In re K.T.B. , 2020 UT 51 ( 2020 )


Menu:
  •                 This opinion is subject to revision before final
    publication in the Pacific Reporter
    
    2020 UT 51
    IN THE
    SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF UTAH
    IN THE MATTER OF THE ADOPTION OF K.T.B
    A PERSON UNDER EIGHTEEN YEARS OF AGE
    V.B.,
    Appellant,
    v.
    A.S.A. and J.K.A.,
    Appellees.
    No. 20150821
    Heard May 12, 2017
    Remand Disposition Received March 8, 2018
    Filed July 21, 2020
    On Direct Appeal
    First District, Logan
    The Honorable Kevin K. Allen
    No. 152100025
    Attorneys:
    Diane Pitcher, Ryan L. Holdaway, Logan, for appellant
    Paul H. Gosnell, Logan, for Appellees
    CHIEF JUSTICE DURRANT authored the opinion of the Court, in
    which JUSTICE HIMONAS and JUSTICE PEARCE joined.
    JUSTICE PETERSEN filed a separate opinion concurring in the result.
    ASSOCIATE CHIEF JUSTICE LEE filed a dissenting opinion.
    CHIEF JUSTICE DURRANT, opinion of the Court:
    Introduction
    ¶1 This is an adoption case. In 2010, V.B. (Mother) gave birth
    to K.T.B. Sometime later, K.T.B. went to live with A.S.A. and J.K.A.
    (collectively, the Adoptive Parents) and has lived with them ever
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    since. In early June 2015, the Adoptive Parents filed an adoption
    petition in the district court and served notice of the proceeding on
    Mother. The notice informed Mother that she had thirty days to file
    a motion to intervene in the case or she would forfeit her parental
    rights in K.T.B. and would be barred from participating further in
    the adoption proceeding.
    ¶2 Mother attempted to intervene, but due to a procedural
    deficiency in the document she filed with the district court, the
    court struck her filing and excluded her from the adoption
    proceeding. Mother then filed a rule 60(b) motion seeking relief
    from the court’s order to strike. Around this time, J.N.—Mother’s
    common-law husband—filed his own motion to intervene,
    asserting, based on his judicially recognized common-law marriage
    to Mother, that he is K.T.B.’s presumptive father. The district court
    denied both motions.
    ¶3 On appeal, Mother challenges the constitutionality of
    Utah’s Adoption Act.1 Specifically, she argues that the Adoption
    Act’s structure, which permits a district court to terminate parental
    rights if the parent does not “fully and strictly comply” with the
    statutory requirements, is unconstitutional as applied to her.2 We
    __________________________________________________________
    1 UTAH CODE §§ 78B-6-101 et seq. Mother specifically challenges
    the constitutionality of Utah Code section 78B-6-112. She argues,
    however, that section 112 “does not operate alone” in the present
    case because the district court relied on provisions in sections 110
    and 120.1 to terminate her parental rights under section 112.
    2  Although at one point in Mother’s brief she states that the
    Adoption Act is unconstitutional “on its face” and “as applied,” we
    note that her claim is more properly viewed as an as-applied
    challenge. “A statute may be unconstitutional either on its face or
    as applied to the facts of a given case. A facial challenge is the most
    difficult because it requires the challenger to ‘establish that no set
    of circumstances exists under which the [statute] would be valid.’
    An as-applied challenge, on the other hand, succeeds if the
    challenger shows that the statute was applied to him or her in an
    unconstitutional manner.” State v. Herrera, 
    1999 UT 64
    , ¶ 4 n.2, 
    993 P.2d 854
    , 857 (quoting United States v. Salerno, 
    481 U.S. 739
    , 745
    (1987)).
    Mother has brought an as-applied challenge. Throughout her
    briefing, and at oral argument, she repeatedly relies on her status
    (Continued)
    2
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                           Opinion of the Court
    agree with Mother on substantive due process grounds, so we
    reverse the district court’s order striking Mother’s filing.
    ¶4 Additionally, J.N. argues that the district court erred in
    denying his motion to intervene because the Adoption Act entitles
    him to certain rights as K.T.B.’s presumptive father. But because
    J.N. had not obtained judicial recognition of his common-law
    marriage at the time the Adoptive Parents filed their adoption
    petition, the Adoptive Parents had no obligation to serve him with
    notice. Instead, he was presumed to be on notice that an adoption
    could occur and was obligated to file a motion to intervene within
    thirty days of the Adoptive Parents’ petition. Because he failed to
    do so, his motion to intervene was untimely and the district court
    did not err in denying it.
    Background
    ¶5 Mother gave birth to K.T.B. in September 2010. His
    biological father is unknown. In 2013, K.T.B. went to live with the
    Adoptive Parents. The Adoptive Parents became his legal
    guardians in June 2014 and one year later they petitioned the
    district court to terminate Mother’s parental rights and allow them
    to adopt K.T.B. Shortly thereafter, the Adoptive Parents served
    __________________________________________________________
    as a mother with fundamental parental rights as the basis for her
    claim. In so doing, she repeatedly attempts to distinguish cases
    where we have upheld strict requirements in the Adoption Act
    against putative fathers or other individuals lacking fundamental
    rights from this case. Because these other cases illustrate that there
    are sets of circumstances where the challenged provisions in this
    case may be constitutionally applied, they are not facially
    unconstitutional. Additionally, Mother’s argument hinges on facts
    specific to this case—she argues that her rights were violated
    “despite the fact [that] she appeared in the action, the court added
    her as the Respondent, and she filed an Answer asserting her
    parental rights.” Because her due process claim hinges on facts
    specific to this case, and she does not argue that any provision of
    the Adoption Act would be unconstitutional under every set of
    circumstances, her due process claim is properly viewed as an
    as-applied challenge.
    3
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    Mother with a notice of the adoption proceedings in accordance
    with Utah Code section 78B-6-110.3
    ¶6 The notice informed Mother that she had thirty days to
    intervene or contest the adoption. It explained that her response
    must be in the form of “a motion to intervene[,] which shall set forth
    the specific relief sought[] and shall be accompanied by a
    memorandum specifying the factual and legal grounds upon which
    the motion is based.” It further stated that her failure to respond
    would “result in [her] waiver of any right to further notice of the
    proceeding,” would cause her to “forfeit any rights in relation to
    [K.T.B.],” and would “bar[] [her] from thereafter bringing or
    maintaining any action to assert any interest in [K.T.B.].”
    ¶7 Within thirty days of receiving the notice of the adoption
    proceeding, Mother filed an “Answer to Verified Petition for
    Termination of Parental Rights and for Adoption of Minor Child.”
    Her answer reads like a typical answer in a civil case—it addresses
    each allegation in the adoption petition separately, denying almost
    all of them. This included a denial of all of the Adoptive Parents’
    allegations regarding her parental unfitness and lack of an
    emotional connection to K.T.B. Importantly, Mother did not
    include an accompanying memorandum “specifying the factual
    and legal grounds upon which the motion [was] based,” and at no
    place in the answer did she make legal or factual assertions beyond
    conclusory admissions or denials of the allegations contained in the
    adoption petition.
    ¶8 Additionally, in the answer’s prayer for relief, Mother
    requested “[t]hat petitioners take nothing by way of their Petition,”
    her reasonable attorney fees, and any other relief the court deemed
    just and appropriate to award.
    ¶9 After thirty days, the Adoptive Parents asked the district
    court to strike Mother’s answer because she did not comply with
    the requirements of section 110 of the Adoption Act. Citing section
    110’s strict compliance requirement, the district court granted the
    Adoptive Parents’ request by striking Mother’s answer. The court
    explained that the “Answer was not accompanied by a
    memorandum supporting intervention.” And it “also did not ‘set
    forth specific relief sought’” because the only relief sought was that
    __________________________________________________________
    3 Utah Code section 78B-6-110(2) provides that “[n]otice of an
    adoption proceeding shall be served on” certain persons, including
    the mother of the adoptee.
    4
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Opinion of the Court
    “Petitioners take nothing by way of their Petition.” According to
    the court, this did not qualify as a request to intervene in the
    adoption, nor did it meet the statutory requirement that the relief
    be “specific.”
    ¶10 Once the court struck the answer, it concluded that Mother
    had failed to intervene within the time allotted by section 110. Due
    to this failure, the court ruled that Mother had “waived any right
    to further notice in connection with the adoption,” had “forfeited
    all rights in relation to the adoptee,” and was “barred [t]hereafter
    from bringing or maintaining any action to assert any interest in
    the adoptee.” It also found that because she failed to intervene, her
    consent to the adoption could be implied under section 120.1.4
    ¶11 One month after Mother’s exclusion from the adoption
    proceeding, the court entered findings of fact and conclusions of
    law, determining that Mother had forfeited her right to consent
    under sections 110 and 1125 and, alternatively, that she had implied
    her consent under section 120.1 by failing to file a timely motion to
    intervene. Because the court barred her from participating in the
    adoption proceeding, she could not present evidence to rebut any
    of the Adoptive Parents’ claims.
    ¶12 Mother challenged the district court’s order by filing a
    motion for relief from the order under rule 60(b) of the Utah Rules
    of Civil Procedure, but the court denied this motion. The court
    again relied upon Mother’s failure to comply with section 110 as its
    basis for excluding her from the adoption proceeding.
    ¶13 Around the same time that Mother filed her rule 60(b)
    motion, J.N.—Mother’s common-law husband—filed a motion to
    intervene in the adoption. In the motion, J.N. argued that the recent
    judicial recognition of his common-law marriage to Mother
    established his role as K.T.B.’s presumptive father. The court
    __________________________________________________________
    4  Utah Code section 78B-6-120.1(3) provides that “[c]onsent or
    relinquishment . . . may be implied by . . . receiving notification of
    a pending adoption proceeding under Subsection 78B-6-110(6) or
    of a termination proceeding under Section 78B-6-112 and failing to
    respond as required.”
    5  Utah Code section 78B-6-112(5) provides that “[t]he district
    court may terminate an individual’s parental rights in a child if . . .
    the individual . . . received notice [under section 110] and . . . failed
    to file a motion for relief . . . within 30 days after the day on which
    the person receives service.”
    5
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    denied this motion as well. Both Mother and J.N. timely filed
    notices of appeal.
    ¶14 On appeal, Mother argues that the district court’s
    application of Utah Code sections 78B-6-110, -112, and -120.1
    violated her due process rights, both procedural and substantive,
    by depriving her of her fundamental right to parent K.T.B.6 And
    J.N. argues that the court abused its discretion when it denied his
    motion to intervene because the Adoption Act entitles him to notice
    of, and to intervene in, the adoption as K.T.B.’s presumptive father.
    After oral argument we temporarily remanded this case to the
    district court for a determination of the enforceability of a post-
    adoption settlement agreement entered into by the parties. The
    district court determined that the agreement was based on an
    illusory promise and was therefore unenforceable. On return from
    remand we must now resolve the case on the merits. We have
    jurisdiction pursuant to Utah Code section 78A-4-103(2)(h).
    Standards of Review
    ¶15 Mother argues that the district court violated her right to
    due process because it applied certain provisions in Utah Code
    sections 78B-6-110, -112, and -120.1 to terminate her parental rights
    over her objection and without a finding of unfitness.
    “Constitutional issues, including questions regarding due process,
    are questions of law, and we review the lower court’s conclusions
    for correctness.”7
    ¶16 Additionally, J.N. argues that the court should have
    allowed him to intervene in the adoption proceedings after his
    common-law marriage to Mother was legally recognized. “A
    determination under rule 24(a)(1)” of the Utah Rules of Civil
    Procedure, “which permits intervention ‘when a statute confers an
    unconditional right to intervene,’ implicates two questions.”8 The
    __________________________________________________________
    6 Mother bases her claim on the guarantees of the Due Process
    Clauses of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments to the United
    States Constitution and of article I, section 7 of the Utah
    Constitution. All three provisions provide that no person shall be
    deprived “of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law.”
    7 Summerhaze Co., L.C. v. Fed. Deposit Ins. Corp., 
    2014 UT 28
    , ¶ 8,
    
    332 P.3d 908
    (citation omitted) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    8 Swallow v. Jessop (In re United Effort Plan Trust), 
    2013 UT 5
    , ¶ 21,
    
    296 P.3d 742
    (citations omitted).
    6
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                               Opinion of the Court
    first is “whether a particular statute affords a particular class of
    persons an unconditional intervention right.”9 This presents “a
    pure question of law because it involves abstract statutory
    construction. A district court would not be entitled to any deference
    to the extent it misinterpreted an intervention statute in the
    abstract.”10 And the second question is “whether a particular
    individual actually fits within the class of persons entitled to
    intervene under a statute.”11 This “presents a classic mixed
    question because it ‘involv[es] application of a legal standard to a
    set of facts unique to a particular case.’”12
    Analysis
    ¶17 Mother argues that the “statutory scheme” of Utah’s
    Adoption Act13 is “constitutionally infirm” because it authorized
    the district court to violate her constitutional rights.14 Specifically,
    she argues that three sections of the Adoption Act—sections 110,
    112, and 120.1 “operated together [to authorize the district court] to
    terminate a mother’s rights, over her objections, and without a
    finding of unfitness or best interest of the minor child.” No one
    __________________________________________________________
    9
    Id. 10 Id.
       11
    Id. 12 Id.
    (alteration in original) (citation omitted).
    13   UTAH CODE §§ 78B-6-101 et seq.
    14 Mother also argues that the district court erred in striking her
    answer, barring her from the adoption proceedings, and entering
    her implied consent to the adoption under Utah Code section
    78B-6-120.1. “Motions to strike pleadings or parts thereof are
    addressed to the judgment and discretion of the trial court. A ruling
    thereon, except under circumstances which amount to a clear abuse
    of discretion, will not be disturbed on appeal.” Francis v. State, 
    2013 UT 65
    , ¶ 19, 
    321 P.3d 1089
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    Because our determination regarding her due process claim makes
    it unnecessary to decide this claim, we decline to address it.
    Additionally, the Adoptive Parents argue that Mother failed to
    preserve her constitutional challenge to the Adoption Act’s scheme.
    But the record reveals that Mother challenged the district court’s
    decision on due process grounds on two separate occasions: first in
    her opposition to the motion to strike and again in her rule 60(b)
    motion. And so we find that she preserved this issue for appeal.
    7
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    disputes that provisions within the Adoption Act authorized the
    district court to terminate Mother’s parental rights. To determine
    whether this termination amounts to either a procedural or
    substantive due process violation, we first consider the Adoption
    Act’s statutory framework. We then analyze whether the district
    court violated Mother’s procedural or substantive due process
    rights when it terminated her parental rights pursuant to
    provisions within the Adoption Act. We ultimately conclude that
    the strict compliance requirement in section 110 of the Adoption
    Act is unconstitutional as applied to Mother.
    ¶18 Additionally, J.N. argues that the district court erred when
    it denied his motion to intervene because he was entitled to do so
    as K.T.B.’s presumptive father.15 Although he filed his motion
    almost four months after the Adoptive Parents filed their adoption
    petition, J.N. argues that it was nevertheless timely because he
    never received the notice to which he was entitled as K.T.B.’s
    presumptive father. But because J.N.’s marriage had not been
    legally recognized at the time the Adoptive Parents filed their
    petition, they were not obligated to serve J.N. with notice. Instead,
    J.N. was presumed to be on notice and had an obligation to file a
    motion to intervene within thirty days of the date the Adoptive
    Parents filed their petition.
    I. Framework of the Adoption Act
    ¶19 Under the Adoption Act, when individuals file a petition
    for adoption, they must serve notice of the adoption proceeding
    upon a number of specified people, including the adoptee’s
    biological mother.16 “A person who has been served with notice of
    an adoption proceeding and who wishes to contest the adoption
    [must] file a motion to intervene in the adoption proceeding . . .
    within 30 days after the day on which the person was served with
    __________________________________________________________
    15  We note that J.N., unlike Mother, has not raised any
    constitutional challenges to the Adoption Act.
    16   UTAH CODE § 78B-6-110(2) (2017) (“Notice of an adoption
    proceeding shall be served on . . . any person or agency whose
    consent or relinquishment is required under Section 78B-6-120 or
    78B-6-121, unless that right has been terminated by: (i) waiver;
    (ii) relinquishment; (iii) actual consent, as described in Subsection
    (12); or (iv) judicial action.”);
    id. § 78B-6-120(c)
    (identifying “mother
    of the adoptee” as a person from whom consent or relinquishment
    is required before an adoption may take place).
    8
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                              Opinion of the Court
    notice.”17 This motion must “set[] forth specific relief sought” and
    be “accompanied by a memorandum specifying the factual and
    legal grounds upon which the motion is based.”18
    ¶20 If the biological mother fails to “fully and strictly comply
    with all of the requirements,” she “(i) waives any right to further
    notice in connection with the adoption; (ii) forfeits all rights in
    relation to the adoptee; and (iii) is barred from thereafter bringing
    or maintaining any action to assert any interest in the adoptee.”19
    Under section 112, a district court may then terminate the mother’s
    parental rights in her child.20 And under section 120.1, the mother
    is deemed to have consented to the adoption or otherwise
    relinquished her rights in her child.21
    ¶21 Together, these three sections of the Adoption Act
    permitted the district court to terminate Mother’s parental rights
    over her objection and without a determination that she was an
    unfit parent. For this reason she argues that the Adoption Act is
    unconstitutional as applied to her.
    II. Mother’s Procedural Due Process Rights Were Not Violated
    ¶22 First, Mother argues that the Adoption Act authorized the
    district court to violate her procedural due process rights.22 “At its
    core, the due process guarantee is twofold—reasonable notice and
    an opportunity to be heard.”23 Because Mother fails to show that
    the Adoption Act authorized the district court to violate either of
    these guarantees, her procedural due process claim fails.
    ¶23 Mother’s right to reasonable notice was not infringed
    upon. “Before a right of property or other important interest is
    __________________________________________________________
    17
    Id. § 78B-6-
    110(6)(a).
    
       18
    Id. 19 Id.
    § 78B-6-110(6)(b).
    20
    Id. § 78B-6-
    112(5)(c).
    
       21
    Id. § 78B-6-
    120.1(3)(d).
    
       22Although Mother categorizes her challenge of the Adoption
    Act as both a procedural and substantive due process challenge,
    she does not direct much, if any, of her argument toward the
    procedural due process standard.
    23In re Adoption of B.Y., 
    2015 UT 67
    , ¶ 16, 
    356 P.3d 1215
    (citing
    United States v. James Daniel Good Real Prop., 
    510 U.S. 43
    , 48 (1993)).
    9
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    foreclosed as a result of state action, reasonable notice must be
    afforded.”24 On appeal, Mother admits that she received notice of
    the adoption proceeding and of her obligation to participate in it.
    Accordingly, her right to reasonable notice has not been violated.
    ¶24 What is less clear, however, is whether Mother received an
    adequate opportunity to be heard. As we have previously
    explained, “[m]ere notice is an empty gesture if it is not
    accompanied by a meaningful chance to make your case.”25 For this
    reason, “the Due Process Clause also guarantees . . . an opportunity
    to be heard at a meaningful time and in a meaningful manner.”26 In
    this case, the district court relied upon the strict compliance
    requirement in section 110 of the Adoption Act to deprive Mother
    of an opportunity to contest the termination of her parental rights
    to K.T.B., as well as K.T.B.’s subsequent adoption.
    ¶25 But the promise of an opportunity to be heard may be
    limited by reasonable procedural prerequisites. 27 Thus if a statute
    of limitations, or some other procedural requirement, bars an
    individual from participating in a legal proceeding affecting his or
    her rights, a procedural due process violation has not occurred
    unless the “procedural bar can be shown to foreclose[] . . .
    meaningful access to the justice system.”28 “In past cases, we have
    found this standard to be met by a showing of impossibility.”29
    ¶26 The impossibility inquiry contemplates whether “the right
    to notice and an opportunity to be heard were ‘completely within
    [the affected person’s] control.’”30 In other words, if the plaintiff
    __________________________________________________________
    24
    Id. ¶ 18
    (citing Mathews v. Eldridge, 
    424 U.S. 319
    , 348 (1976)).
    25
    Id. ¶ 2
    3.
    
       26
    Id. (internal quotation
    marks omitted) (quoting Gray v.
    Netherland, 
    518 U.S. 152
    , 182 (1996)).
    27  See Logan v. Zimmerman Brush Co., 
    455 U.S. 422
    , 437 (1982)
    (“The State may erect reasonable procedural requirements . . . [such
    as] statutes of limitations . . . . And the State certainly accords due
    process when it terminates a claim for failure to comply with a
    reasonable procedural . . . rule.”).
    28  In re Adoption of B.Y., 
    2015 UT 67
    , ¶ 27 (alteration in original)
    (citation omitted) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    29
    Id. ¶ 2
    8.
    
       30
    Id. ¶ 32
    (citation omitted).
    10
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                              Opinion of the Court
    could have complied with the procedural requirement under the
    circumstances, compliance is possible, and the plaintiff’s access to
    the justice system has not been foreclosed. Thus where the statute
    “afford[s] a reasonable opportunity to comply with the statute,” the
    statute’s procedural requirements do not offend procedural due
    process.31
    ¶27 Two of our previous cases illustrate a proper impossibility
    determination. First, in Ellis v. Social Services Department of the
    Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-Day Saints,32 we upheld a putative
    father’s procedural due process claim challenging the requirements
    of the Adoption Act because his compliance with the law was
    shown to have been rendered “impossible” through no fault of his
    own.33 In that case, the adoptee’s biological father and mother were
    engaged to be married and both resided in California, but two
    weeks before the wedding the mother broke off the engagement.34
    Then, just a few days before giving birth, the mother traveled to
    Utah from California without the father’s knowledge, where she
    placed the newborn for adoption (after representing to those
    involved that the father was unknown).35 After considering these
    facts we noted that due process requires a “reasonable opportunity
    to comply” with the statutory prerequisites to the establishment of
    a parental right.36 And because the father could not have complied
    with the Adoption Act’s procedural requirements under the facts
    alleged, we concluded that the requirements had violated the
    father’s due process rights.37
    ¶28 In contrast to our decision in Ellis is our decision in In re
    Adoption of J.S.38 In that case, the district court barred a putative
    father from intervening in an adoption because he failed to file a
    required paternity affidavit within the time the Adoption Act
    __________________________________________________________
    31
    Id. ¶ 31
    (citation omitted).
    32   
    615 P.2d 1250
    (Utah 1980).
    33
    Id. at 1256.
       34
    Id. at 1252.
       35   Id.
    36
    Id. at 1256.
       37
    Id. 38 2014
    UT 51, 
    358 P.3d 1009
    .
    11
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    allotted.39 The father appealed the denial of his motion to intervene.
    As part of his procedural due process argument on appeal, the
    father blamed the deficiency in this filing on “his attorney’s failure
    to advise him that such an affidavit was required.”40 Because the
    father did not specify whether he was bringing a procedural or
    substantive due process challenge to the Adoption Act’s filing
    requirements, we were forced to speculate on the nature of his
    claim.41 We determined that his claim could not be characterized as
    a procedural due process challenge, because he claimed his
    procedural deficiency was due to “his counsel allegedly g[iving]
    him bad legal advice,” not due to an overly difficult procedural
    requirement.42 So our decision in In re Adoption of J.S. suggests that
    the failure to comply with a procedural requirement due to a
    mistake by an attorney cannot sustain a procedural due process
    claim under the impossibility inquiry.43
    ¶29 Like the procedural deficiency in In re Adoption of J.S.,
    Mother’s failure to comply with the Adoption Act’s procedural
    requirements can be attributed to a mistake by legal counsel.
    Mother received notice under section 110 informing her of both
    what was required to intervene in the proceedings and what would
    happen if she did not intervene. Rather than file a motion to
    intervene within thirty days, she filed an answer to the Adoptive
    Parents’ petition, which the district court found did not satisfy
    section 110’s strict compliance requirement. Mother does not
    suggest that compliance was impossible or too difficult.44 In fact,
    compliance clearly was neither impossible nor too difficult because
    Mother was able to file a compliant motion to intervene
    immediately after the Adoptive Parents filed their motion to strike.
    So the only plausible explanation for the deficiencies in Mother’s
    original attempt to intervene is that her legal counsel misread or
    __________________________________________________________
    39
    Id. ¶ 1.
       40
    Id. ¶ 11.
       41
    Id. ¶ 19.
       42
    Id. ¶ 2
    3.
    
       43
    Id. ¶¶ 23–24.
       44 Instead, Mother has argued that strict compliance and
    intervention is unnecessary for a biological mother. This challenge
    is more properly categorized as a substantive due process
    challenge.
    12
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                                Opinion of the Court
    misunderstood section 110’s legal requirements. 45 But as In re
    Adoption of J.S. illustrates, when the failure to comply with a
    “simple and straightforward” procedural requirement is due to
    legal counsel’s mistake, the procedural requirement has not
    foreclosed meaningful access to the justice system. 46 Accordingly,
    Mother fails to show that the Adoption Act deprived her of her
    constitutional right to an opportunity to be heard.
    ¶30 Because Mother’s constitutional rights to reasonable notice
    and an opportunity to be heard were not violated, her procedural
    due process challenge of the Adoption Act fails.
    III. Mother’s Substantive Due Process Rights Were Violated
    Because Section 110’s Strict Compliance Requirement
    is Not Narrowly Tailored
    ¶31 Mother also challenges the Adoption Act’s framework
    under the substantive component of the Due Process Clause. Such
    a claim is distinct from the procedural due process challenge
    analyzed above. In contrast to a procedural due process attack, a
    substantive challenge “involve[s] a broad-side attack on the
    fairness of the procedural bar or limitation, on the ground that the
    right foreclosed is so fundamental or important that it is protected
    from extinguishment.”47 In other words, a substantive due process
    challenge alleges that a procedural requirement is unfair because it
    improperly infringes an important right rather than because it
    operates to unfairly foreclose notice or a meaningful opportunity
    to be heard. So if a statute allows the state to improperly extinguish
    or foreclose a protected right, even if it does so through
    straightforward procedural requirements, it is unconstitutional
    under the substantive component of the Due Process Clause.
    A. The district court applied provisions of the Adoption Act
    to extinguish Mother’s fundamental right to parent K.T.B.
    ¶32 Whether a statute improperly allows the state to
    extinguish or foreclose a protected right depends on the nature of
    the right and its attendant standard of review. If the right infringed
    or foreclosed is a right we have deemed “fundamental,” we review
    __________________________________________________________
    45Mother was represented by counsel when she filed her
    answer.
    46   
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 23.
    47  In re Adoption of B.Y., 
    2015 UT 67
    , ¶ 41, 
    356 P.3d 1215
    (alteration in original) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    13
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    the statute under our strict scrutiny standard.48 But if it is not
    fundamental, we review it under “the deferential, fallback
    standard of rationality or arbitrariness.”49
    ¶33 The importance of correctly characterizing the nature of
    the right at issue was illustrated in our recent decision in In re B.Y.50
    In that case, we considered an unmarried biological father’s
    challenge to a “strict compliance provision of the Adoption Act.”51
    We explained that this procedural provision of the Adoption Act
    had been challenged on procedural and substantive due process
    grounds.52 We then proceeded to analyze the procedural
    requirement under both frameworks.
    ¶34 First, we analyzed the claim on procedural due process
    grounds, determining that the claim failed because “it was not
    impossible” for the unmarried father to comply with the strict
    compliance provision at issue.53 This was the correct analysis for a
    procedural due process claim, and it is the same analysis we have
    applied to Mother’s procedural due process claim in this case.
    ¶35 After deciding the father’s procedural due process claim,
    we turned to his substantive one.54 And we appropriately
    commenced our substantive due process analysis by identifying
    the nature of the infringed right. We determined that the right
    infringed in that case was “merely provisional” because the
    plaintiff was an unmarried biological father who had failed to
    perfect his parental rights by following the procedures established
    __________________________________________________________
    48Jones v. Jones, 
    2015 UT 84
    , ¶ 26, 
    359 P.3d 603
    (“When the court
    has recognized a due process right it deems ‘fundamental,’ it
    consistently has applied a standard of strict scrutiny to the
    protection of such a right.”).
    49In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 56, 
    358 P.3d 1009
    (plurality
    opinion).
    50   
    2015 UT 67
    .
    51
    Id. ¶ 41
    .
    
       52
    Id. 53 Id.
    ¶¶ 16, 37, 40 (internal quotation marks omitted).
    54
    Id. ¶ 41
    (noting that the father had also “challenge[d] the
    application of the strict compliance provision . . . under the
    substantive component of the Due Process Clause.” (emphasis
    omitted)).
    14
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                               Opinion of the Court
    in law.55 Because the unmarried biological father’s right did not rise
    to the level of a fundamental right, we considered the father’s claim
    under the more deferential rational-basis prong of the substantive
    due process analysis.56 Under this standard, we rejected the father’s
    claim because the procedural requirement that barred the father
    from participating in the adoption proceeding—a strict compliance
    provision—was “far from arbitrary.”57 Thus our decision in In re
    B.Y. hinged on the provisional nature of the unmarried father’s
    right and on the standard of review we applied to the statutory
    provision in question.
    ¶36 In contrast to the right at issue in In re B.Y., the right at
    issue in this case is fundamental. Although “[s]ome variation
    exists” among the parental rights of unmarried fathers depending
    on the steps they have taken to perfect their parental rights,58 “no
    similar variation exists” among the parental rights of unmarried
    mothers.59
    ¶37 Unmarried mothers “acquire parental rights—and the
    accompanying right to object to an adoption—as a result of the objective
    __________________________________________________________
    55
    Id. ¶ 43.
    In In re B.Y., we explained that the right of an
    unmarried father is “merely provisional” until the father complies
    with the requirements established for the perfecting of that right.
    Id. This ruling
    is consistent with the United States Supreme Court’s
    decision in Lehr v. Robertson, where the Court explained that an
    unmarried father does not have a recognized parental right until he
    takes some affirmative action to “grasp” the opportunity to
    develop a relationship with his child. 
    463 U.S. 248
    , 262 (1983). Thus
    the right at issue in In re B.Y. was not a fundamental parental right,
    but a provisional right to an “opportunity” to develop a parental
    right. See
    id. at 262–63
    (“We are concerned only with whether New
    York has adequately protected [the unmarried father’s]
    opportunity to form such a relationship.”).
    56 In re B.Y., 
    2015 UT 67
    , ¶ 43 (determining whether “the
    prerequisites established by the state [were] arbitrary” (emphasis
    omitted)).
    57
    Id. ¶ 46.
       58 In re J.P., 
    648 P.2d 1365
    , 1374 (Utah 1982); see also In re Adoption
    of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 2 (distinguishing between the requirements
    imposed on unmarried fathers and unmarried mothers).
    59   In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1374
    –75.
    15
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    manifestation of the commitment to the child that is demonstrated
    by their decision to carry a child to term.”60 So even though an
    unmarried father may be required to comply with certain
    procedural requirements before his parental rights become
    fundamental, an unmarried mother’s parental rights are “vested”61
    and “inherent”62 without her having to comply with the same
    procedural requirements.63 In fact, this court has held that the right
    of a mother “not to be deprived of parental rights without a
    showing of unfitness, abandonment, or substantial neglect is so
    fundamental to our society and so basic to our constitutional order
    . . . that it ranks among those rights referred to in Article I, [section]
    25 of the Utah Constitution and the Ninth Amendment of the
    United States Constitution as being retained by the people.”64 In
    other words, mothers retain a fundamental right in their children
    regardless of a failure to comply with any state-prescribed
    procedure.65 And this right remains in effect absent “a showing of
    unfitness, abandonment, or substantial neglect.”66 So if a statute
    __________________________________________________________
    60   In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 2 (emphasis added).
    61 Wells v. Children’s Aid Soc’y of Utah, 
    681 P.2d 199
    , 206 (Utah
    1984) (citation omitted).
    62   In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1373
    .
    63See In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 2 (explaining that an
    “unwed father’s legal obligation to file the paternity affidavit [was]
    a rough counterpart to the mother’s commitment,” which is
    “demonstrated by [the mother’s] decision to carry a child to term”).
    64In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1375
    (emphases added); see also
    id. at 1372
    (explaining that a mother “has a fundamental right, protected by
    the Constitution, to sustain [her] relationship with [her] child”
    (emphasis added) (citation omitted) (internal quotation marks
    omitted)).
    65 In fact, the Supreme Court has stated that, “[i]f anything,
    persons faced with forced dissolution of their parental rights have
    a more critical need for procedural protections” than do others.
    Santosky v. Kramer, 
    455 U.S. 745
    , 753 (1982). For this reason, states
    “must provide . . . parents with fundamentally fair procedures”
    when moving to destroy parental bonds.
    Id. at 753–54.
       66 
    Wells, 681 P.2d at 204
    ; see also In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1372
    (“[T]he
    correlative of parental rights is parental duties. When parents fail
    to, or are incapable of, performing their parental obligations, the
    (Continued)
    16
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Opinion of the Court
    authorizes a court to terminate a mother’s parental rights without
    her consent or without proof of unfitness, abandonment, or neglect,
    a fundamental right has been infringed upon, and we determine
    the constitutionality of the infringing statute by reviewing it under
    the strict scrutiny standard.67
    ¶38 As applied in this case, the Adoption Act authorized the
    district court to terminate Mother’s parental rights without her
    consent and without proof of parental unfitness, abandonment, or
    neglect. Specifically, section 110 authorized the court to rule that
    Mother had “forfeit[ed] all rights in relation to the adoptee”
    because she failed “to fully and strictly comply with all of the
    requirements” listed in that section. And because she failed to
    strictly comply with the requirements of section 110, section 112
    allowed the court to terminate her parental rights, and section 120.1
    allowed the court to rule that she had lost her right to consent or
    object to the adoption.68
    __________________________________________________________
    child’s welfare must prevail over the right of the parent.” We have
    noted, of course, that mothers and fathers may “choose to waive”
    their parental rights. In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 2 (emphasis
    added).
    67 In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 42. By recognizing that
    statutorily imposed consequences for a failure to comply with
    procedural requirements infringe on a mother’s fundamental right,
    we are not suggesting that mothers may never be subject to
    procedural requirements. Instead, we are merely recognizing that
    where a procedural requirement—and the statutorily imposed
    consequences for failing to comply with that requirement—
    infringe on a fundamental right, that requirement is constitutional
    only so long as it is narrowly tailored to further a compelling state
    interest.
    68The dissent argues that the Adoption Act does not authorize
    the termination of parental rights “without requiring ‘proof of
    unfitness, abandonment, or neglect’” because, had Mother strictly
    complied with the procedural requirements of the Act, she could
    have had an opportunity to defend her parental rights. See infra
    ¶ 154 n.213 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting). Not only does this argument
    ignore the “as-applied” nature of Mother’s substantive due process
    claim, but it also ignores our case law, which clearly recognizes a
    mother’s right to maintain her parental rights unless she
    (Continued)
    17
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    ¶39 The Adoptive Parents argue, however, that Mother’s
    parental rights were not terminated by her failure to strictly comply
    with the Adoption Act’s procedural requirements. Instead, they
    assert that her parental rights were properly terminated after the
    district court considered relevant evidence at the uncontested
    adoption hearing held the following month.69 This argument fails
    because Mother had already been stripped of “all rights in relation
    to the adoptee”70—including the right to contest, or consent to, the
    adoption—by the time the court heard evidence relevant to a
    proper termination of parental rights.71 In other words, because the
    Adoption Act authorized the district court to bar Mother from
    participating in the adoption proceeding, Mother’s right to defend
    her parental rights was extinguished.72 So even if section 110’s strict
    __________________________________________________________
    voluntarily relinquishes them or a court finds that she forfeited
    them by being an unfit parent or by abandoning or neglecting the
    child. So where this right is terminated for some other reason—
    such as in consequence of a mother’s procedural default—the
    termination of the mother’s parental rights must be reviewed under
    our strict scrutiny standard. And we note that, contrary to the
    dissent’s suggestion, this rule does not exempt mothers from
    constitutionally valid procedural requirements.
    69 This assertion is only partially correct. Although the district
    court noted that the Adoptive Parents had provided sufficient
    evidence of abuse, unfitness, and neglect in its findings of fact and
    conclusions of law, it also based its decision to terminate Mother’s
    parental rights on the fact that Mother’s right to consent had been
    forfeited under sections 110 and 112, and that under section 120.1
    her consent could be implied.
    70   UTAH CODE § 78B-6-110(6)(b)(ii).
    71  In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 2 (explaining that a
    mother’s parental rights include the “right to object to an
    adoption”); see also In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1372
    (explaining that a
    mother “has a fundamental right, protected by the Constitution, to
    sustain [her] relationship with [her] child” (emphasis added)
    (citation omitted) (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    72 See In re K.J., 
    2013 UT App 237
    , ¶ 26, 
    327 P.3d 1203
    (explaining
    that in a typical proceeding to terminate parental rights, although
    the “petitioner bears the ultimate burden of proving the grounds
    for termination by clear and convincing evidence, once evidence is
    (Continued)
    18
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                              Opinion of the Court
    compliance requirement did not immediately allow the court to
    extinguish the full spectrum of Mother’s parental rights, it
    nevertheless infringed in part on Mother’s parental rights by
    requiring the court to exclude her from the adoption proceeding
    and mandating the forfeiture of “all [her] rights in relation” to
    K.T.B.73
    B. As applied to this case, section 110’s strict compliance provision
    fails strict scrutiny review
    ¶40 Because the Adoption Act authorized the district court to
    terminate a fundamental right in this case, we must analyze it
    under the strict scrutiny standard.74 Under the strict scrutiny
    standard, “a fundamental right is protected except in the limited
    circumstance in which an infringement of it is shown to be
    ‘narrowly tailored’ to protect a ‘compelling governmental
    interest.’”75 Section 110’s strict compliance requirement fails this
    test.76 Even though the Adoption Act’s procedural requirements
    serve a number of compelling governmental interests, in this case
    the strict compliance requirement in section 110 was not necessary
    __________________________________________________________
    presented that would justify termination, the burden shifts to the
    parent to persuade the court that the [petitioner] had not
    established [the ground for termination] by clear and convincing
    evidence.” (alterations in original) (citations omitted) (internal
    quotation marks omitted)).
    73  In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1372
    –77 (recognizing a parent’s
    fundamental right to “maintain parental ties to his or her child,”
    and “in the care, custody, and management of [his or her] child,”
    as well as the right of a mother “not to be deprived of parental
    rights without a showing of unfitness, abandonment, or substantial
    neglect”).
    74   See Jones, 
    2015 UT 84
    , ¶ 26.
    75
    Id. ¶ 2
    7 
    (quoting Washington v. Glucksberg, 
    521 U.S. 702
    , 721
    (1997)).
    76  Although Mother has challenged three sections of the
    Adoption Act—sections 110, 112, and 120.1—as they work
    together, it is the strict compliance provision of section 110 that
    prompted the district court’s termination of Mother’s parental
    rights. Accordingly, we focus on this requirement in our strict
    scrutiny analysis.
    19
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    to protect those interests and therefore it is unconstitutional as
    applied to Mother.
    ¶41 Although we have previously recognized that the “strict
    laws” in the Adoption Act further the state’s interest in promoting
    prompt and stable adoptions,77 we have not yet considered the
    constitutionality of section 110’s strict compliance requirement
    under a strict scrutiny analysis.78 So even though we have
    previously concluded that section 110’s requirements are not
    merely arbitrary,79 we have not yet determined whether those
    requirements were necessary to achieve the state’s compelling
    adoption-related interests under the circumstances presented in
    this case. We do so now.
    ¶42 The State of Utah has a number of “compelling interest[s]
    in the adoption process.”80 First, “the state has a compelling interest
    in providing stable and permanent homes for adoptive children in
    a prompt manner.”81 Second, it has an interest “in preventing the
    disruption of adoptive placements.”82 And third, it has an interest
    “in holding parents accountable for meeting the needs of
    children.”83 These interests satisfy the strict scrutiny standard’s
    “compelling interest” prong.84 Accordingly, we review section
    __________________________________________________________
    77   In re Adoption of B.B.D., 
    1999 UT 70
    , ¶ 14, 
    984 P.2d 967
    .
    78 See, e.g., In re Adoption of B.Y., 
    2015 UT 67
    , ¶¶ 42–46 (declining
    to consider a putative father’s substantive due process claim under
    a strict scrutiny standard because the father had not yet perfected
    his parental rights and holding that until a putative father perfects
    his parental rights under the Adoption Act, his rights are “merely
    provisional” rather than fundamental).
    79 See
    id. ¶¶ 41–46
    (holding that “the strict compliance provision
    of the Adoption Act” was not arbitrary in the context of a putative
    father’s due process challenge).
    In re Adoption of B.B.D., 
    1999 UT 70
    , ¶ 14 (internal quotation
    80
    marks omitted).
    81   UTAH CODE § 78B-6-102(5)(a).
    82
    Id. 83 Id.
       84See, e.g., Thurnwald v. A.E., 
    2007 UT 38
    , ¶¶ 30, 34, 
    163 P.3d 623
    (concluding that the state had a compelling interest in “speedily
    (Continued)
    20
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                              Opinion of the Court
    110’s strict compliance requirement to determine if it is narrowly
    tailored to facilitate these interests.
    ¶43 Under strict scrutiny’s “narrowly tailored” prong, we
    must determine whether the “legitimate state purpose [could] be
    . . . more narrowly achieved.”85 In other words, we consider
    whether the challenged provisions were “necessary” to achieve the
    state’s purpose in facilitating a prompt and stable adoption of
    K.T.B., in preventing a disruption of that adoption, or in holding
    parents accountable for K.T.B.’s needs.86
    ¶44 Section 110 requires a person to “file a motion to intervene
    in the adoption proceeding.”87 If the person fails to intervene
    within thirty days, that person is excluded from the adoption
    proceeding going forward.88 This timely intervention requirement
    serves the state’s interest in providing prompt adoptions and in
    preventing their disruption by a parent who chose not to intervene
    but later reconsiders this decision.
    ¶45 As part of section 110’s intervention requirement, the
    motion to intervene must “set[] forth specific relief sought” and be
    __________________________________________________________
    identifying those persons who will assume a parental role over
    newborn illegitimate children,” “in promoting early and
    uninterrupted bonding between child and parents[,] and in
    facilitating final and irrevocable adoptions.” (citations omitted)
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    85  In re Boyer, 
    636 P.2d 1085
    , 1090 (Utah 1981). The dissent
    criticizes us for applying this standard. See infra ¶ 165 (Lee, A.C.J.,
    dissenting). But we are merely applying the standard that has been
    well-established by our case law. In contrast to this established
    approach, the dissent suggests that a loss of an indisputably
    fundamental right does not trigger strict scrutiny review where
    that loss stemmed from a procedural default. See infra ¶ 217 (Lee,
    A.C.J., dissenting) (suggesting that “procedures” may never be
    subject to “substantive due process scrutiny”). Because such an
    approach would be inconsistent with controlling precedent, we
    reject it. See infra ¶¶ 51–101.
    86  Wells v. Children’s Aid Soc’y of 
    Utah, 681 P.2d at 207
    (considering whether any “infringement of the [plaintiff’s] rights
    not essential to the statute’s purpose ha[d] been identified”).
    87   UTAH CODE § 78B-6-110(6)(a).
    88
    Id. § 78B-6-
    110(6)(b).
    
    21
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    “accompanied by a memorandum specifying the factual and legal
    grounds upon which the motion is based.”89 These sub-
    requirements serve section 110’s overarching purpose. They do so
    by (1) notifying the court and the petitioners of who will be
    contesting the adoption and (2) informing the court of the legal
    basis on which that person is entitled to intervene, thereby allowing
    the court to quickly weed out improper interveners. Mother’s
    attempt to intervene satisfied section 110’s overarching purpose as
    well as the underlying purposes of section 110’s filing
    requirements.
    ¶46 Mother filed an “Answer to Verified Petition for
    Termination of Parental Rights and for Adoption of Minor Child”
    within thirty days of receiving the notice of the adoption
    proceeding. And although her answer was not accompanied by a
    memorandum “specifying the factual and legal grounds upon
    which the [answer] was based,” she did admit in her answer that
    she was K.T.B.’s mother, as well as deny all of the factual
    allegations upon which the Adoptive Parents based their request to
    terminate her parental rights. Moreover, in the answer’s prayer for
    relief, Mother requested that the Adoptive Parents “take nothing
    by way of their Petition.”
    ¶47 This answer fulfilled the purposes of section 110’s motion
    to intervene requirement. First, we note that “it is the substance, not
    the labeling, of a motion that is dispositive in determining the
    character of the motion.”90 Based on the substance of Mother’s
    answer, the court and the Adoptive Parents knew or should have
    known that Mother wanted to participate in the proceeding in
    order to oppose the adoption. They also knew or should have
    known that Mother intended to participate by providing evidence
    to defend against the factual allegations they advanced in support
    of their request to terminate Mother’s parental rights. And because
    the answer was filed within thirty days, it did not hinder the state’s
    interest in facilitating a prompt adoption.
    ¶48 Second, the court’s interest in barring improper parties
    from the proceedings was not hindered by the procedural
    deficiencies in Mother’s answer. Mother is indisputably K.T.B.’s
    __________________________________________________________
    89
    Id. § 78B-6-
    110(6)(a)(ii), 
    (iii).
    90 Bair v. Axiom Design, L.L.C., 
    2001 UT 20
    , ¶ 9, 
    20 P.3d 388
    ,
    abrogated on other grounds by Gillett v. Price, 
    2006 UT 24
    , ¶ 2, 
    135 P.3d 861
    , as recognized in A.S. v. R.S., 
    2017 UT 77
    , ¶ 21, 
    416 P.3d 465
    .
    22
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Opinion of the Court
    biological mother. And at oral argument before us, the Adoptive
    Parents conceded that timely motions to intervene brought by a
    biological mother are granted as a matter of course. Thus, even
    though Mother’s answer did not trigger scheduled briefing and
    oral argument as a motion to intervene would have done, the
    answer nevertheless fulfilled section 110’s purposes by alerting the
    court—and the Adoptive Parents—that K.T.B.’s biological mother
    sought to participate in the proceedings. Stated differently, in light
    of Mother’s unquestioned status as K.T.B.’s biological mother, the
    contents of the Adoptive Parents and Mother’s pleadings provided
    the district court with all of the information it needed to rule on the
    issue of Mother’s intervention. So in this case, section 110’s
    purposes were fulfilled by Mother’s attempt to intervene through
    her answer.
    ¶49 But section 110 also states that its requirements must be
    “fully and strictly” complied with.91 Despite the fact that Mother’s
    answer did not hinder the state’s compelling interests in promoting
    prompt and stable adoptions, the district court barred her from the
    adoption proceeding because she failed to strictly comply with
    section 110’s filing requirements. And this inevitably led the court
    to terminate all of Mother’s parental rights pursuant to section 112.
    ¶50 Because Mother’s timely filed answer—though not strictly
    compliant with section 110’s procedural sub-requirements—
    achieved everything section 110 is designed to achieve, we cannot
    say that the strict compliance requirement was necessary to achieve
    the state’s compelling adoption-related interests in this case. For
    this reason we hold that section 110’s strict compliance provision is
    unconstitutional as applied to Mother.92 Accordingly, we reverse
    __________________________________________________________
    91   UTAH CODE § 78B-6-110(6)(b).
    92 To be clear, in holding that the strict compliance component
    of section 110 fails the strict scrutiny test, as applied to Mother in
    this case, we are not suggesting, as Mother argues in her brief, that
    the entire motion-to-intervene provision is “meaningless” as
    applied to biological mothers. In fact, by holding that the timing
    and substantive requirements of the provision are necessary to
    further the state’s purposes, see supra ¶¶ 45–46, we have held the
    opposite. So we are not lightly excusing the procedural
    requirements of the Adoption Act in this case. Rather, we have
    narrowed the scope of our opinion to the strict compliance
    (Continued)
    23
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    the district court’s decision to strike Mother’s answer and remand
    to the district court for further proceedings, in which Mother may
    participate, on the Adoptive Parents’ adoption petition.
    C. The arguments raised by the dissent are unpersuasive
    ¶51 The dissent disagrees with our resolution of Mother’s
    substantive due process claim. At its heart, the dissent’s
    disagreement stems from a different view of the right at issue. We
    contend that the right at issue is Mother’s fundamental right to
    parent—a right firmly rooted in our history and case law. Because
    we view the right at issue to be fundamental, any governmental
    __________________________________________________________
    provision in Utah Code section 78B-6-110(6)(b) and to the facts of
    this case.
    We also note that the dissent criticizes our decision on the
    ground that “strict procedural compliance” is “at a premium” in
    the “adoption arena.” See infra ¶ 207 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting). But in
    so doing, the dissent fails to engage with the specific and narrow
    reasoning in our decision. Instead, it argues only that “statutory
    procedures for natural parents to participate in and assert their
    rights” are a core element in the state’s effort to facilitate adoptions.
    See infra ¶ 207 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting). We take no issue with this
    general statement. But the dissent has failed to explain how the
    strict compliance requirement would have aided the State’s effort
    to facilitate adoptions in this case. As we have discussed, in this
    case, Mother’s timely attempt to intervene provided the court and
    the Adoptive Parents all of the information that a strictly compliant
    motion to intervene would have. For this reason, our decision in no
    way hinders the interests advanced by the procedural
    requirements of the Adoption Act.
    The dissent also suggests that, by subjecting the procedural
    requirements of the Adoption Act to a substantive due process
    review, we are foreclosing the state’s ability to impose procedural
    time bars in the adoption setting. See infra ¶ 213 (Lee, A.C.J.,
    dissenting). But our case law makes clear that procedural
    requirements have long been subject to substantive due process.
    And the dissent’s suggestion that subjecting procedural
    requirements to the demands of substantive due process will
    upend all procedural requirements misses the mark. Indeed, in this
    very case, we have upheld other procedural requirements in
    section 110—including          section 110’s thirty-day filing
    requirement—as being narrowly tailored to further the state’s
    interest in prompt adoptions.
    24
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                              Opinion of the Court
    infringement of that right is subject to strict scrutiny review.93 And
    in applying our well-established strict scrutiny test, we have
    determined that the state violated Mother’s fundamental parental
    rights when it terminated those rights despite Mother’s timely, and
    substantially compliant, attempt to intervene. In other words,
    because the strict compliance requirement did not further the
    State’s compelling, adoption-related interests in this case, we hold
    that the strict compliance requirement is unconstitutional as
    applied in this case.
    ¶52 The dissent, in contrast, argues that the rights at issue in
    this case are not Mother’s parental rights—the rights that were
    terminated by the State. Instead, it argues that the right at issue is
    Mother’s right to retain her right to parent despite a failure to comply
    with procedural requirements. In other words, rather than asking
    whether Mother, as K.T.B.’s biological mother, has a
    constitutionally protected interest in engaging in any of the
    conduct inherent in the parent-child relationship, the dissent asks
    whether Mother has a constitutionally protected interest in being
    free from a particular form of governmental interference. But we
    reject this characterization of the right at issue because it is
    inconsistent with our case law, and it would lead us to entirely
    overlook the substantial parental interests at the heart of this case.
    ¶53 But before we discuss the specific ways in which the
    dissent’s approach is inconsistent with our case law, we also note
    that, as a practical matter, the dissent’s approach would strip
    Mother’s parental rights of their fundamental status. The dissent
    concedes that Mother had fundamental parental rights. And it
    cannot dispute that those fundamental rights were terminated by
    the State. Despite this, the dissent argues that the relevant right at
    issue in this case is not one of the fundamental rights that were
    terminated, but Mother’s right to retain her fundamental parental
    rights. And, according to the dissent, this newly identified right is
    not fundamental and so its infringement need not be reviewed
    under our strict scrutiny standard. In other words, although the
    dissent concedes that at least some of Mother’s parental rights were
    fundamental before they were terminated,94 it does not explain
    how we should analyze Mother’s loss of those fundamental rights.
    So the dissent’s proposed approach either ignores Mother’s
    __________________________________________________________
    93   See Jones, 
    2015 UT 84
    , ¶ 26.
    94   See infra ¶ 179 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting).
    25
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    pre-existing fundamental parental rights or treats them as if her
    failure to strictly comply with the challenged procedural
    requirements transformed her fundamental rights into the less
    valuable right the dissent argues is at issue in this case.95 The
    practical effect of this approach is that any procedural requirement
    triggering the forfeiture of fundamental rights is immune from
    strict scrutiny review because the right to retain those rights is not
    fundamental. For this reason, we reject the dissent’s approach.
    ¶54 We also reject the dissent’s approach because it is
    inconsistent with our case law. It is inconsistent for two reasons.
    First, it is inconsistent because it departs from the manner in which
    we, or the United States Supreme Court, have defined parental
    rights in parental rights termination cases.96 Second, it is
    inconsistent because it leads to a misapplication of the doctrine of
    forfeiture.
    __________________________________________________________
    95  The dissent pushes back on the notion that its approach
    transforms the fundamental nature of the underlying parental
    rights into something less than fundamental. See infra ¶ 157 n.215
    (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting) (“The fundamental nature of the
    underlying parental right stays the same throughout—my point is
    just that the right at issue here is distinct from that underlying
    right.”). But in so doing, the dissent confirms that it is ignoring the
    termination of the underlying fundamental right altogether. In
    other words, the dissent confirms that, under its approach, state
    action to terminate a fundamental parental right need not satisfy
    strict scrutiny review so long as the parent failed to comply with a
    procedural requirement—a procedural requirement that need not
    be narrowly tailored to further a compelling state interest.
    96  Although we reject the dissent’s argument because it
    mischaracterizes the right at issue, we note that our case law does
    in fact establish that Mother’s right to retain her parental rights is
    fundamental. We have held that mothers have a fundamental right
    to “maintain parental ties” to their children, In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1377
    , to not be “deprived of parental rights without a showing of
    unfitness, abandonment, or substantial neglect,”
    id. at 1375,
    “to
    sustain [their] relationship with [their] child,”
    id. at 1372
    , and “to
    object to an adoption,” In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 2. Because
    our case law makes clear that Mother has a fundamental right to
    retain her parental rights, even under the dissent’s characterization
    of the right at issue the dissent’s argument fails.
    26
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                             Opinion of the Court
    1. The dissent mischaracterizes the right at issue in this case
    ¶55 We reject the dissent’s argument because it is based on a
    mischaracterization of the right at issue. According to the dissent,
    the right at issue is not Mother’s parental rights, but her “right to
    retain parental rights despite failing to comply with required
    procedure.”97 But this mischaracterizes the right at issue in two
    ways. First, it incorrectly defines the right by referencing the
    manner—forfeiture triggered by a procedural default—in which
    the government interfered with Mother’s parental rights. Because
    this characterization of Mother’s right would mark a fundamental
    departure from the way courts have traditionally defined parental
    rights, we reject it.
    ¶56 Second, the dissent mischaracterizes the right at issue by
    failing to account for a key distinction between the nature of the
    rights of an unmarried biological mother and an unmarried
    biological father. Throughout its opinion, the dissent relies upon
    cases in which we or the United States Supreme Court dealt with
    the provisional, or inchoate, parental rights of unmarried biological
    fathers. Because the case law clearly establishes that mothers have
    a “retained” fundamental right in their children, whereas
    unmarried fathers have only provisional rights that must be
    perfected through compliance with procedure or some other
    means, the dissent’s argument fails.98
    a. The dissent errs in defining the right in reference to the form
    of governmental interference
    ¶57 We first address the dissent’s attempt to characterize the
    right at issue by referencing the procedural requirement that
    triggered the forfeiture of Mother’s parental rights. It states that the
    right at issue is the “right to retain parental rights despite failing to
    __________________________________________________________
    97   See infra ¶ 135 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting) (emphasis added).
    98 In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1375
    (explaining that the right of a mother
    “not to be deprived of parental rights without a showing of
    unfitness, abandonment, or substantial neglect is so fundamental
    to our society and so basic to our constitutional order . . . that it
    ranks among those rights referred to in Article I, [section] 25 of the
    Utah Constitution and the Ninth Amendment of the United States
    Constitution as being retained by the people.” (emphasis added); see
    also
    id. at 1372
    (explaining that a mother “has a fundamental right,
    protected by the Constitution, to sustain [her] relationship with
    [her] child” (citation omitted) (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    27
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    comply with required procedure.”99 To be clear the dissent does not
    dispute that at least some parental rights are fundamental.100 Nor
    does it dispute that Mother lost all of her parental rights in this case.
    But, according to the dissent, the right at issue in this case is not
    Mother’s fundamental right to parent (the right that was forfeited),
    but her right to retain that fundamental right despite her
    noncompliance with the challenged procedural requirement. In
    defining the right at issue in this way, the dissent adopts a novel
    approach to defining due process rights in parentage cases—an
    approach that effectively deprives Mother’s fundamental parental
    rights of the heightened protection our case law would typically
    provide.101
    ¶58 The dissent’s mischaracterization of the right in this case
    appears to rest on a misconception of how we typically define
    parental rights. By incorporating a reference to the challenged
    governmental interference in this case—the procedural
    requirements that triggered the judicially imposed forfeiture of
    Mother’s parental rights—into its definition of the right at issue, the
    dissent would have us define the right at issue based on the
    particular form the governmental interference takes. That is not
    how the United States Supreme Court, nor we, have defined
    parental rights in the past.
    ¶59 Under the approach established by the Supreme Court, the
    nature of parental rights is defined based on (1) the status of the
    individual invoking the right and (2) the parental conduct to be
    protected. For example, in one of the Supreme Court’s seminal
    parental rights cases, Meyer v. Nebraska, the Court explained that
    the “liberty” component of the Due Process Clause includes “the
    right of the individual to . . . establish a home and bring up
    children.”102 The Court then specifically concluded that this liberty
    right included the right of “parents to control the education of their
    own.”103 So the Court defined the right to parent by referring to the
    __________________________________________________________
    99   Infra ¶ 135 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting).
    100   See infra ¶ 179 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting).
    Jones, 
    2015 UT 84
    , ¶ 26 (“When the court has recognized a due
    101
    process right it deems ‘fundamental,’ it consistently has applied a
    standard of strict scrutiny to the protection of such a right.”).
    102   
    262 U.S. 390
    , 399 (1923).
    103
    Id. at 401
    (emphasis added).
    28
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                               Opinion of the Court
    status of the individual claiming the right—the individual’s status
    as a parent—and by referring to the conduct to be protected—the
    education of children.
    ¶60 Following Meyer, the Supreme Court has repeatedly
    looked to the status of the individual and the conduct to be
    protected before determining whether the individual’s claim fell
    within the umbrella of parental rights. For example, the Court has
    looked to an individual’s parental status in distinguishing between
    the rights of parents and grandparents104 and between biological
    parents and foster parents.105 And, importantly for this case, this
    court has distinguished between the rights of unmarried biological
    fathers and unmarried biological mothers.106
    ¶61 The Supreme Court has also looked to the conduct to be
    protected in determining that the right to parent included the right
    to homeschool,107 the right “to direct the religious upbringing of
    [the parent’s] children,”108 and, in a long line of cases, “the
    fundamental right of parents to make decisions concerning the
    care, custody, and control of their children.”109 We also note that
    the Supreme Court has made clear that parental rights protect
    against all forms of “government interference.”110
    ¶62 Thus Supreme Court precedent makes clear that we
    should characterize the parental right at issue in a given case by
    referring to (1) the status of the individual invoking the right and
    (2) the parental conduct to be protected. And our ultimate
    characterization of the right does not depend on the form of
    governmental interference at issue. But that is not how the dissent
    would have us characterize the parental right in this case.
    ¶63 The dissent characterizes the parental right in this case as
    the “right to retain parental rights despite failing to comply with
    __________________________________________________________
    104   See Troxel v. Granville, 
    530 U.S. 57
    , 65–73 (2000).
    105See Smith v. Org. of Foster Families For Equality & Reform, 
    431 U.S. 816
    , 842–47 (1977).
    106   
    See supra
    ¶¶ 33–37.
    107Pierce v. Soc’y of the Sisters of the Holy Names of Jesus & Mary,
    
    268 U.S. 510
    , 534 (1925).
    108   Wisconsin v. Yoder, 
    406 U.S. 205
    , 233 (1972).
    109   
    Troxel, 530 U.S. at 66
    (compiling cases).
    110
    Id. at 65.
    29
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    required procedure.”111 So rather than asking whether parental
    conduct falls within the umbrella of protected parental rights, the
    dissent asks whether parents have a recognized right to be free of a
    particular form of governmental interference—in this case, a
    judicially imposed forfeiture of all parental rights. Accordingly,
    under the dissent’s approach, it is the nature of the governmental
    interference, rather than Mother’s parental status (an unmarried
    biological mother)112 or the conduct in which she would like to
    engage (all parental conduct, or, at the very least, the maintaining
    of her parental rights)113 that would define her parental right. This
    characterization of the right at issue would mark a significant
    departure from the Supreme Court’s method of defining parental
    rights.
    ¶64 The dissent disagrees. Although it concedes that, under
    controlling precedent, parental rights are defined by the status of
    the individual invoking the right and the conduct to be protected,
    it nevertheless argues that its approach is consistent with this
    precedent because it has merely adopted a narrower view of “the
    precise form of parental conduct at issue.”114 So, according to the
    __________________________________________________________
    111   See infra ¶ 135 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting) (emphasis added).
    112In re adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 2 (“Unwed mothers acquire
    parental rights—and the accompanying right to object to an
    adoption—as a result of the objective manifestation of the
    commitment to the child that is demonstrated by their decision to
    carry a child to term.”).
    113 In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1377
    (“For the reasons and upon the
    precedents discussed above, we conclude that the Utah
    Constitution recognizes and protects the inherent and retained
    right of a parent to maintain parental ties to his or her child . . . .”
    (emphasis added)).
    114 See infra ¶ 129 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting). The dissent argues
    that our approach “conflates the parental conduct that is being
    terminated . . . with the conduct triggering that termination.” See
    infra ¶ 146 n.211 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting). From this it appears that,
    in the dissent’s view, the focus of our substantive due process
    review should not be on the state action at issue (termination of all
    parental rights) nor on the nature of the rights being terminated
    (fundamental) but on whether a parent’s conduct in failing to
    comply with a procedural requirement was also constitutionally
    (Continued)
    30
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                               Opinion of the Court
    dissent, our disagreement regarding the nature of the right at issue
    is merely a disagreement regarding the “level of generality at
    which an asserted right [should be] framed.”115
    ¶65 The dissent’s narrow framing fails because, in defining the
    “conduct” at issue by referencing the form of governmental
    interference at issue, the dissent fails to identify any parental
    conduct. And when we correctly identify the parental conduct at
    issue in this case, it is clear that we have framed the right
    appropriately.
    ¶66 The dissent explains that it has narrowly framed “the
    relevant conduct” by “asking whether there is a right to an
    exemption from procedural default.”116 Although it is unclear
    whether “an exemption from procedural default” constitutes
    conduct in any sense, even were we to accept it as such it would not
    constitute the type of parental conduct the Supreme Court uses to
    define parental rights. In identifying the relevant parental conduct
    in its past cases, the Supreme Court focuses on the parent’s conduct
    directed at the parent’s child, not conduct directed at, or from, the
    State. For example, in Wisconsin v. Yoder, the Supreme Court
    identified the relevant conduct as the parents’ conduct in providing
    a religious education and upbringing to their children.117 The Court
    explained that the case involved “the fundamental interest of
    parents . . . to guide the religious future and education of their
    children” and it explained that this right had been “established
    beyond debate as an enduring American tradition.”118 So, in
    defining the conduct at issue, the Yoder Court focused on the
    __________________________________________________________
    protected conduct. So it follows that, under the dissent’s approach,
    where the parent lacked a constitutionally protected right to not
    comply with a procedural requirement, the state is free to terminate
    all of the parent’s constitutionally protected rights, including
    fundamental ones, even where the procedural requirement
    allegedly justifying the state’s action is not narrowly tailored to
    further a compelling state interest (the test the state usually must
    pass before it terminates a fundamental right).
    115   See infra ¶ 146 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting).
    116   See infra ¶ 146 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting).
    117   
    Yoder, 406 U.S. at 232
    .
    118
    Id. 31 IN
    RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    parents’ interactions with their children and asked whether the
    parent had a fundamental right to so interact.
    ¶67 In contrast to the Yoder court’s framing of the relevant
    parental conduct, the dissent frames the relevant conduct by
    focusing on Mother’s interactions with the State. The dissent
    explains that Mother does not have a fundamental right to be free
    of the consequences of a State-imposed forfeiture of parental rights
    because she has failed to “establish a tradition of protecting
    parental rights despite a procedural default.” This is inconsistent
    with the Supreme Court’s approach in Yoder and other parental
    rights cases.
    ¶68 Had the Yoder Court defined the right in that case, as the
    dissent does here—by defining it in terms of the parent’s
    interactions with the State—it would have focused on whether the
    “American tradition” had established a parent’s right to be free
    from criminal prosecution despite the parent’s violation of a
    legislative enactment. So the dissent’s focus on the form of
    governmental interference at issue is clearly inconsistent with the
    Court’s framing of the parental right in Yoder.
    ¶69 The dissent also errs in attempting to narrow the scope of
    the relevant parental conduct in this case. Although the dissent
    correctly notes that the level of generality at which an asserted right
    is framed may be an outcome-determinative issue in some cases, its
    suggestion that the level of generality is an issue in this case
    conflicts with controlling precedent.
    ¶70 The level of generality at which an asserted right is framed
    may properly be considered an unresolved issue only where a
    party argues that the Due Process Clause protects someone whose
    (1) status or (2) conduct had not previously received constitutional
    protection. For example, in Smith v. Organization of Foster Families
    For Equality and Reform, the Supreme Court considered whether the
    “liberty” interest protected by the Due Process Clause extended to
    individuals in “their status as foster parents.”119 In considering this
    question, the Court considered the differences between biological
    families, which are created without state involvement, and foster
    families, which “have their origins in an arrangement in which the
    State has been a partner from the outset.”120 Reasoning that the
    “contours” of the liberty interest protected by the Due Process
    __________________________________________________________
    
    119 431 U.S. at 839
    (emphasis added).
    120
    Id. at 845.
    32
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                                Opinion of the Court
    Clause did not have its source “in state law,” “but in intrinsic
    human rights, as they have been understood in this Nation’s
    history and tradition,” the Court concluded that the “foster
    parents” liberty interest received only the “most limited
    constitutional” protection. So, in Smith, the Supreme Court
    resolved a novel question regarding the constitutional protections
    provided to someone with a particular parental status by
    narrowing—to exclude foster parents—the parental status needed
    to receive full protection under the Due Process Clause.
    ¶71 The same is true of the Court’s decision in Michael H. v.
    Gerald D., the case upon which the dissent’s level-of-generality
    argument principally relies.121 The dissent relies on this case to
    argue that the Supreme Court “has never conclusively established
    a governing standard” for defining the level of generality at which
    an asserted right is framed.122 And, for this reason, the dissent states
    that it is free to define the right at issue as it does. But the
    level-of-generality discussion in Michael H. does not support the
    dissent’s proposed framing of the right in this case.
    ¶72 In Michael H., an unmarried father asserted a fundamental
    parental interest in a daughter who was born into a woman’s
    existing marriage with another man.123 So, as in Smith, the Court in
    Michael H. had to decide whether the “liberty” interest protected by
    the Due Process Clause extended to an individual whose parental
    status had not previously been recognized as deserving full
    due-process protection.124 The justices who joined the plurality
    opinion opted to construe the status of the unmarried father
    narrowly—as an unmarried father of a daughter born into a
    woman’s existing marriage with another man. The dissent, in
    contrast, would have construed the status of the father in more
    general terms—as a parent or father. So the competing opinions in
    __________________________________________________________
    121   
    491 U.S. 110
    (1989).
    122   See infra ¶ 147 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting).
    
    123 491 U.S. at 125
    .
    124
    Id., 491 U.S.
    at 124 (“Thus, the legal issue in the present case
    reduces to whether the relationship between persons in the
    situation of Michael and Victoria [(an unmarried father’s
    relationship with his daughter, who was born while her mother
    was married to another man)] has been treated as a protected
    family unit under the historic practices of our society, or whether
    on any other basis it has been accorded special protection.”).
    33
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    Michael H. suggest that where an individual asserts a fundamental
    parental right based on a parental status (or parental conduct) that
    had not previously been recognized as deserving constitutional
    protection, the level of generality at which the court defines the
    parental status (or conduct) may be an outcome-determinative
    issue.
    ¶73 But the level-of-generality problem discussed in Michael H.
    is not an issue in this case, because our case law has already
    established the level of protection the Due Process Clause provides
    to a biological mother’s parental right in a parental rights
    termination case. In fact, the dissent concedes that Mother’s
    parental status—as a biological mother—affords her certain,
    fundamental parental rights. The dissent’s only disagreement,
    therefore, is over our broad characterization of the parental conduct
    at issue. But our case law makes clear that, where the government
    is attempting to terminate all parental rights, courts should define
    the parental right broadly to encompass the full spectrum of
    constitutionally protected parental conduct inherent in the
    parent-child relationship. In other words, the “parental conduct” at
    issue in a parental rights termination case encompasses the entire
    bundle of parental rights, including the parent’s fundamental
    rights to homeschool,125 “to direct the religious upbringing of [the
    parent’s] children,”126 “to make decisions concerning the care,
    custody, and control of their children,”127 and any other right that
    will be terminated as a result of the State’s termination proceeding.
    ¶74 That the conduct at issue in parental rights termination
    cases encompasses the full spectrum of parental conduct is made
    apparent in the Supreme Court’s decision in Stanley v. Illinois.128 In
    that case, the Court determined whether the State of Illinois’
    “method of procedure,” which created a presumption that
    unmarried fathers were unfit parents, violated principles of due
    process.129 As a result of this procedural rule, the father in the case
    lost his parental rights in his children. In resolving this case, the
    Court explained that the “issue at stake [was] the dismemberment
    __________________________________________________________
    125   
    Pierce, 268 U.S. at 534
    .
    126   
    Yoder, 406 U.S. at 233
    .
    127   
    Troxel, 530 U.S. at 66
    (compiling cases).
    128   
    405 U.S. 645
    (1972).
    129
    Id. at 647.
    34
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                               Opinion of the Court
    of [the father’s] family.”130 And throughout the opinion, it referred
    to the right or interest at issue variously as the interest “of a man in
    the children he has sired and raised,”131 as the “rights to conceive
    and to raise one’s children,”132 as the right of “custody, care and
    nurture of the child,”133 and as an interest in the “integrity of the
    family unit.”134 So the Court did not narrowly frame the right by
    defining it as a right to be free from a particular procedural rule, as
    the dissent would have us do here. Instead, it described the right
    broadly, and more accurately, to encompass all of the interests in
    parental conduct the father would have lost were the state’s
    “method of procedure” upheld.
    ¶75 The Court treated the relevant parental conduct similarly
    in Quilloin v. Walcott.135 There the issue presented was once again
    whether a state could “force the breakup of a natural family”
    through a procedural mechanism that provided fewer protections
    to unmarried fathers than it did to mothers.136 Although, based on
    the father’s unmarried status, the Court ultimately upheld this
    procedure as constitutional, the Court consistently referred to the
    interest at issue in the case as an interest to engage generally in
    parental conduct.137 So the decision in Quilloin likewise suggests
    that, in parental rights termination cases, we must take a broad
    view of the relevant parental conduct.138
    ¶76 Our past parental rights termination cases have also
    described the parental conduct in broad terms. For example, in one
    __________________________________________________________
    130
    Id. at 658.
       131
    Id. at 651.
       132
    Id. 133 Id.
       134
    Id. 135 434
    U.S. 246 (1978).
    136
    Id. at 255
    (citation omitted).
    137
    Id. (describing the
    parental right as an interest in having a
    “relationship between parent and child”).
    138 See also Lehr v. Robertson, 
    463 U.S. 248
    , 256–58 (1983)
    (discussing the parental right variously as an interest in the
    “intangible fibers that connect parent and child,” “family
    relationships,” and as including fundamental rights previously
    recognized by Supreme Court precedent).
    35
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    of our earliest parental rights termination cases, In re J.P., we
    emphasized that the case “involve[d] a permanent termination of
    all parental rights.”139 And we explained that “all parental rights”
    included fundamental rights “to sustain [a parent’s] relationship
    with his [or her] child,” “to direct the upbringing and education of
    children,” and a right in “the custody, care and nurture of the
    child.”140 So, consistent with the Supreme Court precedent, we
    characterized the type of “parental conduct” at issue in parental
    rights termination cases in broad terms.
    ¶77 Following our decision in In re J.P., our decisions in
    parental rights termination cases have consistently referred to the
    relevant parental conduct in broad terms. For example, in Wells v.
    Children’s Aid Society of Utah, we stated broadly that the
    “relationship between parent and child is protected by the federal
    and state constitutions.”141 And in In re adoption of J.S., we
    acknowledged “a fundamental right for a mother not to lose her
    rights to her child absent proof of unfitness, abandonment, or
    neglect,”142 as well as the fundamental parental interest that a
    father has “in the children he has sired and raised.”143 We also cited
    our decision in In re J.P. for the proposition that the “integrity of the
    family and the parents’ inherent right and authority to rear their own
    children have been recognized as fundamental axioms of
    Anglo-American culture, presupposed by all our social, political,
    and legal institutions.”144 As these cases illustrate, in parental rights
    termination cases, we have consistently described the relevant
    parental conduct protected by the Due Process Clause in broad
    terms.145 And in defining parental conduct, we have never defined
    __________________________________________________________
    
    139 648 P.2d at 1366
    .
    140
    Id. at 1372.
       
    141 681 P.2d at 202
    .
    142   
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 38.
    143
    Id. ¶ 40
    (citation omitted).
    144
    Id. ¶ 39
    (emphasis added).
    145The dissent relies on our decision in In re adoption of J.S. to
    argue that we must narrowly frame the relevant “conduct” at issue.
    But the narrow framing at issue in that case did nothing to limit the
    scope of relevant parental conduct. Instead, it more narrowly
    construed the parental status—to exclude unmarried fathers who
    (Continued)
    36
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Opinion of the Court
    it, as the dissent does in this case, by referencing the particular form
    of governmental interference. Accordingly, the level-of-generality
    problem identified by the dissent is not at issue in this case, and the
    dissent’s purported framing of the relevant conduct in this case is
    inconsistent with our case law.
    ¶78 In sum, Supreme Court precedent makes clear that
    parental rights should be characterized based on (1) the status of
    the individual invoking the right and (2) the parental conduct to be
    protected. The dissent’s characterization of the right, in contrast,
    defines the right in reference to the form of governmental
    interference. In other words, rather than asking whether Mother, as
    K.T.B.’s biological mother, has a constitutionally protected interest
    in engaging in any of the conduct inherent in the parent-child
    relationship, the dissent asks whether Mother has a constitutionally
    protected interest in being free from a particular form of
    governmental interference. Because such a characterization of the
    right at issue is inconsistent with our case law, and would lead us
    to entirely overlook the substantial parental interests at the heart of
    this case, we reject it.
    b. The dissent errs in failing to distinguish between the
    constitutionally protected status of biological mothers and
    the provisional parental status of unmarried biological
    fathers
    ¶79 Additionally, we also reject the dissent’s characterization
    of the right at issue in this case because it fails to account for a key
    distinction between the nature of the rights of a biological mother
    and the rights of an unmarried biological father. As we have
    __________________________________________________________
    had not perfected their parental rights—deserving full due process
    protection. See
    id. ¶ 2
    (“Unwed mothers acquire parental rights—
    and the accompanying right to object to an adoption—as a result of
    the objective manifestation of the commitment to the child that is
    demonstrated by their decision to carry a child to term. An unwed
    father’s legal obligation to file the paternity affidavit is a rough
    counterpart to the mother’s commitment.”). So our decision in In re
    adoption of J.S. merely reaffirmed an important distinction, based on
    parental status, between mothers and unmarried fathers that had
    previously been established in our case law. See In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1374
    –75 (distinguishing between the variation in the protections
    afforded unwed fathers before noting that, “[i]n contrast, no similar
    variation exists among mothers who are unwed”).
    37
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    discussed, parental rights should be defined based, in part, on the
    status of the individual invoking the right. And our case law has
    firmly established a clear distinction between the parental status of
    mothers and unmarried fathers. But, despite this, the dissent
    attempts to apply unmarried father cases to the facts of this case.
    Because the case law clearly establishes that mothers have a
    “retained” fundamental right in their children, whereas unmarried
    fathers have only provisional rights that must be perfected through
    compliance with procedure or some other means, the dissent’s
    argument fails.146
    ¶80 We first addressed the distinction between the nature of
    the parental rights of a mother and an unmarried biological father
    in In re J.P.147 In that case, we considered an unmarried biological
    mother’s challenge to a statute that permitted a court to “decree an
    involuntary termination of all parental rights solely on the basis of
    a finding that such termination will be in the child’s best
    interest.”148 We began our review of the mother’s challenge by
    summarizing the United States Supreme Court’s decisions in
    Stanley and Quilloin as standing for the proposition that “[s]ome
    variation [in the protection provided by the Due Process Clause]
    exists among unwed fathers.”149
    ¶81 So, under the rule established in those decisions, we
    explained that unwed fathers “who have fulfilled a parental role
    over a considerable period of time are entitled to a high degree of
    protection” but “unwed fathers whose relationships to their
    children are merely biological or very attenuated may, in some
    __________________________________________________________
    146  In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1375
    (explaining that the right of a
    mother “not to be deprived of parental rights without a showing of
    unfitness, abandonment, or substantial neglect is so fundamental
    to our society and so basic to our constitutional order . . . that it
    ranks among those rights referred to in Article I, [section] 25 of the
    Utah Constitution and the Ninth Amendment of the United States
    Constitution as being retained by the people.” (emphasis added)
    (citation omitted)); see also
    id. at 1372
    (explaining that a mother “has
    a fundamental right, protected by the Constitution, to sustain [her]
    relationship with [her] child” (citation omitted) (internal quotation
    marks omitted)).
    147
    Id. at 1374
    –75.
    
       148
    Id. at 1374
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    149
    Id. 38 Cite
    as: 
    2020 UT 51
                               Opinion of the Court
    circumstances, be deprived of their parental status merely on the
    basis of a finding of the ‘best interest’ of the child.”150 Thus the
    nature of an unmarried father’s right may vary from case to case
    depending on what the father has done to develop a relationship
    with his child.151
    ¶82 But in contrast to unwed fathers, we explained that “no
    similar variation exists among mothers who are unwed” and that
    “all unwed mothers are entitled to a showing of unfitness before
    being involuntarily deprived of their parental rights.” 152 And we
    explained that this right “is so fundamental to our society and so
    basic to our constitutional order . . . that it ranks among those rights
    . . . retained by the people.”153
    ¶83 So our discussion of parental rights in In re J.P. makes clear
    that only unmarried fathers need comply with procedural
    mechanisms to perfect their parental rights. In other words, the
    parental status of all biological mothers, whether married or
    unmarried, gives mothers a right to not “be deprived of parental
    rights without a showing of unfitness, abandonment, or substantial
    neglect,” and this right is not contingent upon compliance with any
    procedural requirement that the state may establish. Accordingly,
    the dissent’s discussion of Mother’s rights in this case is
    inconsistent with our holding in In re J.P.
    ¶84 The dissent’s discussion of Mother’s rights is also
    inconsistent with our holding in In re Adoption of J.S.154 As our
    discussion of In re J.P. above makes clear, an unmarried father’s
    parental right is “merely provisional” until the father takes steps to
    perfect it. And in In re Adoption of J.S., we considered an unwed
    __________________________________________________________
    150
    Id. at 1375.
       151  We note that in later cases we have clarified that an
    unmarried father may perfect his right by complying with certain
    provisions in the Adoption Act, which include such requirements
    as filing an affidavit of paternity. See, e.g., In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 2 (explaining that the provision describing a paternity
    affidavit “prescribes the requirements that an unwed father must
    meet in order to secure the right to assert his parental rights and
    object to an adoption”).
    152   In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1375
    .
    153
    Id. (emphasis added).
       154   
    2014 UT 51
    .
    39
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    father’s challenge to provisions in the Adoption Act that provided
    a procedural mechanism for unwed fathers to perfect their parental
    rights.155 Echoing the distinction between mothers and unmarried
    biological fathers we made in In re J.P., we explained that “[u]nwed
    mothers acquire parental rights—and the accompanying right to
    object to an adoption—as a result of the objective manifestation of
    the commitment to the child that is demonstrated by their decision
    to carry a child to term.”156 But with unmarried fathers there is no
    such “objective manifestation,” so the father’s “legal obligation to
    file the paternity affidavit” described in the Adoption Act serves as
    “a rough counterpart to the mother’s [objective] commitment” to
    her child.157 Based on this distinction, we stated that a child may be
    placed for adoption only “if the mother and father choose to waive
    [their parental] right[s]—or in the case of a father, fails to assert the
    right by filing the paternity affidavit in a timely fashion.”158 So our
    decision in In re Adoption of J.S. recognized that the vested nature of
    a mother’s parental rights meant that only unmarried fathers could
    lose their rights to their children by failing to comply with
    state-instituted procedure.
    ¶85 With this distinction in mind, we proceeded to the merits
    of the unmarried father’s claim. After noting that the father had not
    brought a procedural due process claim, we then proceeded to
    analyze the Adoption Act’s paternity affidavit requirement under
    a substantive due process analysis.159 In so doing, we noted that
    procedural limitations “may be challenged on either procedural or
    substantive due process grounds.”160 And that a substantive due
    process claim may be brought where otherwise fair procedures are
    __________________________________________________________
    155
    Id. ¶ 2
    .
    
       156
    Id. By “saying
    that the established procedures determine how
    and whether [Mother’s parental] right is preserved,” the dissent
    fails to account for this key distinction. Infra ¶ 205 (Lee, A.C.J.,
    dissenting).
    157   In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 2.
    158
    Id. (emphases added).
       159
    Id. ¶ 6.
       160
    Id. ¶ 2
    2 
    (emphases omitted).
    40
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                           Opinion of the Court
    alleged to be unfair in light of the “fundamental or important” right
    they foreclose.161
    ¶86 We then analyzed the nature of the right of the unmarried
    father. Although we recognized that we had already determined
    that the parental rights of mothers are fundamental (in In re J.P.),
    we clarified that this labeling had been limited to mothers because
    of “extensive historical evidence of the ‘deeply rooted’ nature of [a
    mother’s] right.”162 A plurality of the court then noted that the
    father in the case had not made the “required showing of ‘deeply
    rooted’ history and tradition [that] was made in J.P. [regarding the
    rights of mothers],”163 and so, absent such a showing, the father’s
    substantive due process claim would be reviewed on the
    “deferential, fallback standard of rationality or arbitrariness.”164
    Accordingly, our discussion of parental rights in In re Adoption of
    J.S. clarified that the parental rights of mothers are fundamental,
    requiring strict scrutiny analysis, but the parental rights of
    unmarried fathers are merely provisional, absent some future
    showing of “extensive historical evidence” that unmarried father’s
    rights are likewise fundamental.
    ¶87 As this discussion of In re J.P. and In re Adoption of J.S.
    demonstrates, our case law has established a significant distinction
    between the parental rights of unmarried biological mothers and
    unmarried biological fathers. Under this distinction, the
    fundamental parental rights of a mother are not contingent on
    compliance with any procedural requirements that may be
    imposed by the state. Because the dissent’s characterization of the
    right at issue, and its discussion of our previous cases, fails to
    adequately account for this significant distinction, its argument
    fails.
    ¶88 In fact, even though the dissent concedes that Mother,
    based on her parental status as a biological mother, did not need to
    strictly comply with the procedures in the Adoption Act to render
    her parental rights fundamental, it nevertheless argues that strict
    compliance was necessary to preserve the fundamental nature of her
    rights. So the dissent would create a novel framework in which a
    __________________________________________________________
    161   Id.
    162
    Id. ¶ 39
    .
    163
    Id. ¶ 54
    .
    
       164
    Id. ¶ 56.
    41
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    right, although concededly perfected and fundamental, can lose the
    protection of strict scrutiny review where the holder of the right
    fails to take on-going steps to preserve it. But the dissent cites no
    authority for such a framework. And our case law clearly refutes it.
    ¶89 Our case law makes clear that the fundamental parental
    right is a “retained”165 right that stems from “nature and human
    instinct,” which is “chronologically prior” to “state or federal
    statutory law.”166 It also states that the right includes a fundamental
    right for parents to “sustain” their relationships with their
    children.167 If these phrases mean anything, they mean that the
    fundamental nature of a recognized parental right does not lose its
    fundamental status because of a failure to comply with a
    procedural requirement instituted by the State.
    ¶90 To be clear, we are not suggesting that the state can never
    terminate a fundamental parental right based on the parent’s
    failure to comply with a statutory requirement. Instead, we are
    merely reaffirming the firmly established principle that where the
    state intervenes “to terminate [a parent-child] relationship,” that
    intervention, whether accomplished through the imposition of a
    procedural requirement or some other means, “must be
    accomplished by procedures meeting the requisites of the Due
    Process Clause.”168 Applying this principle in this case, we have
    concluded that the State’s termination of mother’s fundamental
    parental rights, based on her failure to strictly comply with a State-
    created procedural requirement, would be constitutional only if the
    procedural requirement is narrowly tailored to achieve a
    compelling state interest. The dissent’s criticism of this
    straightforward approach to substantive due process is misplaced.
    ¶91 Because the dissent fails to adequately account for a key
    distinction our case law has established between the status of
    biological mothers and unmarried biological fathers, it
    mischaracterizes the right at issue in this case. And the dissent’s
    attempts to defend this mischaracterization by proposing a
    theoretical framework in which the state could deprive an
    individual’s fundamental rights of strict-scrutiny protection
    __________________________________________________________
    165   In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1375
    .
    166
    Id. at 1373.
       167
    Id. at 1372.
       168   
    Lehr, 463 U.S. at 258
    (emphasis added) (citation omitted).
    42
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                               Opinion of the Court
    through the imposition of a preservation requirement is likewise
    inconsistent with our case law.
    ¶92 In sum, we reject the dissent’s characterization of the right
    at issue in this case because it incorrectly defines the right at issue
    based on the particular form the governmental interference takes
    and because it fails to adequately distinguish between the
    “retained” and fundamental nature of a mother’s parental rights
    and the merely provisional nature of an unmarried father’s rights.
    2. The dissent misapplies the doctrine of forfeiture in this case
    ¶93 The dissent’s mischaracterization of the right at issue in
    this case is also problematic because it leads to a misapplication of
    the doctrine of forfeiture to Mother’s due process claim. As
    discussed, the dissent argues that the right at issue in this case is
    not Mother’s indisputably fundamental right to parent, but her
    right to retain that fundamental right despite her noncompliance
    with the challenged procedural requirement. Based on this
    characterization, the dissent argues that we have established a new
    right “to flout a legal filing requirement but avoid the normal
    consequence of such a move”169 and that, under our approach, a
    fundamental right can never “be forfeited due to a procedural
    default.”170 But the dissent misreads our opinion. And its proposed
    alternative approach misapplies the doctrine of forfeiture in this
    case.
    ¶94 Contrary to the dissent’s characterization of our opinion,
    we are not suggesting that the “mere possession of a fundamental
    right . . . forever insulate[s] the mother from ever losing that
    right.”171 And we are not saying that fundamental rights are
    entirely “beyond the procedural reach of the State’s regulatory
    authority.”172 Instead, we are merely reaffirming the firmly
    established principle that where the state intervenes “to terminate
    [a parent-child] relationship,” that intervention, whether
    accomplished through the imposition of a procedural requirement
    or some other means, “must be accomplished by procedures meeting
    __________________________________________________________
    169   See infra ¶ 126 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting).
    170   See infra ¶ 133 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting).
    171   See infra ¶ 133 n.208 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting).
    172   See infra ¶ 163 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting).
    43
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    the requisites of the Due Process Clause.”173 In other words, we are
    stating only that the imposition of unconstitutional procedures, as
    applied to the fundamental right in this case, is beyond the
    regulatory authority of the State.
    ¶95 Based on this principle, we have analyzed the facts of this
    case to determine whether the procedural mechanism through
    which the state terminated Mother’s fundamental rights was
    constitutional. And, after a straightforward application of the
    Supreme Court’s strict scrutiny standard, we have determined that
    the strict compliance provision in section 110 of the Adoption Act
    was unconstitutionally applied in this case. In other words, we are
    saying that the enforcement of the strict compliance requirement
    violated the Due Process Clause because it triggered the loss of
    fundamental rights even though it was not necessary to further the
    State’s compelling adoption-related interests in this case. And we
    are saying that because the strict compliance provision violated the
    Due Process Clause, as it was applied to Mother, it cannot justify
    the State’s termination of Mother’s parental rights.
    ¶96 In contrast, the dissent argues that the state did not
    terminate any fundamental rights in this case, because Mother
    forfeited her rights when she failed to comply with the procedural
    requirements of the Act. But the dissent’s argument assumes,
    without analysis, that the procedural requirement that triggered
    Mother’s default was constitutional. In other words, the dissent
    avoids the central question presented by Mother’s substantive due
    process claim.
    ¶97 So, in effect, the dissent argues that the procedural
    requirement that authorized the state to terminate Mother’s
    fundamental parental rights is constitutional because Mother failed
    __________________________________________________________
    173
    Lehr, 463 U.S. at 258
    (emphasis added) (citation omitted). The
    dissent cites two cases, Yakus v. United States, 
    321 U.S. 414
    , 444
    (1944) and State v. Rettig, 
    2017 UT 83
    , ¶¶ 15, 17, 
    416 P.3d 520
    , for the
    proposition that constitutional rights may be forfeited through
    procedural default. We agree with this assertion. But neither Yakus
    nor Rettig stand for the proposition that a party can be barred from
    challenging an unconstitutional procedural requirement due to
    that party’s failure to comply with that unconstitutional
    requirement. That proposition would be inconsistent with “the
    longstanding law of procedural default.”
    44
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                             Opinion of the Court
    to comply with that procedure. This approach is not only circular,
    it is inconsistent with the doctrine of forfeiture.
    ¶98 Forfeiture “is not appropriate when it is inconsistent with
    the provision creating the right sought to be secured.”174 The
    relevant provision in this case is the Due Process Clause of the
    Constitution. As we explained above, the substantive component
    of the Due Process Clause allows plaintiffs to challenge the
    “fairness of [a] procedural bar or limitation, on the ground that the
    right foreclosed is so fundamental or important that it is protected
    from extinguishment.”175 And Due Process Clause case law has
    further clarified that “fundamental” rights may be extinguished
    through the operation of procedural provisions only where those
    provisions survive strict scrutiny review.176 So, in other words, the
    substantive component of the Due Process Clause protects
    individuals from being deprived of fundamental rights through the
    operation of procedures that are not narrowly tailored to further
    __________________________________________________________
    174 New York v. Hill, 
    528 U.S. 110
    , 116 (2000). Although the
    Supreme Court in Hill addresses the issue of express waiver, rather
    than forfeiture, the principle for which we cite Hill applies equally
    in forfeiture cases. Waiver is sometimes used as an umbrella term
    encompassing all statements and acts that result in any loss of a
    right without a disposition on the merits. And we note that the Hill
    Court supported its statement—that “waiver is not appropriate
    when it is inconsistent with the provision creating the right sought
    to be secured”—by citing a case that is best characterized as a
    forfeiture case.
    Id. at 116
    (citing Crosby v. United States, 
    506 U.S. 255
    ,
    258–59 (1993) (holding that a criminal defendant’s right to be
    present at the beginning of trial cannot be forfeited through a
    failure to be present)).
    175In re B.Y., 
    2015 UT 67
    , ¶ 41 (alteration in the original) (internal
    quotation marks omitted). So, by arguing that Mother is precluded
    from challenging the fairness of procedural bars on substantive due
    process grounds, the dissent would have us implicitly overturn the
    rule we established in In re B.Y.
    176 See, e.g., 
    Quilloin, 434 U.S. at 254
    –55 (applying a substantive
    due process analysis to a challenge of a procedural provision);
    
    Stanley, 405 U.S. at 650
    (applying a substantive due process analysis
    to an Illinois “procedure”).
    45
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    compelling state interests.177 And, as our analysis above
    demonstrates, the procedural requirements that triggered the loss
    of Mother’s fundamental parental rights were not narrowly
    tailored. So applying the doctrine of forfeiture to defeat Mother’s
    substantive due process claim in this case would be inconsistent
    with the Due Process Clause.
    ¶99 Because forfeiture “is not appropriate when it is
    inconsistent with the provision creating the right sought to be
    secured,”178 and the dissent’s proposed application of forfeiture in
    this case would be inconsistent with the substantive component of
    the Due Process Clause, we reject the dissent’s forfeiture argument.
    And in so doing, we clarify that the doctrine of forfeiture does not
    prevent an individual from challenging the constitutionality of a
    procedural requirement based on the individual’s failure to comply
    with that procedural requirement.
    ¶100 Accordingly, we reject the arguments the dissent raises
    for two reasons. First, we reject them because the dissent
    mischaracterizes the right at issue; second, we reject them because
    __________________________________________________________
    177 See also 
    Stanley, 405 U.S. at 647
    (applying the strict scrutiny
    standard where a state terminated a fundamental right through a
    “method of procedure”). The dissent states that strict scrutiny need
    not be applied in every instance in which a state terminates
    parental rights, but the only support for this position comes from
    cases far outside the parental rights field of law. The dissent argues
    that the “‘fundamental’ nature of a given right is not alone enough
    to trigger strict scrutiny of any procedural regulation of that right.”
    See infra ¶ 159 (Lee, A.C.J., dissenting). It then cites cases involving
    abortion rights, the right to free speech, the right to free exercise of
    religion, and the right to vote. See infra ¶ 159 (Lee, A.C.J.,
    dissenting). But we do not view these cases, in which the Supreme
    Court articulated exceptions to the general rule based on the
    unique nature of the right at issue, to be relevant to this case. This
    case deals with the termination of all parental rights of a biological
    mother. And controlling precedent has clearly set forth the
    standard of scrutiny to be applied where a state attempts to
    terminate all of a biological mother’s fundamental parental rights.
    For this reason, the cases the dissent cites from other areas of law
    are unpersuasive.
    178   
    Hill, 528 U.S. at 116
    .
    46
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Opinion of the Court
    the dissent misapplies the doctrine of forfeiture to the facts of this
    case.
    ¶101 In sum, Mother has fundamental parental rights. The
    district court severed those rights because Mother failed to strictly
    comply with the procedural requirements of section 110. Because
    the strict compliance provision in section 110 was not narrowly
    tailored, we hold that the strict compliance provision is
    unconstitutional as applied in this case.
    IV. J.N.’s Motion to Intervene was Properly Denied
    ¶102 We now turn to J.N.’s claim. He argues that he should
    have been allowed to intervene in the adoption proceedings after
    his marriage to Mother was judicially recognized. Although J.N.
    admits that he is not the biological father, he argues that due to his
    common-law marriage to Mother, he is K.T.B.’s presumptive
    father179 and therefore was entitled to notice of the adoption
    petition under section 120 of the Adoption Act. Because the
    Adoptive Parents did not serve him with notice, he contends that
    his motion to intervene was timely, and he was therefore entitled
    to intervene in the adoption proceeding under Rule 24 of the Utah
    Rules of Civil Procedure.180 We disagree.
    ¶103 At the time the Adoptive Parents filed their adoption
    petition, J.N.’s marriage to Mother had not been legally recognized.
    After the court barred Mother from the adoption proceeding, J.N.
    sought this recognition by filing an action in a different district
    court. He succeeded, and the second district court recognized his
    marriage as beginning “on or about June 16, 2010,” or three months
    __________________________________________________________
    179”A man is presumed to be the father of a child if . . . he and
    the mother of the child are married to each other and the child is
    born during the marriage.” UTAH CODE § 78B-15-204(1)(a).
    180UTAH R. CIV. P. 24 (“Upon timely application anyone shall be
    permitted to intervene in an action: (1) when a statute confers an
    unconditional right to intervene; or (2) when the applicant claims
    an interest relating to the property or transaction which is the
    subject of the action and he is so situated that the disposition of the
    action may as a practical matter impair or impede his ability to
    protect that interest, unless the applicant’s interest is adequately
    represented by existing parties.”).
    47
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    before the birth of K.T.B.181 With this judicial decree in hand, J.N.
    then filed his motion to intervene in this case. The district court
    denied his motion, in part, because it was untimely.
    ¶104 On appeal, J.N. argues that at the time the adoption
    petition was filed, his marriage to Mother—which, according to the
    subsequent judicial marriage decree, began on June 16, 2010—
    created a presumption that he is K.T.B.’s father, thereby entitling
    him to notice of the adoption. He reasons that because he never
    received notice of the adoption proceeding, section 110’s thirty-day
    time period to intervene was never triggered. Thus he argues his
    motion to intervene was timely, and he was therefore entitled to
    intervene under rule 24.
    ¶105 In support of his argument J.N. cites our decision in
    Whyte v. Blair.182 In Whyte we held that once a common-law
    marriage is legally recognized it can have retroactive legal effect
    from the time the marriage was entered.183 But contrary to J.N.’s
    assertion, Whyte did not answer the question of whether a
    common-law marriage entitles a couple to state-recognized marital
    rights in the absence of a judicial decree. That question is answered
    by the plain language of Utah Code section 30-1-4.5, Utah’s
    common-law marriage statute.
    ¶106 Under section 30-1-4.5, a person may seek legal
    recognition of a common-law marriage by obtaining a judicial or
    administrative order. Once this occurs, a common-law marriage “is
    treated as any other marriage for all purposes.”184 And as our
    decision in Whyte makes clear, these marital rights may apply
    retroactively once they are recognized.185 But the plain language of
    two provisions within section 30-1-4.5 also makes it clear that the
    marital rights stemming from a common-law marriage are merely
    __________________________________________________________
    181 In their opposition on appeal, the Adoptive Parents allege
    that J.N. failed to notify the second district court of the adoption
    pending in this case, as required by rule 100 of the Utah Rules of
    Civil Procedure. Although such a failure could seriously
    undermine the validity of J.N.’s marriage decree, we do not address
    it here because the marriage decree has not been appealed.
    182   
    885 P.2d 791
    (Utah 1994).
    183
    Id. at 793–94.
       184
    Id. at 793.
       185   See generally
    id. 48 Cite
    as: 
    2020 UT 51
                              Opinion of the Court
    conditional unless they have been legally recognized through a
    judicial or administrative order.
    ¶107 First, section 30-1-4.5(1) states that a common-law
    marriage “shall be legal and valid if a court or administrative order
    establishes that it arises out of a contract between a man and a
    woman”       who     satisfy   certain     common-law       marriage
    requirements. 186 Thus, by negative implication, a common-law
    marriage is not legal and valid in the absence of such an order.
    ¶108 Second,       section 30-1-4.5(2)    states    that  “[t]he
    determination or establishment of a [common-law] marriage shall
    occur during the relationship . . . or within one year following the
    termination of that relationship.” So if a couple terminates a
    relationship that would have qualified as a common-law marriage,
    but fails to obtain judicial recognition of that relationship within
    one year of termination, then any marital rights the couple could
    have enjoyed through legal recognition are forfeited. In other
    words, if a couple fails to perfect marital rights stemming from a
    common-law marriage within the one-year limitations period, it is
    as if the marriage never occurred.
    ¶109 These two aspects of section 30-1-4.5 suggest that the
    rights stemming from a common-law marriage must be perfected
    through a judicial proceeding before those rights take legal effect.
    This makes sense. “[M]arriage is a keystone of our social order.”187
    For this reason, when “a couple vows to support each other, so does
    society pledge to support the couple, offering symbolic recognition
    and material benefits to protect and nourish the union.” 188 In this
    way, marital status serves as a basis for the conferral of a number
    of “governmental rights, benefits, and responsibilities,” including
    rights in the areas of adoption and child custody.189 But the state
    cannot confer these rights on a married couple unless the married
    couple makes their marital status known to it. And the inverse is
    also true: a married couple living in an as-of-yet unrecognized
    common-law marriage cannot obligate the state to respect rights
    __________________________________________________________
    186   UTAH CODE § 30-1-4.5(1) (emphasis added).
    187   Obergefell v. Hodges, 
    135 S. Ct. 2584
    , 2601 (2015).
    188
    Id. 189Id.; see
    also Sanchez v. L.D.S. Soc. Servs., 
    680 P.2d 753
    , 755 (Utah
    1984) (“Marriage is the institution established by society for the
    procreation and rearing of children.”).
    49
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    stemming from that marriage until it has been legally
    recognized.190 But this is essentially what J.N. is asking the court to
    do.
    ¶110 At the time of the Adoptive Parents’ adoption petition,
    J.N.’s marital rights, including rights to notice or to intervene in the
    adoption as a presumptive father, had not been legally recognized
    by the State.191 Additionally, because J.N. admits that he is not
    K.T.B.’s biological father, he also did not have any rights in the
    adoption as K.T.B.’s putative father.192 J.N.’s lack of any legally
    recognized rights in K.T.B. at the time the Adoptive Parents filed
    their petition ultimately defeats his claim.
    __________________________________________________________
    190  See State v. Holm, 
    2006 UT 31
    , ¶ 32, 
    137 P.3d 726
    (“[Because]
    a marriage license represents a contract between the State and the
    individuals entering into matrimony . . . [the defendant], as a result
    of his [unsanctioned marriage] ceremony with [his alleged spouse],
    [is] not entitled to any legal benefits attendant to a state-sanctioned
    marriage.”).
    191  Similar to our holding in Scott v. Scott, we find that the
    relevant date for consideration is the date the adoption petition was
    filed. 
    2017 UT 66
    , ¶ 30, 
    423 P.3d 1275
    (requiring an ex-spouse to be
    cohabitating with a boyfriend at the time the petition to terminate
    alimony was filed); see also Grupo Dataflux v. Atlas Glob. Grp., L.P.,
    
    541 U.S. 567
    , 571 (2004) (“[J]urisdiction of the court depends upon
    the state of things at time of the action brought. . . . . [The time-of-
    filing rule] measures all challenges to subject-matter jurisdiction
    premised upon diversity of citizenship against the state of facts that
    existed at the time of filing.” (internal quotation marks omitted));
    Int’l Trading Corp. v. Edison, 
    109 F.2d 825
    , 826 (D.C. Cir. 1939)
    (requiring a “duty [to] exist at the time of filing a petition for
    mandamus”); Koch v. Carmona, 
    643 N.E.2d 1376
    , 1381 (Ill. App. Ct.
    1994) (evaluating an attorney’s conduct “under the circumstances
    existing at the time of the filing”).
    192 See In re Baby Girl T., 
    2012 UT 78
    , ¶ 11, 
    298 P.3d 1251
    (“[A]n
    unwed father’s biological connection to his child does not
    automatically grant him a fundamental constitutional right to
    parenthood. Rather, an unwed father has a provisional right to
    parenthood, and due process requires only that an unwed father
    have a meaningful chance to preserve his opportunity to develop a
    relationship with his child.” (citation omitted) (internal quotation
    marks omitted)).
    50
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                              Opinion of the Court
    ¶111 The crux of J.N.’s argument is his assertion that the
    Adoptive Parents were obligated to provide him with notice as a
    presumptive father. According to him, their failure to do so
    prevented the Adoption Act’s thirty-day intervention window
    from beginning and so his motion to intervene, filed nearly four
    months after the petition, was timely. But because he did not have
    any presumptive rights at that time, neither the Adoptive Parents
    nor anyone else was obligated to serve notice on him. So we must
    determine whether J.N., as merely a potential presumptive father,
    had a duty to timely intervene in the adoption proceeding despite
    the lack of notice. He did.
    ¶112 Although the Adoption Act does not establish
    requirements with which a merely potential presumptive father
    must comply before intervening in an adoption, we find that
    certain requirements the Adoption Act imposes on a potential
    biological father are applicable. Under the Adoption Act, an
    unmarried biological father “has a duty to protect his own rights
    and interests” by filing the necessary documents before relevant
    deadlines.193 If he does so, he preserves a right to notice and to
    intervene in the adoption.194 But until then, he “is considered to be
    on notice that . . . an adoption proceeding regarding the child may
    occur.”195 Although the method for protecting his rights differs
    from that of an unmarried biological father,196 placing the burden
    __________________________________________________________
    193   UTAH CODE § 78B-6-110(1)(a)(ii).
    194
    Id. § 78B-6-
    110(3).
    
       195
    Id. § 78B-6-
    110(1)(a)(i); 
    see also In re Baby Girl T., 
    2012 UT 78
    ,
    ¶ 11 (“The Act’s requirements operate under the presumption that
    an unwed father knows that his ‘child may be adopted without his
    consent unless he strictly complies with the provisions of [the
    Act].’” (alteration in original) (citing UTAH CODE § 78B-6-102(6)(f))).
    196 We note that a potential presumptive father could protect his
    right to notice of an adoption by obtaining judicial recognition of
    his common-law marriage before an adoption petition is filed or he
    could protect his right to intervene by obtaining a judicial marriage
    decree, either within the adoption proceeding or as part of another
    case, within thirty days of the date on which the adoption petition
    was filed. Additionally, we note that in most cases section 110(2)(g)
    would guarantee a potential presumptive father the right to notice
    even in the absence of a judicial marriage decree because he would
    (Continued)
    51
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Opinion of the Court
    on J.N., as a potential presumptive father with no legally
    recognized parental rights, is equally appropriate.
    ¶113 Due to the unperfected nature of J.N.’s presumptive
    parental rights, he was responsible to take necessary steps to
    preserve his rights in the adoption. Had he done so by obtaining
    judicial recognition of his marriage before the Adoptive Parents
    filed their adoption petition, the Adoptive Parents would have
    been obligated to provide him with notice and he would have had
    thirty days to file a motion to intervene upon receipt of such
    notice.197 But in the absence of a legally recognized marriage, the
    Adoptive Parents had no such obligation, and so J.N. was
    considered to be on notice of the adoption proceeding once the
    Adoptive Parents filed their petition.198 This presumed notice
    initiated the Adoption Act’s thirty-day intervention window.199
    __________________________________________________________
    have been living in the same home as the child and holding himself
    out to be the child’s father. UTAH CODE § 78B-6-110(2)(g) (requiring
    notice to be served on “a person who is . . . openly living in the
    same household with the child at the time . . . and . . . [is] holding
    himself out to be the child’s father”). J.N. does not argue that he
    was entitled to notice under this provision.
    197J.N. argues that at the time the petition was filed he could not
    have intervened because his marriage had not yet been judicially
    recognized. Not only does this argument undermine J.N.’s
    contention that his common-law marriage was legally effective at
    the time the adoption proceeding commenced, but it also ignores
    the fact that he could have sought judicial recognition of his
    marriage within this case.
    198 We note that to hold otherwise would retroactively impose a
    burden on the Adoptive Parents as well as inject unnecessary delay
    and uncertainty into the adoption proceeding. This is something
    we seek to avoid. See
    id. § 78B-6-102(6)(c)
    (“A certain degree of
    finality is necessary in order to facilitate the state’s compelling
    interest. The Legislature finds that the interests of the state, the
    mother, the child, and the adoptive parents described in this section
    outweigh the interest of an unmarried biological father who does
    not timely grasp the opportunity to establish and demonstrate a
    relationship with his child in accordance with the requirements of
    this chapter.”).
    199 See UTAH R. CIV. P. 24(a) (granting an intervention of right
    only if there is a “timely application” to intervene).
    52
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                    Petersen, J., concurring in the result
    Because J.N. failed to file a motion to intervene within this time, his
    motion was untimely and the district court had the discretion to
    deny it. Accordingly, we affirm the district court’s denial of J.N.’s
    motion to intervene.
    Conclusion
    ¶114 Because section 110 of Utah’s Adoption Act authorized
    the district court to terminate Mother’s fundamental right to parent
    her child, we review its application to Mother under our strict
    scrutiny standard. And under this standard, section 110’s strict
    compliance requirement, as applied to Mother, is not narrowly
    tailored to achieve the state’s compelling interest in prompt
    adoption proceedings. Accordingly, we reverse the district court’s
    decision to bar Mother from the adoption proceeding and remand
    for a new hearing in which Mother may participate. Additionally,
    we affirm the district court’s decision to deny J.N.’s motion to
    intervene because his motion was untimely.
    JUSTICE PETERSEN, concurring in the result:
    ¶115 I concur in the result of the majority opinion. And I agree
    with much of the majority’s analysis. But the dissent raises some
    concerns that I share, which the majority has not sufficiently
    answered.200
    ¶116 I agree with the majority that Mother has parental rights,
    which are fundamental. And as a general matter, a state
    infringement of a fundamental right is subject to heightened
    scrutiny. Further, substantive due process principles are applicable
    to laws of both a substantive and a procedural nature. See, e.g., In re
    Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶¶ 21–22, 
    358 P.3d 1009
    . So I do not find
    it inappropriate to apply such principles here. But I do find our
    application of strict scrutiny to a straightforward preservation rule
    to be novel. Because of this, I think we should acknowledge that we
    __________________________________________________________
    200 I also agree with the dissent’s observation that “[t]his court
    may well have the authority to prescribe a procedural default rule
    that could govern in a case like this one,” see infra ¶ 123 n.201,
    pursuant to our constitutional power to “adopt rules of procedure
    and evidence to be used in the courts of the state,” see UTAH CONST.
    art. VIII, § 4. But as the dissent notes, Mother did not raise this
    issue.
    53
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    are applying strict scrutiny in a new context and clarify the
    parameters of our holding.
    ¶117 The majority asserts that its reasoning follows directly
    from established precedent. See, e.g., supra ¶¶ 62, 76, 78. But neither
    the majority nor Mother has identified any case where we or the
    United States Supreme Court has applied heightened scrutiny to a
    rule of preservation. And that is what we have here. As the dissent
    rightly observes, “[t]his is a rule of preservation—a law prescribing
    the form or timing of an objection necessary for a litigant to proceed
    with the assertion of her legal rights.” Infra ¶ 122.
    ¶118 In my view, applying strict scrutiny to a rule of
    preservation for the first time is significant because, as the dissent
    notes, “[s]uch rules abound in our law.” Infra ¶ 122. And they
    perform a critical function. At a very basic level, they set the rules
    for the orderly processing of civil and criminal litigation. But the
    majority insists we are not breaking new ground.
    ¶119 I think we should acknowledge that we are. First, we
    should recognize that we have never applied heightened scrutiny
    to a standard rule of preservation. And we should explain why we
    are extending strict scrutiny to this context.
    ¶120 Second, we should clarify the parameters of our holding.
    This decision could be read to apply to the many deadlines, filing
    requirements, and other rules of preservation found throughout
    the law, including in our own rules of procedure. Certainly, these
    rules at times affect litigants’ fundamental rights if they fail to
    comply with them. Even though this case involves an as-applied
    challenge ostensibly confined to its facts, this does not sufficiently
    define the reach of our holding. The material facts here would seem
    to be present whenever a litigant could establish that she had a
    fundamental right of some kind, and it was terminated by a
    preservation rule with which she substantially complied but did
    not fully comply. As it is, the majority’s holding seems open-ended.
    In light of the ubiquity of preservation rules and the core function
    they perform in our legal system, this has the potential to create
    confusion.
    ASSOCIATE CHIEF JUSTICE LEE, dissenting:
    ¶121 The Utah Adoption Act requires a mother who wishes to
    oppose the adoption of her biological child to file a motion to
    intervene in the adoption proceedings. See UTAH CODE
    § 78B-6-110(6). By statute, the mother must “strictly comply” with
    54
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                           Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    this requirement.
    Id. § 78B-6-
    110(6)(b). 
    Failure to do so within thirty
    days of being served with notice of the proceedings results in a
    “forfeit[ure]” of the mother’s parental rights.
    Id. § 78B-6-
    110(6)(b)(ii).
    ¶122 This is a rule of preservation—a law prescribing the form
    or timing of an objection necessary for a litigant to proceed with the
    assertion of her legal rights. Such rules abound in our law. And the
    long-established consequence of the failure to follow such rules is
    a procedural default, with a resulting loss of the underlying right.
    ¶123 The majority opposes this effect of the Adoption Act. It
    overrides the plain text of the statute, excuses the mother from her
    procedural default, and adopts a new rule of preservation of its
    own making—a rule that allows a mother to avoid forfeiture of her
    rights if she files a document that “fulfill[s] the purpose[]” of a
    motion to intervene.201 Supra ¶ 47.
    ¶124 I respectfully dissent from this decision. The court claims
    to find support for it in a body of substantive due process case law.
    But the court’s holding does not follow from that case law. It is a
    bold, policy-driven override of a law enacted by the legislature. I
    dissent because I find no basis for today’s decision in the due
    __________________________________________________________
    201  This court may well have the authority to prescribe a
    procedural default rule that could govern in a case like this one. See
    UTAH CONST. art. VIII, § 4 (recognizing this court’s power to “adopt
    rules of procedure and evidence to be used in the courts of the
    state”); State v. Rettig, 
    2017 UT 83
    , ¶¶ 58, 58 n.12, 
    416 P.3d 520
    (strongly suggesting that filing deadlines triggering procedural
    default or forfeiture of legal rights are “procedural” and thus
    within our constitutional power to establish). The Adoption Act’s
    default rule, moreover, may be subject to constitutional challenge
    on the ground that it is procedural and the legislature has not
    properly exercised its authority to amend our rules. See Rettig, 
    2017 UT 83
    , ¶¶ 52, 60 (expressing “doubts” about whether a statutory
    rule of procedural default would withstand scrutiny under article
    VIII, section 4 of the Utah Constitution but declining to reach the
    question because it had not been raised); Brown v. Cox, 
    2017 UT 3
    ,
    ¶¶ 17–18, 
    387 P.3d 1040
    (identifying the process the legislature
    must follow to amend our rules). This court has not enacted any
    such rule, however. And the mother has not raised a constitutional
    claim under article VIII, section 4. For that reason this question is
    not properly before us.
    55
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    process principles cited by the majority and foresee significant
    mischief caused by it.
    ¶125 The mother in this case failed to follow the statutory
    filing requirement. She did so not because of any difficulty in
    following the requirement, but because she got bad advice from her
    lawyer. The requirement, moreover, is admittedly fair and entirely
    constitutional as a matter of procedural due process. The majority
    agrees. 
    See supra
    ¶ 29 (citing In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 23,
    
    358 P.3d 1009
    for the proposition that “when the failure to comply
    with a ‘simple and straightforward’ procedural requirement is due
    to legal counsel’s mistake, the procedural requirement has not
    foreclosed meaningful access to the justice system”). 202 Yet the
    court proceeds to establish a new constitutional right of due
    process that excuses the mother’s procedural default. It holds that
    “mothers retain a fundamental right in their children regardless of
    a failure to comply with any state-prescribed procedure.”203 Supra
    ¶ 37.
    ¶126 The majority seeks to portray its decision as a matter that
    follows from settled precedent. But that is incorrect. No court, to
    __________________________________________________________
    202 The court’s procedural due process holding, in fact, follows
    from established principles of forfeiture. Most legal rights are
    subject to forfeiture by procedural default. See Yakus v. United
    States, 
    321 U.S. 414
    , 444 (1944) (noting that “constitutional right[s]
    may be forfeited in criminal as well as civil cases by the failure to
    make timely assertion of the right”); see also Rettig, 
    2017 UT 83
    ,
    ¶¶ 15, 17 (noting that “procedural bar[s]” such as rules “requir[ing]
    parties to raise issues or arguments at specified times and by certain
    means” on penalty of losing the right to do so are “commonplace”
    and “embedded in our case law” (citations omitted)). The due
    process right to be heard is no exception. If a party fails to avail
    herself of an established means of asserting a legal right, then that
    right is forfeited. Such a party is in no position to complain of the
    lack of a constitutionally guaranteed “opportunity to be heard” as
    that opportunity was lost not as a result of state action but by an act
    of the party’s agent (her counsel).
    203The mother asserts both federal and state grounds for a new
    right of substantive due process, supra ¶ 14 n.6, but the majority
    never draws any distinction between the two grounds in its
    opinion, and it relies exclusively on precedent pertaining to federal
    (Continued)
    56
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    my knowledge, has ever established a constitutional right of a
    litigant (even one seeking to protect a fundamental right) to flout a
    legal filing requirement but avoid the normal consequence of such
    a move (procedural default). Certainly the majority has not cited
    such a case. And with that in mind, the court should take
    ownership of the novelty of its decision. It is the court’s prerogative
    to establish new rights in the name of the constitution—the
    principle of substantive due process opens the door to such
    decisions. But in so doing the court cannot properly be viewed as
    merely endorsing a mechanical application of existing precedent.
    That is not what is going on here. The court is certainly citing a line
    of precedent. But its decision involves a significant extension of the
    cited cases. And the extension will sow the seeds of confusion in
    our law for years to come.
    ¶127 The court cites a string of cases (several from the United
    States Supreme Court and a few from this court) in which a parent’s
    fundamental right is framed on the basis of “(1) the status of the
    individual invoking the right and (2) the parental conduct to be
    protected.” Supra ¶ 59. Because the cited cases have “looked to the
    status of the individual and the conduct to be protected before
    determining whether the individual’s claim fell within the
    umbrella of parental rights” (which are admittedly fundamental),
    the court objects to my more specific framing of the inquiry into the
    asserted “right” in question. Supra ¶ 60. On that basis the majority
    seeks to turn my criticism of the novelty of its approach against me.
    It asserts that I am the one who is pressing a novel framing of the
    inquiry into fundamental parental rights. The court’s argument
    proceeds in two steps. First, the court complains that its cited cases
    ask only “whether parental conduct falls within the umbrella of
    protected parental rights,” not “whether parents have a recognized
    right to be free of . . . a judicially imposed forfeiture of all parental
    rights.” Supra ¶ 63. And because a mother’s parental rights need
    not be “perfected” in the manner required of unwed fathers, the
    majority next insists that the mother’s fundamental right “is not
    __________________________________________________________
    due process. So I presume that it is establishing a new right of
    federal due process.
    57
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    contingent upon compliance with any procedural requirement that
    the state may establish.” Supra ¶ 83.
    ¶128 Each of these points begins with a correct premise. But
    the court’s starting premises do not support its broad, sweeping
    conclusions.
    ¶129 On the first point, I can stipulate to a focus on “the status
    of the individual and the conduct to be protected” in deciding
    whether to endorse a new right of substantive due process. Supra
    ¶ 60. But that framing begs the question of what conduct, and at
    what level of generality to assess it. A broad framing would ask
    whether parental rights generally are subject to substantive due
    process protection. Yet that is not the only way to frame things. We
    could also look to the precise form of parental conduct at issue. And
    although the United States Supreme Court has not always been
    consistent on the appropriate framing, our recent precedent
    suggests a narrow framing that looks at the precise form of the
    relevant conduct.204
    ¶130 The United States Supreme Court has sometimes framed
    the inquiry into the existence of a new substantive due process right
    at the highest level of generality. When that court established new
    substantive due process rights to access contraception and
    abortion, for example, it framed the inquiry in broad, sweeping
    terms—whether there was an established tradition of respect for
    private decisions within a “zone of privacy.”205 But the Court’s case
    law has not been consistent. In other cases the court has called for
    a much narrower framing of the inquiry into the existence of a new
    substantive right. In rejecting a claim to a new right to
    physician-assisted suicide, for example, the court narrowly framed
    __________________________________________________________
    204 The majority’s “status” framing also runs into a line of United
    States Supreme Court precedent that cuts against its framework. In
    referring to “status,” the majority is noting that parental rights are
    fundamental. 
    See supra
    ¶¶ 60, 79. But the fundamental nature of a
    given right does not dictate the application of strict scrutiny to all
    regulations of that right. This is apparent from an important line of
    voting rights cases, which expressly reject the idea that all
    regulations of voting rights trigger strict scrutiny. See infra ¶¶ 159–
    61 (citing Burdick v. Takushi, 
    504 U.S. 428
    (1992) and Crawford v.
    Marion Cty. Election Bd., 
    553 U.S. 181
    (2008)).
    205See Roe v. Wade, 
    410 U.S. 113
    , 152–53 (1973); Griswold v.
    Connecticut, 
    381 U.S. 479
    , 484–85 (1965).
    58
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                             Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    the inquiry in terms of a “right to commit suicide” instead of the
    proposed broader framing of a “right to die.”206 This is a key,
    unresolved problem in the high court’s substantive due process
    precedent, and a question that has attracted the attention of a range
    of commentators. 207
    ¶131 A plurality of this court acknowledged this problem in
    our recent decision in In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , 
    358 P.3d 1009
    . And it endorsed a requirement of narrowly framing any new,
    alleged right of substantive due process. To avoid the prospect of a
    court making new policy in the guise of constitutional law-making,
    the lead opinion in J.S. (which was joined by Chief Justice Durrant)
    __________________________________________________________
    206  Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S 702, 722–23 (1997); see also
    id. (rejecting other
    broad framings of the right at issue, including
    the right to “choose how to die,” the right to “control of one’s final
    days,” the right to “choose a humane, dignified death,” and the
    right to “shape death”).
    207  See, e.g., Rick Kozell, Note, Striking the Proper Balance:
    Articulating the Role of Morality in the Legislative and Judicial Processes,
    47 AM. CRIM. L. REV. 1555, 1573 (2011) (explaining that “the Court
    has failed to articulate a method for determining the proper level
    of generality at which a substantive due process inquiry should be
    performed” despite the fact that “the level of generality with which
    the Court defines the conduct in question . . . often affects whether
    the Court finds that that conduct is entitled to protection based on
    history and tradition”); John F. Basiak, Jr., Inconsistent Levels of
    Generality in the Characterization of Unenumerated Fundamental
    Rights, 16 U. FLA. J.L. & PUB. POL’Y 401, 403 (2005) (pointing out that
    “when asked to recognize a fundamental right under the Due
    Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, the U.S. Supreme
    Court has failed to articulate a substantial justification for the level
    of generality in characterizing the legal issue” (citations omitted));
    David Crump, How do the Courts Really Discover Unenumerated
    Fundamental Rights? Cataloguing the Methods of Judicial Alchemy, 19
    HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL’Y 795, 863–71 (1996) (describing the dilemma
    as “[d]etermining the reach of fundamental rights by defining the
    degree of abstraction” for “characterizing the relevant tradition”);
    Laurence H. Tribe & Michael C. Dorf, Levels of Generality in the
    Definition of Rights, 57 U. CHI. L. REV. 1057, 1058 (1990) (rejecting a
    methodology that requires narrow framing of substantive due
    process rights while acknowledging that “[t]he selection of a level
    of generality necessarily involves value choices”).
    59
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    endorsed a requirement that a party make “a specific showing that
    the precise interest asserted by the parent is one that is deeply rooted
    in this Nation’s history and tradition and in the history and culture
    of Western civilization.”
    Id. ¶ 57
    (plurality opinion) (emphases
    added) (citation and internal quotation marks omitted). The
    “specific showing” of a “precise interest” suggested by J.S. is what
    I would require here—a showing not just of a well-rooted tradition
    of respect for parental rights generally, but of a tradition endorsing
    the right to retain parental rights without following procedural
    requirements set forth by law. The court’s contrary approach not
    only cuts against the lead opinion in J.S; it also picks sides in a key
    point of debate in the law of substantive due process.
    ¶132 The majority’s second point is similarly problematic. The
    notion that a mother’s rights need not be “perfected” in the manner
    required of unwed fathers is only half right. And the half-wrong
    part underscores the degree to which the majority is making new
    law while claiming only to be applying established precedent.
    ¶133 It is of course true that a mother need not make a
    threshold showing of her parentage to establish her fundamental
    parental rights in the first instance. A mother’s parental rights are
    perfected at the outset without any need for her to file a paternity
    petition or present evidence establishing the degree to which she
    supported or was willing to support her child. See
    Id. ¶ 2
    (majority
    opinion). To that extent the majority is right to say that a mother’s
    fundamental rights are not contingent on compliance with the
    “procedural requirement[s]” imposed by our law on fathers. Supra
    ¶ 83. But that is not the question presented here. The question here
    is whether a right that is admittedly perfected without the need for
    procedural compliance at one stage can ever be forfeited due to a
    procedural default at a later stage. The majority upholds that right
    as a matter of substantive due process. And in so doing it breaks
    significant new ground. No court has ever recognized this sort of
    right.208
    ¶134 It is true that I have cited no cases in which a biological
    mother forfeited her parental rights through procedural default,
    __________________________________________________________
    208The majority tries to avoid this characterization by describing
    the right at issue as the mother’s “‘retained’ fundamental right.”
    Supra ¶ 56. But asserting that a fundamental right is “retained”
    merely begs the question: retained as of when and by what acts?
    The mere possession of a fundamental right does not forever
    (Continued)
    60
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                           Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    and a court upheld such default against a substantive due process
    challenge. 
    See supra
    ¶ 79 (criticizing me for citing only cases
    involving putative fathers). But this is just a reflection of the fact
    that there are no reported cases that are directly on point—no case
    in which a mother forfeited her rights through procedural default,
    but a court excused that failure (and obviated her forfeiture) on the
    basis of a substantive due process right.
    ¶135 Our decision in J.S. is the most obviously relevant
    precedent. In that case an unmarried biological father lost his
    parental rights as a result of a procedural default—failure to perfect
    his rights by jumping through the procedural hoops required by
    our law (principally, the filing of an affidavit of support of his
    child). 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 1. And we upheld those procedures against a
    substantive due process challenge.
    Id. ¶¶ 5–6.
    In so doing, as noted
    above, we required more than a showing of a tradition of respect
    for the parental rights of fathers generally—for their “status” and
    “conduct” at that level of generality. Instead we required the
    defaulting parent to demonstrate that the right to retain parental
    rights despite failing to comply with required procedure is “deeply
    rooted” in “history and tradition.”
    Id. ¶ 54
    (plurality opinion). This
    is also the showing we should require here.
    ¶136 The procedure at issue in J.S. was admittedly not the sort
    of procedure that would be required of a mother for the
    preservation of her rights. The majority seizes on this point, noting
    that “mothers have a ‘retained’ fundamental right in their children,
    whereas unmarried fathers have only provisional rights that must
    be perfected through compliance with procedure.” Supra ¶ 79. But
    again, this is a partial truism. All parties to litigation are bound by
    __________________________________________________________
    insulate the mother from ever losing that right. It simply means that
    she retains it prior to the initiation of any legal proceedings. The
    majority concedes the general point—acknowledging that a
    fundamental right may be lost through procedural default. 
    See supra
    ¶ 98 (acknowledging that “’fundamental’ rights may be
    extinguished through the operation of procedural provisions . . .
    where those provisions survive strict scrutiny review”). It just
    obviates the forfeiture here through the doctrine of substantive due
    process. Supra ¶ 98. The court is holding that a mother has a
    fundamental right to retain her parental rights despite her
    procedural default because the underlying parental right itself is
    fundamental. But that is circular. And it is a novel, sweeping
    extension of existing case law.
    61
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    some procedure. And until today, no court had ever held that a
    fundamental parental right, once perfected, is subject only to those
    rules of procedure that can survive strict scrutiny review. The
    majority leans heavily on the “fundamental” nature of such rights
    to justify this result. But nowhere in the case law does the fact that
    a right is “fundamental” entitle its holder to forgo compliance with
    any procedure except that which withstands strict scrutiny. That
    conclusion certainly does not follow from the premise that the
    procedures necessary for a father’s perfection of his parental rights
    at the outset do not apply to mothers in the first instance.209
    ¶137 A mother is not required to jump through procedural
    hoops to establish her parental rights in the first instance. But that
    is not because mothers are categorically exempt from the law of
    procedure. It is because they are not subject to a specific species of
    procedure—paternity filing requirements imposed on putative
    fathers before their rights can be perfected. See UTAH CODE
    § 78B-6-121(3) (in contrast to biological mothers, the “consent of an
    unmarried biological father [to an adoption] is not required unless
    . . . the unmarried biological father . . . initiates proceedings . . . to
    establish paternity” and complies with other procedures). For that
    reason, the majority’s argument proves too much. Mothers are
    admittedly subject to some procedure. Rules of preservation in
    particular have always applied to all litigants. We cannot excuse a
    mother’s compliance with the law of preservation just because
    mothers are exempt from compliance with other procedures.
    ¶138 None of the majority’s cited cases is a case like this one—
    in which a parent’s rights were terminated as a result of the parent’s
    procedural default. The court’s cited cases stand for a threshold
    proposition that is not in dispute in this case. They say only that a
    person’s parental rights may not be terminated by operation of a
    law that cuts off the right to be heard and substitutes instead a
    __________________________________________________________
    209 It is true to a point that “the case law clearly establishes that
    mothers have a ‘retained’ fundamental right in their children.”
    Supra ¶ 79. But the key question is “retained” as of when, and in
    what procedural context? No prior court has ever established a
    mother’s right to retain her parental rights despite the kind of
    procedural default that would normally result in a forfeiture. So in
    that sense this case presents a question of first impression. I think
    the answer follows clearly from the framing of the inquiry in J.S.
    The majority concludes otherwise. But it cannot properly be heard
    to insist that its decision follows from established case law.
    62
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    conclusive presumption of unfitness. That is the holding of Quilloin
    v. Walcott, 
    434 U.S. 246
    (1978), Stanley v. Illinois, 
    405 U.S. 645
    (1972),
    and In re J.P., 
    648 P.2d 1364
    (Utah 1982). And that proposition has
    no purchase here. In this case the law did not authorize the
    termination of parental rights without an opportunity for a parent
    to be heard. It expressly provided for such an opportunity—and
    imposed a natural consequence (forfeiture by default) for the
    failure to comply with the required procedure. The question here,
    then, is whether a mother who lost her parental rights by forfeiture
    through procedural default may excuse that default by claiming a
    substantive due process right to ignore existing procedure (unless
    the procedure withstands strict scrutiny). And there is no support
    in any precedent for the establishment of such a right.
    ¶139 The court’s holding, in fact, runs directly counter to
    another line of precedent that the majority ignores. Voting rights
    are undoubtedly “fundamental” under a long line of United States
    Supreme Court authority. See Ill. State Bd. of Elections v. Socialist
    Workers Party, 
    440 U.S. 173
    , 184 (1979); Dunn v. Blumstein, 
    405 U.S. 330
    , 336 (1972); Williams v. Rhodes, 
    393 U.S. 23
    , 38 (1968); Yick Wo v.
    Hopkins, 
    118 U.S. 356
    , 370 (1886). But the United States Supreme
    Court has gone out of its way to emphasize that the fundamental
    nature of this right does not subject all procedural regulation of the
    right to strict scrutiny. See Burdick v. Takushi, 
    504 U.S. 428
    , 432–33
    (1992); Munro v. Socialist Workers Party, 
    479 U.S. 189
    , 193 (1986). In
    the voting rights realm, a neutral, nondiscriminatory regulation
    like a procedural default rule would not trigger strict scrutiny.
    Crawford v. Marion Cty. Election Bd., 
    553 U.S. 181
    , 203–04 (2008). It
    would trigger a deferential standard of scrutiny that would uphold
    the constitutionality of our neutral rules of procedural default. The
    same holds for regulation of other fundamental rights like the
    rights to privacy, free speech, and free exercise of religion. See infra
    ¶ 159 (discussing privacy, speech, and religion cases). And the
    majority’s holding today is incompatible with all of these cases. See
    infra ¶¶ 160–65 (discussing the voting rights cases).
    ¶140 The majority’s basis for a substantive due process right
    to avoid the usual effect (forfeiture) of a procedural default is thus
    as novel as it is sweeping. The court’s holding, moreover, will
    introduce substantial confusion and uncertainty going forward. If
    the majority opinion takes root, the whole idea of procedural
    regulation by a uniform set of rules will be placed in jeopardy. If
    our law requires case-by-case scrutiny of whether our procedural
    rules are the “least restrictive means” of advancing “compelling
    governmental interests,” most any procedural default rule may be
    63
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    set aside as unconstitutional. Most procedural rules, after all, are in
    a sense arbitrary. That means that there will almost always be a less
    restrictive means of advancing the underlying goal. And that will
    open the door for our courts to second-guess a broad range of rules
    of procedural default whenever our judges think that the purpose
    of a governing rule could be advanced in a less restrictive way. This
    is problematic.
    ¶141 I respectfully dissent for reasons explained in greater
    detail below. In Part I, I address the strict scrutiny argument—
    analyzing the cases cited in the mother’s brief and applied by the
    majority, outlining the standard applied to regulation of the
    fundamental right to vote, and emphasizing the novel extension of
    the law endorsed by the majority opinion. Then in Part II, I identify
    the confusion and upheaval that the majority’s framework will
    introduce into our law.
    I
    ¶142 The mother seeks to avoid the effects of forfeiture by
    asserting a substantive due process right. Yet she has failed to cite
    any precedent sustaining a substantive due process right to avoid
    the natural consequence (forfeiture) of a procedural default. And
    the majority opinion is similarly deficient.
    ¶143 The fulcrum of the majority opinion is the notion that the
    mother has “fundamental rights” as a parent. The mother’s brief is
    premised on the same notion. Citing In re J.P., 
    648 P.2d 1364
    (Utah
    1982) and Quilloin v. Walcott, 
    434 U.S. 246
    (1978), the mother asserts
    that the governing precedent “condemn[s] the termination of a
    mother’s parental rights over her objection and without a finding
    of unfitness.” And the majority correctly notes that the mother’s
    parental rights include the right to object to an adoption. Supra ¶ 37.
    ¶144 This is all correct as far as it goes. But the fundamental
    right recognized in the cited case law has no currency here. The
    mother’s rights were not terminated “over her objection.” She just
    failed to object under the procedures set forth in our law. The
    mother’s right to object to an adoption is not a right to object in any
    manner she chooses. It is a right to object in accordance with
    prescribed procedure. And the natural consequence of the failure
    to comply with that procedure is a default—forfeiture of her rights.
    ¶145 As the majority notes, our case law identifies a
    substantive due process basis for a party to establish an exception
    to this normal consequence—by providing proof of a “deeply
    rooted” history and tradition at a very specific level of generality.
    64
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                           Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    This is the standard set forth in In re J.P. and reinforced in J.S. But
    the mother has failed to carry her burden under these cases. She
    nowhere establishes a “deeply rooted” history and tradition of a
    right to preserve parental rights despite non-compliance with the
    procedure required by law. And her assertion of a substantive due
    process right accordingly fails.
    ¶146 The majority objects to this framing of the right at issue.
    It contends that we should focus on “the status of the individual
    invoking the right”210 and “the parental conduct to be protected,”
    supra ¶ 59, by asking “whether [such] parental conduct falls within
    the umbrella of protected parental rights,” supra ¶ 63. That is fine
    as far as it goes. But the majority’s approach—inquiring into the
    protected status of parental conduct—begs the question: at what
    level of generality should the relevant conduct be characterized in
    assessing whether it is protected by substantive due process? The
    majority rejects my narrow framing of the relevant conduct
    (whether there is a right to an exemption from procedural default)
    in favor of a much broader framing (whether there is a right to
    parent generally).211 But this is a disputed question implicating a
    __________________________________________________________
    210The majority points to Meyer v. Nebraska, 
    262 U.S. 390
    (1923)
    in support of its view that the right at issue in today’s case should
    be defined by “the individual’s status as a parent,” supra ¶ 59,
    rather than by the “form of governmental interference,” supra
    ¶¶ 62–63. In light of the level of generality problem discussed
    herein, this distinction is inapposite. Regardless, the Meyer court’s
    discussion of a parent’s right to control the education of her
    children does not speak to the issue in this case—whether a
    fundamental parental right encompasses the right to be free from
    the normal rules of procedural default.
    211  The majority complains that my framing is wrong because I
    “fail[] to identify any parental conduct.” Supra ¶ 65. Continuing the
    thought, the majority says that the proper framing must consider
    conduct “directed at the parent’s child”—the “parents’ interactions
    with their children and . . . whether the parent had a fundamental
    right to so interact”—“not conduct directed at, or from, the State.”
    Supra ¶ 66. To support this view, the court cites a United States
    Supreme Court case, Wisconsin v. Yoder, 
    406 U.S. 205
    , 232 (1972),
    that maintains the focus on this form of parental conduct. 
    See supra
    ¶¶ 66–68.
    (Continued)
    65
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    serious and extensive debate in constitutional law. The level of
    generality at which an asserted right is framed can be
    outcome-determinative—the narrower the framing, the harder it
    will be to establish that the right is “deeply rooted” in history and
    tradition.
    ¶147 The level of generality problem is on display in some of
    the United States Supreme Court’s most prominent substantive
    due process decisions. Some of that court’s most fractured,
    controversial decisions have implicated this problem. Yet the high
    court has never conclusively established a governing standard. The
    justices openly debated the question of the appropriate level of
    __________________________________________________________
    But Yoder is unhelpful. And the court’s premises are nothing
    more than a restatement of its ultimate holding—certainly not a
    reflection of any established law. The majority’s framing conflates
    the parental conduct that is being terminated (“the entire bundle of
    parental rights” and “conduct inherent in the parent-child
    relationship,” supra ¶ 73) with the conduct triggering that
    termination. Forfeiture of parental rights is triggered by procedural
    default on the part of the parent. And the acts leading to a
    procedural default are the relevant “parental conduct” in a case like
    this one.
    This case presents a question of first impression. And it is hardly
    surprising that in the very different context of deciding whether a
    parent has parental rights in the first place, courts have not focused
    on “conduct directed at, or from, the State.” Supra ¶ 66. That said,
    no court has ever held that we may not consider a parent’s conduct
    “directed at, or from, the State” in deciding whether there is a
    substantive due process right that forecloses the effects of a
    procedural bar. What other conduct would we consider in deciding
    the constitutionality of a procedural bar? And if a parent defaults
    her parental rights, how can that be anything other than “parental
    conduct”?
    In some settings, it is certainly true that the inquiry into a
    parent’s fundamental rights is based on parental conduct “directed
    at” the child, and not “at, or from, the State.” But there is no
    universal rule to this effect. And the majority’s framing cannot hold
    in the context of forfeiture by procedural default unless we mean
    to foreclose the possibility of such forfeiture altogether—which of
    course is the key question presented in this case. The court’s
    decision accomplishes that task. But it finds no support in any
    relevant authority in so doing.
    66
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    generality in Michael H. v. Gerald D., 
    491 U.S. 110
    , 127 n.6 (1989)
    (plurality opinion) (arguing for a framing at “the most specific level
    at which a relevant tradition protecting, or denying protection to,
    the asserted right can be identified”);
    id. at 139
    (Brennan, J.,
    dissenting) (asserting that the inquiry should be framed broadly:
    “whether parenthood is an interest that historically has received
    our attention and protection”);
    id. at 132
    (O’Connor, J., concurring
    in part) (criticizing the plurality’s methodology as “inconsistent
    with our past decisions in this area” which sometimes
    “characterize[] [the] relevant traditions protecting asserted rights
    at levels of generality that might not be the most specific level
    available” (citations and internal quotation marks omitted)). But
    there was no majority view on the matter. And elsewhere the Court
    has been consistently inconsistent—sometimes framing the inquiry
    at a high level of generality, and sometimes opting for a much
    narrower framing of the proposed right at issue. 
    See supra
    ¶ 130.
    ¶148 Commentators have highlighted both the inconsistency
    in the United States Supreme Court’s substantive due process
    framework and also its significance. In the words of one
    commentator, “the determination of whether history and tradition
    entitle a particular type of conduct to protection depends upon the
    breadth with which the Court defines the conduct in question.” Rick
    Kozell, Note, Striking the Proper Balance: Articulating the Role of
    Morality in the Legislative and Judicial Processes, 47 AM. CRIM. L. REV.
    1555, 1572 (2011) (emphasis added). Another observes that “[t]he
    manner in which the court characterizes the issue critically defines
    the scope and boundaries of its reasoning and significantly impacts
    its holding,” and emphasizes that the high court “fails to provide
    jurisprudence that is consistent enough to guide lower federal
    courts.” John F. Basiak, Jr., Inconsistent Levels of Generality in the
    Characterization of Unenumerated Fundamental Rights, 16 U. FLA. J.L.
    & PUB. POL’Y 401, 403, 405 (2005) (emphasis added). Professors
    Tribe and Dorf, for their part, acknowledge that “[t]he selection of
    a level of generality necessarily involves value choices,” but argue
    in favor of a broad framing of the inquiry. See Laurence H. Tribe &
    Michael C. Dorf, Levels of Generality in the Definition of Rights, 57 U.
    CHI. L. REV. 1057, 1058 (1990).
    ¶149 The majority acknowledges the general point, but claims
    that the level of generality at which to frame the mother’s asserted
    substantive due process right “is not an issue in this case.” Supra
    ¶ 73. It argues that “[t]he level of generality at which an asserted
    right is framed may properly be considered an unresolved issue
    only where a party argues that the Due Process Clause protects
    67
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    someone whose (1) status or (2) conduct had not previously
    received constitutional protection.” Supra ¶ 70. That is fine as far as
    it goes—I agree that once controlling precedent has established the
    relevant level of generality there is no reason to rehash the
    question. And I agree that the level of generality at which to frame
    the mother’s asserted substantive due process right in this case is
    not an unresolved issue. But I think that our Utah case law, in J.S.,
    prescribes a narrow framing for an alleged new substantive right,
    while the majority argues that our case law calls for a broad
    framing. Supra ¶ 73.
    ¶150 In arguing for a broad framing, the majority leans
    heavily on the idea that in cases addressing termination of parental
    rights, “courts should define the parental right broadly to
    encompass the full spectrum of constitutionally protected parental
    conduct inherent in the parent-child relationship” because “the
    ‘parental conduct’ at issue in a parental rights termination case
    encompasses the entire bundle of parental rights.” Supra ¶ 73.
    Again, however, the majority seems to conflate the parental
    conduct that is terminated (encompassing the “full spectrum of
    constitutionally protected parental conduct”) with the conduct
    triggering that termination. 
    See supra
    ¶ 146 n.211. And for the same
    reason the various propositions it attributes to its cited cases miss
    the mark. 
    See supra
    ¶¶ 74–77 (for example emphasizing that In re
    J.P. “involve[d] a permanent termination of all parental rights”
    (alteration in original)).
    ¶151 Our recent decision in J.S., however, speaks directly to
    the level of generality question. And unlike United States Supreme
    Court case law, our Utah case law not only acknowledges the
    problem but suggests an answer. The lead opinion in J.S. called for
    a narrow framing of any alleged, new substantive right—a framing
    that considers the precise form of the relevant conduct in assessing
    whether there is a sufficient history and tradition of protecting such
    conduct to justify the establishment of a new constitutional right.
    The requirement it put forth, specifically, is of “a specific showing
    that the precise interest asserted by the parent is one that is deeply
    rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition and in the history and
    culture of Western civilization.” In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    ,
    ¶ 57 (plurality opinion) (emphases added) (citations and internal
    quotation marks omitted)). In explaining this requirement the J.S.
    opinion emphasized that the showing helps ensure that the power
    to establish new substantive due process rights is not transformed
    into a vehicle for judicial policy-making. See
    id. ¶ 61
    (noting that
    “due process innovations” absent “any effective limiting principle”
    68
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    will put courts in the “problematic realm” of making “policy
    judgments[, which] are matters for legislative action” (plurality
    opinion) (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    ¶152 We should apply this standard here. We should require
    a “specific showing of a precise interest” before establishing a new
    right of substantive due process. That showing requires more than
    just a tradition of respecting parental rights generally. To establish
    this new right the mother must establish a tradition of protecting
    parental rights despite a procedural default. This is the framework
    suggested by J.S. And the majority does not present a satisfactory
    reason for departing from it on this high-stakes point of debate in
    the jurisprudence of substantive due process.212
    ¶153 In framing the right at issue broadly (and inconsistently
    with J.S.), the majority paints a picture of a disposition that follows
    naturally from settled precedent upholding the fundamental
    nature of parental rights generally. But framed properly, the
    specific right established by the majority can be seen for what it is—
    a novel holding in a case of first impression. No court has ever
    established a substantive due process right to override a forfeiture
    of parental rights resulting from a procedural default. This court
    has held, at most, that a mother has a fundamental right “not to be
    deprived of parental rights without a showing of unfitness,
    abandonment, or substantial neglect.” In re 
    J.P., 648 P.2d at 1375
    ; see
    also Wells v. Children’s Aid Soc. of Utah, 
    681 P.2d 199
    , 203 (Utah 1984).
    United States Supreme Court precedent is to the same effect. In
    Quilloin v. Walcott, the Court concluded that it would violate a right
    of substantive due process for the state “to force the breakup of a
    natural family, over the objections of the parents and their children,
    without some showing of unfitness and for the sole reason that to
    do so was thought to be in the children’s best interest.” 434 U.S. at
    __________________________________________________________
    212 In a related critique, the majority chides me for denying the
    right at issue “the heightened protection our case law would
    typically provide [it].” Supra ¶ 57 (emphasis added). But this point
    suffers from the same misstep. The court is again characterizing the
    purported fundamental right at the highest level of generality,
    presuming that the right at issue encompasses the right to avoid
    procedural default—that such protection is “typical.” This is
    incorrect. The majority extends this protection in this case of first
    impression—and a protection cannot be “typical” if it has not been
    extended before.
    69
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    255. This same premise is inherent in the Court’s analysis in Stanley
    v. Illinois, 
    405 U.S. 645
    (1972).
    ¶154 This precedent tells us that strict scrutiny is triggered by
    a statute that authorizes the termination of a mother’s parental
    rights over her properly asserted objection and without a
    requirement of proof of unfitness, abandonment, or neglect. But the
    Adoption Act did not authorize such termination. 213 And strict
    __________________________________________________________
    213 The Adoption Act did not authorize the district court to
    terminate a mother’s parental rights without requiring “proof of
    unfitness, abandonment, or neglect.” It required proof on those
    points as a prerequisite to parental termination, and afforded the
    mother an avenue to advance her views on these questions. UTAH
    CODE § 78B-6-110(6)(a). The statute admittedly does allow for
    termination without a finding of unfitness, etc. in the event of a
    default by the mother—failure to comply with the statutory
    procedures for her appearance as a party. UTAH CODE
    § 78B-6-112(5)(c) (2015). But that doesn’t mean that the statute
    exempts mothers from the requirement of proof of grounds for
    termination. It just means that the statute prescribes specific
    procedures for a mother to assert her position in court. And it
    shows that the Adoption Act is in line with our longstanding law
    of forfeiture or procedural default—which provides that most any
    party may lose her rights by the failure to assert them in the manner
    and at the time required by law. The mother did not lose her
    parental rights, in other words, as a result of a statute that
    eliminated a requirement of proof of grounds for termination for a
    class of parents. She lost her rights as a result of her failure to avail
    herself of procedures afforded by law for her to assert her position
    on such grounds.
    The majority claims that this position “ignore[s] the ‘as-applied
    nature of Mother’s substantive due process claim”—presumably
    because in this case the mother’s parental rights were terminated
    without proof of unfitness, abandonment, or neglect. Supra ¶ 38
    n.68. But that will always be the case when parental rights are
    terminated by a parent’s procedural default. The majority also
    insists that a mother “maintain[s] her parental rights unless she
    voluntarily relinquishes them or a court finds that she forfeited
    them by being an unfit parent or by abandoning or neglecting the
    child.” Supra ¶ 38 n.68. This is true as far as it goes. But the majority
    errs in its failure to read this requirement against the longstanding
    background principle of procedural default. See Yakus v. United
    (Continued)
    70
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                           Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    scrutiny review is accordingly not triggered under the above
    cases.214
    __________________________________________________________
    States, 
    321 U.S. 414
    , 444 (1944) (noting that “constitutional right[s]
    may be forfeited . . . by the failure to make timely assertion of the
    right”); see also Rettig, 
    2017 UT 83
    , ¶¶ 15, 17 (explaining that
    “procedural bar[s]” such as rules “requir[ing] parties to raise issues
    or arguments at specified times and by certain means” on penalty
    of losing the right to do so are “commonplace” and “embedded in
    our caselaw”(citations omitted).
    214 In so concluding I have not “avoid[ed] the central question
    presented by Mother’s substantive due process claim.” Supra ¶ 96.
    I have simply applied the applicable substantive due process
    standard from J.S. and concluded that the mother has failed to carry
    her burden under that standard. The majority thus misstates my
    position. I am not saying that “‘procedures’ may never be subject
    to ‘substantive due process scrutiny’,” supra ¶ 43 n.85, that “a party
    can be barred from challenging an unconstitutional procedural
    requirement due to that party’s failure to comply with that
    unconstitutional requirement,” supra ¶ 94 n.173, or that the mother
    in this case is “precluded from challenging the fairness of
    procedural bars on substantive due process grounds,” supra ¶ 98
    n.175. The mother has every right to mount such a substantive due
    process challenge. I am only insisting that she do so in compliance
    with the test put forth in J.S.—a test that frames the issue narrowly
    by requiring “a specific showing” of a “precise interest” that is
    “deeply rooted” in history and tradition. In re J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 57
    (plurality opinion).
    And it is because the mother failed to make the showing
    required by our precedent that I would decline to strike down the
    challenged procedural requirement on substantive due process
    grounds. I have not “assume[d], without analysis, that the
    procedural requirement that triggered Mother’s default was
    constitutional.” Supra ¶ 96. Nor have I “argue[d] that the
    procedural requirement that authorized the State to terminate
    Mother’s fundamental parental rights [wa]s constitutional because
    Mother failed to comply with that procedure.” Supra ¶ 97. I agree
    with the majority that such an approach would be circular. But it is
    not the approach that I have taken. And the majority has cited no
    part of my opinion to support its contention that I claim that the
    Act’s strict compliance provision is constitutional because the
    mother defaulted under it.
    71
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    ¶155 The key factual premise of the majority opinion is the
    notion that the district court “terminate[d] Mother’s parental rights
    without her consent and without proof of parental unfitness,
    abandonment, or neglect.” 
    See supra
    ¶ 38. That is true as far as it
    goes. But that premise alone does not support the majority’s
    conclusion that section 110 of the Adoption Act is subject to strict
    scrutiny. 
    See supra
    ¶ 37. The majority opinion overlooks the crucial
    facts that the statute (a) retains the mother’s right to insist on proof
    of unfitness, abandonment, or neglect as a precondition to the
    termination of her rights, and (b) outlines clear steps for the mother
    to take in order to preserve her right to assert her views on these
    matters before her rights were terminated (steps the majority
    concedes comply with the demands of procedural due process, see
    supra ¶¶ 22–30). The statute also prescribes clear consequences for
    the failure to follow the stated procedures. These include
    termination—not on the ground that the mother was unfit—but on
    the ground that she procedurally defaulted. The statute, in other
    words, did not take away the mother’s right to insist that the court
    make a finding of unfitness before terminating her rights; the
    mother just forfeited that right by defaulting under the statute—by
    not filing the required motion to intervene.
    ¶156 That leaves the question whether the mother may excuse
    her forfeiture by claiming a substantive due process right to ignore
    the procedural requirements of the Adoption Act. The majority
    concludes that the mother has that right. It says that “mothers
    retain a fundamental right in their children regardless of a failure to
    comply with any state-prescribed procedure.” Supra ¶ 37 (emphasis
    added). The court cites no authority for that proposition. But the
    premise of its holding is the notion that a mother’s parental rights
    are fundamental and that procedural compliance is not necessary
    to preserve their fundamental nature. Supra ¶ 88. In describing its
    holding, the court says that substantive due process “protects
    individuals from being deprived of fundamental rights through the
    operation of procedures that are not narrowly tailored to further
    compelling state interests.” Supra ¶ 98.
    ¶157 This is the essence of the court’s holding. Because I
    oppose it, the court accuses me of creating a “novel framework”
    under which a fundamental right “can lose the protection of strict
    scrutiny review where the holder of the right fails to take on-going
    steps to preserve it.” Supra ¶ 88. But the “novel framework” the
    majority accuses me of establishing is nothing more than the
    longstanding law of procedural default. And the fundamental
    72
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    nature of a parental right is in no way undermined by the
    determination that it is subject to such law.215
    ¶158 The case law in this field also does not sustain the
    majority’s holding. An important line of precedent from the United
    States Supreme Court establishes that states retain the power to
    regulate even “fundamental” rights through procedure—and
    clearly rejects the notion that all such regulation is subject to strict
    scrutiny. The parental rights cases cited by the majority are not to
    the contrary. None of those cases comes close to establishing the
    substantive due process right established by the court today. The
    governing standard should be the one set forth in our opinion in
    J.S., and the mother has not come close to satisfying that standard.
    A. Standards of Scrutiny for Regulation of Fundamental Rights
    ¶159 The “fundamental” nature of a given right is not alone
    enough to trigger strict scrutiny of any procedural regulation of
    that right. The United States Supreme Court has applied something
    less than strict scrutiny review to the infringement of many
    fundamental rights, including the right to privacy, the right to
    freedom of speech, and the right to free exercise of religion. See
    generally, e.g., Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
    (1992)
    (discarding the strict scrutiny-based abortion trimester framework
    of Roe v. Wade, 
    410 U.S. 113
    (1973) for a more lenient “undue
    burden” test); United States v. O’Brien, 
    391 U.S. 367
    (1968) (applying
    a more deferential standard to content-neutral regulation of speech
    than the strict scrutiny generally triggered by content-based
    regulations); Employ’t Div. v. Smith, 
    494 U.S. 872
    (1990) (holding
    strict scrutiny inappropriate for neutral and generally applicable
    laws burdening religious practice). One commentator looking at
    these trends has observed that “the notion that government
    __________________________________________________________
    215 The majority also misses the mark in characterizing my
    position as resting on the notion that “strict compliance [i]s
    necessary to preserve the fundamental nature of [the mother’s]
    rights.” Supra ¶ 88. The fundamental nature of the underlying
    parental right stays the same throughout—my point is just that the
    right at issue here is distinct from that underlying right. The right
    at issue is the right to be exempt from forfeiture by procedural
    default (unless the defaulted procedure survives strict scrutiny).
    And it is this difference in characterization of the right at issue
    (based on different levels of generality) that underlies much of my
    disagreement with the majority. See, e.g., supra ¶¶ 146–52.
    73
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    restrictions on fundamental rights are [always] subject to strict
    scrutiny review is fundamentally wrong” because “[s]ome
    fundamental rights trigger intermediate scrutiny,” some are
    “protected only by reasonableness or rational basis review,” and
    others “are governed by categorical rules, with no formal ‘scrutiny’
    or standard of review whatsoever.” Adam Winkler, Fundamentally
    Wrong About Fundamental Rights, 23 CONST. COMMENT. 227, 227–28
    (2006).216
    ¶160 The fact that fundamental rights do not always trigger
    the protection of strict scrutiny is made especially clear in a body
    of voting rights cases. The right to vote is described as
    “fundamental” in United States Supreme Court precedent. See
    Burdick v. Takushi, 
    504 U.S. 428
    , 433 (1992). But the high court has
    expressly rejected the proposition that this means that any
    regulation of this fundamental right triggers strict scrutiny. See
    id. at 432–34.
    In Burdick the Court described the idea that “a law that
    imposes any burden upon the [fundamental] right . . . must be
    subject to strict scrutiny” as an “erroneous assumption.”
    Id. at 432.
    It also warned that a decision “to subject every . . . regulation [of a
    fundamental right] to strict scrutiny and to require that the
    regulation be narrowly tailored to advance a compelling state
    interest” would impermissibly “tie the hands of States.”
    Id. at 433.
    With this in mind, the Court has applied different levels of scrutiny
    to various regulations of the fundamental right to vote, depending
    on the degree to which the regulation restricts the right.
    ¶161 This framework is on display in Crawford v. Marion
    County Election Board, 
    553 U.S. 181
    (2008), in which the Court
    upheld a challenge to the constitutionality of an Indiana voter
    identification law. The Crawford case failed to produce a majority
    opinion. But the plurality and concurring opinions set forth two
    frameworks for analysis that both repudiate the idea of strict
    scrutiny of all regulation of the fundamental right to vote. Justice
    Stevens’ plurality opinion describes the operative regime as a
    __________________________________________________________
    216Professor Winkler has further explained that the notion that
    fundamental rights always trigger strict scrutiny “remains popular
    because it makes a rather complex doctrinal reality quite simple
    and easy to memorize,” but that “[s]uch simplicity[] . . . comes at
    considerable cost . . . breeding confusion and misunderstanding
    about how constitutional law works.” Adam Winkler,
    Fundamentally Wrong About Fundamental Rights, 23 CONST.
    COMMENT. 227, 239 (2006).
    74
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    “balancing approach” that weighs “the precise interests put
    forward by the State” against the “asserted injury to the right to
    vote.”
    Id. at 190
    (citation omitted). On the other hand, Justice
    Scalia’s concurring opinion suggests that the Court applies a
    “two-track approach” that applies a “deferential ‘important
    regulatory interests’ standard for nonsevere, nondiscriminatory
    restrictions,” and “strict scrutiny for laws that severely restrict the
    right to vote.”
    Id. at 204-05.
         ¶162 Thus, the United States Supreme Court has made clear
    that voting rights “are not absolute and are necessarily subject to
    qualification” by state regulation, Munro v. Socialist Workers Party,
    
    479 U.S. 189
    , 193 (1986), despite the fact that such rights are “of the
    most fundamental significance under our constitutional structure,”
    Illinois State Bd. of Elections v. Socialist Workers Party, 
    440 U.S. 173
    ,
    184 (1979). Regulation will invariably impose some burden on an
    individual’s fundamental rights (to vote and associate freely). But
    the Court has nonetheless held that “as a practical matter, there
    must be . . . substantial regulation . . . if some sort of order, rather
    than chaos, is to accompany the democratic processes [of asserting
    these rights].” Storer v. Brown, 
    415 U.S. 724
    , 730 (1974).
    ¶163 The same conclusion must logically hold in the realm of
    parental rights. Such rights have been acknowledged to be
    fundamental, but they are not beyond the procedural reach of the
    State’s regulatory authority. And the mere fact that such rights are
    “fundamental” does not mean that any regulation of them is subject
    to strict scrutiny.
    ¶164 The procedural regulation at issue here is admittedly
    distinct from that at issue in the above-cited voting rights cases.
    Here we are dealing with longstanding rules of procedural default.
    But that kind of regulation, if anything, would seem to trigger a
    more permissive standard of scrutiny—not strict scrutiny. Under
    either the balancing approach of the Crawford plurality or the
    two-track approach set forth in the concurrence, there is no basis
    for a strict scrutiny standard. Here we are dealing with the
    application of neutral, longstanding rules of procedure. Because
    such rules impose no significant burden on parental rights and are
    nondiscriminatory, the Crawford opinions suggest the applicability
    of a deferential standard of scrutiny.
    ¶165 We have no briefing from the parties on this line of cases.
    And the majority opinion sidesteps them entirely. So we have no
    reason to render a conclusive holding on the effect of these cases on
    our decision. I cite them, however, because they thoroughly
    75
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    undermine the majority’s notion that any regulation of a
    fundamental right is always subject to strict scrutiny.
    B. Parental Rights Cases
    ¶166 None of the majority’s parental rights cases is to the
    contrary. The Quilloin case specifically identifies the forfeiture
    question that I have highlighted here but stops far short of
    establishing the substantive right to override a procedural default.
    And prior decisions of this court actively undermine the
    substantive due process extension established by the majority
    today. Our cases require far more than the vague assertion that a
    mother’s parental rights, broadly framed, are “fundamental.” The
    standard set forth in In re J.P. and reinforced by J.S. requires proof
    of a “deeply rooted” history and tradition at a very specific level of
    generality—here, a right to preserve a parental right despite
    non-compliance with the procedure required by law. The mother
    has failed to carry her burden under these cases. And her assertion
    of a substantive due process right to avoid forfeiture by procedural
    default should accordingly be rejected.
    1. Quilloin v. Walcott
    ¶167 The putative father in Quilloin had “never married . . . or
    established a home” with the mother of his 
    child. 434 U.S. at 247
    .
    Soon after the child’s birth, the mother married another man and
    consented to adoption of the child by her husband.
    Id. Mr. Quilloin
    “attempted to block the adoption and to secure visitation rights,
    but he did not seek custody or object to the child’s continuing to
    live with [the mother and her husband].”
    Id. The Georgia
    court
    terminated his rights upon a finding that adoption of the child by
    the mother’s husband “was in the ‘best interests of [the] child.’”
    Id. at 251
    (alteration in original). There was no determination of the
    putative father’s unfitness.
    Id. at 252.
    And the putative father
    asserted that his substantive due process rights were infringed
    because the state lacked sufficient justification for terminating his
    parental rights.
    Id. ¶168 The
    Quilloin court ruled against Mr. Quilloin. It did so on
    the basis of some core differences between the substantive interest
    established by Mr. Quilloin and that presented by the putative
    father in a prior parental rights case—Stanley v. Illinois, 
    405 U.S. 645
    .
    The father in Stanley had lived with his children and their mother
    for many years.
    Id. at 646.
    And he had thereby established a
    commitment and connection by which his parental rights were
    deemed to be perfected.
    Id. at 652.
    With this in mind, the Stanley
    court struck down an Illinois statute as an infringement of the
    76
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    father’s substantive due process rights.
    Id. at 659.
    The Illinois
    statute established a conclusive presumption that unwed fathers
    were unfit as parents as a matter of law.
    Id. at 649.
    And the Stanley
    court held that the statute infringed Mr. Stanley’s fundamental
    parental rights because the state did not have a sufficiently
    compelling interest to terminate the rights of unwed fathers by
    operation of a legal presumption.
    Id. at 652–53.
        ¶169 The Quilloin case was different. This was “not a case in
    which the unwed father at any time had, or sought, actual or legal
    custody of his 
    child.” 434 U.S. at 255
    . And that fact was sufficient to
    substantially alter the balance at issue in the case—whether the
    state had a sufficient reason to justify terminating Mr. Quilloin’s
    parental rights without proof of unfitness.
    ¶170 The Court expressed “little doubt” that it would violate
    a right of substantive due process for the state “to force the breakup
    of a natural family, over the objections of the parents and their
    children, without some showing of unfitness and for the sole reason
    that to do so was thought to be in the children’s best interest.”
    Id. But the
    Court found that Mr. Quilloin’s substantive interests were
    outweighed by the state’s in these circumstances. It thus upheld the
    substantive authority of the state to terminate Mr. Quilloin’s
    parental rights as a matter of law—explaining that it could not “say
    that the State was required in this situation to find anything more
    than that the adoption, and denial of legitimation, were in the ‘best
    interests of the child.’”
    Id. ¶171 Georgia
    law, as the Court noted, afforded to putative
    fathers a procedural mechanism for perfecting their parental rights.
    That mechanism was the filing of a “legitimation petition.”
    Id. at 253.
    Such a petition would have given Mr. Quilloin the same right
    to veto an adoption petition that a mother (or married father) had.
    See
    id. at 249.
    If Mr. Quilloin had filed such a petition, he could have
    objected to the adoption of his child, precluding the termination of
    his parental rights except upon a finding of unfitness.
    Id. Yet he
    failed to do so. The Georgia court concluded that Mr. Quilloin
    lacked standing to challenge the adoption on that basis. And the
    Supreme Court ultimately reversed the judgment of the Georgia
    court on substantive due process grounds. But the Quilloin court
    was not holding that the father’s procedural default or forfeiture
    could be excused on substantive due process grounds. It stopped
    far short of establishing a substantive due process right for a parent
    to retain parental rights “regardless of a failure to comply with any
    state-prescribed procedure.” Supra ¶ 37.
    77
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    ¶172 The Quilloin majority begins by noting an argument
    made by the adoptive parents (an argument that aligns precisely
    with the approach I am proposing in this case)—the notion that
    “due process was not violated, regardless of the standard applied
    by the trial court, since any constitutionally protected interest
    appellant might have had was lost by his failure to petition for
    legitimation during the 11 years prior to [the] filing” of the
    adoption 
    petition. 434 U.S. at 254
    . This is a straightforward
    forfeiture argument. It is the idea that the father’s substantive due
    process argument is foreclosed because the State afforded the
    father a right to assert his interests and he failed to avail himself of
    that procedure. It says that “regardless” of the substantive standard
    applied for balancing the putative father’s interests against the
    state’s, the putative father loses because he stands in default or
    forfeiture by not having availed himself of a preservation
    procedure for asserting his interests.
    ¶173 The Quilloin court expressly avoided this basis for
    disposition. And it did so in a way that undermines the majority’s
    assertion that the Quilloin line of cases sustains the substantive due
    process right that the court establishes today. After noting the
    adoptive parents’ argument, the court expressed concern about
    resting its judgment on this basis. It concluded that it didn’t need
    to address the forfeiture argument “since under the circumstances
    of th[e] case [Mr. Quilloin’s] substantive rights were not violated
    by application of a ‘best interests of the child’ standard.”
    Id. The Court’s
    point was that it didn’t matter whether Mr. Quilloin might
    lose on forfeiture grounds because his substantive argument failed
    in any event. See
    id. (noting “hesitat[ion]”
    regarding “rest[ing] [a]
    decision on this ground, in light of evidence in the record that
    appellant was not aware of the legitimation procedure until after
    the adoption petition was filed”).
    ¶174 This makes clear that the Quilloin court was not saying
    that a substantive due process defect can cure a party’s procedural
    default or forfeiture. It was saying it didn’t need to address the
    procedural default because the substantive due process claim failed
    on its merits in any event. This highlights a key shortcoming of the
    majority opinion. It clarifies that the United States Supreme Court
    has never recognized a substantive due process right for a parent
    to preserve her parental rights despite a prior procedural default.
    2. In re J.P.
    ¶175 The same goes for our case law. Utah Supreme Court
    precedent has come nowhere close to endorsing the right
    78
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                           Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    established by the court today. And in fact, our cases chart a burden
    for establishing a substantive due process right that the mother in
    this case has not carried.
    ¶176 In In re J.P. we emphasized the importance of framing
    substantive due process rights narrowly and embedding the
    analysis in premises that are “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history
    and tradition” and in the “history and culture of Western
    
    civilization.” 648 P.2d at 1375
    (citations omitted). We warned of the
    perils of “innovations” in substantive due process extensions
    premised on “undisciplined . . . abstract formulae.”
    Id. (citations and
    internal quotation marks omitted). And with this concern in
    mind, we framed the substantive due process in precise, specific
    terms. We did not frame the inquiry at a high level of generality by
    simply stating that a parent has a vague right that is
    “fundamental,” and proceed from that sweeping premise to our
    own formulation of the appropriate nature and extent of that right.
    Instead we recognized a narrow, specific right—the “right of a
    parent not to be deprived of parental rights without a showing of
    unfitness, abandonment, or substantial neglect.”
    Id. And we
    based
    that conclusion not on our own sense of the policies supporting this
    sort of right, but on the fact that firmly rooted “history” and
    longstanding tradition of the “common law” had established such
    a right.
    Id. ¶177 Our
    framing of the analysis in J.P. is significant. We
    based our determination of a substantive due process right on
    longstanding history and tradition. And we framed the recognized
    right at a highly specific level. We came nowhere close to
    employing substantive due process in a manner giving a parent a
    substantive right to avoid a default resulting from the failure to
    follow procedures required by law.
    ¶178 The J.P. framework requires proof of established history
    and tradition at a precise level of specificity. It is not enough to
    assert generally that a mother’s parental rights are fundamental. To
    succeed under J.P., the mother would have to present evidence of
    an established history and tradition of a right of mothers “not to be
    deprived of parental rights despite failure to comply with
    procedure afforded to allow the mother to assert her interests.”
    And the mother here has made no such showing, as I explain
    further below.
    3. In re J.S.
    ¶179 The majority also claims support for its substantive due
    process analysis in our decision in In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    .
    79
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    Citing J.S., the majority says that “a substantive due process claim
    may be brought where otherwise fair procedures are alleged to be
    unfair in light of the ‘fundamental or important’ right they
    foreclose.” Supra ¶ 85 (citation omitted). Because the mother’s right
    to parent her child is concededly fundamental, the majority says
    that J.S. establishes a basis for substantive scrutiny of the fairness
    of the procedures set forth in the Adoption Act—and thus a basis
    for concluding that the mother in this case has a right to retain her
    parental rights despite her failure to comply with required
    procedures.
    ¶180 J.S. does not support the majority’s approach, however.
    In fact, the standard set forth in J.S. reiterates and extends the
    warnings stated in J.P. J.S. nowhere endorses the idea of a
    substantive due process right to retain parental rights despite
    failure to comply with required procedure. Certainly it doesn’t say
    that such a right can be premised purely on the general notion that
    a mother’s parental rights are “fundamental.” Instead it asks for
    proof at a highly specific level of generality.
    ¶181 In J.S. the father asserted a “substantive right” to
    establish his parentage without complying with the procedural
    elements of the statute. 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 24. The governing procedure
    under the Adoption Act in J.S. was the requirement that a putative
    father file a detailed affidavit to preserve his parental rights. UTAH
    CODE § 78B-6-121(3). And the father sought to assert a “due process
    challenge . . . to the ‘substantive constitutionality of the affidavit
    requirement at issue,’ while emphasizing that that claim subsisted
    regardless of whether the statutory limitations in question were
    ‘applied in a procedurally fair manner.’” In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 27. Thus, the father “repeatedly characterize[d] his claim
    as one challenging the statutory affidavit requirement as
    ‘substantively unconstitutional,’” or in other words as “aimed at
    establishing a ‘fundamental,’ ‘substantive right’ of an unwed father
    as a parent” without complying with the statutory affidavit
    requirement.
    Id. ¶ 2
    4.
    ¶182 In this sense J.S. is directly applicable to this case. As in
    this case, the question in J.S. came down to whether there was a
    substantive due process right to preserve parentage without
    complying with the procedural requirements of the law. But the
    standard set forth by the J.S. opinion is not at all compatible with
    the approach taken by the majority today. J.S. acknowledges the
    possibility of a limited form of substantive scrutiny of procedure—
    in a case in which a party can show not only that a general right or
    80
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    interest is “fundamental,” but also that there is an established,
    longstanding tradition entitling a party to the protection of such
    right without compliance with procedures prescribed by the
    government. See
    id. ¶ 57
    (plurality opinion) (explaining that a party
    would need to “establish a specific showing that the precise interest
    asserted by the parent is one that is deeply rooted in this Nation’s
    history and tradition and in the history and culture of Western
    civilization” (citation and internal quotation marks omitted)). In
    other words, J.S. speaks to the appropriate level of generality at
    which to frame an inquiry into the existence of a substantive due
    process right. It suggests a specific and narrow framing—not the
    broad, sweeping level of generality that the majority today
    espouses.217
    ¶183 In articulating this standard, the J.S. opinion went out of
    its way to warn of the “slippery slope problems” associated with
    any decision to endorse a new substantive due process right in this
    field.
    Id. ¶ 59
    (plurality opinion). It noted that the father asserted a
    broad historical basis for recognizing the rights of unwed fathers.
    But it concluded that that was insufficient. The putative father had
    failed “to identify any longstanding, widespread basis in our
    history and culture for recognizing a perfected right in unmarried
    biological fathers arising upon their mere filing of a paternity suit (and
    without following other requirements set forth by law).”
    Id. (emphasis added).
    And it noted that “[e]ndorsement of a substantive right in
    this case would inevitably lead to a series of line-drawing problems
    going forward, requiring courts to make policy judgments about
    __________________________________________________________
    217  The majority concedes the narrow framing in J.S. but
    attempts to cabin that framing by arguing that J.S. “did nothing to
    limit the scope of relevant parental conduct” but instead “more
    narrowly construed the parental status—to exclude unmarried
    fathers who had not perfected their parental rights—deserving full
    due process protection.” Supra ¶ 77 n.145. The majority’s point
    seems to be that a holding dealing only with “status” would not be
    binding when it comes to “conduct.” I disagree with the court’s
    premise and with its conclusion. First, I don’t think the narrow
    framing in J.S. dealt with status as opposed to conduct. Second,
    even accepting the majority’s premise for the sake of argument, I
    see no reason why the level of generality would be different for
    “conduct” as opposed to “status”; the majority itself posits that the
    nature of the right at issue is defined by both the conduct and status
    of the parent. 
    See supra
    ¶¶ 59, 62, 78.
    81
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    whether the biological father before the court had done enough to
    properly justify the recognition of his parental rights.”
    Id. ¶ 60.
    J.S.
    explained that such “policy judgments are matters for legislative
    action.”
    Id. ¶ 61.
        ¶184 J.S. also noted that “[o]ur legislature has spoken to th[e]
    question” of where to draw the line on the procedure for a putative
    father to preserve the assertion of his parental rights—“prescribing
    a series of prerequisites” to the assertion of his rights.
    Id. It rejected
    the putative father’s attempt to “second-guess those requirements”
    by “establish[ing] a substantive due process right to perfect his
    parental rights on something less than the grounds prescribed by
    the legislature—by filing a paternity action but not the affidavit
    called for by statute.”
    Id. “Doing so,”
    the plurality explained,
    “would put us in the problematic realm of making ‘due process
    innovations’ dictated by ‘abstract formulae’ and without any
    effective limiting principle.”
    Id. And with
    this in mind it held the
    putative father to the substantive due process standard quoted
    above—a standard framed at a specific level of generality.
    ¶185 The opinion also connected this standard to the law of
    procedural default or forfeiture. It noted that the putative father in
    that case was merely “claim[ing] that he ignored” the procedural
    requirements of our law “on the (bad) advice of counsel.”
    Id. ¶ 63.
    And while acknowledging that this was “unfortunate,” it
    emphasized that “bad legal advice is no excuse for failure to
    follow” procedural prerequisites to the assertion of a party’s legal
    rights, noted that “our legal system treats attorneys as agents for
    their clients,” and explained that we “deem clients responsible for
    the decisions they make on advice of counsel.”
    Id. ¶18
    6 J.S. thus emphasizes the narrowness of the operative
    notion of substantive due process. In rejecting the father’s
    substantive due process claim in that case, the lead opinion
    explained that the father had failed to “make the kind of showing,”
    id. ¶ 58,”
    needed to establish such a right—proof of a
    “longstanding, widespread basis in our history and culture for
    recognizing a perfected right in unmarried biological fathers
    arising upon their mere filing of a paternity suit (and without
    following other requirements set forth by law),”
    id. ¶ 59.
    And it also
    connected this strict standard of substantive due process to the law
    of procedural default or forfeiture.
    ¶187 The above bears no resemblance to the standard applied
    by the majority in this case. The majority invokes J.S. in support of
    a substantive standard of scrutiny of the statutory procedure under
    82
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                           Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    review—here, the requirement of a motion to intervene. 
    See supra
    ¶¶ 84–86. And it roots its holding in the bare notion that a mother’s
    rights in a child are “fundamental”—presupposing that the inquiry
    should be framed at a broad, sweeping level of generality. 
    See supra
    ¶¶84–86. But that is not the approach taken in J.S. J.S. took the
    substantive due process claim at issue on its own terms—framing
    it at a highly specific level of generality. And the plurality in J.S.
    rejected that claim on the ground that the father had not established
    a basis in history and tradition for the notion of a substantive
    right—narrowly framed—to preserve parental rights without
    complying with the established statutory procedure.
    ¶188 J.S. thus charts a narrow, limited domain for a claimed
    substantive right to preserve parental rights despite a party’s
    default under established procedure. And it highlights the
    novelty—and error—in the majority’s decision to endorse a
    substantive right to preserve parental rights despite a procedural
    default under the law.218
    4. In re B.Y.
    ¶189 The majority also claims support for its approach in In re
    Adoption of B.Y., 
    2015 UT 67
    . Citing B.Y., the majority says that our
    substantive due process analysis opens the door to scrutiny of the
    “fairness” of a “procedural bar or limitation” in a statute “on the
    ground that the right foreclosed is so fundamental or important
    that it is protected from extinguishment.” Supra ¶¶ 31, 98. Because
    the mother’s right to parent her child is concededly fundamental,
    the majority says that B.Y. establishes a basis for substantive
    scrutiny of the fairness of the procedures set forth in the Adoption
    Act—and thus a basis for concluding that the mother in this case
    __________________________________________________________
    218 J.S. admittedly involved the rights of a putative father. And
    the substantive rights of an unmarried father are concededly only
    inchoate—“merely provisional.” 
    See supra
    ¶¶ 84, 86. But the
    majority misses a key point in resting its decision on the fact that a
    mother’s parental rights are automatically fundamental. While this
    is true, it leaves unanswered the question of whether and to what
    extent a party with rights that are concededly fundamental may
    ignore existing procedures for the assertion of those rights without
    suffering the consequence of a default. The answer to that question
    cannot be the bare assertion that the underlying right is
    fundamental. That is circular. And it overrides the strict standard
    set forth in the case law.
    83
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    has a right to retain her parental rights despite her failure to comply
    with required procedures. Supra ¶¶ 31, 98. But the B.Y. opinion is
    consistent with Quilloin, J.P., and J.S—it comes nowhere close to
    establishing a substantive due process right to retain parental
    rights despite a procedural default.
    ¶190 In B.Y. a putative father sought to challenge the
    Adoption Act’s mandate of “strict compliance” with the procedural
    requirements of the statute—specifically, the requirement of filing
    a paternity action prior to the mother’s consent or relinquishment
    of the child for adoption. 
    2015 UT 67
    ; UTAH CODE § 78B-6-121(3)
    (The “consent of an unmarried biological father is not required
    unless, prior to the time the mother executes her consent for
    adoption or relinquishes the child for adoption, the unmarried
    biological father . . . initiates proceedings . . . to establish paternity
    . . . .”). Despite the failure to fulfill this procedural requirement, the
    father in B.Y. asserted that he “did enough to ‘grasp’ his
    ‘opportunity . . . to develop a relationship with his offspring’” to
    perfect a fundamental parental right under United States Supreme
    Court precedent. 
    2015 UT 67
    , ¶ 42 (omission in original). And he
    asserted that the strict compliance requirement infringed his
    substantive due process rights as a parent.
    ¶191 We acknowledged the possibility of a substantive due
    process claim in this realm, but we rejected it on its merits. We
    noted that “[a]n unwed father’s rights are merely provisional,”
    emphasized that he “must comply with legal prerequisites
    established by the state” to perfect such rights, and concluded that
    “[f]ailure to do so leaves the father’s parental rights without any
    substantive protection—except in the narrow circumstance in
    which the prerequisites established by the state are arbitrary.”
    Id. ¶ 43.
    In so doing we emphasized that “[t]he Due Process Clause . . .
    is not a license for courts to second-guess the prerequisites
    established by the legislature for a putative father to perfect his
    parental rights.”
    Id. ¶ 44.
    “Instead,” we said that “the well-settled
    standard yields substantial deference to the state’s chosen
    prerequisites.”
    Id. And we
    explained that “[i]t does so in light of the
    state’s important interest in ‘immediate and secure adoptions for
    eligible newborns.’”
    Id. We held
    that the putative father’s claim
    “fail[ed] under this standard.”
    Id. ¶ 46.
        ¶192 The majority seeks to distinguish B.Y. and to claim
    support for its approach in that opinion. It says that B.Y. supports
    the application of a standard of strict scrutiny in assessing the
    “fairness” of the procedure set forth in the Adoption Act—the
    84
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                           Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    requirement of filing a motion to intervene. Supra ¶¶ 31, 98. And it
    bases that determination on the fact that this case involves the
    parental rights of a mother, which are automatically
    “fundamental,” while B.Y. involved the rights of a putative father,
    which are “merely provisional.” Supra ¶ 35. The point is correct as
    far as it goes. But until today, no court has ever extended it in the
    manner endorsed by the majority. The majority is of course right to
    say that a biological mother’s rights are inherently and
    automatically “fundamental” under the law. And the court is
    equally correct in its observation that the parent’s alleged right in
    B.Y. was inchoate or “merely provisional.” This was, moreover, a
    key basis for our decision in B.Y. The substantive due process claim
    in B.Y. was deficient because a putative father’s provisional right
    required additional acts on the father’s part before the right could
    be perfected as fundamental. And we had no trouble rejecting the
    father’s substantive due process right in light of the cited premises
    in our case law—the need for “substantial deference” to the state’s
    chosen procedural “prerequisites” to the establishment of a
    parental right, and the substantial basis for protecting “the state’s
    important interest in ‘immediate and secure adoptions for eligible
    newborns.’” B.Y., 
    2015 UT 67
    , ¶ 44.
    ¶193 But the majority’s analysis assumes that a fundamental
    right once acquired is therefore insulated against forfeiture through
    procedural default. The court cites no case law in support of its
    decision to establish a new substantive right to retain a
    fundamental parental right despite procedural default. And such a
    right does not at all follow from the fact that the underlying right
    is itself protected as a matter of substantive due process. Again, a
    mother’s parental rights are automatically fundamental in the
    sense that she is not required to jump through the procedural hoops
    to perfect those rights required of fathers under our case law. See
    J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 2 (explaining requirements for fathers to file
    paternity petitions and present evidence regarding their support of
    the child to make a threshold showing of parentage and perfect
    their parental rights). But the connection between procedural
    compliance and the initial perfection of parental rights is beside the
    point here. Here the parental right at issue is admittedly perfected
    (and was so without the need for the procedural compliance
    required of fathers), so the question is whether that concededly
    perfected right can later be forfeited through procedural default. By
    holding that it cannot, the majority establishes a new right of
    substantive due process.
    85
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    ¶194 The majority repeatedly insists otherwise. Citing cases
    establishing a mother’s lack of need for procedural compliance at
    the perfection stage, it says that the mother must likewise have no
    obligation to comply with another set of procedures (for
    preservation) at a later stage. Supra ¶¶ 36–37; 79–91. But this is a
    big step. The fact that a mother need not jump through procedural
    hoops to perfect her parental rights not only bears on a different
    stage of procedural compliance; it also has no bearing on
    procedural default generally.
    ¶195 The mother is not required to jump through procedural
    hoops to establish her parental rights in the first instance. But that
    is not because her fundamental parental rights encompass a right
    to flout procedural requirements generally. It is because there is an
    established tradition—framed in narrow, specific terms—of
    respecting a mother’s rights without any requirement of any
    procedural act aimed at perfecting those rights. That tradition is
    reflected in the fact that the law does not extend the requirement of
    compliance with this procedure to mothers. See UTAH CODE
    § 78B-6-121(3).
    ¶196 None of these premises apply to the procedures at issue
    here. The procedural rules of preservation assuredly do apply to
    both mothers and fathers. And in the absence of evidence of an
    established tradition allowing a mother to retain her rights despite
    a failure to comply with those rules, the court has no basis to
    establish the existence of such a right.
    ¶197 By focusing on the difference between mothers’ and
    fathers’ rights at the threshold stage of perfection and importing
    that distinction to any later instance of procedural default, the
    majority also ignores the fact that the state’s interest in procedural
    compliance at these later stages is the same for both mothers and
    fathers. The fact that the mother’s rights are automatically
    fundamental does not mean that she can blithely avoid any need to
    follow state procedure in an adoption proceeding.
    ¶198 The Adoption Act’s procedural requirements are not
    aimed only at putative fathers. They are also aimed at mothers. See
    UTAH CODE § 78B-6-110(6)(a) (requiring that a mother, or any other
    party who receives notice of adoption, must file motion to
    intervene in adoption proceeding within 30 days);
    id. § 78B-6-110(6)(b)
    (stating that a mother who fails to “fully and
    strictly comply” with this requirement “forfeits all rights in relation
    to the adoptee”). And the legislature has articulated substantial
    interests that are advanced by requiring a mother to intervene as a
    86
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                           Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    party and assert her position regarding any claimed basis for
    termination of her rights (such as unfitness, abandonment, or
    neglect). The legislature has expressly found, for example, that “the
    state has a compelling interest in providing stable and permanent
    homes for adoptive children in a prompt manner, in preventing the
    disruption of adoptive placements, and in holding parents
    accountable for meeting the needs of children.”
    Id. § 78B-6-
    102(5)(a). It has also concluded that “adoptive children
    have a right to permanence and stability in adoptive placements.”
    Id. § 78B-6-
    102(5)(c). These are important concerns. And they are
    obviously furthered by a requirement that a mother intervene as a
    party in a timely fashion and assert any proffered challenge to
    termination of her parental rights. Failure to do so results in a
    forfeiture of those rights. Neither the mother nor the majority has
    identified any basis in the law of forfeiture by procedural default
    or in the Adoption Act to contradict that conclusion.
    ¶199 The state’s interests in assuring “stable and permanent
    homes for adoptive children in a prompt manner” and “preventing
    the disruption of adoptive placements” thus remain intact whether
    the parental rights at stake are those of a biological mother or a
    putative father. See
    id. UTAH CODE
    § 78B-6-102(5)(a). And it is in this
    sense that the question of perfection is irrelevant. It is not—as the
    majority suggests—a threshold question that can obviate the need
    to establish a historical basis for noncompliance with governing
    procedure. The historical inquiry is not aimed at finding a basis for
    whether the parent’s right is fundamental or not. The historical
    inquiry is aimed at finding a basis for noncompliance with
    procedure despite holding fundamental parental rights. It bears
    repeating that no court has ever established a substantive due
    process right of a mother to retain her parental rights despite
    defaulting those rights under governing procedure. We certainly
    didn’t establish such a right in B.Y. In fact, B.Y. left intact the
    standard put forth in J.S.—a standard that requires much more
    than a mere challenge to the “unfairness” of procedure for
    preserving parental rights, and that instead requires a deeply
    rooted historical basis for a fundamental right to retain parental
    rights despite failing to comply with the governing procedure.
    And, again, the mother has not come close to carrying that burden
    here, as discussed in more detail below.
    ¶200 J.S., admittedly, is not a case involving a biological
    mother’s forfeiture of parental rights through procedural default.
    So it is true that my proposed disposition would be an extension of
    J.S. insofar as that case did not involve a substantive due process
    87
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    challenge to forfeiture of a mother’s parental rights. But this only
    buttresses my point that this a case of first impression. And J.S. is
    our most relevant precedent, both bearing on forfeiture of parental
    rights through procedural default and suggesting a position in the
    levels of generality debate discussed above. 
    See supra
    ¶¶ 179–88.
    The J.S. plurality advocated for a specific framing of the new right
    proposed to be established as a matter of substantive due process.
    And because the framing question is independent of whether a
    parent is a father or a mother, it bears directly on today’s case and
    I would apply it.
    ¶201 The majority charges me with mischaracterizing the
    right at issue. It complains that I am “mark[ing] a fundamental
    departure from the way courts have traditionally defined parental
    rights.” Supra ¶ 55. I am puzzled by this charge. I concede that there
    is a lot of novelty in this case. But the novelty comes from the
    majority’s extension of the law of substantive due process—from
    its reframing of the alleged new right at the highest level of
    generality.
    ¶202 The cases I have cited admittedly deal only with the
    rights of putative fathers. But it does not at all follow that a
    mother’s rights are insulated from procedural default. The mother,
    as noted, is not required to jump through procedural hoops to
    protect her rights at the outset. But the majority is seizing on a false
    procedural equivalence in insisting that that means she can never
    be subject to any procedure at any stage. The majority is
    accordingly right to highlight the novelty of this case. The novelty,
    however, is entirely in the majority opinion.
    C. Application of the Governing Standard
    ¶203 For the above reasons there is no basis in existing case
    law for the establishment of a substantive due process right for a
    mother to avoid the usual effect (forfeiture) of a procedural default.
    Certainly that does not follow from the premise that a mother’s
    rights are unquestionably “fundamental.” Much more analytical
    work is required under the above precedent. To sustain a right to
    preserve parental rights despite the failure to comply with
    established procedure, the mother should be required to make a
    showing at a specific level of generality based on firmly rooted
    history and tradition. See In re Adoption of J.S., 
    2014 UT 51
    , ¶ 57
    (plurality opinion). She should have to show not just the general
    notion of a fundamental right as a mother, but a right to preserve
    her rights without complying with established statutory procedure.
    88
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    ¶204 The mother has made no effort at such a showing.
    Instead she claims only (a) that mothers generally have rights that
    are automatically fundamental, and (b) that the procedure required
    by the Adoption Act is generally “unfair.” The majority opinion’s
    analysis is to the same effect. 
    See supra
    ¶ 37 (asserting that “[a] right
    of a mother not to be deprived of parental rights without a showing
    of unfitness, abandonment, or substantial neglect is . . .
    fundamental” (citation and internal quotation marks omitted)).219
    ¶205 This falls far short under our law. And the mother’s
    substantive due process claim should be rejected on the ground
    that she has failed to carry the heavy burden set forth in our cases—
    __________________________________________________________
    219 The majority also claims support for its view in the dictum in
    New York v. Hill, 
    528 U.S. 110
    , 116 (2000)—the notion that forfeiture
    “is not appropriate when it is inconsistent with the provision
    creating the right sought to be secured.” Supra ¶ 98 n.174. In the
    majority’s view this means that a decision allowing forfeiture “to
    defeat Mother’s substantive due process claim in this case would
    be inconsistent with the Due Process Clause.” Supra ¶ 98. But that
    is entirely circular. The court is asserting that the Due Process
    Clause prohibits forfeiture in this case because such forfeiture is
    inconsistent with the Due Process Clause.
    That does not follow from Hill. That case, for one thing, deals
    with express waiver, not forfeiture by procedural default. And one
    of the two cases cited in support of the quoted statement is also an
    express waiver case. See 
    Hill, 528 U.S. at 116
    (citing Smith v. United
    States, 
    360 U.S. 1
    , 9 (1959)). The other case, emphasized by the
    majority, is admittedly a forfeiture case. 
    See supra
    ¶ 98 n.174 (citing
    Crosby v. United States, 
    506 U.S. 255
    , 258–59 (1993)). Crosby held that
    a criminal defendant’s right to be present at trial cannot be forfeited
    by failure to 
    appear. 506 U.S. at 258
    –59. But the Crosby court based
    its holding on well-established case law finding that specific right
    to be 
    unwaivable. 506 U.S. at 259
    . In other words, the right to
    exemption from the normal consequence of procedural default
    (forfeiture) was both narrowly framed and supported by history
    and tradition as shown by the long line of case law establishing that
    right. And that is surely not the case here—the majority cites not a
    single case establishing the right to avoid forfeiture in this context.
    The court’s cited case law is accordingly unhelpful to it. Hill (and
    the cases it cites) are by no means a general license for a right to
    avoid forfeiture despite a procedural default, and on the contrary
    supports the approach I advocate for here.
    89
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    a burden that the majority distorts in its decision today. Contrary
    to the majority’s claim, I am not saying that the substantive due
    process right at issue is defined by “referencing the form of
    governmental interference.” Supra ¶ 65. I am simply saying that the
    established procedures determine how and whether such a right is
    preserved.
    ¶206 It is tempting to see a technical defect in procedural
    compliance as a matter that should lightly be excused. But
    procedural rules are always two-edged. There is always an interest
    on the other side of the equation. And the procedural requirements
    of the Adoption Act are no exception.
    ¶207 The adoption arena is one where strict procedural
    compliance is at a premium. The state has a compelling interest in
    “providing stable and permanent homes for adoptive children in a
    prompt matter” and “preventing the disruption of adoptive
    placements.” UTAH CODE § 78B-6-102(5)(a). To serve the interest of
    protecting “the welfare of the child, a determination that a child can
    be adopted must be final as well as immediate.” Wells v. Children’s
    Aid Soc. of Utah, 
    681 P.2d 199
    , 203 (Utah 1984). And statutory
    procedures for natural parents to participate in and assert their
    rights in adoption proceedings are a core element of this system.
    ¶208 We have long respected the interests advanced by the
    procedural requirements of the Adoption Act. We should continue
    do so here. The state’s interests in stability and finality are no less
    substantial here—in a case involving a biological mother. And the
    majority has identified no legal basis for avoiding this conclusion.
    II
    ¶209 In setting the procedural rules for participation in an
    adoption proceeding, our legislature could have required that a
    biological mother be formally named as a party and served with a
    summons and petition for adoption. Some other states structure
    their law in this way.220 And I can see an argument for favoring this
    __________________________________________________________
    220 See, e.g., IOWA CODE § 232.112 (stating that the child’s parents
    are “necessary parties to a termination of parent-child relationship
    proceeding and are entitled to receive notice and an opportunity to
    be heard”); MINN. STAT. § 260C.163(2) (parents of a child have “the
    right to participate in all proceedings on a petition” to terminate
    parental rights or a petition for an adoption); MO. REV. STAT.
    §§ 211.453 (requiring a petition for termination of parental rights be
    (Continued)
    90
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    sort of scheme. If I were a legislator I might be tempted to vote for
    this kind of adoption regime.
    ¶210 But I am not a legislator. And we are not being asked to
    take on the role of super-legislature. We are being asked to decide
    whether the constitution invalidates the adoption provisions that
    were enacted into law by the legislature that was elected into office
    by the people. The answer to that question is no. The majority
    breaks new constitutional ground in concluding otherwise. It cites
    no on-point precedent to support its novel adoption of a
    substantive due process right to override the effect that our law has
    long prescribed for a party’s procedural default—forfeiture of the
    party’s rights.
    ¶211 The majority’s due process standard, moreover,
    threatens a wide range of adoption procedures in place in
    numerous states across the nation. Procedural default is a
    well-established basis for the termination of parental rights.221 Yet
    the majority’s standard calls this basis into question. When parental
    rights are terminated as a result of a mother’s procedural default,
    the effect will always come about without proof of unfitness,
    abandonment, or neglect. And this effect, in the majority’s view,
    will always trigger strict scrutiny. Supra ¶ 37. This sweeping
    extension of strict scrutiny threatens the viability of the procedures
    __________________________________________________________
    served on the biological mother and informing the mother of her
    right to attend and participate in the dispositional hearing); 23 PA.
    CONS. STAT. § 2513 (requiring that notice be given to the parents
    before their rights are terminated and allowing them to freely
    participate in the hearing); S.C. CODE ANN. §§ 63-7-2550, -2560
    (requiring a petition for termination of parental rights be served on
    the biological mother and guaranteeing the mother the right to
    legal counsel during the proceedings).
    221 See, e.g., FLA. STAT. § 39.801(7) (permitting termination of
    parental rights based on a failure to appear at a scheduled hearing);
    OKLA. STAT. tit. 10A, § 1-4-905 (same); see also, e.g., C.R. v. Dep’t of
    Children & Families, 
    225 So. 3d 393
    , 394-95 (Fla. Dist. Ct. App. 2017)
    (terminating a mother’s parental rights following her failure to
    appear at trial); In re H.L.L., 
    179 S.W.3d 894
    (Mo. 2005) (en banc)
    (terminating a father’s parental rights based on his failure to appear
    at a termination hearing); In re Welfare of S.I., 
    337 P.3d 1114
    , 1115
    (Wash. Ct. App. 2014) (terminating a mother’s parental rights based
    on her failure to appear at a termination hearing).
    91
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    and rules of procedural default or forfeiture. The majority seeks to
    mask this upheaval by emphasizing the “narrowness” of its
    holding, insisting that procedures regulating fundamental rights
    may yet be preserved—so long as they are “‘narrowly tailored’ to
    protect a ‘compelling governmental interest.’” Jones v. Jones, 
    2015 UT 84
    , ¶ 27, 
    359 P.3d 603
    (quoting Washington v. Glucksberg, 
    521 U.S. 702
    , 721 (1997)).
    ¶212 But this is no real brake on the majority’s approach. The
    majority holds that a party’s noncompliance with procedure is
    excused (on substantive due process grounds) so long as the
    purpose of a procedural requirement is fulfilled. 
    See supra
    ¶¶ 47–48.
    The standard states, in other words, that a procedural requirement
    whose purpose can be fulfilled in an alternative manner is a
    procedural requirement that is not narrowly tailored.
    ¶213 And that is a principle with unlimited potential for
    mischief. The application of a strict scrutiny standard to procedural
    regulation of fundamental rights forecloses the whole idea of
    regulation by a uniform set of procedural rules. If the majority’s
    approach takes root, our law will require case-by-case analysis of
    the viability of any and all procedural rules that may sustain the
    sanction of a default of a fundamental right. And this will
    undermine the whole point of procedural regulation. Our rules will
    be pointless if parties can ignore them and instead secure
    personalized standards set by the courts on a case-by-case basis.
    ¶214 The majority’s framework calls into question a broad
    range of established procedures. The majority seeks to minimize
    the impact of its decision. Supra ¶ 37 n.67. But it has identified no
    meaningful limiting principle. Almost all procedure is not narrowly
    tailored. Most all procedural rules, by nature, are in a sense quite
    arbitrary. And that means that there will almost always be a less
    restrictive means of advancing the underlying goal.
    ¶215 Consider a standard procedural time bar, like a
    requirement that a party file an answer within thirty days, or a
    response to a motion for summary judgment within a prescribed
    timeframe. If a mother fails to file a timely answer or response to
    the motion her case may be defaulted. Does the principle of
    substantive due process give her the right to ignore the time limits
    in our rules because the time limits we have prescribed are
    arbitrary numbers and the underlying purpose is still served by a
    late filing? That is not how our law of procedure works. And the
    doctrine of substantive due process has never been employed in a
    92
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 51
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    manner calling into question the enforceability of the procedural
    default rules built into our law of procedure.
    ¶216 Procedural default rules serve the state’s compelling
    interests in promoting prompt and stable adoptions. 
    See supra
    ¶ 42
    (citing Thurnwald v. A.E., 
    2007 UT 38
    , ¶¶ 30, 34, 
    163 P.3d 623
    ). But
    such rules may often not be the least restrictive means of advancing
    those interests. When a rule of procedural default is not the least
    restrictive means of advancing the state’s interests, the rule will be
    struck down as unconstitutional. And this will upset longstanding
    principles of procedural default and forfeiture—and undercut the
    reliance interests of adoptive parents and children. 
    See supra
    ¶¶ 42,
    82.
    ¶217 The majority opens the door to a new frontier of
    substantive due process scrutiny—scrutiny of the fairness of the
    procedures prescribed for the procedural default or forfeiture of
    legal rights. If the majority opinion is taken to its logical end, the
    law of procedural default or forfeiture will be forever pressed into
    a state of limbo. And parties in cases involving fundamental rights
    will stand in a particular state of unease.
    ¶218 Today we speak only to the rights of parents. But the
    logic of today’s decision sweeps much more broadly. As framed by
    the court, it would cover any of a wide range of other fundamental
    rights—including the right to liberty (freedom from incarceration)
    or the right to vote. Our laws require those asserting their interest
    in freedom from incarceration to comply with procedural rules in
    the law of preservation. See, e.g., UTAH CODE § 78B-9-106
    (precluding relief under the Postconviction Remedies Act on any
    ground that “could have been but was not raised at trial or on
    appeal” or that “is barred by the limitation period established in
    Section 78B-9-107”); see also, e.g., Taylor v. State, 
    2012 UT 5
    , 
    270 P.3d 471
    (rejecting defendant’s Postconviction Remedies Act claims
    because they were procedurally barred). The same goes for
    fundamental rights like the right to vote. See, e.g., UTAH CODE
    § 20A-2-102.5 (establishing a voter registration deadline with
    limited exceptions). In the wake of today’s decision the parties to a
    case involving these and other fundamental rights should be on
    notice that the usual effect of a procedural default (forfeiture) may
    not hold. The courts will retain the prerogative of second-guessing
    these procedures—and may set them aside if the majority’s strict
    scrutiny standard is taken seriously.
    ¶219 This is troubling. The majority’s novel approach
    threatens the very foundations of the law of procedural default or
    93
    IN RE K.T.B.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    forfeiture. And it places no meaningful limit on judicial discretion
    to second-guess the law in this field. Our precedent has charted a
    more principled course for recognizing viable substantive due
    process claims. I would apply that precedent here. And I would
    conclude that the mother has failed to carry her burden of proving
    a deeply rooted historical basis for a fundamental right to retain
    parental rights despite failing to comply with the governing
    procedure.
    94
    

Document Info

Docket Number: Case No. 20150821

Citation Numbers: 2020 UT 51

Filed Date: 7/21/2020

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 7/22/2020

Authorities (48)

State v. Rettig , 2017 UT 83 ( 2017 )

Koch v. Carmona , 268 Ill. App. 3d 48 ( 1994 )

Obergefell v. Hodges , 135 S. Ct. 2584 ( 2015 )

In Re JP , 1982 Utah LEXIS 992 ( 1982 )

Wells v. Children's Aid Soc. of Utah , 1984 Utah LEXIS 788 ( 1984 )

Grupo Dataflux v. Atlas Global Group, L. P. , 124 S. Ct. 1920 ( 2004 )

International Trading Corporation v. Edison , 109 F.2d 825 ( 1939 )

Thurnwald v. A.E. , 577 Utah Adv. Rep. 8 ( 2007 )

In Re Adoption of B.Y. , 356 P.3d 1215 ( 2015 )

Illinois State Board of Elections v. Socialist Workers Party , 99 S. Ct. 983 ( 1979 )

Quilloin v. Walcott , 98 S. Ct. 549 ( 1978 )

Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey , 112 S. Ct. 2791 ( 1992 )

United States v. James Daniel Good Real Property , 114 S. Ct. 492 ( 1993 )

Washington v. Glucksberg , 117 S. Ct. 2258 ( 1997 )

Brown v. Cox , 830 Utah Adv. Rep. 12 ( 2017 )

Yick Wo v. Hopkins , 6 S. Ct. 1064 ( 1886 )

Pierce v. Society of Sisters , 45 S. Ct. 571 ( 1925 )

Employment Div., Dept. of Human Resources of Ore. v. Smith , 110 S. Ct. 1595 ( 1990 )

Crosby v. United States , 113 S. Ct. 748 ( 1993 )

Stanley v. Illinois , 92 S. Ct. 1208 ( 1972 )

View All Authorities »