Coleman v. Court of Appeals of Maryland , 132 S. Ct. 1327 ( 2012 )


Menu:
  • (Slip Opinion)              OCTOBER TERM, 2011                                       1
    Syllabus
    NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is
    being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued.
    The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been
    prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader.
    See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 
    200 U. S. 321
    , 337.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    Syllabus
    COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MARYLAND
    ET AL.
    CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR
    THE FOURTH CIRCUIT
    No. 10–1016. Argued January 11, 2012—Decided March 20, 2012
    The Family and Medical Leave Act of 1993 (FMLA) entitles an employ-
    ee to take up to 12 work weeks of unpaid leave per year for (A) the
    care of a newborn son or daughter; (B) the adoption or foster-care
    placement of a child; (C) the care of a spouse, son, daughter, or par-
    ent with a serious medical condition; and (D) the employee’s own se-
    rious health condition when the condition interferes with the employ-
    ee’s ability to perform at work. 
    29 U. S. C. §2612
    (a)(1). The FMLA
    also creates a private right of action for equitable relief and damages
    “against any employer (including a public agency) in any Federal or
    State court.” §2617(a)(2). For present purposes, subparagraphs (A),
    (B), and (C) are referred to as the family-care provisions, and subpar-
    agraph (D) as the self-care provision. In Nevada Dept. of Human Re-
    sources v. Hibbs, 
    538 U. S. 721
    , 730−732, this Court held that Con-
    gress could subject States to suit for violations of subparagraph (C)
    based on evidence of family-leave policies that discriminated on the
    basis of sex.
    Petitioner filed suit, alleging that his employer, the Maryland
    Court of Appeals, an instrumentality of the State, violated the FMLA
    by denying him self-care leave. The Federal District Court dismissed
    the suit on sovereign immunity grounds. The Fourth Circuit af-
    firmed, holding that unlike the family-care provision in Hibbs, the
    self-care provision was not directed at an identified pattern of gen-
    der-based discrimination and was not congruent and proportional to
    any pattern of sex-based discrimination on the part of States.
    Held: The judgment is affirmed.
    
    626 F. 3d 187
    , affirmed.
    2              COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    Syllabus
    JUSTICE KENNEDY, joined by THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE THOMAS,
    and JUSTICE ALITO, concluded that suits against States under the
    self-care provision are barred by sovereign immunity. Pp. 3−12.
    (a) Under the federal system, States, as sovereigns, are immune
    from damages suits, unless they waive that defense. See, e.g., Kimel
    v. Florida Bd. of Regents, 
    528 U. S. 62
    , 72−73. Congress may also ab-
    rogate the States’ immunity pursuant to its powers under §5 of the
    Fourteenth Amendment, but it must make that intention “unmistak-
    ably clear in the language of the statute,” Hibbs, 
    supra, at 726
    . It did
    so in the FMLA. Congress also “must tailor” legislation enacted un-
    der §5 “to remedy or prevent” “conduct transgressing the Fourteenth
    Amendment’s substantive provisions.” Florida Prepaid Postsecond-
    ary Ed. Expense Bd. v. College Savings Bank, 
    527 U. S. 627
    , 639.
    “There must be a congruence and proportionality between the injury
    to be prevented or remedied and the means adopted to that end.”
    City of Boerne v. Flores, 
    521 U. S. 507
    , 520. Pp. 3−5.
    (b) The sex-based discrimination that supported allowing subpara-
    graph (C) suits against States is absent with respect to the self-care
    provision. Petitioner’s three arguments to the contrary are unper-
    suasive. Pp. 5–12.
    (1) Petitioner maintains that the self-care provision addresses
    sex discrimination and sex stereotyping. But the provision, standing
    alone, is not a valid abrogation of the States’ immunity from suit. At
    the time the FMLA was enacted, there was no evidence of such dis-
    crimination or stereotyping in sick-leave policies. Congress was con-
    cerned about the economic burdens imposed by illness-related job loss
    on employees and their families and about discrimination based on
    illness, not sex. Although the self-care provision offers some women
    a benefit by allowing them to take leave for pregnancy-related ill-
    nesses, the provision, as a remedy, is not congruent and proportional
    to any identified constitutional violations. When the FMLA was en-
    acted, Congress had no evidence that States were excluding pregnan-
    cy-related illnesses from their leave policies. Pp. 6–7.
    (2) Petitioner also argues that the self-care provision is a neces-
    sary adjunct to the family-care provision sustained in Hibbs. But his
    claim—that the provisions work in tandem to ensure the equal avail-
    ability of total FMLA leave time to women and men despite their dif-
    ferent leave-usage patterns―is unconvincing and does not comply
    with the requirements of City of Boerne. Also, there are no congres-
    sional findings of, or evidence on, how the self-care provision is nec-
    essary to the family-care provisions or how it reduces employer dis-
    crimination against women. Pp. 8–11.
    (3) Finally, petitioner contends that the self-care provision helps
    single parents keep their jobs when they get ill. The fact that most
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)                      3
    Syllabus
    single parents happen to be women demonstrates, at most, that the
    self-care provision was directed at remedying neutral leave re-
    strictions that have a disparate effect on women.                However,
    “[a]lthough disparate impact may be relevant evidence of . . . discrim-
    ination . . . such evidence is insufficient [to prove a constitutional
    violation] even where the Fourteenth Amendment subjects state ac-
    tion to strict scrutiny.” Board of Trustees of Univ. of Ala. v. Garrett,
    
    531 U. S. 356
    , 373. Because it is unlikely that many of the neutral
    leave policies affected by the self-care provision are unconstitutional,
    the scope of the self-care provision is out of proportion to its supposed
    remedial or preventive objectives. Pp. 11−12.
    JUSTICE SCALIA adhered to his view that the Court should abandon
    the “congruence and proportionality” approach in favor of one that is
    properly tied to the text of §5, which grants Congress the power “to
    enforce, by appropriate legislation,” the other provisions of the Four-
    teenth Amendment. Outside the context of racial discrimination,
    Congress’s §5 power should be limited to the regulation of conduct
    that itself violates the Fourteenth Amendment and thus would not
    reach a State’s failure to grant self-care leave to its employees.
    Pp. 1−2.
    KENNEDY, J., announced the judgment of the Court and delivered an
    opinion, in which ROBERTS, C. J., and THOMAS and ALITO JJ., joined.
    THOMAS, J., filed a concurring opinion. SCALIA, J., filed an opinion con-
    curring in the judgment. GINSBURG, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in
    which BREYER, J., joined, and in which SOTOMAYOR and KAGAN, JJ.,
    joined as to all but footnote 1.
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)                              1
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the
    preliminary print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested to
    notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Wash-
    ington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order
    that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 10–1016
    _________________
    DANIEL COLEMAN, PETITIONER v. COURT OF
    APPEALS OF MARYLAND ET AL.
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT
    [March 20, 2012]
    JUSTICE KENNEDY announced the judgment of the Court
    and delivered an opinion, in which THE CHIEF JUSTICE,
    JUSTICE THOMAS, and JUSTICE ALITO joined.
    The question in this case is whether a state employee
    is allowed to recover damages from the state entity that
    employs him by invoking one of the provisions of a federal
    statute that, in express terms, seeks to abrogate the
    States’ immunity from suits for damages. The statute in
    question is the Family and Medical Leave Act of 1993, 
    107 Stat. 6
    , 
    29 U. S. C. §2601
     et seq. The provision at issue
    requires employers, including state employers, to grant
    unpaid leave for self care for a serious medical condition,
    provided other statutory requisites are met, particularly
    requirements that the total amount of annual leave taken
    under all the Act’s provisions does not exceed a stated
    maximum. §2612(a)(1)(d). In agreement with every Court
    of Appeals to have addressed this question, this Court now
    holds that suits against States under this provision are
    barred by the States’ immunity as sovereigns in our feder-
    al system. See 
    626 F. 3d 187
     (CA4 2010) (case below);
    Nelson v. University of Tex., 
    535 F. 3d 318
     (CA5 2008);
    2          COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    Miles v. Bellfontaine Habilitation Center, 
    481 F. 3d 1106
    (CA8 2007) (per curiam); Toeller v. Wisconsin Dept. of
    Corrections, 
    461 F. 3d 871
     (CA7 2006); Touvell v. Ohio
    Dept. of Mental Retardation & Developmental Disabilities,
    
    422 F. 3d 392
     (CA6 2005); Brockman v. Wyoming Dept. of
    Family Servs., 
    342 F. 3d 1159
     (CA10 2003); Laro v. New
    Hampshire, 
    259 F. 3d 1
     (CA1 2001).
    I
    A
    The Family and Medical Leave Act of 1993 (FMLA or
    Act) entitles eligible employees to take up to 12 work
    weeks of unpaid leave per year. An employee may take
    leave under the FMLA for: (A) “the birth of a son or
    daughter . . . in order to care for such son or daughter,” (B)
    the adoption or foster-care placement of a child with the
    employee, (C) the care of a “spouse . . . son, daughter, or
    parent” with “a serious health condition,” and (D) the
    employee’s own serious health condition when the condi-
    tion interferes with the employee’s ability to perform at
    work. 
    29 U. S. C. §2612
    (a)(1). The Act creates a private
    right of action to seek both equitable relief and money
    damages “against any employer (including a public agen-
    cy) in any Federal or State court of competent jurisdic-
    tion.” §2617(a)(2). As noted, subparagraph (D) is at issue
    here.
    This Court considered subparagraph (C) in Nevada
    Dept. of Human Resources v. Hibbs, 
    538 U. S. 721
     (2003).
    Subparagraph (C), like (A) and (B), grants leave for rea-
    sons related to family care, and those three provisions are
    referred to here as the family-care provisions. Hibbs held
    that Congress could subject the States to suit for viola-
    tions of subparagraph (C), §2612(a)(1)(C). That holding
    rested on evidence that States had family-leave policies
    that differentiated on the basis of sex and that States
    administered even neutral family-leave policies in ways
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)            3
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    that discriminated on the basis of sex. See id., at 730–732.
    Subparagraph (D), the self-care provision, was not at issue
    in Hibbs.
    B
    Petitioner Daniel Coleman was employed by the Court
    of Appeals of the State of Maryland. When Coleman
    requested sick leave, he was informed he would be termi-
    nated if he did not resign. Coleman then sued the state
    court in the United States District Court for the District of
    Maryland, alleging, inter alia, that his employer violated
    the FMLA by failing to provide him with self-care leave.
    The District Court dismissed the suit on the basis that
    the Maryland Court of Appeals, as an entity of a sovereign
    State, was immune from the suit for damages. The parties
    do not dispute the District Court’s ruling that the Mary-
    land Court of Appeals is an entity or instrumentality of
    the State for purposes of sovereign immunity. The Dis-
    trict Court concluded the FMLA’s self-care provision did
    not validly abrogate the State’s immunity from suit. App.
    to Pet. for Cert. 15–20. The Court of Appeals for the
    Fourth Circuit affirmed, reasoning that, unlike the family-
    care provision at issue in Hibbs, the self-care provision
    was not directed at an identified pattern of gender-based
    discrimination and was not congruent and proportional to
    any pattern of sex-based discrimination on the part of
    States. 
    626 F. 3d 187
    . Certiorari was granted. 564 U. S.
    ___ (2011).
    II
    A
    A foundational premise of the federal system is that
    States, as sovereigns, are immune from suits for damages,
    save as they elect to waive that defense. See Kimel v.
    Florida Bd. of Regents, 
    528 U. S. 62
    , 72–73 (2000); Alden
    v. Maine, 
    527 U. S. 706
     (1999). As an exception to this
    4          COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    principle, Congress may abrogate the States’ immunity
    from suit pursuant to its powers under §5 of the Four-
    teenth Amendment. See, e.g., Fitzpatrick v. Bitzer, 
    427 U. S. 445
     (1976).
    Congress must “mak[e] its intention to abrogate unmis-
    takably clear in the language of the statute.” Hibbs, 
    538 U. S., at 726
    . On this point the Act does express the clear
    purpose to abrogate the States’ immunity. 
    Ibid.
     (“The
    clarity of Congress’ intent” to abrogate the States’ immun-
    ity from suits for damages under the FMLA “is not fairly
    debatable”). Congress subjected any “public agency” to
    suit under the FMLA, 
    29 U. S. C. §2617
    (a)(2), and a “pub-
    lic agency” is defined to include both “the government of
    a State or political subdivision thereof ” and “any agency of
    . . . a State, or a political subdivision of a State,” §§203(x),
    2611(4)(A)(iii).
    The question then becomes whether the self-care provi-
    sion and its attempt to abrogate the States’ immunity are
    a valid exercise of congressional power under §5 of the
    Fourteenth Amendment. Section 5 grants Congress the
    power “to enforce” the substantive guarantees of §1 of
    the Amendment by “appropriate legislation.” The power
    to enforce “ ‘includes the authority both to remedy and to
    deter violation[s] of rights guaranteed’ ” by §1. See Board
    of Trustees of Univ. of Ala. v. Garrett, 
    531 U. S. 356
    , 365
    (2001) (quoting Kimel, 
    supra, at 81
    ). To ensure Congress’
    enforcement powers under §5 remain enforcement powers,
    as envisioned by the ratifiers of the Amendment, rather
    than powers to redefine the substantive scope of §1, Con-
    gress “must tailor” legislation enacted under §5 “ ‘to rem-
    edy or prevent’ ” “conduct transgressing the Fourteenth
    Amendment’s substantive provisions.” Florida Prepaid
    Postsecondary Ed. Expense Bd. v. College Savings Bank,
    
    527 U. S. 627
    , 639 (1999).
    Whether a congressional Act passed under §5 can im-
    pose monetary liability upon States requires an assess-
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)            5
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    ment of both the “ ‘evil’ or ‘wrong’ that Congress intended
    to remedy,” ibid., and the means Congress adopted to
    address that evil, see City of Boerne v. Flores, 
    521 U. S. 507
    , 520 (1997). Legislation enacted under §5 must be
    targeted at “conduct transgressing the Fourteenth
    Amendment’s substantive provisions.” Florida Prepaid,
    
    supra, at 639
    ; see Kimel, 
    supra, at 88
    ; City of Boerne,
    
    521 U. S., at 525
    . And “[t]here must be a congruence
    and proportionality between the injury to be prevented or
    remedied and the means adopted to that end.” 
    Id., at 520
    .
    Under this analysis Hibbs permitted employees to re-
    cover damages from States for violations of subparagraph
    (C). In enacting the FMLA, Congress relied upon evidence
    of a well-documented pattern of sex-based discrimination
    in family-leave policies. States had facially discriminatory
    leave policies that granted longer periods of leave to wom-
    en than to men. 
    538 U. S., at
    730–731. States also admin-
    istered facially neutral family-leave policies in gender-
    biased ways. 
    Id., at 732
    . These practices reflected what
    Congress found to be a “pervasive sex-role stereotype that
    caring for family members is women’s work,” 
    id., at 731
    ,
    a stereotype to which even this Court had succumbed in
    earlier times, 
    id., at 729
    . Faced with “the States’ record of
    unconstitutional participation in, and fostering of, gender-
    based discrimination in the administration of leave bene-
    fits,” Hibbs concluded that requiring state employers to
    give all employees the opportunity to take family-care
    leave was “narrowly targeted at the faultline between
    work and family—precisely where sex-based overgenerali-
    zation has been and remains strongest.” 
    Id., at 735, 738
    .
    B
    The same cannot be said for requiring the States to give
    all employees the opportunity to take self-care leave.
    Petitioner advances three arguments for allowing employ-
    ees to recover damages from States that violate the
    6         COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    FMLA’s self-care provision: The self-care provision stand-
    ing alone addresses sex discrimination and sex stereotyp-
    ing; the provision is a necessary adjunct to the family-care
    provision sustained in Hibbs; and the provision eases the
    burden on single parents. But what the family-care provi-
    sions have to support them, the self-care provision lacks,
    namely evidence of a pattern of state constitutional viola-
    tions accompanied by a remedy drawn in narrow terms to
    address or prevent those violations.
    1
    Standing alone, the self-care provision is not a valid
    abrogation of the States’ immunity from suit. When the
    FMLA was enacted, “ninety-five percent of full-time state-
    and local-government employees were covered by paid sick
    leave plans and ninety-six percent of such employees
    likewise enjoyed short-term disability protection.” Brief
    for States of Texas et al. as Amici Curiae 13–14 (hereinaf-
    ter Texas Brief) (citing Bureau of Labor Statistics, U. S.
    Dept. of Labor, Employee Benefits in State and Local
    Governments 17–26 (1994) (hereinafter BLS Rept.)). The
    evidence did not suggest States had facially discriminatory
    self-care leave policies or that they administered neutral
    self-care leave policies in a discriminatory way. And there
    is scant evidence in the legislative history of a purported
    stereotype harbored by employers that women take self-
    care leave more often than men. Congress considered
    evidence that “men and women are out on medical leave
    approximately equally.” H. R. Rep. No. 101–28, pt. 1, p.
    15 (1989) (hereinafter H. R. Rep.). Nothing in the record
    shows employers formulated self-care leave policies based
    on a contrary view.
    Without widespread evidence of sex discrimination or
    sex stereotyping in the administration of sick leave, it is
    apparent that the congressional purpose in enacting the
    self-care provision is unrelated to these supposed wrongs.
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)            7
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    The legislative history of the self-care provision reveals a
    concern for the economic burdens on the employee and the
    employee’s family resulting from illness-related job loss
    and a concern for discrimination on the basis of illness, not
    sex. See, e.g., S. Rep. No. 103–3, pp. 11–12 (1993); H. R.
    Rep., at 23. In the findings pertinent to the self-care
    provision, the statute makes no reference to any distinc-
    tion on the basis of sex. See 
    29 U. S. C. §2601
    (a)(4)
    (“[T]here is inadequate job security for employees who
    have serious health conditions that prevent them from
    working for temporary periods”). By contrast, with regard
    to family care Congress invoked concerns related to gen-
    der. See §2601(a)(5) (“[D]ue to the nature of the roles of
    men and women in our society, the primary responsibility
    for family caretaking often falls on women, and such
    responsibility affects the working lives of women more
    than it affects the working lives of men”).
    It is true the self-care provision offers some women a
    benefit by allowing them to take leave for pregnancy-
    related illnesses; but as a remedy, the provision is not
    congruent and proportional to any identified constitutional
    violations. At the time of the FMLA’s enactment, “ninety-
    five percent” of state employees had paid sick-leave plans
    at work, and “ninety-six percent” had short-term disability
    protection. Texas Brief 13–14 (citing BLS Rept. 17–26).
    State employees presumably could take leave for pregnancy-
    related illnesses under these policies, and Congress did
    not document any pattern of States excluding pregnancy-
    related illnesses from sick-leave or disability-leave poli-
    cies. “Congress . . . said nothing about the existence or
    adequacy of state remedies.” Florida Prepaid, 527 U. S.,
    at 644. It follows that abrogating the States’ immunity
    from suits for damages for failure to give self-care leave is
    not a congruent and proportional remedy if the existing
    state leave policies would have sufficed.
    8          COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    2
    As an alternative justification for the self-care provision,
    it has been suggested that the provision is a necessary
    adjunct to the family-care provisions. Petitioner argues
    that employers may assume women are more likely to
    take family-care leave than men and that the FMLA
    therefore offers up to 12 weeks of leave for family care and
    self care combined. According to petitioner, when the self-
    care provision is coupled with the family-care provisions,
    the self-care provision could reduce the difference in the
    expected number of weeks of FMLA leave that different
    employees take for different reasons.
    The fact that self-care leave could have this effect does
    not mean that it would. If, for example, women are ex-
    pected to take 20 days of family-care leave per year and
    men to take 10, and women and men are each expected to
    take 5 days of self-care leave per year, the difference in the
    expected number of days of leave and cost to the employer
    remains the same regardless of the availability of self-care
    leave. Congress made no findings, and received no specific
    testimony, to suggest the availability of self-care leave
    equalizes the expected amount of FMLA leave men and
    women will take. Even if women take family-care leave
    more often than men, men do not take self-care leave more
    often than women; and there is little evidence that em-
    ployers assume they do. See H. R. Rep., at 15. Petitioner
    suggests that some women will be expected to take all 12
    weeks of leave under the FMLA for family-care purposes,
    and therefore that any amount of self-care leave taken by
    men will diminish the difference in the amount of FMLA
    leave taken by men and women. But there is little evi-
    dence to support petitioner’s assumption about the magni-
    tude of women’s expected FMLA leave for family-care
    purposes. And men are only expected to take five days of
    sick leave per year, see ibid., so the self-care provision
    diminishes the difference in expected leave time by a
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)           9
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    maximum of five days. And that is only to the extent
    women use all their available FMLA leave for family-care
    reasons. Petitioner’s overly complicated argument about
    how the self-care provision works in tandem with the
    family-care provisions is unconvincing and in the end does
    not comply with the clear requirements of City of Boerne.
    In addition petitioner’s first defense of the self-care
    provision contradicts his second defense of the provision.
    In the first defense, the Court is told employers assume
    women take more self-care leave than men. See Tr. of
    Oral Arg. 10–12. In the second defense, the Court is told
    the self-care provision provides an incentive to hire women
    that will counteract the incentives created by the family-
    care provisions because employers assume women take
    more family-care leave than men. But if the first defense
    is correct, the second defense is wrong. In other words, if
    employers assume women take self-care leave more often
    than men (the first defense), a self-care provision will not
    provide an incentive to hire women. To the contrary, the
    self-care provision would provide an incentive to discrimi-
    nate against women.
    There is “little support in the record for the concerns
    that supposedly animated” the self-care provision. Florida
    Prepaid, supra, at 639. Only supposition and conjecture
    support the contention that the self-care provision is
    necessary to make the family-care provisions effective.
    The evidence documented in support of the self-care provi-
    sion is, to a large degree, unrelated to sex discrimination,
    or to the administration of the family-care provisions. See
    supra, at 7. Congress made no findings and did not cite
    specific or detailed evidence to show how the self-care
    provision is necessary to the family-care provisions or how
    it reduces an employer’s incentives to discriminate against
    women. And “Congress . . . said nothing about the exist-
    ence or adequacy of state” sick-leave policies. Florida
    Prepaid, supra, at 644; see Garrett, 
    531 U. S., at 373
    .
    10         COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    Under this Court’s precedents, more is required to sub-
    ject unconsenting States to suits for damages, particularly
    where, as here, it is for violations of a provision (the self-
    care provision) that is a supposedly preventive step in aid
    of already preventive provisions (the family-care provi-
    sions). See Florida Prepaid, 
    527 U. S., at 642
     (“[T]he
    legislative record still provides little support for the prop-
    osition that Congress sought to remedy a Fourteenth
    Amendment violation in enacting the Patent Remedy
    Act”); Kimel, 
    528 U. S., at 88
     (“One means by which we
    have made such a determination . . . is by examining the
    legislative record containing the reasons for Congress’
    action”).
    The “few fleeting references” to how self-care leave is
    inseparable from family-care leave fall short of what is
    required for a valid abrogation of States’ immunity from
    suits for damages. Florida Prepaid, supra, at 644. These
    “isolated sentences clipped from floor debates” and testi-
    mony, Kimel, 
    supra, at 89
    , are stated as conclusions,
    unsupported by evidence or findings about how the self-
    care provision interrelates to the family-care provisions to
    counteract employers’ incentives to discriminate against
    women. Congress must rely on more than abstract gener-
    alities to subject the States to suits for damages. Other-
    wise, Congress could choose to combat the purported
    effects of the family-care provisions by allowing employees
    to sue States that do not permit employees to take vaca-
    tion time under the FMLA. There is nothing in particular
    about self-care leave, as opposed to leave for any personal
    reason, that connects it to gender discrimination. And
    when the issue, as here, is whether subparagraph (D) can
    abrogate a State’s immunity from damages, there is no
    sufficient nexus, or indeed any demonstrated nexus, be-
    tween self-care leave and gender discrimination by state
    employers. Documented discrimination against women in
    the general workplace is a persistent, unfortunate reality,
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)           11
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    and, we must assume, a still prevalent wrong. An explicit
    purpose of the Congress in adopting the FMLA was to
    improve workplace conditions for women. See 
    29 U. S. C. §§2601
    (b)(4), (5). But States may not be subject to suits
    for damages based on violations of a comprehensive stat-
    ute unless Congress has identified a specific pattern of
    constitutional violations by state employers. See City of
    Boerne, 
    521 U. S., at 532
    .
    3
    The petitioner’s last defense of the self-care provision is
    that the provision helps single parents retain their jobs
    when they become ill. This, however, does not explain
    how the provision remedies or prevents constitutional
    violations. The fact that most single parents happen to be
    women, see, e.g., S. Rep. No. 103–3, at 7, demonstrates, at
    most, that the self-care provision was directed at remedy-
    ing employers’ neutral leave restrictions which have a
    disparate effect on women. “Although disparate impact
    may be relevant evidence of . . . discrimination . . . such
    evidence alone is insufficient [to prove a constitutional
    violation] even where the Fourteenth Amendment subjects
    state action to strict scrutiny.” Garrett, supra, at 372–373;
    see Tuan Anh Nguyen v. INS, 
    533 U. S. 53
    , 82–83 (2001)
    (O’Connor, J., dissenting); Washington v. Davis, 
    426 U. S. 229
    , 239 (1976). To the extent, then, that the self-care
    provision addresses neutral leave policies with a disparate
    impact on women, it is not directed at a pattern of consti-
    tutional violations. Because, moreover, it is “unlikely that
    many of the [neutral leave policies] . . . affected by” the
    self-care provision are unconstitutional, “the scope of the
    [self-care provision is] out of proportion to its supposed
    remedial or preventive objectives.” Kimel, supra, at 82;
    see City of Boerne, 
    supra, at 519
    .
    Of course, a State need not assert its Eleventh Amend-
    ment immunity from suits for damages. See, e.g., Sossa-
    12         COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    mon v. Texas, 563 U. S. ___, ___ (2011) (slip op., at 5) (“A
    State . . . may choose to waive its immunity in federal
    court at its pleasure”). Discrimination against women is
    contrary to the public policy of the State of Maryland, see,
    e.g., Maryland’s Fair Employment Practices Act, Md. State
    Govt. Code Ann. §20–606 (Lexis 2009), and the State has
    conceded that the Act is good social policy, see Tr. of Oral
    Arg. 35. If the State agrees with petitioner that damages
    liability for violations of the self-care provision is neces-
    sary to combat discrimination against women, the State
    may waive its immunity or create a parallel state law
    cause of action.
    *    *     *
    As a consequence of our constitutional design, money
    damages are the exception when sovereigns are defend-
    ants. See, e.g., Pennhurst State School and Hospital v.
    Halderman, 
    451 U. S. 1
    , 29 (1981). Subjecting States to
    suits for damages pursuant to §5 requires more than a
    theory for why abrogating the States’ immunity aids in, or
    advances, a stated congressional purpose. To abrogate the
    States’ immunity from suits for damages under §5, Con-
    gress must identify a pattern of constitutional violations
    and tailor a remedy congruent and proportional to the
    documented violations. It failed to do so when it allowed
    employees to sue States for violations of the FMLA’s self-
    care provision. The judgment of the Court of Appeals is
    affirmed.
    It is so ordered.
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)           1
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 10–1016
    _________________
    DANIEL COLEMAN, PETITIONER v. COURT OF
    APPEALS OF MARYLAND ET AL.
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT
    [March 20, 2012]
    JUSTICE THOMAS, concurring.
    I join the plurality’s opinion holding that Congress did
    not validly abrogate the States’ immunity from suit for
    money damages for violations of the self-care provision of
    the Family and Medical Leave Act of 1993 (FMLA), 
    29 U. S. C. §2612
    (a)(1)(D). As the plurality explains, this
    case is distinguishable from Nevada Dept. of Human
    Resources v. Hibbs, 
    538 U. S. 721
     (2003), which held that
    Congress validly abrogated the States’ immunity from suit
    for violations of the FMLA’s family-care provision,
    §2612(a)(1)(C). Ante, at 5–6. I write separately only to
    reiterate my view that Hibbs was wrongly decided because
    the family-care provision is not sufficiently linked to a
    demonstrated pattern of unconstitutional discrimination
    by the States. See 
    538 U. S., at
    745–754 (KENNEDY, J.,
    joined by SCALIA and THOMAS, JJ., dissenting); Tennessee
    v. Lane, 
    541 U. S. 509
    , 565–566 (2004) (THOMAS, J., dis-
    senting). The self-care provision at issue in this case is
    even further removed from any such pattern.
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)            1
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 10–1016
    _________________
    DANIEL COLEMAN, PETITIONER v. COURT OF
    APPEALS OF MARYLAND ET AL.
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT
    [March 20, 2012]
    JUSTICE SCALIA, concurring in the judgment.
    The plurality’s opinion seems to me a faithful applica-
    tion of our “congruence and proportionality” jurisprudence.
    So does the opinion of the dissent. That is because the
    varying outcomes we have arrived at under the “congru-
    ence and proportionality” test make no sense. Which in
    turn is because that flabby test is “a standing invitation to
    judicial arbitrariness and policy-driven decisionmaking,”
    Tennessee v. Lane, 
    541 U. S. 509
    , 557–558 (2004) (SCALIA,
    J., dissenting). Moreover, in the process of applying (or
    seeming to apply) the test, we must scour the legislative
    record in search of evidence that supports the congres-
    sional action. See ante, at 6–11; post, at 16–20 (opinion
    of GINSBURG, J.). This grading of Congress’s homework
    is a task we are ill suited to perform and ill advised to
    undertake.
    I adhere to my view that we should instead adopt an
    approach that is properly tied to the text of §5, which
    grants Congress the power “to enforce, by appropriate
    legislation,” the other provisions of the Fourteenth
    Amendment. (Emphasis added.) As I have explained in
    greater detail elsewhere, see Lane, 
    supra,
     at 558–560,
    outside of the context of racial discrimination (which is
    different for stare decisis reasons), I would limit Con-
    gress’s §5 power to the regulation of conduct that itself
    2         COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    violates the Fourteenth Amendment. Failing to grant
    state employees leave for the purpose of self-care—or any
    other purpose, for that matter—does not come close.
    Accordingly, I would affirm the judgment of the Court of
    Appeals.
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)           1
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 10–1016
    _________________
    DANIEL COLEMAN, PETITIONER v. COURT OF
    APPEALS OF MARYLAND ET AL.
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT
    [March 20, 2012]
    JUSTICE GINSBURG, with whom JUSTICE BREYER joins,
    and with whom JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR and JUSTICE KAGAN
    join as to all but footnote 1, dissenting.
    Section 1 of the Fourteenth Amendment provides: “No
    State shall . . . deny to any person within its jurisdiction
    the equal protection of the laws.” Section 5 grants Con-
    gress the “power to enforce, by appropriate legislation, the
    provisions of this article.” Congress’ §5 enforcement power
    includes the authority to remedy and deter violations of
    §1’s substantive guarantees by prohibiting conduct “not
    itself forbidden by the Amendment’s text.” Kimel v. Flor-
    ida Bd. of Regents, 
    528 U. S. 62
    , 81 (2000). “In other
    words, Congress may enact so-called prophylactic leg-
    islation that proscribes facially constitutional conduct,
    in order to prevent and deter unconstitutional conduct.”
    Nevada Dept. of Human Resources v. Hibbs, 
    538 U. S. 721
    ,
    727–728 (2003).
    The Family and Medical Leave Act of 1993 (FMLA or
    Act) entitles eligible employees to 12 weeks of job-secured
    leave during any 12-month period: (A) to care for a new-
    born son or daughter; (B) to care for a newly adopted son
    or daughter; (C) to care for a spouse, child, or parent with
    a serious health condition; or (D) because the employee
    has a serious health condition that makes her unable
    to perform the functions of her position. 29 U. S. C.
    2            COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    §2612(a)(1).
    Even accepting this Court’s view of the scope of Con-
    gress’ power under §5 of the Fourteenth Amendment, I
    would hold that the self-care provision, §2612(a)(1)(D),
    validly enforces the right to be free from gender discrimi-
    nation in the workplace.1
    I
    Section 5 legislation “must be targeted at conduct trans-
    gressing the Fourteenth Amendment’s substantive provi-
    sions,” ante, at 5 (internal quotation marks omitted),
    “[a]nd ‘[t]here must be a congruence and proportionality
    between the injury to be prevented or remedied and the
    means adopted to that end.’ ” Ibid. (quoting City of Boerne
    v. Flores, 
    521 U. S. 507
    , 520 (1997)). The first step of the
    now-familiar Boerne inquiry calls for identification of the
    constitutional right Congress sought to enforce. See, e.g.,
    Tennessee v. Lane, 
    541 U. S. 509
    , 522 (2004). The FMLA’s
    self-care provision, Maryland asserts, trains not on the
    right to be free from gender discrimination, but on an
    “equal protection right to be free from irrational state
    employment discrimination based on a medical condition.”
    Brief for Respondents 14. The plurality agrees, concluding
    that the self-care provision reveals “a concern for discrim-
    ination on the basis of illness, not sex.” Ante, at 7. In so
    declaring, the plurality undervalues the language, pur-
    ——————
    1Iremain of the view that Congress can abrogate state sovereign
    immunity pursuant to its Article I Commerce Clause power. See
    Seminole Tribe of Fla. v. Florida, 
    517 U. S. 44
    , 100 (1996) (Souter, J.,
    dissenting). Beyond debate, 
    29 U. S. C. §2612
    (a)(1)(D) is valid Com-
    merce Clause legislation. See infra, at 21. I also share the view that
    Congress can abrogate state immunity pursuant to §5 of the Four-
    teenth Amendment where Congress could reasonably conclude that
    legislation “constitutes an appropriate way to enforce [a] basic equal
    protection requirement.” Board of Trustees of Univ. of Ala. v. Garrett,
    
    531 U. S. 356
    , 377 (2001) (BREYER, J., dissenting) (internal quotation
    marks omitted).
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)            3
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    pose, and history of the FMLA, and the self-care provi-
    sion’s important role in the statutory scheme. As well, the
    plurality underplays the main theme of our decision in
    Hibbs: “The FMLA aims to protect the right to be free
    from gender-based discrimination in the workplace.” 
    538 U. S., at 728
    .
    I begin with the text of the statute, which repeatedly
    emphasizes gender discrimination. One of the FMLA’s
    stated purposes is to “entitle employees to take reasonable
    leave,” 
    29 U. S. C. §2601
    (b)(2), “in a manner that, con-
    sistent with the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth
    Amendment, minimizes the potential for employment dis-
    crimination on the basis of sex by ensuring generally
    that leave is available for eligible medical reasons (includ-
    ing maternity-related disability) and for compelling family
    reasons, on a gender-neutral basis.” §2601(b)(4). Another
    identified aim is “to promote the goal of equal employment
    opportunity for women and men, pursuant to [the Equal
    Protection Clause].” §2601(b)(5). “[E]mployment stand-
    ards that apply to one gender only,” Congress expressly
    found, “have serious potential for encouraging employers
    to discriminate against employees and applicants for
    employment who are of that gender.” §2601(a)(6).
    The FMLA’s purpose and legislative history reinforce
    the conclusion that the FMLA, in its entirety, is directed
    at sex discrimination. Indeed, the FMLA was originally
    envisioned as a way to guarantee—without singling out
    women or pregnancy—that pregnant women would not
    lose their jobs when they gave birth. The self-care provi-
    sion achieves that aim.
    A brief history is in order. In his 1982 congressional
    campaign, then-candidate Howard Berman pledged to
    introduce legislation similar to the California law chal-
    lenged in California Fed. Sav. & Loan Assn. v. Guerra,
    
    479 U. S. 272
     (1987). S. Wisensale, Family Leave Policy:
    The Political Economy of Work and Family in America 134
    4            COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    (2001) (hereinafter Wisensale). California’s law, enacted
    in 1978, made it unlawful for an employer to refuse to
    grant female employees disabled by pregnancy or child-
    birth up to four months’ unpaid, job-protected leave. See
    1978 Cal. Stats. ch. 1321, §1, now codified at Cal. Govt.
    Code Ann. §12945(a)(1) (West Supp. 2012).
    The California law sharply divided women’s rights ad-
    vocates. “Equal-treatment” feminists asserted it violated
    the Pregnancy Discrimination Act’s (PDA) commitment
    to treating pregnancy the same as other disabilities.2 It
    did so by requiring leave only for disability caused by
    pregnancy and childbirth, thereby treating pregnancy as
    sui generis. See Brief for American Civil Liberties Union
    et al. as Amici Curiae in California Fed., O. T. 1985,
    No. 85–494, pp. 5–10. “Equal-opportunity” feminists dis-
    agreed, urging that the California law was consistent with
    the PDA because it remedied the discriminatory burden
    that inadequate leave policies placed on a woman’s right
    to procreate. See Brief for Coalition for Reproductive
    Equality in the Workplace et al. as Amici Curiae in id.,
    at 2–6. See also Williams, Equality’s Riddle: Pregnancy
    and the Equal Treatment/Special Treatment Debate, 13
    N. Y. U. Rev. L. & Soc. Change 325, 326–328 (1984–1985)
    (hereinafter Williams) (discussing disagreement).
    While California Fed. moved through the lower federal
    courts, equal-treatment feminists began work on a gender-
    neutral leave model, which eventually became the FMLA.
    ——————
    2 Enacted as an addition to the section defining terms used in Title
    VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, the Pregnancy Discrimination Act of
    1978 (PDA) provides: “The terms ‘because of sex’ or ‘on the basis of sex’
    include, but are not limited to, because of or on the basis of pregnancy,
    childbirth, or related medical conditions; and women affected by preg-
    nancy, childbirth, or related medical conditions shall be treated the
    same for all employment-related purposes, including receipt of benefits
    under fringe benefit programs, as other persons not so affected but
    similar in their ability or inability to work . . . .” 
    92 Stat. 2076
    , 42
    U. S. C. §2000e(k).
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)                   5
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    See Ross, Legal Aspects of Parental Leave, in Parental
    Leave and Child Care 97 (J. Hyde & M. Essex eds. 1991)
    (hereinafter Ross). Then-Congressman Berman met with
    the Women’s Legal Defense Fund’s Donna Lenhoff, a
    drafter of the first FMLA bill. Id., at 114–115, n. 27;
    Wisensale 136.3 They agreed that any national bill would
    focus not only on pregnancy, but on equal treatment for all
    workers. Ross 114–115, n. 27. See also Kazmier v. Wid-
    mann, 
    225 F. 3d 519
    , 547 (CA5 2000) (Dennis, J., dissent-
    ing) (“Perceiving that enacting the PDA had not achieved
    the intended result of preventing discrimination against
    either women or men in the granting of leave time in that
    the States felt it necessary to affirmatively grant preg-
    nancy leave to women and not men, in 1985 Congress
    began considering the issue of family and medical leave.”).
    Though this Court, in California Fed., eventually upheld
    California’s pregnancy-only leave policy as not preempted
    by the PDA, equal-treatment feminists continued to be-
    lieve that viewing pregnancy as sui generis perpetuated
    widespread discrimination against women.4 They there-
    ——————
    3 Lenhoff advanced The Parental and Disability Act of 1985, intro-
    duced by Rep. Patricia Schroeder. See S. Wisensale, Family Leave
    Policy: The Political Economy of Work and Family in America 136–138
    (2001). She was later named Vice Chair of the Commission on Leave,
    created by the FMLA to study family and medical leave policies. See 
    29 U. S. C. §§2631
    –2632; U. S. Commission on Family and Medical Leave,
    A Workable Balance: Report to Congress on Family and Medical Leave
    Policies 210 (Apr. 30, 1996).
    4 For example, in addition to mandating pregnancy leave, the Califor-
    nia statute allowed employers to discriminate against pregnant work-
    ers. Employers could refuse to select a pregnant woman for a training
    program if she would not finish the program at least three months
    before giving birth. See 1978 Cal. Stats. ch. 1321, §1. The law limited
    pregnancy disability leave to six weeks, §1, and provided that women
    were to receive paid disability benefits for only three weeks after
    childbirth, §2, even if a particular woman remained disabled beyond
    the three-week period, and even if a man received paid disability
    benefits throughout his disability. Finally, although it prohibited
    6            COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    fore maintained their commitment to gender-neutral
    leave. See Joint Hearing on H. R. 925 before the Sub-
    committee on Civil Service and the Subcommittee on
    Compensation and Employee Benefits of the House Com-
    mittee on Post Office and Civil Service, 100th Cong., 1st
    Sess., 36 (1987) (hereinafter 1987 House Hearing) (state-
    ment of Prof. Eleanor Holmes Norton, Georgetown Uni-
    versity Law Center) (“[If California Fed.] becomes the
    model, employers will provide something for women af-
    fected by pregnancy that they are not required to provide
    for other employees. This gives fodder to those who seek
    to discriminate against women in employment. . . . In the
    [California Fed.] case, I would have preferred the inter-
    pretation urged by the [equal-treatment feminists].”).
    Congress agreed. See infra, at 14–15. Adhering to
    equal-treatment feminists’ aim, the self-care provision, 
    29 U. S. C. §2612
    (a)(1)(D), prescribes comprehensive leave for
    women disabled during pregnancy or while recuperating
    from childbirth—without singling out pregnancy or child-
    birth. See S. Rep. No. 101–77, p. 32 (1989) (A “significant
    benefit of the temporary medical leave provided by this
    legislation is the form of protection it offers women work-
    ers who bear children. Because the bill treats all employ-
    ees who are temporarily unable to work due to serious
    health conditions in the same fashion, it does not create
    the risk of discrimination against pregnant women posed
    by legislation which provides job protection only for
    pregnancy-related disability. Legislation solely protecting
    ——————
    employers from refusing to promote a woman because of pregnancy, it
    did not forbid refusing to hire a woman on that basis. See §1. See also
    Brief for National Organization for Women et al. as Amici Curiae in
    California Fed. Sav. & Loan Assn. v. Guerra, O. T. 1985, No. 85–494,
    pp. 14–15. These provisions were all expressly made inapplicable to
    employers covered by Title VII, “[i]n the event Congress enacts legisla-
    tion amending Title VII . . . to prohibit sex discrimination on the basis
    of pregnancy,” namely, the PDA. See 1978 Cal. Stats. ch. 1321, §4.
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)            7
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    pregnant women gives employers an economic incentive to
    discriminate against women in hiring policies; legislation
    helping all workers equally does not have this effect.”). In
    view of this history, it is impossible to conclude that “noth-
    ing in particular about self-care leave . . . connects it to
    gender discrimination.” Ante, at 10.
    II
    A
    Boerne next asks “whether Congress had evidence of
    a pattern of constitutional violations on the part of the
    States.” Hibbs, 
    538 U. S., at 729
    . See also Boerne, 
    521 U. S., at
    530–532. Beyond question, Congress had evi-
    dence of a well-documented pattern of workplace discrimi-
    nation against pregnant women. Section 2612(a)(1)(D)
    can therefore “be understood as responsive to, or designed
    to prevent, unconstitutional behavior.” 
    Id., at 532
    .
    Although the PDA proscribed blatant discrimination on
    the basis of pregnancy, see 42 U. S. C. §§2000e(k), 2000e–
    2, supra, at 4, n. 2, the Act is fairly described as a nec-
    essary, but not a sufficient measure. FMLA hearings
    conducted between 1986 and 1993 included illustrative testi-
    mony from women fired after becoming pregnant or giving
    birth. For example, Beverly Wilkenson was granted seven
    weeks of leave upon the birth of her child. On the eve of
    her return to work, a superior informed her that her job
    had been eliminated. He stated: “Beverly, the best thing
    for you to do is stay home and take care of your baby and
    collect your unemployment.” Hearing on H. R. 770 before
    the Subcommittee on Labor-Management Relations of the
    House Committee on Education and Labor, 101st Cong.,
    1st Sess., 12 (1989) (hereinafter 1989 House Hearing)
    (statement of Beverly Wilkenson). See also S. Rep. No.
    102–68, p. 27 (1991) (hereinafter 1991 Senate Report)
    (describing Ms. Wilkenson’s testimony). Similarly, Linda
    Pillsbury was notified that she no longer had a job three
    8            COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    weeks after her daughter was born.5 Three secretaries at
    the same workplace were also forced out of their jobs when
    they returned to work within weeks of giving birth. See
    Hearings on S. 249 before the Subcommittee on Children,
    Family, Drugs and Alcoholism of the Senate Committee on
    Labor and Human Resources, 100th Cong., 1st Sess., pt.
    2, pp. 16, 23 (1987) (hereinafter 1987 Senate Hearings)
    (statement of Linda Pillsbury).
    These women’s experiences, Congress learned, were
    hardly isolated incidents. A spokeswoman for the Mayor’s
    Commission on Women’s Affairs in Chicago testified: “The
    lack of uniform parental and medical leave policies in the
    workplace has created an environment where discrimina-
    tion is rampant. Very often we are contacted by women
    workers who are at risk of losing their jobs or have lost
    them because they are pregnant, [or have] given birth.”
    Id., at 170 (statement of Peggy Montes). See also Joint
    Hearing on The Parental and Medical Leave Act of 1986
    before the Subcommittee on Labor-Management Relations
    and the Subcommittee on Labor Standards of the House
    Committee on Education and Labor, 99th Cong., 2d
    Sess., 110, n. 18 (1986) (hereinafter 1986 House Hearing)
    (statement of Women’s Legal Defense Fund) (“[W]omen
    who are temporarily unable to work due to pregnancy,
    child-birth, and related medical conditions such as morn-
    ing sickness, threatened miscarriage, or complications
    arising from childbirth, often lose their jobs because of
    the inadequacy of their employers’ leave policies.”); 1991
    Senate Report 28 (recording that an Atlanta-based job
    counseling hotline received approximately 100 calls each
    year from women who were fired, harassed, or forced out
    of their jobs due to pregnancy or maternity-disability
    ——————
    5 The medical recovery period for a normal childbirth is four to eight
    weeks. See Nevada Dept. of Human Resources v. Hibbs, 
    538 U. S. 721
    ,
    731, n. 4 (2003).
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)           9
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    leave); 139 Cong. Rec. 1826 (1993) (remarks of Sen. Ed-
    ward Kennedy) (“[W]omen who are pregnant are discrimi-
    nated against as a general rule in our society and have
    difficulty retaining their jobs.”). As summarized by the
    American Bar Association:
    “Historically, denial or curtailment of women’s em-
    ployment opportunities has been traceable directly to
    the pervasive presumption that women are mothers
    first, and workers second. This prevailing ideology
    about women’s roles has in turn justified discrimina-
    tion against women when they are mothers or mothers-
    to-be.” 1989 House Hearing 248 (American Bar
    Association Background Report). See also Hibbs, 
    538 U. S., at 736
     (quoting same language).
    “Many pregnant women have been fired when their em-
    ployer refused to provide an adequate leave of absence,”
    Congress had ample cause to conclude. See H. R. Rep. No.
    99–699, pt. 2, p. 22 (1986). Pregnancy, Congress also
    found, has a marked impact on women’s earnings. One
    year after childbirth, mothers’ earnings fell to $1.40 per
    hour less than those of women who had not given birth.
    See 1991 Senate Report 28. See also 1989 House Hearing
    356–357 (Report of 9to5, National Association of Working
    Women (citing same study)).
    Congress heard evidence tying this pattern of discrimi-
    nation to the States. A 50-state survey by the Yale Bush
    Center Infant Care Leave Project concluded that “[t]he
    proportion and construction of leave policies available to
    public sector employees differs little from those offered
    private sector employees.” Hibbs, 
    538 U. S., at 730, n. 3
    (quoting 1986 House Hearing 33 (statement of Meryl
    Frank)). Roughly 28% of women employed in the public
    sector did not receive eight weeks of job-protected medical
    leave to recover from childbirth. See 1987 Senate Hear-
    ings, pt. 1, pp. 31, 35, 39 (statement of James T. Bond,
    10         COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    National Counsel of Jewish Women). A South Carolina
    state legislator testified: “[I]n South Carolina, as well as in
    other states . . . no unemployment compensation is paid
    to a woman who is necessarily absent from her place of
    employment because of pregnancy or maternity.” See 
    id.,
    pt. 2, p. 361 (statement of Rep. Irene Rudnick). According
    to an employee of the State of Georgia, if state employees
    took leave, it was held against them when they were
    considered for promotions: “It is common practice for my
    Department to compare the balance sheets of workers who
    have and have not used [leave] benefits in determining
    who should and should not be promoted.” Hearing on
    H. R. 2 before the Subcommittee on Labor-Management
    Relations of the House Committee on Education and
    Labor, 102d Cong., 1st Sess., 36 (1991) (statement of
    Robert E. Dawkins). See also id., at 33 (One type of leave
    for Georgia state employees “boils down to whether your
    supervisor wants you to come back or not.”). In short,
    Congress had every reason to believe that a pattern of
    workplace discrimination against pregnant women existed
    in public-sector employment, just as it did in the private
    sector.
    B
    “[A] state’s refusal to provide pregnancy leave to its
    employees,” Maryland responds, is “not unconstitutional.”
    Brief for Respondents 23 (citing Geduldig v. Aiello, 
    417 U. S. 484
    , 495 (1974)). Aiello’s footnote 20 proclaimed that
    discrimination on the basis of pregnancy is not discrimi-
    nation on the basis of sex. In my view, this case is a fit
    occasion to revisit that conclusion. Footnote 20 reads:
    “The dissenting opinion to the contrary, this case is
    . . . a far cry from cases like Reed v. Reed, 
    404 U. S. 71
    (1971), and Frontiero v. Richardson, 
    411 U. S. 677
    (1973), involving discrimination based upon gender as
    such. The California insurance program does not
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)             11
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    exclude anyone from benefit eligibility because of gen-
    der but merely removes one physical condition—
    pregnancy—from the list of compensable disabili-
    ties. While it is true that only women can become
    pregnant, it does not follow that every legislative
    classification concerning pregnancy is a sex-based
    classification . . . .
    “The lack of identity between the excluded disability
    and gender as such under this insurance program
    becomes clear upon the most cursory analysis. The
    program divides potential recipients into two groups—
    pregnant women and nonpregnant persons. While the
    first group is exclusively female, the second includes
    members of both sexes. The fiscal and actuarial bene-
    fits of the program thus accrue to members of both
    sexes.” 
    417 U. S., at 496, n. 20
    .
    First, “[a]s an abstract statement,” it is “simply false”
    that “a classification based on pregnancy is gender-
    neutral.” Bray v. Alexandria Women’s Health Clinic, 
    506 U. S. 263
    , 327 (1993) (Stevens, J., dissenting). Rather,
    discriminating on the basis of pregnancy “[b]y definition
    . . . discriminates on account of sex; for it is the capacity
    to become pregnant which primarily differentiates the fe-
    male from the male.” General Elec. Co. v. Gilbert, 
    429 U. S. 125
    , 161–162 (1976) (Stevens, J., dissenting). See
    also Issacharoff & Rosenblum, Women and the Workplace:
    Accommodating the Demands of Pregnancy, 
    94 Colum. L. Rev. 2154
    , 2180 (1994) (“[I]t is precisely because
    pregnancy is a condition unique to women that the exclu-
    sion of pregnancy from disability coverage is a sex-based
    classification . . . .”).
    This reality is well illustrated by the facts of Aiello. The
    California disability-insurance program at issue granted
    disability benefits for virtually any conceivable work
    disability, including those arising from cosmetic surgery,
    12        COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    skiing accidents, and alcoholism. See Brief for EEOC as
    Amicus Curiae in Aiello, O. T. 1973, No. 73–640, p. 7. It
    also compensated men for disabilities caused by ailments
    and procedures that affected men alone: for example,
    vasectomies, circumcision, and prostatectomies. See Brief
    for American Civil Liberties Union et al. as Amici Curiae
    in 
    id.,
     at 17–18. Only pregnancy was excluded from the
    definition of disability. See Cal. Un. Ins. Code Ann. §2626
    (West 1972); Aiello, 
    417 U. S., at 489
    . As Justice Brennan
    insightfully concluded in dissent, “a limitation is imposed
    upon the disabilities for which women workers may re-
    cover, while men receive full compensation for all disabili-
    ties suffered . . . . Such dissimilar treatment of men and
    women, on the basis of physical characteristics inextricably
    linked to one sex, inevitably constitutes sex discrimina-
    tion.” 
    Id., at 501
    .
    Second, pregnancy provided a central justification for
    the historic discrimination against women this Court
    chronicled in Hibbs. See 
    538 U. S., at 729
     (“[A] proper
    discharge of [a woman’s] maternal functions—having in
    view not merely her own health, but the well-being of the
    race—justif[ies] legislation to protect her from the greed
    as well as the passion of man.” (quoting Muller v. Oregon,
    
    208 U. S. 412
    , 422 (1908); 2d and 3d alterations in Hibbs)).
    See also Siegel, Employment Equality Under the Preg-
    nancy Discrimination Act of 1978, 94 Yale L. J. 929, 942
    (1985) (Pregnancy “is a biological difference central to the
    definition of gender roles, one traditionally believed to
    render women unfit for employment.”). Relatedly, dis-
    crimination against pregnant employees was often “based
    not on the pregnancy itself but on predictions concerning
    the future behavior of the pregnant woman when her child
    was born or on views about what her behavior should be.”
    Williams 355. See also S. Rep. No. 95–331, p. 3 (1977)
    (“[T]he assumption that women will become pregnant and
    leave the labor market is at the core of the sex stereotyp-
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)           13
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    ing resulting in unfavorable disparate treatment of women
    in the workplace.”).
    In sum, childbearing is not only a biological function
    unique to women. It is also inextricably intertwined with
    employers’ “stereotypical views about women’s commit-
    ment to work and their value as employees.” Hibbs, 
    538 U. S., at 736
    . Because pregnancy discrimination is in-
    evitably sex discrimination, and because discrimination
    against women is tightly interwoven with society’s beliefs
    about pregnancy and motherhood, I would hold that Aiello
    was egregiously wrong to declare that discrimination on
    the basis of pregnancy is not discrimination on the basis of
    sex.
    C
    Boerne’s third step requires “ ‘a congruence and propor-
    tionality between the injury to be prevented or remedied
    and the means adopted to that end.’ ” Ante, at 5 (quoting
    
    521 U. S., at 520
    ). Section 2612(a)(1)(D), I would conclude,
    is an appropriate response to pervasive discriminatory
    treatment of pregnant women. In separating self-care
    leave for the physical disability following childbirth,
    §2612(a)(1)(D), which affects only women, from family-
    care leave for parenting a newborn baby, §2612(a)(1)(A),
    for which men and women are equally suited, Congress
    could attack gender discrimination and challenge stereo-
    types of women as lone childrearers. Cf. Hibbs, 
    538 U. S., at 731
     (States’ extended “maternity” leaves, far exceeding
    a woman’s physical disability following childbirth, were
    attributable “to the pervasive sex-role stereotype that
    caring for family members is women’s work.”).
    It would make scant sense to provide job-protected leave
    for a woman to care for a newborn, but not for her recov-
    ery from delivery, a miscarriage, or the birth of a stillborn
    baby. And allowing States to provide no pregnancy-
    disability leave at all, given that only women can become
    14         COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    pregnant, would obviously “exclude far more women than
    men from the workplace.” 
    Id., at 738
    .
    The plurality’s statement that Congress lacked “wide-
    spread evidence of sex discrimination . . . in the admin-
    istration of sick leave,” ante, at 6, misses the point. So too
    does the plurality’s observation that state employees likely
    “could take leave for pregnancy-related illnesses”—
    presumably severe morning sickness, toxemia, etc.—under
    paid sick-leave plans, ante, at 7. Congress heard evidence
    that existing sick-leave plans were inadequate to ensure
    that women were not fired when they needed to take time
    out to recover their strength and stamina after childbirth.
    The self-care provision responds to that evidence by re-
    quiring employers to allow leave for “ongoing pregnancy,
    miscarriages, . . . the need for prenatal care, childbirth,
    and recovery from childbirth.” S. Rep. No. 103–3, p. 29
    (1993).
    That §2612(a)(1)(D) entitles all employees to up to 12
    weeks of unpaid, job-protected leave for a serious health
    condition, rather than singling out pregnancy or child-
    birth, does not mean that the provision lacks the requisite
    congruence and proportionality to the identified constitu-
    tional violations. As earlier noted, supra, at 6–7, Congress
    made plain its rationale for the prescription’s broader
    compass: Congress sought to ward off the unconstitutional
    discrimination it believed would attend a pregnancy-only
    leave requirement. Under the caption “Equal protection
    and non-discrimination,” Congress explained:
    “The FMLA addresses the basic leave needs of all
    employees. . . . This is an important principle reflected
    in the bill.
    “A law providing special protection to women . . . ,
    in addition to being inequitable, runs the risk of caus-
    ing discriminatory treatment. Employers might be
    less inclined to hire women . . . . For example, legisla-
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)           15
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    tion addressing the needs of pregnant women only
    might encourage discriminatory hiring practices
    against women of child bearing age. Legislation ad-
    dressing the needs of all workers equally does not
    have this effect. By addressing the serious leave
    needs of all employees, the FMLA avoids providing
    employers the temptation to discriminate [against
    women].
    .             .         .          .           .
    “The legislation is [thus] based not only on the Com-
    merce Clause, but also on the guarantees of equal pro-
    tection . . . embodied in the Fourteenth Amendment.”
    H. R. Rep. No. 102–135, pt. 1, pp. 27–28 (1991) (here-
    inafter 1991 House Report).
    Congress’ concern was solidly grounded in workplace
    realities. After this Court upheld California’s pregnancy-
    only leave policy in California Fed., Don Butler, President
    of the Merchants and Manufacturers Association, one of
    the plaintiffs in that case, told National Public Radio
    reporter Nina Totenberg that, as a result of the decision,
    “many employers will be prone to discriminate against
    women in hiring and hire males instead.” 1987 House
    Hearing 36. Totenberg replied, “But that is illegal, too”—
    to which Butler responded, “Well, that is illegal, but try to
    prove it.” Ibid.
    Finally, as in Hibbs, it is important to note the moderate
    cast of the FMLA, in particular, the considerable limi-
    tations Congress placed on §§2612(a)(1)(A)–(D)’s leave
    requirement. See 
    538 U. S., at
    738–739. FMLA leave is
    unpaid. It is limited to employees who have worked
    at least one year for the employer and at least 1,250
    hours during the past year. §§2611(2)(A), 2612(c)(1).
    High-ranking employees, including state elected officials
    and their staffs, are not within the Act’s compass.
    §§203(e)(2)(C), 2611(3). Employees must provide advance
    notice of foreseeable leaves. §2612(e). Employers may
    16             COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    require a doctor’s certification of a serious health condi-
    tion. §2613(a). And, if an employer violates the FMLA,
    the employees’ recoverable damages are “strictly defined
    and measured by actual monetary losses.” Hibbs, 
    538 U. S., at
    740 (citing §§2617(a)(1)(A)(i)–(iii)). The self-care
    provision, I would therefore hold, is congruent and propor-
    tional to the injury to be prevented.
    III
    But even if Aiello senselessly holds sway, and impedes
    the conclusion that §2612(a)(1)(D) is an appropriate re-
    sponse to the States’ unconstitutional discrimination
    against pregnant women,6 I would nevertheless conclude
    that the FMLA is valid §5 legislation. For it is a meet
    response to “the States’ record of unconstitutional partici-
    ——————
    6 Notably,    the plurality does not cite or discuss Geduldig v. Aiello, 
    417 U. S. 484
     (1974), perhaps embarrassed by that opinion’s widely criti-
    cized conclusion that discrimination based on pregnancy does not
    involve “discrimination based upon gender as such,” 
    id., at 496, n. 20
    .
    See supra, at 10–13; E. Chemerinsky, Constitutional Law 759 (3d ed.
    2006) (“It is hard to imagine a clearer sex-based distinction” than
    the one at issue in Aiello); Kay, Equality and Difference: The Case of
    Pregnancy, 1 Berkeley Women’s L. J. 1, 31 (1985) (“[Aiello] results in
    unequal treatment of similarly situated women and men who have
    engaged respectively in reproductive conduct [and wish to continue
    working]. It should be overruled.”); Law, Rethinking Sex and the
    Constitution, 
    132 U. Pa. L. Rev. 955
    , 983–984 (1984) (“Criticizing
    [Aiello] has . . . become a cottage industry. Over two dozen law review
    articles have condemned both the Court’s approach and the result. . . .
    Even the principal scholarly defense of [Aiello] admits that the Court
    was wrong in refusing to recognize that the classification was sex-based
    . . . .”); Karst, The Supreme Court 1976 Term Foreword: Equal Citizen-
    ship under the Fourteenth Amendment, 
    91 Harv. L. Rev. 1
    , 54, n. 304
    (1977) (“[T]he constitutional sport of [Aiello] and last Term’s even sillier
    statutory counterpart, General Elec. Co. v. Gilbert, 
    429 U. S. 125
     (1976),
    with their Alice-in-Wonderland view of pregnancy as a sex-neutral
    phenomenon, are good candidates for early retirement. These decisions
    are textbook examples of the effects of underrepresentation on “legisla-
    tive” insensitivity. Imagine what the presence of even one woman
    Justice would have meant to the Court’s conferences.”).
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)          17
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    pation in, and fostering of, gender-based discrimination
    in the administration of [parental and family-care] leave
    benefits.” Hibbs, 
    538 U. S., at 735
    . See also 
    id.,
     at 729–
    731, and n. 5 (Congress adduced evidence “of a pattern of
    constitutional violations on the part of the States” in
    granting parental and family-care leave).
    Requiring States to provide gender-neutral parental and
    family-care leave alone, Congress was warned, would
    promote precisely the type of workplace discrimination
    Congress sought to reduce. The “pervasive sex-role stereo-
    type that caring for family members is women’s work,” 
    id., at 731
    , Congress heard, led employers to regard required
    parental and family-care leave as a woman’s benefit.
    Carol Ball, speaking on behalf of the U. S. Chamber of
    Commerce, testified that she did not think “there are
    going to be many men that take up . . . parental leave.”
    See Hearing on S. 345 before the Subcommittee on Chil-
    dren, Family, Drugs, and Alcoholism of the Senate Com-
    mittee on Labor and Human Resources, 101st Cong., 1st
    Sess., 39 (1989) (statement of Carol Ball). She frankly
    admitted that she herself would choose to hire a man over
    an equally qualified woman if parental leave was required
    by law. Id., at 30.
    Others similarly testified that mandating gender-
    neutral parental leave would lead to discrimination
    against women. A representative of the National Federal
    of Independent Business stated: “Requiring employers to
    provide parental leave benefits creates clear pressures for
    subtle discrimination based on . . . sex. When choosing
    between two equally qualified candidates, an employer
    may be more likely to hire the candidate least likely to
    take the leave. It is the wage levels and jobs of women of
    childbearing years which are most at risk in such a situa-
    tion.” Hearing on H. R. 1 before the Subcommittee on
    Labor-Management Relations of the House Committee
    on Education and Labor, 103d Cong., 1st Sess., 95 (1993).
    18           COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    See also 1989 House Hearing 169 (statement of Cynthia
    Simpler, American Society for Personnel Administration)
    (“Since working women will be viewed as the most likely
    candidates for parental leave, hidden discrimination will
    occur if this bill becomes law. Women of child-bearing age
    will be viewed as risks, potentially disrupting operations
    through an untimely leave.”).
    Conversely—unlike perceptions surrounding who takes
    parental and family-care leave—Congress was told that
    men and women take medical leave approximately equal-
    ly. According to one study, male workers missed an aver-
    age of 4.9 days of work per year due to illness or injury;
    female workers missed 5.1 days. See 1991 House Report,
    pt. 1, p. 28. “[T]he incidence of serious medical conditions
    that would be covered by medical leave under the bill,”
    Congress determined, “is virtually the same for men and
    women. Employers will find that women and men will
    take medical leave with equal frequency.” Ibid. “[P]a-
    rental and medical leave,” Congress was thus alerted,
    “are inseparable”:
    “In the words of an old song, ‘You can’t have one with-
    out the other.’
    .            .           .           .          .
    “Adoption of parental leave protections without
    medical leave would . . . encourage discrimination
    against women of child-bearing age, who constitute
    approximately 73 percent of all the women in the la-
    bor force.
    “Employers would tend to hire men, who are much
    less likely to claim [the parental leave] benefit. . . .
    “Parental leave without medical leave would be the
    modern version of protective labor laws.” 1986 House
    Hearing 33–34 (Statement of Irene Natividad, Na-
    tional Women’s Political Caucus).
    Congress therefore had good reason to conclude that the
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)           19
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    self-care provision—which men no doubt would use—
    would counter employers’ impressions that the FMLA
    would otherwise install female leave. Providing for self-
    care would thus reduce employers’ corresponding incentive
    to discriminate against women in hiring and promotion.
    In other words, “[t]he availability of self-care leave to men
    serves to blunt the force of stereotypes of women as prima-
    ry caregivers by increasing the odds that men and women
    will invoke the FMLA’s leave provisions in near-equal
    numbers.” See Brief for National Partnership for Women
    & Families et al. as Amici Curiae 26. As Judge Lipez
    explained:
    “If Congress had drawn a line at leave for caring for
    other family members, there is greater likelihood that
    the FMLA would have been perceived as further rea-
    son to avoid granting employment opportunities to
    women. Heretofore, women have provided most of the
    child and elder care, and legislation that focused on
    these duties could have had a deleterious impact be-
    cause of the prevalent notion that women take more
    advantage of such leave policies. The inclusion of per-
    sonal medical leave in the scheme, unrelated to any
    need to care for another person, undermines the as-
    sumption that women are the only ones taking leave
    because men, presumably, are as likely as women to
    get sick.” Laro v. New Hampshire, 
    259 F. 3d 1
    , 21
    (CA1 2001) (dissenting opinion).
    Senator Barbara Boxer advanced a similar point. Re-
    sponding to assertions that the FMLA would lead employ-
    ers to discriminate against women, Senator Boxer stated:
    “[T]o say that women will not be hired by business is a
    specious argument . . . . Men also get sick. They get
    cancer. They get heart disease. They have ailments. And
    this bill applies to men and women.” 139 Cong. Rec. 1697
    (1993). See also 1987 Senate Hearings, pt. 2, p. 536 (“I
    20         COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    just think it’s wrong that there will be a perception that
    this is something that only women will take and they are,
    therefore, more expensive. Both men and women have
    medical conditions . . . .” (statement of Prof. Susan Deller
    Ross, Georgetown University Law Center)).
    The plurality therefore gets it wrong in concluding that
    “[o]nly supposition and conjecture support the contention
    that the self-care provision is necessary to make the family-
    care provisions effective.” Ante, at 9. Self-care leave, I
    would hold, is a key part of Congress’ endeavor to make it
    feasible for women to work and have families. See 1991
    Senate Report 25–26 (“This legislation is essential if the
    nation is to address the dramatic changes that have oc-
    curred in the American workforce in recent years. . . . The
    once-typical American family, where the father worked for
    pay and the mother stayed at home with the children, is
    vanishing. . . . Today, more than one-half of all mothers
    with infants under one year of age work outside the home.
    That figure has doubled since 1970 . . . . By the year 2000,
    about three out of every four American children will have
    mothers in the workforce.”). By reducing an employer’s
    perceived incentive to avoid hiring women, §2612(a)(1)(D)
    lessens the risk that the FMLA as a whole would give rise
    to the very sex discrimination it was enacted to thwart.
    The plurality offers no legitimate ground to dilute the
    force of the Act.
    IV
    Two additional points. First, this Court reached a dif-
    ferent conclusion than the one I reach here in Board of
    Trustees of Univ. of Ala. v. Garrett, 
    531 U. S. 356
     (2001),
    and Kimel, 
    528 U. S. 62
    . In those cases, as we observed in
    Hibbs, we reviewed statutes targeting disability and age
    discrimination, respectively. Neither disability nor age is
    a suspect classification under this Court’s Equal Protec-
    tion Clause jurisprudence; States may discriminate on the
    Cite as: 566 U. S. ____ (2012)            21
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    basis of disability or age as long as the classification is
    rationally related to a legitimate state interest. See Gar-
    rett, 
    531 U. S., at
    366–367; Kimel, 
    528 U. S., at
    83–84.
    Therefore, for the statutes to be responsive to or designed
    to prevent unconstitutional discrimination, Congress
    needed to rely on a pattern of irrational state discrimina-
    tion on the basis of disability or age. See Garrett, 
    531 U. S., at 368
    ; Kimel, 
    528 U. S., at 89
    . Here, however,
    Congress homed in on gender discrimination, which trig-
    gers heightened review. See United States v. Virginia, 
    518 U. S. 515
    , 531 (1996) (“Parties who seek to defend gender-
    based government action must demonstrate an exceeding-
    ly persuasive justification for that action.” (internal quota-
    tion marks omitted)). “[I]t was [therefore] easier for
    Congress to show a pattern of state constitutional violations.”
    Hibbs, 
    538 U. S., at 736
    .
    Finally, the plurality’s opinion does not authorize state
    employers to violate the FMLA, although it does block
    injured employees from suing for monetary relief. The
    self-care provision remains valid Commerce Clause legis-
    lation, Maryland concedes, and consequently binds the
    states, as well as the private sector. Tr. of Oral Arg. 25;
    Brief for Respondents 32–33. An employee wrongly denied
    self-care leave, Maryland also acknowledges, may, pursu-
    ant to Ex parte Young, 
    209 U. S. 123
     (1908), seek injunc-
    tive relief against the responsible state official. See Brief
    for Respondents 33. Moreover, the U. S. Department of
    Labor may bring an action against a state for violating the
    self-care provision and may recover monetary relief on an
    employee’s behalf. 
    29 U. S. C. §§2617
    (b)(2)–(3), (d).
    V
    The plurality pays scant attention to the overarching
    aim of the FMLA: to make it feasible for women to work
    while sustaining family life. Over the course of eight
    years, Congress considered the problem of workplace
    22        COLEMAN v. COURT OF APPEALS OF MD.
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    discrimination against women, and devised the FMLA to
    reduce sex-based inequalities in leave programs. Essen-
    tial to its design, Congress assiduously avoided a legisla-
    tive package that, overall, was or would be seen as geared
    to women only. Congress thereby reduced employers’
    incentives to prefer men over women, advanced women’s
    economic opportunities, and laid the foundation for a more
    egalitarian relationship at home and at work. The self-
    care provision is a key part of that endeavor, and, in my
    view, a valid exercise of congressional power under §5 of
    the Fourteenth Amendment. I would therefore reverse the
    judgment of the U. S. Court of Appeals for the Fourth
    Circuit.
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 10-1016

Citation Numbers: 182 L. Ed. 2d 296, 132 S. Ct. 1327, 566 U.S. 30, 2012 U.S. LEXIS 2315

Judges: Scalia, Kennedy, Roberts, Thomas, Auto, Scaua, Ginsburg, Breyer, Sotomayor, Kagan

Filed Date: 3/20/2012

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 10/19/2024

Authorities (17)

Pennhurst State School and Hospital v. Halderman , 101 S. Ct. 1531 ( 1981 )

Seminole Tribe of Florida v. Florida , 116 S. Ct. 1114 ( 1996 )

City of Boerne v. Flores , 117 S. Ct. 2157 ( 1997 )

Board of Trustees of Univ. of Ala. v. Garrett , 121 S. Ct. 955 ( 2001 )

Tuan Anh Nguyen v. Immigration & Naturalization Service , 121 S. Ct. 2053 ( 2001 )

Nevada Department of Human Resources v. Hibbs , 123 S. Ct. 1972 ( 2003 )

California Federal Savings & Loan Ass'n v. Guerra , 107 S. Ct. 683 ( 1987 )

Muller v. Oregon , 28 S. Ct. 324 ( 1908 )

Jennifer Miles v. Bellfontaine Habilitation Center , 481 F.3d 1106 ( 2007 )

Reed v. Reed , 92 S. Ct. 251 ( 1971 )

United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co. , 26 S. Ct. 282 ( 1906 )

Brockman v. Wyoming Department of Family Services , 342 F.3d 1159 ( 2003 )

Mary Touvell v. Ohio Department of Mental Retardation and ... , 422 F.3d 392 ( 2005 )

Kimel v. Florida Board of Regents , 120 S. Ct. 631 ( 2000 )

Coleman v. Maryland Court of Appeals , 626 F.3d 187 ( 2010 )

Nelson v. University of Texas at Dallas , 535 F.3d 318 ( 2008 )

George S. Toeller v. Wisconsin Department of Corrections , 461 F.3d 871 ( 2006 )

View All Authorities »

Cited By (39)

Fletcher v. LA Dept of Trans ( 2021 )

Paula Maliandi v. Montclair State University , 845 F.3d 77 ( 2016 )

Tina Elizabeth Lee v. State of Iowa and Polk County Clerk ... , 2016 Iowa Sup. LEXIS 17 ( 2016 )

Sherri L. Renner v. Supreme Court of Florida ( 2022 )

Chondra Johnson v. Prairie View A and M Univ , 587 F. App'x 213 ( 2014 )

Kristie Bellow v. Bd of Supr LA State University ( 2013 )

Duncan Giles v. National Railroad Passenger Corporation ( 2023 )

Bryant v. Texas Department of Aging & Disability Services , 781 F.3d 764 ( 2015 )

Colleen Cimerman v. Gary Cook , 561 F. App'x 447 ( 2014 )

Coleman v. Columbus State Community College , 2015 Ohio 4685 ( 2015 )

Freddie Goode v. Central Virginia Legal Aid Society , 807 F.3d 619 ( 2015 )

Mojsilovic v. Oklahoma Ex Rel. Board of Regents , 841 F.3d 1129 ( 2016 )

Alison Minnis v. State of Washington, Departmen , 675 F. App'x 728 ( 2017 )

Amended April 22, 2016 Tina Elizabeth Lee v. State of Iowa ... ( 2016 )

Tina Lee v. State of Iowa, Polk County Clerk of Court , 2012 Iowa Sup. LEXIS 53 ( 2012 )

Lott v. Not-For-Profit Hospital Corporation ( 2019 )

Stewart v. White , 61 F. Supp. 3d 118 ( 2014 )

Hubbard v. St. Louis Psychiatric Rehabilitation Center , 556 F. App'x 547 ( 2014 )

Kristie Bellow v. Bd of Supr LA State University , 550 F. App'x 181 ( 2013 )

Ramirez v. State ex rel CYFD ( 2014 )

View All Citing Opinions »