual drunkard” used in the
    interdiction statute does neither.
    The distinction between occasional and “habitual” drunkards is a question of
    degree, and it’s true that the line may sometimes blur. It is also true that Virginia’s courts
    haven’t provided much guidance beyond that contained in the statutory text. See Jackson
    v. Commonwealth, 
    604 S.E.2d 122
    , 125 (Va. Ct. App. 2004) (defining a habitual
    drunkard as one who “is admittedly in the continual habit of being intoxicated from
    alcohol” (quoting Fisher v. Coleman, 
    486 F. Supp. 311
    , 315 (W.D. Va. 1979))). But
    there can be little doubt as to the basic conduct that would qualify one as a habitual
    drunkard: repeatedly consuming alcohol to excess.           This is enough to satisfy the
    82
    constitutional vagueness standard. Accord Ledezma-Cosino v. Sessions, 
    857 F.3d 1042
    ,
    1047 (9th Cir. 2017) (en banc).
    B.
    Nor does Virginia’s interdiction statute run afoul of the Eighth Amendment’s bar
    against cruel and unusual punishment. The core dispute in this case is whether Robinson
    prohibits only the criminalization of status, or also of conduct compelled by status. I am
    satisfied that Robinson is better understood as distinguishing status from conduct, which
    is the interpretation that most courts have adopted in the decades since Robinson was
    decided.
    And despite the majority’s suggestion to the contrary, Powell v. Texas, 
    392 U.S. 514
     (1968), did not alter Robinson’s distinction between status and conduct. Rather,
    Judge Wilkinson is I think correct in concluding that “the judgment in Powell neither
    extended or contracted Robinson, which was left undisturbed.”
    Plaintiffs’ Eighth Amendment claim therefore turns on whether Robinson can and
    should be extended to prohibit statutes that criminalize conduct compelled by addiction.
    In my view, this question is one to be answered in the first instance by the Supreme
    Court.
    Because the majority holds otherwise, I respectfully dissent.
    83