Snetsinger v. Montana University System , 325 Mont. 148 ( 2004 )


Menu:
  •                                           No. 03-238
    IN THE SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF MONTANA
    
    2004 MT 390
    CAROL SNETSINGER, NANCY SIEGEL,
    CARLA GRAYSON, ADRIANNE NEFF, and
    PRIDE, INC., A Montana Non-Profit Corporation,
    Plaintiffs and Appellants,
    v.
    MONTANA UNIVERSITY SYSTEM, STATE OF MONTANA,
    RICHARD CROFTS, in his official capacity as Commissioner of
    Higher Education, and MARGIE THOMPSON, ED JASMIN, LYNN
    MORRISON-HAMILTON, CHRISTIAN HUR, JOHN MERCER,
    RICHARD ROEHM and MARK SEMMENS, in their official capacities
    as members of the Board of Regents,
    Defendants and Respondents.
    APPEAL FROM:        District Court of the First Judicial District,
    In and for the County of Lewis and Clark, Cause No. CDV 2002-097,
    The Honorable Thomas C. Honzel, Judge presiding.
    COUNSEL OF RECORD:
    For Appellants:
    Holly Jo Franz (argued), Franz & Driscoll, Helena, Montana
    Tamara Lange (argued), American Civil Liberties, New York, New York
    Beth Brenneman, ACLU of Montana, Helena, Montana
    For Respondents:
    LeRoy H. Schramm (argued), Montana University System, Helena,
    Montana
    For Amicus Northwest Women’s Law Center:
    James P. Reynolds, Reynolds, Motl and Sherwood, Helena, Montana
    For Amicus Montana Human Rights Network, Outfield Alliance, Rainbow
    Connection, University Congregational United Church of Christ, Missoula,
    United Congregational United Church of Christ, Butte, and Flathead Valley
    United Church of Christ, Kalispell:
    Monte Jewell, Jewell Law Office, Missoula, Montana
    For Amicus MEA-MFT:
    Jennifer C. Pizer, Lambda Legal Defense & Education Fund, Los
    Angeles, California
    Debra D. Parker; Mark S. Connell, Connell Law Firm, Missoula, Montana
    For Amicus Women’s Law Caucus:
    Joan Jonkel, Kimberly P. Dudik, Attorneys at Law, Missoula, Montana
    For Amicus United Families International:
    Paul Benjamin Linton, Attorney at Law, Northbrook, Illinois
    Lance Lovell, The Lovell Law Firm, Billings, Montana
    For Amicus The Montana Catholic Conference:
    Michael J. Rieley, Attorney at Law, Helena, Montana
    For Amicus Focus on the Family and Family Research Council:
    Jason L. Harkins, Attorney at Law, Billings, Montana
    Glen Lavy, Alliance Defense Fund, Scottsdale, Arizona
    For Amicus Members of the Leadership of the 58th Montana Legislature:
    Bridgitt Erickson, Attorney at Law, Lincoln, Montana
    For Amicus The National Legal Foundation:
    Patrick F. Flaherty, Attorney at Law, Great Falls, Montana
    Steven W. Fitschen, Attorney at Law, Virginia Beach, Virginia
    Orally Argued and Submitted: November 13, 2003
    Decided: December 30, 2004
    Filed:
    __________________________________________
    Clerk
    Justice Jim Regnier delivered the Opinion of the Court.
    ¶1       Appellants filed an action in the First Judicial District Court, Lewis and Clark County,
    2
    seeking a declaratory judgment that the Montana University System’s policy prohibiting
    employees from receiving dependent insurance coverage for their same-sex domestic partners
    violates their rights under the Montana Constitution. The Montana University System filed
    a Motion to Dismiss, which the District Court granted.
    ¶2     The sole issue raised on appeal is whether the Montana University System’s policy
    prohibiting gay employees from receiving insurance coverage for their same-sex domestic
    partners violates their rights under the Montana Constitution.
    ¶3     We reverse the District Court.
    BACKGROUND
    ¶4     Carol Snetsinger and Nancy Siegel are same-sex domestic partners, as are Carla
    Grayson and Adrianne Neff. Snetsinger and Grayson are employees of the Montana
    University System, but their domestic partners, Siegel and Neff, are not. Snetsinger, Siegel,
    Grayson, and Neff, along with PRIDE, Inc., a non-profit organization of lesbian, gay,
    bisexual and transgender Montanans and their supporters, filed an action in the District Court
    challenging the University System’s policy prohibiting same-sex domestic partners of gay1
    employees from purchasing dependent benefits.
    ¶5     Snetsinger and Siegel consider themselves married and hold themselves out to their
    families and their community as a couple in a committed, marital relationship. They have
    stated they would marry if legally permitted to do so. They own their home together in joint
    tenancy with rights of survivorship, have a joint checking account and share all living
    1
    We adopt Appellants’ use of the term “gay” to mean lesbians, gay men and
    bisexual people.
    3
    expenses. Likewise, Grayson and Neff consider themselves married and hold themselves out
    as such. They own their home together, share living expenses and are raising a child
    together.
    ¶6      As a benefit of employment, the University System provides a group health insurance
    plan for its employees and their dependents. The University System pays the premium for
    the employee; if the employee would like coverage for any dependents, the employee must
    pay an additional premium. The University System’s policy defines dependent eligibility.
    It states:
    An eligible employee . . . may enroll the following dependents in the Plan.
    1. Spouse–A lawful spouse as defined in Montana law. See 26-1-602, 40-1-
    301, and 40-1-311 MCA. A Declaration of Common-Law Spouse form may
    be obtained from the campus payroll/personnel office and must be used if a
    common-law spouse is to be enrolled in the Plan.
    2. Child(ren)–An unmarried dependent child under age 19.
    3. Student–An unmarried student under age 25, who is a dependent of the
    employee and/or spouse and dependent on the employee and/or spouse for
    support and maintenance, and whose time is principally devoted to the
    attendance of a school or college. The Claims Administrator may periodically
    require the submission of proof that student status is maintained.
    ¶7      Snetsinger and Grayson are not permitted to enroll their same-sex domestic partners
    because they are not “dependents” as defined by the University System’s policy. They argue
    the policy impermissibly discriminates against them based on their sex, sexual orientation
    and marital status and violates their rights to equal protection and dignity provided by Article
    II, Section 4, the right to privacy provided by Article II, Section 10, and the rights to pursue
    life’s basic necessities and to seek safety, health and happiness provided by Article II,
    Section 3, of the Montana Constitution because the policy does not extend coverage to same-
    4
    sex domestic partners.
    ¶8     The University System filed a Motion to Dismiss in the District Court pursuant to
    Rule 12(b)(6), M.R.Civ.P., on the ground the Complaint did not state a legal claim upon
    which relief could be granted. The District Court granted the motion. Snetsinger and the
    other plaintiffs appeal from the District Court’s Order.
    ¶9     We note that an unusual number of Amici Curiae briefs have been filed in this appeal.
    The following amici have submitted briefs in support of the Appellants: Northwest Women’s
    Law Center; Montana Human Rights Network, Outfield Alliance, Rainbow Connection,
    University Congregational United Church of Christ, Missoula, United Congregational United
    Church of Christ, Butte, and Flathead Valley United Church of Christ, Kalispell; MEA-
    MFT; Women’s Law Caucus. Amici who submitted briefs in support of the Respondents
    are: The Honorable Roy Brown, Duane Grimes, Doug Mood, Fred Thomas, and Corey
    Stapleton, Members of the Leadership of the 58th Montana Legislature; the Montana Catholic
    Conference; the National Legal Foundation; Focus On the Family and Family Research
    Council; United Families International.
    STANDARD OF REVIEW
    ¶10    A complaint should not be dismissed for failure to state a claim unless it appears
    beyond doubt that the plaintiff can prove no set of facts in support of a claim which would
    entitle the plaintiff to relief. Dukes v. Sirius Const., Inc., 
    2003 MT 152
    , ¶ 11, 
    316 Mont. 226
    , ¶ 11, 
    73 P.3d 781
    , ¶ 11 (citation omitted). A motion to dismiss under Rule 12(b)(6),
    M.R.Civ.P., has the effect of admitting all well-pleaded allegations in the complaint. Dukes,
    ¶ 11. In considering the motion, the complaint is construed in the light most favorable to the
    5
    plaintiff and all allegations of fact contained therein are taken as true. Dukes, ¶ 11 (citation
    omitted).
    ¶11    The District Court's determination that the Appellants failed to state a claim for which
    relief was available is a conclusion of law. Our standard of review of a district court's
    conclusion of law is whether its interpretation of the law is correct. Dukes, ¶ 11.
    DISCUSSION
    ¶12    Whether the Montana University System’s policy prohibiting gay employees from
    receiving insurance coverage for their same-sex domestic partners violates their rights under
    the Montana Constitution.
    ¶13    At the outset, it is important to note what this case is not about. Lest there be any
    doubt, the Appellants clearly stated, both in their brief and in oral argument, that they are not
    challenging Montana’s marriage laws which provide marriage is available only to partners
    of the opposite sex. Although the constitutionality of such laws has been attacked in various
    states recently with much national attention, the Appellants emphasized during oral argument
    that this case does not present such a challenge. Therefore, we have not been asked nor will
    we address the question of whether Montana’s marriage statutes discriminates against same-
    sex couples by denying them the right to marry.
    ¶14     Appellants argue that the University System’s Policy violates their rights to equal
    protection and dignity provided by Article II, Section 4, by classifying them based on their
    sex, sexual orientation and marital status and depriving them, without sufficient justification,
    of the benefits other employees and their families receive as compensation. They also argue
    the policy violates their right to privacy provided by Article II, Section 10, and the rights to
    6
    pursue life’s basic necessities and to seek safety, health and happiness provided by Article
    II, Section 3, of the Montana Constitution.
    ¶15    Article II, Section 4, of the Montana Constitution guarantees equal protection of the
    law to all persons. It provides that “[n]o person shall be denied the equal protection of the
    laws.” “The Fourteenth Amendment to the United States Constitution and Article II, Section
    4, of the Montana Constitution embody a fundamental principle of fairness: that the law must
    treat similarly-situated individuals in a similar manner.” McDermott v. Montana Dept. of
    Corrections, 
    2001 MT 134
    , ¶ 30, 
    305 Mont. 462
    , ¶ 30, 
    29 P.3d 992
    , ¶ 30. Article II, Section
    4, of the Montana Constitution provides even more individual protection than the Equal
    Protection Clause in the Fourteenth Amendment of the United States Constitution. Cottrill
    v. Cottrill Sodding Serv. (1987), 
    229 Mont. 40
    , 42, 
    744 P.2d 895
    , 897.
    ¶16    When analyzing an equal protection challenge, we “must first identify the classes
    involved and determine whether they are similarly situated.” Henry v. State Compensation
    Ins. Fund, 
    1999 MT 126
    , ¶ 27, 
    294 Mont. 449
    , ¶ 27, 
    982 P.2d 456
    , ¶ 27 (citation omitted).
    A law or policy that contains an apparently neutral classification may violate equal
    protection if “in reality [it] constitut[es] a device designed to impose different burdens on
    different classes of persons.” State v. Spina, 
    1999 MT 113
    , ¶ 85, 
    294 Mont. 367
    , ¶ 85, 
    982 P.2d 421
    , ¶ 85.
    ¶17    Once the relevant classifications have been identified, we next determine the
    appropriate level of scrutiny. Henry, ¶ 29. We apply one of three levels of scrutiny when
    addressing a challenge under the Montana Constitution’s Equal Protection Clause: strict
    scrutiny, middle-tier scrutiny, or the rational basis test. McDermott, ¶¶ 31-32. Strict scrutiny
    7
    applies if a suspect class or fundamental right is affected. McDermott, ¶ 31. Under the strict
    scrutiny standard, the State has the burden of showing that the law, or in this case the policy,
    is narrowly tailored to serve a compelling government interest. McDermott, ¶ 31.
    ¶18    We apply middle-tier scrutiny if the law or policy affects a right conferred by the
    Montana Constitution, but is not found in the Constitution’s Declaration of Rights.
    McDermott, ¶ 32. Under middle-tier scrutiny, the State must demonstrate the law or policy
    in question is reasonable and the need for the resulting classification outweighs the value of
    the right to an individual. McDermott, ¶ 32.
    ¶19    The third level of scrutiny is the rational basis test. McDermott, ¶ 32. The rational
    basis test is appropriate when neither strict scrutiny nor middle-tier scrutiny apply.
    McDermott, ¶ 32. Under the rational basis test, the law or policy must be rationally related
    to a legitimate government interest. McDermott, ¶ 32.
    ¶20    The District Court began its analysis by noting the University System’s policy
    provides that its employees may obtain health benefits for their dependents, and dependent
    eligibility is limited to spouses and certain children. The court then defined the classes, for
    equal protection purposes, as employees who have dependents and those who do not. Thus,
    according to the District Court, the policy is neutral with respect to gender and sexual
    orientation. Inherent in this classification definition, however, is the statutory definition of
    spouse. The District Court reasoned the classification is based on marital status. The
    District Court determined the marital relationship imposes on married persons certain legal
    responsibilities, including the duty to support each other out of their property and labor.
    Section 40-2-102, MCA. The court noted the Appellants are not subject to similar legal
    8
    obligations and responsibilities as are imposed on married persons. This distinction
    apparently persuaded the District Court to conclude the University System’s policy to
    provide benefits only to married couples satisfied the rational basis test.
    ¶21    On appeal, the University System predictably echoes the District Court’s conclusion
    that the policy in question classifies people based on marital status. In arguing the
    classifications are rational, the University System relies on Montana’s statute defining
    marriage as a relationship between a man and a woman. Section 40-1-103, MCA. The
    University System also cites to § 40-1-401, MCA, which explicitly states a marriage between
    persons of the same sex is prohibited. It posits that because state and federal statutes are full
    of distinctions between married and unmarried individuals (i.e. taxes, inheritance, adoption,
    rights of witnesses and eligibility for government benefits), the University System’s reliance
    on Montana’s marriage statute for its classification is “inherently rational.” It argues the
    marriage distinction provides a rational and administratively simple method to determine
    eligibility for defining dependent status for health benefits.
    ¶22    In adopting such a policy, the University System rejected the concept of “domestic
    partners,” which would provide same-sex couples the same health benefits as opposite-sex
    couples. As pointed out by Amicus Northwest Women’s Law Center, this is in direct
    contrast to many universities, corporations and municipalities throughout the United States
    that do allow same-sex domestic partners to qualify for benefits. Among the list of such
    entities are the states of Washington, Oregon, and California as well as the United States
    House of Representatives. The University System’s policy at issue here permits three classes
    of employees to purchase health benefits for their partners: 1) those, who with their partners,
    9
    are joined in “solemnized marriage” under § 40-1-301, MCA; 2) those, who with their
    partners, have elected to enter into marriage using a Declaration of Marriage without
    solemnization under § 40-1-311, MCA; and 3) those, who with their opposite-sex partners,
    are not married but who sign an “Affidavit of Common Law Marriage.” This third avenue
    is not provided by statute nor does it satisfy § 40-1-311, MCA.
    ¶23    Although the University System maintains its system is “inherently rational” because
    it is based on the Montana marriage statutes, we conclude the policy is inherently flawed.
    The policy allows unmarried opposite-sex couples, who may only have a fleeting
    relationship, to receive health insurance benefits by signing an Affidavit. The Affidavit is
    provided by the University System and is typically used to establish benefit eligibility for a
    partner in a relationship that has not been solemnized or registered as a marriage under
    Montana law. Presumably, a couple who declines to sign a statutory written declaration of
    marriage without solemnization, and instead signs the Affidavit provided by the University
    System, may choose not to marry at all, but rather may choose to sign a document in order
    to receive employment benefits.
    ¶24    Common law marriage in Montana is an equitable doctrine used to ensure people are
    treated fairly once a relationship ends. Under our common law, such a marriage is
    established when a couple: 1) is competent to enter into a marriage, 2) mutually consents
    and agrees to a common law marriage, and 3) cohabits and is reputed in the community to
    be husband and wife. In re Ober, 
    2003 MT 7
    , ¶ 9, 
    314 Mont. 20
    , ¶ 9, 
    62 P.3d 1114
    , ¶ 9
    (citing Matter of Estate of Hunsaker, 
    1998 MT 279
    , ¶ 32, 
    291 Mont. 412
    , ¶ 32, 
    968 P.2d 281
    , ¶ 32). A closer examination of common law marriage in Montana discloses that the
    10
    concept is designed, in part, to prevent an unjust economic harm to couples who have held
    themselves out as husband and wife as our common law marriage cases typically deal with
    the equitable distribution of economic benefits after the death of one of the parties or
    separation of the relationship. We are aware of no Montana case in which a common law
    marriage was established prospectively. In fact, one writer has noted that no jurisdiction
    permits a statement of future intent to create a common law marriage. See, e.g., Hon. John
    B. Crawley, Is the Honeymoon over for Common-Law Marriage: A Consideration of the
    Continued Viability of the Common-Law Marriage Doctrine, 29 Cumb.L.Rev. 399, 403
    (1998-99). We are also not aware of any Montana case in which a common law marriage
    was established without one of the parties involved in the relationship using extrinsic
    evidence to prove “that the three elements of common-law marriage all existed at one time.”
    Hunsaker, ¶ 43. At the very least, despite assertions by the University System, common law
    marriages are not automatically recognized by signing their Affidavit. The University
    System’s policy creates no such marriage, nor should it. A policy that allows unmarried
    opposite-sex couples to sign an Affidavit asserting they are common law married, when they
    may not be able to legally establish a common law marriage, certainly does not promote
    marriage, and instead, detracts from it.
    ¶25    In Matter of Estate of McClelland (1975), 
    168 Mont. 160
    , 
    541 P.2d 780
    , although the
    couple signed an affidavit asserting a common law marriage, we declined to recognize such
    a marriage. In McClelland, Genie Driver appealed the District Court’s determination that
    she was not the common law wife of James McClelland. We affirmed the District Court’s
    decision, despite the fact that James and Genie signed affidavits declaring their intention to
    11
    be common law married in order to receive welfare benefits from the states of Oregon and
    Montana. We reasoned the evidence, including the affidavit, when considered in its entirety,
    did not support the elements of a common law marriage.
    ¶26    A closer look at the University System’s policy discloses that marital status, as
    defined by Montana statutes and case law, plays little if any role in determining who is
    eligible for benefits. Under the policy, the partner of a non-gay employee would qualify for
    benefits by signing an Affidavit, when the partner of a gay employee would not qualify for
    the same benefits when signing the same Affidavit.
    ¶27    Thus, we conclude the District Court erred in its first step of equal protection analysis.
    In adopting marital status as the litmus test and then reasoning that the classes involved are
    employees with dependents vs. employees without dependents, the District Court
    misinterpreted the University System policy. As pointed out above, marital status is not the
    defining difference. In truth, unmarried opposite-sex couples are able to avail themselves
    of health benefits under the University System’s policy while unmarried same-sex couples
    are denied the health benefits. These two groups, although similarly situated in all respects
    other than sexual orientation, are not treated equally and fairly. The principal purpose of the
    Equal Protection Clause, Article II, Section 4, of the Montana Constitution, is to ensure
    citizens are not subject to arbitrary and discriminatory state action. Therefore, we conclude
    there is no justification for treating the two groups differently, nor is the University System’s
    policy rationally related to a legitimate governmental interest. Once the illusory marital
    status is removed from the analysis, there is no legitimate governmental interest in treating
    the two groups differently. As former Chief Justice Turnage recognized in his concurrence
    in Gryczan v. State (1997), 
    283 Mont. 433
    , 456, 
    942 P.2d 112
    , 126, when the State
    12
    criminalizes sexual acts between persons of the same-sex and decriminalizes the same sexual
    conduct engaged in by opposite-sex couples, it is “[c]learly . . . a denial of the constitutional
    guarantee of equal protection of the law in violation of . . . Article II, Section 4 of the
    Montana Constitution.” Similarly, the University System’s policy of denying health benefits
    to unmarried same-sex couples while granting the benefits to unmarried opposite-sex couples
    results in a denial of equal protection.
    ¶28    Further, we are unconvinced that the University System’s policy is justified based on
    administrative efficiency. Other policies could certainly be adopted without infringing on
    the important constitutional provisions that protect all Montanans. We are confident the
    University System can meet this task.
    ¶29    Because we hold that the University System’s policy violates equal protection of the
    laws under the Montana Constitution by impermissibly treating unmarried same-sex couples
    differently than unmarried opposite-sex couples, we need not address the Appellants’
    arguments that the policy violates equal protection by classifying them based on sex or that
    it violates their rights under Article II, Sections 3 and 10, of the Montana Constitution.
    ¶30    At this point it is important to respond to several of the points urged by the dissent.
    The dissent contends that we have decided this case on a theory or issue that was not argued
    or raised by the parties. This simply is not true. The Appellants squarely argued in their
    brief that the University System’s policy was constitutionally infirm because of the Affidavit
    procedure employed by the University System. Additionally, the issue presented by
    Appellants in their brief clearly states: “Whether a public employer that provides an
    opportunity for employees to purchase insurance for spouses or for different-sex domestic
    partners who sign an Affidavit of Common Law Marriage but not for same-sex domestic
    13
    partners violates the rights to equal protection and dignity . . . .” Further, the Affidavit
    procedure was a major focus during oral argument; both sides aired their respective positions
    eloquently and fully on the issue as framed in this Opinion.
    ¶31      The dissent argues “[t]he problem is that Appellants did not raise this claim [the
    Affidavit procedure] in the District Court, the District Court did not consider or rule upon
    such claim, and therefore, Appellants are not permitted to raise a new argument on appeal.”
    However, nowhere in its brief does the Respondent raise the dissent’s argument that the
    Affidavit procedure was not raised at the District Court level and therefore we should not
    consider it. Respondent actually devotes approximately five pages of its brief to a common
    law marriage analysis that includes the Affidavit process, yet never argues the issue was not
    brought up at the District Court level. Additionally, the constitutionality of the University
    System’s policy of allowing opposite-sex couples to receive benefits while denying same-sex
    couples those same benefits has always been the issue, both at the District Court and in this
    Court.
    ¶32      The dissent also mistakenly contends that somehow we have rewritten the doctrine
    of common law marriage in Montana. Again, the dissent misinterprets our decision. In
    truth, it is the dissent who suggests that we deviate from our common law marriage
    jurisprudence. The dissent apparently takes the position that because the University
    System’s policy is rationally related to the institution of marriage, by applying the
    “thousands of years of cultural experience,” “hundreds of years of legal precedent” and our
    statutory presumption provided in § 26-1-601(30), MCA, the policy is legitimate. By this
    rationale, those employees who fill in the Affidavit supplied by the University System are
    instantly joined or recognized to be in a common law marriage. Notwithstanding this
    14
    statutory presumption which has existed for decades, our case law has required more than
    signing a piece of paper to establish a common law marriage. The dissent now urges that
    we abandon this precedent and declare that only the University System’s Affidavit is
    necessary because the State has an interest in promoting marriage. This rationale is just not
    correct.
    ¶33    Meanwhile, we rely on our past precedent that clearly defines what is required to
    create a common law marriage. We reiterate–we know of no case where a common law
    marriage has been recognized prospectively. Our case law consistently holds that one of the
    parties to the relationship must assert, through extrinsic evidence, that all of the common
    law marriage elements were met and occurred at the same time, sometime during their
    relationship. This type of relationship–a marriage–cannot be created through an Affidavit
    procedure used to provide benefits for University System employees. While the Affidavit
    could possibly be used as one part of the extrinsic evidence used to demonstrate a common
    law marriage existed, it does not a marriage make. Those employees who sign an Affidavit
    may not be legally married under Montana law and may not have legal responsibilities to one
    another, like a married couple would have to each other. Those opposite-sex couples who
    fill out the Affidavit in order to receive benefits may be shocked to think that they have in
    fact entered into a marriage that requires court action to dissolve as suggested by the dissent.
    ¶34    Although the dissent relies on the marriage statutes to provide a rational basis for the
    University System’s policy, we believe the University System’s Affidavit process actually
    serves to dilute marriage as defined and provided for by Montana statute. In this state, there
    is no common law in any case where the law is declared by statute. Section 1-1-108, MCA.
    In Montana, common law marriages are declared valid by statute. Section 40-1-403, MCA.
    15
    However, a common law procedure–a written declaration of a common law marriage such
    as an affidavit–cannot be followed when it is inconsistent with clear statutory law. Should
    opposite-sex employees wish to prospectively assure their marital status through the use of
    an affidavit, there is no need to resort to the “common law” since Montana statutory law
    provides for a written declaration of marriage without solemnization and they may avail
    themselves of this informal statutory process as provided by the Legislature in § 40-1-311,
    MCA.
    ¶35    Our opinion today reiterates and reaffirms existing common law marriage
    jurisprudence. We haven’t changed anything. We do make clear, however, that any
    organization that adopts an administrative procedure in order to provide employment benefits
    to opposite-sex partners who may not be in a legal marital relationship, must do the same for
    same-sex couples. To not do so violates equal protection.
    ¶36    As one last point, the dissent worries that state, federal and private agencies that
    routinely recognize common law marriages by administrative declaration, and pay financial
    benefits based upon that administrative action could be affected by this decision. However,
    as the dissent points out, “those agencies defer to the law of the applicant’s domiciliary state
    in regard to the validity and establishment of a common law marriage.” Here, we have not
    changed common law marriage. These agencies may continue to operate in any fashion they
    desire and rely on our long history of case law in determining whether individuals are
    “married” by common law. However, should the agencies wish to give prospective
    recognition of common law marriage, they should require the parties to comply with § 40-1-
    311, MCA.
    ¶37    Reversed.
    16
    /S/ JIM REGNIER
    We Concur:
    /S/ JAMES C. NELSON
    /S/ PATRICIA O. COTTER
    /S/ W. WILLIAM LEAPHART
    17
    Justice James C. Nelson specially concurs.
    I. Introduction
    ¶38    “We the people”--Montana’s Constitution begins with these three words. These
    words precede “the people[‘s]” statement of shared commitment to improving their quality
    of life and equality of opportunity and to securing the blessings of liberty for present and
    future generations. In these three words, there is no mention of race, there is no mention of
    gender, nor is there any reference to religious affiliation, to ethnic background, to marital
    status or to sexual orientation. Simply and eloquently, the first words of Montana’s
    Constitution are words of inclusion.
    ¶39    Yet, for many Montanans these words carry no such promise. These Montanans live
    and work and raise their families knowing that, truly, they are not part of “the people.”
    These Montanans are gays and lesbians. And, for that--for being who they are--they are
    ridiculed, ostracized, despised, demonized and condemned. Their pleas for respect and for
    equal justice are answered by their government, by their institutions--and by “We the
    people”--with intolerance and bigotry, albeit impeccably adorned in sanctimonious rhetoric,
    sterile logic and hollow assurances.
    ¶40    Though marginalized by their government and institutions, gay and lesbian couples
    live in 55 of 56 counties in Montana. More than twelve hundred Montana households
    identified themselves in the 2000 census as being headed by gay and lesbian couples. That
    is roughly 0.6% of the total coupled households in this state, married or unmarried.2 Smith
    2
    See U.S. Census Bureau, United States Census 2000, Table PCT22, Unmarried
    Partner Households and Sex of Partners, at
    http://www.census.gov/main/www/cen2000.html; David Smith and Gary Gates, Gay and
    19
    and Gates estimate that these official data represent an undercount of about 62%. 3
    ¶41    I concur in our Opinion. However, Montana’s Constitution provides a stronger
    bulwark against the majoritarian oppression that gays and lesbians suffer daily in this State
    and for the claims under consideration here. It is for this reason that I write separately.
    ¶42    I begin with some background and then turn to my interpretation of Montana’s
    Constitution as regards the issue before us. Finally, I will conclude with what I believe is
    a proper basis for resolving this case in addition to that set out in this Court’s Opinion.
    II. Background
    ¶43    The amicus brief filed by the Montana Human Rights Network, et al., in this case
    thoroughly discusses how gays and lesbians historically have been unfairly stigmatized and
    stereotyped. They have been wrongfully accused of having impaired judgment, stability,
    reliability and general social and vocational capabilities. The evidence is to the contrary.
    American Psychiatric Association, Fact Sheet: Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Issues (Feb.
    2000) (hereinafter APA Fact Sheet); American Psychological Association, Minutes of the
    Annual Meeting of the Council of Representatives, 30 Am. Psychologist 620, 633 (1975).
    They have been falsely stereotyped as being pedophiles. Carole Jenny, et al., Are Children
    at Risk of Sexual Abuse by Homosexuals?, 94 Pediatrics 44 (1994) (finding that only 0.7%
    of child sex abusers are homosexual); John Boswell, Christianity, Social Tolerance and
    Homosexuality 16 (1980) (noting that accusations of child molestation have historically been
    Lesbian Families in the United States: Same-Sex Unmarried Partner Households (2001),
    at http://www.hrc.org/content/contentgroups/ (hereinafter Smith).
    3
    See Smith, at n.2.
    20
    made against disfavored minorities vulnerable to such “propaganda,” be they homosexuals,
    Jews or others).
    ¶44    Children raised by gay and lesbian parents have been found to develop no differently
    than children raised by heterosexual parents in terms of self-esteem, psychological well-
    being, cognitive functioning and social adjustment, despite claims to the contrary. APA
    Fact Sheet (“[N]umerous studies have shown that the children of gay parents are as likely
    to be healthy and well adjusted as children raised in heterosexual households.”); Judith
    Stacey and Timothy Biblarz, (How) Does the Sexual Orientation of Parent Matter?, 66 Am.
    Soc. Rev. 159, 161 (2001) (surveying research); Ellen C. Perrin, M.D., and the Committee
    on Psychological Aspects of Child and Family Health, American Academy of Pediatrics,
    Policy Statement: Coparent or Second Parent Adoption by Same Sex Parents, 109 Pediatrics
    339, 339 (Feb. 2002). And, there is no evidence that gays and lesbians do not function as
    effectively in the workplace or that they contribute any less to society than do their
    heterosexual counterparts.
    ¶45    It is overwhelmingly clear that gays and lesbians have been historically subject to
    unequal treatment and invidious discrimination. See, e.g., Watkins v. United States Army
    (9th Cir. 1989), 
    875 F.2d 699
    , 724-28 (Norris, J., concurring), cert. denied, 
    498 U.S. 957
    ,
    
    111 S. Ct. 384
    , 
    112 L. Ed. 2d 395
     (1990); High Tech Gays v. Defense Indus. Sec. Clearance
    Office (9th Cir. 1990), 
    895 F.2d 563
    , 573; Ben-Shalom v. Marsh (7th Cir. 1989), 
    881 F.2d 454
    , 465, cert denied by Ben-Shalom v. Stone, 
    494 U.S. 1004
    , 
    110 S. Ct. 1296
    , 
    108 L. Ed. 2d 473
     (1990); Padula v. Webster (D.C. Cir. 1987), 
    822 F.2d 97
    , 104; Tanner v. Oregon Health
    Sciences Univ. (1998), 
    971 P.2d 435
    , 447; Laurence H. Tribe, American Constitutional Law
    21
    1616 (2d ed. 1988).
    ¶46    Gays and lesbians have been stereotyped as Communists and security risks. Patricia
    A. Cain, Litigating for Lesbian and Gay Rights: A Legal History, 
    79 Va. L
    . Rev. 1551, 1565
    (Oct. 1993) (hereinafter Cain). In 1953, President Eisenhower issued Executive Order
    10,450 which required the dismissal of all homosexual government employees. Cain, at
    1566. Until 1965, homosexual aliens could not be admitted to the United States because
    they were classified as sexual deviants under 8 U.S.C. § 1182(a)(4). Tracey Rich, Sexual
    Orientation Discrimination in the Wake of Bowers v. Hardwick, 
    22 Ga. L
    . Rev. 773, 773 n.4.
    (Spring 1988); Boutilier v. INS (1967), 
    387 U.S. 118
    , 124, 
    87 S. Ct. 1563
    , 1567, 
    18 L. Ed. 2d 661
     (upholding deportation because “Congress commanded that homosexuals not be allowed
    to enter.”)
    ¶47    Similarly, in the workplace, gays and lesbians historically have been the focus of
    discriminatory treatment. See, e.g., Weaver v. Nebo School Dist. (D. Utah 1998), 
    29 F. Supp. 2d 1279
     (lesbian high school coach in Utah fired because of sexual orientation);
    Miguel v. Guess (Wash.App.Div.3 2002), 
    51 P.3d 89
     (lesbian x-ray technician in hospital
    fired because of sexual orientation); De Santis v. Pacific Tel. & Tel. Co. (9th Cir. 1979), 
    608 F.2d 327
     (California telephone company discriminated against gay and lesbian operators);
    Quinn v. Nassau County Police Dept. (E.D.N.Y. 1999), 
    53 F. Supp. 2d 347
     (gay New York
    police officer sexually harassed because of his sexual orientation).
    ¶48    And, gays and lesbians are frequently the victims of violence and hate crimes.
    Federal Bureau of Investigation, Hate Crime Statistics 2000 (November 19, 2001), and 2001
    22
    (November 25, 2002).4 Indeed, grim testament to this sort of violence and hate occurred in
    our sister state of Wyoming in October 1998, when Matthew Shephard, a gay college
    student, was savagely beaten, tied to a fence and left to die.
    ¶49    Gay and lesbian parents are frequently denied custody of their children or are
    subjected to burdensome restrictions because of their sexual orientation and irrespective of
    their parenting ability. See, e.g., Ex parte H.H. (Ala. 2002), 
    830 So. 2d 21
    , 26 (Moore, C.J.,
    concurring in denial of custody to lesbian mother on ground that “[h]omosexual conduct is
    . . . abhorrent, immoral, detestable, a crime against nature, and a violation of the laws of
    nature and of nature’s God [and] an inherent evil against which children must be
    protected.”); Weigand v. Houghton (Miss. 1999), 
    730 So. 2d 581
    , 586-87; Bottoms v. Bottoms
    (Va. 1995), 
    457 S.E.2d 102
    , 107-08.
    4
    See also Bureau of Justice Statistics, Hate Crimes Reported in NIBRS 1997-99
    (Sept. 2001), at http://www.ojp.gov/bjs/pub/pdf/hcrn99.pdf (homosexuals face
    disproportionate levels of bias-motivated violence and harassment).
    23
    ¶50    The American Psychiatric Association points out that
    when compared to other social groups, homosexuals are still among the most
    stigmatized groups in the nation. Hate crimes are prevalent. Gay men and
    lesbians are still banned from serving openly in the US military service. Child
    custody decisions still frequently view gay and lesbian people as unfit parents.
    Gay and lesbian adolescents are often taunted and humiliated in their school
    settings. Many professional persons and employees in all occupations are still
    fearful of identifying as gay or lesbians in their work settings. Gay
    relationships are not recognized in any legal way.
    APA Fact Sheet. In fact, gays and lesbians share a history of persecution comparable to that
    of blacks and women. People v. Garcia (Cal.App.4th Dist. 2000), 
    77 Cal. App. 4th 1269
    ,
    1276, 
    92 Cal. Rptr. 2d 339
    .
    ¶51    Similarly, majoritarian politics relegates gays and lesbians to a position of political
    powerlessness. As Justices Brennan and Marshall observed, “[b]ecause of the immediate
    and severe opprobrium often manifested against homosexuals once so identified publicly,
    members of this group are particularly powerless to pursue their rights openly in the political
    arena.” Rowland v. Mad River Local School Dist. (1985), 
    470 U.S. 1009
    , 1014, 
    105 S. Ct. 1373
    , 1377, 
    84 L. Ed. 2d 392
     (Brennan, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari; joined by
    Marshall, J.).
    ¶52    Montana reflects this discriminatory animus. Despite the judicial de-criminalization
    of same-sex relationships in Gryczan v. State (1997), 
    283 Mont. 433
    , 
    942 P.2d 112
    , and
    despite pleas every session by the gay community, the Legislature has refused to amend
    §§ 45-2-101(20) and 45-5-505, MCA, to except out of the deviate sexual conduct statutes
    non-commercial, same-sex conduct between consenting adults. The 1997 Legislature
    amended § 40-1-401, MCA, to specifically prohibit same sex marriages and contractual civil
    relationships. In 2001, a bill seeking to add sexual orientation to Montana’s hate crime
    24
    statute (HB 233) never made it out of the House Judiciary Committee. Constitutional
    Initiative 96, amending the Montana Constitution to prohibit same sex marriages, passed
    overwhelmingly at the November 2004 general election. Sadly, many politicians and “We
    the people” rarely pass up an opportunity to bash and condemn gays and lesbians despite the
    fact that these citizens are our neighbors and that they work, pay taxes, vote, hold public
    office, own businesses, provide professional services, worship, raise their families and serve
    their communities in the same manner as heterosexuals.
    ¶53    In terms of the workplace, there is no evidence either in the record here or anecdotally
    that gays and lesbians are any less qualified, reliable or productive employees than are
    heterosexuals. Indeed, as amicus MEA-MFT points out, because equal work merits equal
    pay and benefits, nearly 200 educational institutions in at least 35 states and thousands of
    companies, including 40% of Fortune 500 companies, include domestic partners in their
    benefits policies.5 Likewise, there is no evidence either in the record here or anecdotally that
    extending health and medical insurance benefits to gay and lesbian domestic partners
    increases the benefit or administrative costs of insurance plans. Indeed, the evidence is to
    the contrary.6
    5
    See Human Rights Campaign WorkNet, Domestic Partnership Benefits, Colleges
    and Universities, at
    http://www.hrc.org/worknet/asp_search/results.asp?sKey=List&List=III&t=DP and
    http://www.hrc.org/worknet/dp/index.asp.
    6
    See, for example, KPMG Peat Marwick, Health Benefits in 1997, Executive
    Summary 6 (June 1997); International Society of Certified Employee Benefit Specialists,
    Domestic Partner Benefits: Commentary, Census (May 1995), at 1 (hereinafter ISCEBS);
    Society for Human Resources Management, Domestic Partner Benefits Mini-Survey
    (1997) (hereinafter SHRM Mini-Survey); Hewitt Associates, Domestic Partner Benefits
    2000 1, 27 (2000).
    25
    III. Montana’s Constitution
    ¶54    When the Declaration of Rights of Montana’s Constitution was drafted, the Bill of
    Rights Committee (the Committee) clearly intended that the rights set out in Article II stand
    on their own footing and provide individuals with fundamental rights and protections far
    broader than those available through the federal system. The Committee’s February 22,
    1972 transmittal letter to the Convention delegates states that “new safeguards” had been
    added to the Declaration [Bill] of Rights “to meet the changing circumstances of
    contemporary life” and:
    In presenting this proposed Declaration of Rights, the committee notes
    that the guidelines and protections for the exercise of liberty in a free society
    come not from government but from the people who create that government.
    It is that spirit which has motivated this committee to insure for
    Montana’s future, through this bill of rights, a more responsible government
    that is Constitutionally commanded never to forget that government is created
    solely for the welfare of the people so that the people can more fully enjoy the
    heritage of American liberty within the structure of that government.
    Montana Constitutional Convention, Bill of Rights Committee Proposal, February 22, 1972,
    p. 619 (hereinafter Proposal).
    ¶55    Taking these admonitions to heart, this Court has, for example, applied the broader
    protections of Montana’s Constitution in a number of contexts involving individual privacy
    (Gryczan v. State (1997), 
    283 Mont. 433
    , 
    942 P.2d 112
    ); personal autonomy (Armstrong v.
    State, 
    1999 MT 261
    , 
    296 Mont. 361
    , 
    989 P.2d 364
    ); search and seizure (State v. Bullock
    (1995), 
    272 Mont. 361
    , 
    901 P.2d 61
    ; State v. Siegal (1997), 
    281 Mont. 250
    , 
    934 P.2d 176
    ,
    overruled in part by State v. Kuneff, 
    1998 MT 287
    , 
    291 Mont. 474
    , 
    970 P.2d 556
    ; State v.
    Elison, 
    2000 MT 288
    , 
    302 Mont. 228
    , 
    14 P.3d 456
    ); the right to counsel (State v. Johnson
    (1986), 
    221 Mont. 503
    , 
    719 P.2d 1248
    ); the environment (MEIC v. Dept. of Environmental
    26
    Quality, 
    1999 MT 248
    , 
    296 Mont. 207
    , 
    988 P.2d 1236
    ); and the right of participation and the
    right to know (Common Cause v. Statutory Committee (1994), 
    263 Mont. 324
    , 
    868 P.2d 604
    ;
    Great Falls Tribune v. Public Schools (1992), 
    255 Mont. 125
    , 
    841 P.2d 502
    ; Associated
    Press v. Bd. of Public Educ. (1991), 
    246 Mont. 386
    , 
    804 P.2d 376
    ; Jarussi v. Board of
    Trustees (1983), 
    204 Mont. 131
    , 
    664 P.2d 316
    ).
    ¶56    Furthermore, and acknowledging the Committee’s statement that no part of the
    Constitution is more important, Proposal, p. 619, we have repeatedly recognized the rights
    found in Montana’s Declaration of Rights as being “fundamental,” meaning that these rights
    are significant components of liberty, any infringement of which will trigger the highest level
    of scrutiny, and thus, the highest level of protection by the courts. Walker v. State, 
    2003 MT 134
    , ¶ 74, 
    316 Mont. 103
    , ¶ 74, 
    68 P.3d 872
    , ¶ 74 (citing Dorwart v. Caraway, 
    2002 MT 240
    ,
    ¶ 96, 
    312 Mont. 1
    , ¶ 96, 
    58 P.3d 128
    , ¶ 96 (Nelson, J., concurring); Butte Community Union
    v. Lewis (1986), 
    219 Mont. 426
    , 430, 
    712 P.2d 1309
    , 1311; Kloss v. Edward D. Jones & Co.,
    
    2002 MT 129
    , ¶ 52, 
    310 Mont. 123
    , ¶ 52, 
    54 P.3d 1
    , ¶ 52 (Nelson, J., concurring), cert.
    denied, 
    538 U.S. 956
    , 
    123 S. Ct. 1633
    , 
    155 L. Ed. 2d 506
     (2003)).
    ¶57    It follows, therefore, that Montana’s Constitution should, likewise, provide more
    protection against discrimination based on sexual orientation than the Court’s Opinion in this
    case reflects.
    ¶58    The case at bar is one involving the fundamental guarantee of individual dignity and
    equal protection protected under Article II, Section 4 of the Montana Constitution. For more
    than a decade and a half we have recognized that Montana’s equal protection clause “provides
    for even more individual protection” than does the federal equal protection clause in section
    27
    one of the Fourteenth Amendment. Cottrill v. Cottrill Sodding Service (1987), 
    229 Mont. 40
    ,
    42, 
    744 P.2d 895
    , 897.
    ¶59    Montana’s equal protection clause, Article II, Section 4, provides:
    Individual dignity. The dignity of the human being is inviolable. No
    person shall be denied the equal protection of the laws. Neither the state nor
    any person, firm, corporation, or institution shall discriminate against any
    person in the exercise of his civil or political rights on account of race, color,
    sex, culture, social origin or condition, or political or religious ideas.
    As Professors Larry Elison and Fritz Snyder observe:
    As a practical matter, the vagaries of life coupled with the allure of power and
    privilege deny equality among persons, and make difficult the application and
    enforcement of equal protection before the law. Perhaps that is why “in recent
    years the equal protection guarantee has become the single most important
    concept in the Constitution for the protection of individual rights.”
    Larry M. Elison and Fritz Snyder, The Montana Constitution: A Reference Guide 34 (2001)
    (hereinafter Elison) (quoting John E. Nowwak & Ronald D. Rotunda, Constitutional Law 595
    (5th ed. 1995)).
    ¶60    Historically, the mantle of equal protection law has expanded steadily to protect
    different groups of persons who were prosecuted and abused for simply being who they were
    born to be--racial and religious minorities and women, are examples.
    Prior to passage of the Fourteenth Amendment to the U.S. Constitution
    (and perhaps the French Revolution), the idea of equality was limited to
    persons of power, usually free, white male property owners. . . . Over time, the
    notion of equality under law has expanded [to include Blacks and women], and
    theoretically most persons are now included. The 1972 Montana Constitution
    provides the most inclusive scheme of “equal rights” of any known
    constitution.
    Elison, at 35. And, “[a]t the heart of the Constitution’s guarantee of equal protection lies the
    simple command that the Government must treat citizens as individuals, not as simply
    28
    components of a racial [or] sexual . . . class.” J.E.B. v. Alabama ex rel. T.B. (1994), 
    511 U.S. 127
    , 152-53, 
    114 S. Ct. 1419
    , 1434, 128 L.Ed.2d. 89.
    ¶61    However much equal protection jurisprudence has enlarged the scope of persons
    guaranteed this right, unfortunately gays and lesbians have been left behind. Sexual and
    gender orientation is not considered a “suspect class” and discrimination so based does not
    merit strict scrutiny/compelling interest analysis under federal law. See Lofton v. Kearney
    (S.D. Fla. 2001), 
    157 F. Supp. 2d 1372
    , 1382 (collecting cases at n.14), affirmed by Lofton v.
    Sec’y of the Dep’t of Children and Family Services (11th Cir. 2004), 
    358 F.3d 804
    ; Baker v.
    State (Vt. 1999), 
    744 A.2d 864
    , 878 n.10; Lawrence v. Texas (2003), 
    539 U.S. 558
    , 579-88,
    
    123 S. Ct. 2472
    , 2484-85, 
    156 L. Ed. 2d 508
     (O’Connor, J., concurring). In fact, as this
    separate Opinion earlier points out, gays and lesbians continue to suffer the effects of unequal
    treatment, often with the blessing, express or implied, of the government, its institutions, and
    its elected officials. Indeed, as already noted, laws and policies have been adopted which
    specifically target gays and lesbians for unequal treatment.
    ¶62    As with federal case law, this Court’s jurisprudence has never acknowledged gender
    orientation as a suspect class. Although we have stated that Article II, Section 4 provides
    more individual protection than does its federal counterpart, Cottrill, 299 Mont. at 42, 744
    P.2d at 897, in practice, Montana’s equal protection jurisprudence--as the Court’s Opinion
    demonstrates--largely follows federal law. See Vicki C. Jackson, Constitutional Dialogue
    29
    and Human Dignity: States and Transnational Constitutional Discourse, 
    65 Mont. L
    . Rev.
    15, 28-29 n.45 (Winter 2004) (hereinafter Jackson); Elison, at 36-38. 7
    ¶63    This approach, however, is antithetical to the plain language of Montana’s equal
    protection clause and, in particular, to one of its components--the guarantee of inviolable
    human dignity--a textual protection unique among the fifty states. Jackson, at 21.
    ¶64    Montana’s human dignity clause was drawn from the Puerto Rican Constitution,
    Article II, Section 1. Jackson, at 22. This clause follows a history of international and
    foreign constitution-making and human rights declarations at the end of World War II and
    reflects the international community’s focus on human dignity as a fundamental value.
    Jackson, at 26. Puerto Rican courts and constitutional scholars have characterized the
    concept of the dignity of the human being as
    “the moral basis for democratic government,” and implies the “essential
    equality” of all people before the law. In other words, the inviolable dignity
    of human beings must be reflected in both the governance structures of a
    democracy and the way in which individual members are treated.
    Jackson, at 23 (quoting Juan M. Garcia-Passalacqua, Puerto Rican Constitutional Law 41
    (1974)).
    ¶65    Notwithstanding these venerable roots, however, this Court’s jurisprudence has, for
    the most part, treated the human dignity clause, not as a fundamental value to be recognized
    7
    But see Dorwart, ¶ 84 (federal constitutional decisions may neither bound nor
    weaken similar, but greater guarantees of individual rights afforded by Montana’s
    Constitution).
    30
    in its own right,8 but rather, as reinforcing other values such as the protection against unlawful
    searches and seizures, government discrimination, and privacy. Jackson, at 27-32.
    ¶66    The dimensions of the individual dignity clause included within Article II, Section 4,
    have not been well developed by this Court. See Elison, at 34, 36; Matthew O. Clifford and
    Thomas P. Huff, Some Thoughts on the Meaning and Scope of the Montana Constitution’s
    “Dignity” Clause With Possible Applications, 
    61 Mont. L
    . Rev. 301 (hereinafter Clifford).
    Nor have we discussed the various clauses within Article II, Section 4 in relation to each
    other and with a view to interpreting this section as a coherent whole.
    ¶67    For example, in Walker, we held that, read together with Article II, Section 22, the
    individual dignity clause provides Montanans with greater protections from cruel and unusual
    punishments than does the federal constitution. We also noted that the federal constitution
    does not expressly provide for the right to human dignity. Walker, ¶ 73. And, in In re Mental
    Health of K.G.F., 
    2001 MT 140
    , ¶¶ 45-60, 
    306 Mont. 1
    , ¶¶ 45-60, 
    29 P.3d 485
    , ¶¶ 45-60, we
    stated that the dignity of those persons subject to involuntary mental health commitments
    required effective assistance of counsel and appropriate due process and that groups of
    people should not be singled out and “devalued as members of society” or treated as “an
    inferior second-class of citizens.” We have also invoked the dignity clause in other contexts:
    Armstrong, ¶¶ 71-73 (bodily integrity); Oberg v. Billings (1983), 
    207 Mont. 277
    , 280, 
    674 P.2d 494
    , 495 (right not to be subjected to a polygraph exam as a condition of employment);
    Girard v. Williams, 
    1998 MT 231
    , ¶¶ 77-80, 
    291 Mont. 49
    , ¶¶ 77-80, 
    966 P.2d 1155
    , ¶¶ 77-
    8
    But see Walker, ¶ 82, where we recognized the right of inviolable human dignity
    as a separate, stand-alone right.
    31
    80 (Nelson, J., concurring) (child custody); and In re C.R.O., 
    2002 MT 50
    , ¶¶ 45-54, 
    309 Mont. 48
    , ¶¶ 45-54, 
    43 P.3d 913
    , ¶¶ 45-54 (Nelson, J., Cotter, J., Leaphart, J., dissenting)
    (termination of parental rights).
    ¶68    Our approach, however, has failed to give full effect to the language and unique
    constituent parts of Montana’s equal protection clause and to the textual protection of
    inviolable human dignity in cases involving fundamental human rights.
    Article II, section 4 reaches beyond the boundaries of traditional equal
    protection. The language is unique to the extent it recognizes human dignity
    as a dimension of, or corollary to, the concept of equal protection of the law.
    The language also portends to create a right to equality within the realm of
    private activity, eliminating the “state action” requirement attached to the
    comparable provision of the U.S. Constitution.
    Elison, at 35.
    ¶69    In my view, this Court’s equal protection jurisprudence has been too long bounded by
    federal equal protection case law where fundamental human rights are at issue. There is no
    good reason why we should not begin to afford all Montanans the full protections intended
    by the framers when they adopted Article II, Section 4. As one commentator has suggested,
    “Montana lawyers should jettison federal discrimination analysis in favor of a Montana
    analysis free of gender-based standards.” Elison, at 36 (quoting Wendy A. Fitzgerald,
    Toward Dignity in the Workplace: Miller-Wohl and Beyond, 
    49 Mont. L
    . Rev. 147 (1988)).
    ¶70    I agree and I believe that this is the appropriate case in which we should begin to
    develop the law of equal protection based on Montana’s unique Constitutional guarantee of
    the inviolability of human dignity coupled with the right to equal protection of the law and
    the prohibition against private and State discrimination. It is to that approach that I now turn.
    IV. The Analytical Model
    32
    ¶71    Again, Article II, Section 4 provides:
    Individual dignity. The dignity of the human being is inviolable. No
    person shall be denied the equal protection of the laws. Neither the state nor
    any person, firm, corporation, or institution shall discriminate against any
    person in the exercise of his civil or political rights on account of race, color,
    sex, culture, social origin or condition, or political or religious ideas.
    Clifford and Huff point out that this provision of the Constitution is composed of three
    clauses: the individual dignity clause (after which the entire section is named); the equal
    protection clause; and the anti-discrimination clause. Clifford, at 304.
    ¶72    However, our canons of constitutional construction require that we treat each separate
    clause as both substantively meaningful and not redundant. “In construing a constitutional
    provision it is our duty to give meaning to every word, phrase, clause, and sentence therein,
    if it is possible so to do.” State ex rel. Diederichs v. State Highway Comm’n (1931), 
    89 Mont. 205
    , 211, 
    296 P. 1033
    , 1035. Clifford and Huff suggest that the plain language of
    Article II, Section 4 be interpreted as a cohesive whole so as to fulfill this canon of
    construction:
    [T]he language of the dignity provision moves in a logical progression from the
    general to the specific. The title of the provision itself is “Individual Dignity;”
    thus, we must presume that all the language in the provision treats this topic in
    some respect. The first sentence, the dignity clause, obviously addresses
    dignity by declaring that human dignity is inviolable. The second sentence, we
    believe, goes on to declare one way in which human dignity can be violated--
    by denying someone the equal protection of the law based on some sort of
    arbitrary classification. . . .
    The third sentence of Article 4 [sic], the anti-discrimination clause, we
    believe, fleshes out the meaning of the equal protection right by enumerating
    certain types of classifications which the authors of the dignity provision
    believed to be arbitrary. . . .
    Clifford, at 305-06.
    33
    ¶73   Using this analytical model, I address the issue before us: Whether the Montana
    University System’s policy prohibiting homosexual employees from receiving insurance
    coverage for their same-sex domestic partners violates their rights under the Montana
    Constitution.
    34
    A.
    ¶74    Article II, Section 4 is entitled “Individual dignity.” The first clause of Article II,
    Section 4, the “individual dignity clause,” provides: “The dignity of the human being is
    inviolable.” As to this clause, Clifford and Huff state:
    The title of the provision itself is “Individual Dignity;” thus, we must presume
    that all the language in the provision treats this topic in some respect. The first
    sentence, the dignity clause, obviously addresses dignity by declaring that
    human dignity is inviolable.
    Clifford, at 305.
    ¶75    Under this part of the model, we must necessarily start by acknowledging the obvious:
    pursuant to Article II, Section 4, the right of human dignity is “inviolable.” That means that
    this right is “incapable of being violated.” Black’s Law Dictionary 832 (7th ed. 1999). As
    Clifford and Huff observe: “To say, as the Montana Constitution does, that ‘[t]he dignity of
    the human being is inviolable’ is thus to assert that the intrinsic worth, the basic humanity,
    of persons may not be violated.” Clifford, at 303.
    ¶76    This statement strikes at the heart of the issue before us. The intrinsic worth and the
    basic humanity of gays and lesbians--i.e., their human dignity--has not been recognized to
    date.9 Indeed, as already demonstrated, this fundamental, core value is, in many instances,
    denied gays and lesbians through laws and policies enacted by the government, as here.
    9
    Gryczan was decided on privacy grounds under Article II, Section 10. Gryczan,
    283 Mont. at 456, 942 P.2d at 126. However, then Chief Justice Jean A. Turnage would
    have reached the same result in Gryczan on the basis of equal protection. Gryczan, 283
    Mont. at 456-58, 942 P.2d at 126-28 (Turnage, C.J., concurring and dissenting).
    35
    ¶77    That human dignity is described as being “inviolable” is significant, as this right is the
    only Article II guarantee that carries this absolute prohibition: Human dignity may not be
    violated--no exceptions.
    ¶78    Article II, Section 4 is consistent with this Country’s historical treatment of human
    dignity as a central, foundational ideal at the root of our concept and system of ordered liberty
    and of our ethical tradition. See Clifford, at 308-14. There is nothing in the record or debates
    of Montana’s Constitutional Convention which would demonstrate that the delegates had any
    other view of the scope of human dignity. Indeed, Delegate Wade Dahood, chair of the
    Committee, stated: “[t]he intent of Section 4 is simply to provide that every individual in the
    State of Montana, as a citizen of this state, may pursue his inalienable rights without having
    any shadows cast upon his dignity through unwarranted discrimination.”                 Montana
    Constitutional Convention, Verbatim Transcript, March 7, 1972, p. 1643.
    ¶79    Laws and policies which single out, degrade and demonize persons based on their
    gender or sexual orientation--i.e., for simply being who they are--casts a shadow on the
    individual dignity of such persons and devalues those persons basic humanity and the intrinsic
    worth that all people possess. See Walker, ¶¶ 81-82. Such treatment repudiates the “essential
    equality” of all people before the law and the “moral basis for democratic government.”
    Jackson, at 23. Gays and lesbians have the moral right and moral responsibility to confront
    the most fundamental questions about the meaning and value of their own lives, to answer
    to their own consciences and convictions, see Armstrong, ¶ 72, and, as autonomous human
    beings, the inherent right to form relationships with whomever they choose. These rights are
    no more nor less than heterosexuals enjoy. Indeed, they are precisely the same rights that
    36
    those representing and supporting the Respondents rightly enjoy and demand. Unequal
    treatment based on sexual orientation is an affront to the inviolable right of human dignity.
    Government policies that allow or require such treatment are, in my view, per se unlawful
    under the dignity clause of Article II, Section 4. Such is the University’s policy at issue here-
    -it treats gay and lesbian couples unequally in terms of employment; equal work does not
    merit equal benefits based on nothing else than gender and sexual orientation.
    B.
    ¶80    The second clause of Article II, Section 4, the “equal protection clause,” provides:
    “No person shall be denied the equal protection of the laws.” As to that clause, Clifford’s and
    Huff’s model provides:
    The second sentence, we believe, goes on to declare one way in which human
    dignity can be violated--by denying someone the equal protection of the law
    based on some sort of arbitrary classification.
    Clifford, at 305-06.
    ¶81    Again it must be noted at the outset, that the equal protection clause states that “No
    person” shall be denied the equal protection of the laws. The language is clear and
    unambiguous. “No person” means simply that--there is no language in this clause excepting
    out of this guarantee gays and lesbians. At least our society has not come to the position that
    homosexuals are not even to be considered as persons.
    ¶82     As has already been pointed out, neither federal jurisprudence nor this Court’s case
    law recognizes gender or sexual orientation as an arbitrary classification or “suspect class”
    for equal protection purposes. This view, however popular, is inherently illogical when one
    acknowledges that the entire focus of laws directed at gays and lesbians is sex. Majoritarian
    37
    morality and prevailing political ideology are offended by the fact that people of the same sex
    have sexual relations with each other. This offense translates into laws and policies that
    explicitly or implicitly demonize homosexuals and make them a disfavored class.
    Heterosexuals, on the other hand, are a favored class because their sexual relations are with
    persons of the opposite sex. Homosexuals are a disfavored class because their sexual
    relations are with persons of the same sex. Regardless, however, the defining criteria of
    either class is plainly and simply sex--or, to be more specific, with which sex one is having
    sex. To paraphrase an old adage, “When they say it isn’t about sex, it’s about sex.”
    ¶83    Laws based on gender orientation are palpably sex-based and are, therefore, suspect
    classifications under conventional equal protection analysis.
    ¶84    Andrew Koppelman, an associate professor of law and political science at
    Northwestern University, makes this point in two starkly simple syllogisms:
    First syllogism:
    (1) Laws that make people’s legal rights depend on their sex are
    sex-based classifications.
    (2) Laws that discriminate against gay people are laws that make
    people’s legal rights depend on their sex. . . .
    Therefore,
    (3) Laws that discriminate against gay people are sex-based
    classifications.
    Second syllogism:
    (1) Sex-based classifications are subject to heightened scrutiny.
    (2) (from the first syllogism) Laws that discriminate against gay
    people are sex-based classifications.
    Therefore,
    (3) Laws that discriminate against gay people are subject to
    heightened scrutiny.
    Andrew Koppelman, The Gay Rights Question in Contemporary American Law 53-54 (2002)
    (hereinafter Koppelman).
    38
    ¶85    Moreover, it has been the law in Montana for two decades that
    [a] suspect class is one “saddled with such disabilities, or subjected to such a
    history of purposeful unequal treatment, or relegated to such a position of
    political powerlessness as to command extraordinary protection from the
    majoritarian political process.”
    In re C.H. (1984), 
    210 Mont. 184
    , 198, 
    683 P.2d 931
    , 938 (quoting San Antonio School
    District v. Rodriguez (1973), 
    411 U.S. 1
    , 28, 
    93 S. Ct. 1278
    , 1294, 
    36 L. Ed. 2d 16
    ). Given the
    discussion with which I began this separate Opinion, it cannot reasonably be argued that gays
    and lesbians do not fit within this definition of suspect class.
    ¶86    Therefore, I conclude that gays and lesbians constitute a suspect class under
    conventional equal protection analysis. Unequal treatment based on sexual orientation denies
    the person equal treatment, equal justice, and equal protection under the law.
    ¶87    In the case at bar, heterosexual couples are entitled to more and better employment
    benefits than are homosexual couples. This unequal treatment is based on gender and sexual
    orientation and is, therefore, sex-based--it is a classification which is inherently arbitrary and
    suspect, because it violates the inviolable human dignity of the persons so classified and those
    persons’ fundamental right to equal protection of the laws.
    C.
    ¶88    The third clause of Article II, Section 4, the “anti-discrimination clause,” provides:
    “Neither the state nor any person, firm, corporation, or institution shall discriminate against
    any person in the exercise of his civil or political rights on account of race, color, sex, culture,
    social origin or condition, or political or religious ideas.” The final part of Clifford’s and
    Huff’s model states:
    39
    The third sentence of Article 4 [sic], the anti-discrimination clause, we
    believe, fleshes out the meaning of the equal protection right by enumerating
    certain types of classifications which the authors of the dignity provision
    believed to be arbitrary. . . .
    Clifford, at 306.
    ¶89    The arbitrary classifications enumerated in the discrimination clause of Section 4 are
    race, color, sex, culture, social origin or condition, and political or religious ideas. But, as
    Clifford and Huff point out, this list is not exhaustive of arbitrary classifications, because if
    that were the case, then the second clause, the equal protection clause, would be surplusage.
    Presumably the framers of the Constitution included the more general equal protection clause
    so as to leave open the possibility of other prohibited classifications beyond those recognized
    at that time. Moreover, the inclusion of the more general provision protecting the right of
    human dignity must presume that dignity can be violated in ways that do not involve arbitrary
    classifications. Clifford, at 306. Were that not the case, then the individual dignity clause
    would be surplusage as well; it would have no independent significance in the scheme of
    Article II, Section 4.
    ¶90    Notwithstanding my conclusion that discrimination based on sexual orientation is sex-
    based under conventional equal protection analysis, infra, I agree with Clifford and Huff that
    the list of arbitrary classifications in the third clause of Article II, Section 4 is not--and,
    indeed, should not--be exhaustive. I would hold that homosexuals comprise a suspect class
    in their own right. I reach that conclusion by reference to another important, but virtually
    ignored, section in the Declaration of Rights.
    ¶91    The Delegates’ intention that our Constitution’s Declaration of Rights not be
    interpreted as limiting civil rights, but, rather, as the enumeration of basic guarantees that a
    40
    free and sovereign society--“We the people”--should enjoy is best exemplified in the
    Committee’s proposal of Article II, Section 34 to the Convention delegates and in the
    subsequent adoption of this provision. Article II, Section 34 states:
    Unenumerated rights. The enumeration in this constitution of certain
    rights shall not be construed to deny, impair, or disparage others retained by the
    people.
    ¶92    In proposing the adoption of this section, the Committee did two things. First, it
    recognized that the rights enumerated in Montana’s Constitution were not exclusive--i.e., that
    there are unenumerated rights or “rights beyond those specifically listed” which are retained
    by the people. Proposal, p. 645. Second, and important to my discussion here, the
    Committee considered this section to be “a crucial part of any effort to revitalize the state
    government’s approach to civil liberties questions. [And that this section] may be the source
    of innovative judicial activity in the civil liberties field.” Proposal, p. 645.
    ¶93    The proceedings of the Constitutional Convention reveal no debate on Article II,
    Section 34. Rather, it was adopted unanimously on the straightforward, yet eloquent
    recommendation of Delegate Dorothy Eck, who stated: “I think that [this section] is
    completely self-explanatory. There are rights which are not enumerated which the people of
    Montana should not be denied.” Montana Constitutional Convention, Verbatim Transcript,
    March 9, 1972, p. 1832.
    ¶94    Elison and Snyder observe that the Committee’s belief that Article II, Section 34 could
    be the source of “innovative judicial activity” in the area of civil liberties has not been
    realized; that there are no cases referencing or interpreting this section. Elison, at 86. While
    technically inaccurate that no cases have referenced this section, see Dorwart, n.3 (Nelson,
    41
    J., concurring), it is true that this Court has not applied Article II, Section 34 in any
    substantive context.
    ¶95    Elison and Snyder suggest:
    The section could be used as the basis for the introduction of a theory
    of natural law or an expansion of the use of substantive due process or judicial
    finding of unstated individual rights hidden in the self-reliant, free-thinking,
    idiosyncratic Montanan mythology. Presumptively, this could limit state police
    power and enlarge existing rights or create new rights. . . . While plenary state
    legislative power and unenumerated rights might appear to be in conflict or
    contradictory, they are not. In a state constitution a provision on unenumerated
    rights as a balance against state police power is a potentially useful idea, but
    something of an anomaly. Historically, within the context of state governments
    in a federal system, the limitations on plenary legislative power are the specific
    prohibitions and restrictions found in a constitutional declaration of rights.
    Adding unenumerated rights to specific prohibitions and restrictions could
    transfer to the people indirectly, and to the courts directly, additional means of
    checking plenary legislative power.
    Elison, at 87.
    ¶96    Given that Article II, Section 34 was specifically adopted as a Constitutional source
    by which “to revitalize the state government’s approach to civil liberties questions,”
    Proposal, at 645, it is entirely appropriate that the enumerated protections afforded by Article
    II, Section 4 be interpreted in that broader context in the case at bar. In point of fact, it is
    entirely appropriate that we hold, under Article II, Section 34, that one of the unenumerated
    prohibited classifications beyond those recognized at the time the Constitution was adopted
    is the classification of individuals based on gender or sexual orientation.
    ¶97    In summary, applying the Clifford and Huff model, I would hold that: (a) laws and
    policies that make people’s rights dependent on gender or sexual orientation violate the
    inviolable human dignity clause of Article II, Section 4; (b) classifications of persons on the
    basis of gender or sexual orientation are sex-based and are therefore arbitrary and suspect
    42
    under conventional equal protection analysis; and, in what I believe to be a better approach,
    (c) reading Article II, Sections 4 and 34 together, it is appropriate to establish, as a matter of
    Montana constitutional law, that classifications based on gender or sexual orientation are
    suspect classifications in their own right and are in addition to those enumerated in the third
    clause of this State’s equal protection provision.
    ¶98    Pursuant to this analysis, I would hold that applying strict scrutiny, the Respondents
    have failed to demonstrate a compelling state interest for treating heterosexual and
    homosexual couples differently in terms of the benefits relating to employment. See Gryczan,
    283 Mont. at 449, 942 P.2d at 122. I reach this conclusion for the following reasons.
    ¶99    The Respondents’ arguments are framed in terms of who can be married and who
    cannot--heterosexuals can and homosexuals cannot. Amici supporting the Respondents focus
    their arguments on family values, majoritarian concepts of morality, religious doctrine and
    preserving the sanctity of marriage both as a civil and as a sectarian institution. These
    arguments are red herrings. They miss the mark and ignore the core issue here--whether
    gays and lesbians have the right to individual human dignity, equal protection of the laws and
    freedom from discrimination under Article II, Section 4 of the Montana Constitution with
    respect to obtaining the same economic benefits of employment that heterosexuals receive
    for the same work.
    ¶100 Certainly, secular organizations and religions have the right to define for their own
    members their beliefs, doctrines, moral tenets, rules and rituals. Individuals have the right
    to hold whatever personal opinions they choose. That is not to say, however, that these
    institutions, groups and persons may impose their philosophies and values on minorities and
    43
    on others who ascribe to a different view and whose conduct and life styles cause no harm.
    We stated in Gryczan:
    James Madison decried the potential for a tyranny of the majority,
    pointing out that it was as important in our system of government to guard the
    minority in our society against injustice by the majority, as it was to guard
    society from the oppression of its rulers. The Federalist, No. 51, at 351 (James
    Madison) (Jacob E. Cooke ed., 1961). . . .
    . . . [Despite governmental laws and policies and perceived societal
    notions of what is acceptable in a moral sense] there are certain rights so
    fundamental that they will not be denied to a minority no matter how despised
    by society.
    Gryczan, 283 Mont. at 455, 942 P.2d at 125-26. As individual privacy was such a right in
    Gryczan, the fundamental rights to human dignity, to equal protection of the laws and to
    freedom from invidious discrimination, are in the case at bar.
    ¶101 The University in particular and employers in general are perfectly capable of
    providing gays and lesbians and gay and lesbian couples with the same economic benefits of
    employment that heterosexuals enjoy. And that is all this case is about--providing similarly
    situated employees the same economic benefits from employment. This case is not about gay
    marriage or gay unions, as the Court’s Opinion clearly acknowledges.
    ¶102 As already noted, because providing gay and lesbian couples with the same
    employment benefits that heterosexual couples receive can be accomplished without
    additional cost or administrative burden to the employer, there is no legitimate economic
    rationale for the Respondents’ position, much less that of Amici. As this case shows,
    employers are able to determine partner benefits on criteria generally applicable to all people.
    ¶103 Here, the criteria arbitrarily chosen is marriage. But, as the Court’s Opinion
    demonstrates, marriage can be proven by the simple expedient of two people signing an
    44
    affidavit. However, if the underlying rationale of providing partner benefits is to insure that
    the partners are residing together and have accepted mutual commitments of financial
    support, that can be satisfied by affidavit, declaration, contract or some other writing in
    addition to proof of marriage. Even assuming one can create a common law marriage by
    signing an affidavit (which as our Opinion shows is a false premise, see In re Estate of
    McClelland (1975), 
    168 Mont. 160
    , 164-65, 
    541 P.2d 780
    , 783), the employer has no real
    basis for insuring that such persons are, in fact, married, or that their arrangement is simply
    not one of convenience to acquire important health insurance benefits. Indeed, there is
    nothing stopping such persons from simply walking away from the whole arrangement when
    it suits their circumstances to do so.
    ¶104 Furthermore, the only basis for the argument that granting gay and lesbian couples
    equal employment benefits will destroy the institution of marriage is that the employer has
    made an arbitrary decision to use marriage as the defining criteria for granting these benefits.
    Were the defining criteria different--as it could easily be--the whole issue of marriage,
    religion and morality would cease to exist. Paying homosexual workers the same as their
    heterosexual counterparts has not destroyed any important institutions in or the moral fabric
    of our society, and there is no evidentiary basis for concluding that extending health insurance
    benefits to gay and lesbian couples will have that effect either. Indeed, that has not occurred
    in those states and with those many employers and institutions that have extended such
    benefits already.
    45
    ¶105 Additionally, there are three reasons why the preserving-the-institution-of-marriage
    argument fails. First, this is not a gay marriage case. This case is about providing equal
    financial benefits to similarly situated employees of the same employer.
    ¶106 Second, the premise that extending economic employment benefits to gay and lesbian
    couples will somehow harm marriage is itself without merit. There is no actual evidence in
    the record here to support that conclusion. Indeed, arguably, heterosexuals have done more
    to denigrate the institution of marriage than gay and lesbian couples ever have or likely ever
    will. In the years since 1998, the divorce rate in Montana has averaged nearly 40%.10
    Moreover, this rate does not take into account any number of heterosexuals “living in sin,”
    without the benefit of any marriage, nor does it take into account married heterosexuals who
    are engaged in extra-marital affairs. Our society lionizes professional athletes, entertainers,
    and high-profile politicians despite (although one would sometimes think, because of) marital
    infidelity and divorces. One need simply turn on the television to understand that the “Ozzie
    and Harriet” and “Leave it to Beaver” genre of television shows are historical artifacts which
    have no popularity with the American viewing public. I submit that those championing the
    preservation-of-marriage argument accord a good deal more to the sanctity of the institution
    than do a substantial percentage of Montanans and other Americans as evidenced by their
    actual conduct.
    ¶107 Third, and importantly for our discussion here, the preservation-of-marriage argument
    is, transparently, little more than a convenient vehicle through which to condemn and to
    discriminate against gays and lesbians because of their lifestyles and gender orientations. See
    10
    National Center for Health Statistics at http://www.cdc.gov/nchs.
    46
    Clifford, at 334-35. To be sure, homosexuality offends many people’s sense of morality and
    the teachings of many religions. However, we live in a pluralistic society, and, as we said in
    Gryczan:
    With respect to regulation of morals, the police power should properly be
    exercised to protect each individual’s right to be free from interference in
    defining and pursuing his own morality but not to enforce a majority morality
    on persons whose conduct does not harm others. . . . Indeed, what is
    considered to be “moral” changes with the times and is dependent upon societal
    background. Spiritual leadership, not the government, has the responsibility
    for striving to improve the morality of individuals. Campbell [v. Sundquist
    (Tenn.Ct.App. 1996)], 926 S.W.2d [250,] 265-66 (quoting Commonwealth v.
    Bonadio (1980), 
    490 Pa. 91
    , 
    415 A.2d 47
    , 50).
    . . . Our Constitution does not protect morality; it does, however,
    guarantee to all persons, whether in the majority or in a minority, those certain
    basic freedoms and rights which are set forth in the Declaration of Rights. . .
    .
    Gryczan, 283 Mont. at 454, 942 P.2d at 125. Again, as the right of individual privacy was
    one of those basic freedoms and rights in Gryczan, the right of human dignity, equal
    protection of the laws and freedom from discrimination are, likewise, basic freedoms and
    rights which must be protected in the case at bar. A policy of classifying persons for its own
    sake cannot be justified. Romer v. Evans (1996), 
    517 U.S. 620
    , 635, 
    116 S. Ct. 1620
    , 1629,
    
    134 L. Ed. 2d 855
    . There is no compelling state interest for the Respondent’s policy at issue
    here.
    47
    Conclusion
    ¶108 While I concur in the Court’s Opinion, I also believe that this case calls for a new
    approach to analyzing cases arising under Article II, Section 4 of the Montana Constitution.
    I submit that the approach discussed above honors the plain language, the framers’ intent and
    the historical underpinnings of Montana’s unique provisions protecting the rights of
    individual human dignity and of equal protection of the laws and prohibiting discrimination.
    ¶109 Using this approach, I would hold that (a) laws and policies that make people’s rights
    dependent on gender or sexual orientation violate the inviolable human dignity clause of
    Article II, Section 4; (b) classifications of persons on the basis of gender or sexual orientation
    are sex-based and are therefore arbitrary and suspect under conventional equal protection
    analysis; and, in what I believe to be a better view, (c) reading Article II, Sections 4 and 34
    together, it is appropriate to establish, as a matter of Montana Constitutional law, that
    classifications based on gender or sexual orientation are suspect classifications in their own
    right in addition to those enumerated in the third clause of this State’s equal protection
    provision. I would also hold that laws and policies which are based on gender or sexual
    orientation are subject to strict scrutiny/compelling state interest analysis and that under that
    analysis, the Respondents’ policy at issue here fails.
    ¶110 Indeed, in this approach we give real meaning to the plain language and to the spirit
    of Article II, Section 4 and we realize the Constitutional Convention’s charge under Article II,
    Section 34 that our decisions become a crucial part of the effort to revitalize the state
    48
    government’s approach to civil liberties questions--civil liberties that “We the people” are,
    without exception, entitled to enjoy.
    ¶111 With this additional rationale, I concur in our Opinion.
    /S/ JAMES C. NELSON
    49
    Justice Jim Rice dissenting.
    ¶112 I respectfully dissent. The Court fails to reference or properly apply the statutes and
    case law, thereby radically altering common law marriage in Montana, and failing to honor
    the reliance that many couples place in the law. I will begin with the Court’s opinion, then
    turn to the claims pled by the Appellants in the District Court, and conclude with a response
    to the concurrence.
    ¶113 Before turning to the legal analysis, two preliminary points must be made. First, the
    Court’s opinion does not address the issues which were pled by the Appellants. No part of
    the rationale upon which the Court resolves this case–that the Affidavit process fails to
    establish a common-law marriage–was a part of the challenge filed by the Appellants in the
    District Court. Indeed, the Appellants pled precisely the opposite, arguing that the policy is
    discriminatory for the very reason that the University grants benefits based upon marriage,
    including common-law marriage. As stated in their Complaint:
    The State of Montana explicitly prohibits same-sex marriage. By
    conditioning receipt of critical employment benefits on solemnized or common-
    law marriage while denying lesbians and gay men the right to marry,
    Defendants deprive Plaintiffs of their fundamental rights under the Montana
    Constitution.
    Complaint, ¶ 3 (emphasis added). Appellants’ claims are constitutional challenges. However,
    the Court has ignored those pled claims and generated an alternative rationale on its own.
    This creates an unfairness in the proceeding for the Respondents, who had no opportunity to
    defend against the defects in its Affidavit process which are asserted by the Court.
    ¶114 The Court responds to this issue by stating: “The dissent contends that we have
    decided this case on a theory or issue that was not argued or raised by the parties. This is
    50
    simply not true.     The Appellants squarely argued in their brief . . . .”        See ¶ 30.
    Unfortunately, the Court misunderstands the nature of this issue. I agree with the Court that
    Appellants raised the issue of the validity of the common-law Affidavit in their brief filed
    before this Court. However, that is not the problem. The problem is that Appellants did not
    raise this claim in the District Court, the District Court did not consider or rule upon such
    claim, and therefore, Appellants are not permitted to raise a new argument on appeal.
    Allowing Appellants to do so grants them favorable treatment not granted to any other litigant
    before this Court.
    ¶115 This is confirmed by a review of the Appellants’ Complaint and the District Court
    record. The Complaint states:
    53. Opposite-sex domestic partners who have not obtained a solemnized
    marriage may obtain access to such benefits by signing an affidavit of common-
    law marriage.
    ....
    57. A solemnized marriage between persons of the same sex is
    prohibited. Mont. Code. Ann. § 40-1-401.
    58. Likewise, common-law marriage between persons of the same sex
    is prohibited. Mont. Code Ann. § 40-1-401.
    59. Montana law prohibits the Plaintiff couples from entering into
    either solemnized or common-law marriage.
    60. For an employee’s domestic partner to qualify as a “dependent”
    under Defendants’ interpretation and administration of applicable state statutes
    and regulations, or, in the alternative, under those statutes and regulations
    themselves, the employee and his or her partner must enter into a solemnized
    marriage or sign an affidavit of common-law marriage.
    51
    61. Gay and lesbian employees are not permitted to obtain coverage for
    their same-sex domestic partners because Defendants intentionally condition
    the receipt of such benefits on marriage while denying lesbians and gay men
    the right to marry.
    (Emphasis added.) As can be seen, the Complaint’s allegations clearly challenged the
    University’s policy of conditioning benefits based upon marriage, either solemnization or
    common law. Nowhere does the Complaint allege that the Affidavit itself was insufficient
    to establish a common-law marriage–that is a new argument on appeal. In fact, the
    Complaint’s prayer requested eight specific forms of relief: all eight ask that the court declare
    that the marriage statutes and the University’s regulations based thereon are unconstitutional
    because “Defendants, or in the alternative, the governing Montana statutes and regulations,
    deny to unmarried employees certain employment benefits that are provided to married
    employees . . . .” Complaint, ¶ 86 (emphasis added).
    ¶116 Respondents, Defendants below, filed a motion to dismiss the Complaint. Because
    Appellants had only raised constitutional claims in their Complaint, these were the only issues
    discussed by Respondents in their motion to dismiss and supporting brief:
    The gist of the Complaint is that the University System group benefits
    eligibility criterion for spouses of employees, based as it is on the marriage
    relationship as recognized in Montana law, prevents the two University
    employed Plaintiffs from securing coverage for their same-sex partners. . . .
    Plaintiffs claim that the inability of University System employees to cover their
    same-sex domestic partners under the group benefits plan violates four different
    sections of the Montana Constitution.
    (Emphasis added.)
    52
    ¶117 Respondents’ motion to dismiss then discussed Appellants’ eight constitutional claims
    and asked the District Court to dismiss them. In response to the motion to dismiss, Appellants
    explained the nature of the claims they were making, reaffirming the allegations pled in their
    Complaint. Appellants’ brief in opposition to Respondents’ motion to dismiss stated as
    follows:
    Like all lesbian and gay employees of the Montana University System,
    Plaintiffs are not permitted to purchase benefits for their same-sex partners
    because Defendants limit dependent benefits to legal spouses. In contrast,
    opposite-sex couples may obtain dependent benefits merely by signing an
    Affidavit of Common-Law Marriage or entering into a solemnized marriage.
    By conditioning receipt of critical employment benefits on solemnized or
    common-law marriage, Defendants discriminatorily deprive Plaintiffs of
    adequate and affordable insurance protection for their family members,
    violating their fundamental rights under the Montana Constitution.
    ....
    . . . Defendants’ argument rests on the faulty presumption that using
    marriage to define eligibility for benefits makes their policy gender neutral and
    insulates it from equal protection review. In reality, however, Defendants’
    policy classifies employees and their partners based on sex because [emphasis
    in original] they use “spouse,” a specifically sex-based term, to determine
    eligibility for benefits.
    ....
    . . . The university could have chosen to distribute benefits using any
    number of guidelines . . . . Among these many options, the university chose
    marriage as the defining line. By definition, using marriage means defining
    eligibility for benefits in sex-based terms . . . . This lawsuit only asks the Court
    to determine whether Defendants have a compelling reason for using the sex-
    based definition of marriage to determine eligibility for benefits.
    (Emphasis added.)
    53
    ¶118 Consequently, in rendering its decision, the District Court analyzed the issues precisely
    as framed by the Appellants:
    Plaintiffs . . . contend that by conditioning receipt of health insurance on
    marriage, while denying lesbians and gay men the right to marry, Defendants
    are depriving them of their fundamental rights under the Montana constitution.
    They ask for a declaratory judgment that the Defendants’ interpretation and
    administration of the applicable state statutes and regulations violate their right
    to dignity, to privacy, to equal protection, to seek safety, health and happiness,
    and to pursue life’s basic necessities. Alternatively Plaintiffs ask the Court to
    declare that the statutes and the regulations violate their rights.
    The District Court did not address the sufficiency of the common-law Affidavit in its order,
    because it was not an issue raised by the Appellants before the District Court.
    ¶119 Thus, as pled, argued, submitted and decided in the District Court, this case was
    strictly a constitutional challenge to the University’s use of marriage for benefit eligibility.
    Indeed, this the way the Appellants defined their own claims before the District Court: “This
    lawsuit only asks the Court to determine whether Defendants have a compelling reason for
    using the sex-based definition of marriage . . . .” At no time did they challenge the Affidavit
    process as failing to properly apply the law of common-law marriage.
    ¶120 Our Court does not address new arguments or changes of argument on appeal. “The
    rule is well established that this Court will not address an issue raised for the first time on
    appeal.” State v. McCaslin, 
    2004 MT 212
    , ¶ 49, 
    322 Mont. 350
    , ¶ 49, 
    96 P.3d 722
    , ¶ 49. See
    also State v. Bar-Jonah, 
    2004 MT 344
    , ¶ 124, 
    324 Mont. 278
    , ¶ 124, ___ P.3d ___,¶ 124;
    State v. Heath, 
    2004 MT 58
    , ¶ 39, 
    320 Mont. 211
    , ¶ 39, 
    89 P.3d 947
    , ¶ 39; State v. Peterson,
    
    2002 MT 65
    , ¶ 24; 
    309 Mont. 199
    , ¶ 24, 
    44 P.3d 499
    , ¶ 24; State v. Weaselboy, 
    1999 MT 54
    274, ¶ 16, 
    296 Mont. 503
    , ¶ 16, 
    989 P.2d 836
    , ¶ 16; State v. Lucero, 
    2004 MT 248
    , ¶ 20, 
    323 Mont. 42
    , ¶ 20, 
    97 P.3d 1106
    , ¶ 20; Ellenburg v. Chase, 
    2004 MT 66
    , ¶ 18, 
    320 Mont. 315
    ,
    ¶ 18, 
    87 P.3d 473
    , ¶ 18; State v. Martinez, 
    2003 MT 65
    , ¶ 17, 
    314 Mont. 434
    , ¶ 17, 
    67 P.3d 207
    , ¶ 17; State v. Minez, 
    2003 MT 344
    , ¶ 19, 
    318 Mont. 478
    , ¶ 19, 
    82 P.3d 1
    , ¶ 19;
    Schlemmer v. N. Cent. Life Ins. Co., 
    2001 MT 256
    , ¶ 22, 
    307 Mont. 203
    , ¶ 22, 
    37 P.3d 63
    ,
    ¶ 22; Unified Industries, Inc. v. Easley, 
    1998 MT 145
    , ¶ 15, 
    289 Mont. 255
    , ¶ 15, 
    961 P.2d 100
    , ¶ 15. As this partial list of recent cases illustrates, our rule is firm. As we reasoned in
    State v. Adgerson, 
    2003 MT 284
    , ¶ 12, 
    318 Mont. 22
    , ¶ 12, 
    78 P.3d 850
    , ¶ 12, “[t]he rule is
    well established that this Court will not address an issue raised for the first time on appeal.
    . . . A party may not raise new arguments or change its legal theory on appeal, because it is
    fundamentally unfair to fault the trial court for failing to rule on an issue it was never given
    the opportunity to consider.” Adgerson, ¶ 12 (citations omitted). The purpose for our rule
    is well illustrated here, where the District Court was not presented with Appellants’
    arguments.
    ¶121 The Court replies that Respondent University did not raise an objection to Appellants’
    new argument in its brief. The Court apparently believes that, somehow, this cures the
    problem for which the rule exists–unfairness to the district court and disrespect for the
    process. The Court errs again. We have routinely and consistently applied the rule, regardless
    of whether the opposing party raised the issue. State v. Heath is a recent example. There we
    declined to address an issue the Appellant had failed to raise in the district court. Heath, ¶
    55
    39. However, Respondent State had not raised the Appellant’s failure to raise the issue in the
    district court as an objection in its briefing.
    ¶122 Thus, by accepting the arguments which Appellants have raised for the first time on
    appeal, and incorporating them into its opinion, the Court has violated our longstanding rule
    and has afforded special treatment to Appellants which is not afforded to other litigants who
    come before this Court.
    ¶123 The second preliminary matter is that numerous factual assertions and assumptions
    offered by the Court are without evidentiary support. The District Court resolved this matter
    by granting the Respondents’ motion to dismiss the Appellants’ Complaint. There was no
    factfinding, and there is no factual record other than pleaded facts. Nonetheless, in ¶ 23, the
    Court states that “[p]resumably, a couple who declines to sign a statutory written declaration
    of marriage without solemnization, and instead signs the Affidavit provided by the University
    System, may choose not to marry at all . . . .” However, there is no evidence that the couples
    who signed an Affidavit “may choose not to marry at all.” To the contrary, this statement
    directly conflicts with the claims in Appellants’ Complaint, quoted above, and with the
    University’s Affidavit of Common-Law Marriage, which states:
    AFFIDAVIT OF COMMON-LAW MARRIAGE
    We, the undersigned, both being over the age of 18 years, have mutually
    consented and contracted to become husband and wife; we are now, and have
    been since________________ (date), living together as husband and wife, and
    have mutually consented to hold towards each other the relationship of
    husband and wife, and to assume towards each other all the responsibilities and
    duties which the law attached to such a relationship.
    56
    The Affidavit plainly states that the couple has “mutually consented” to be husband and wife
    and have assumed “all the responsibilities and duties which the law attached to such
    relationship.” This is the factual record in this matter. It is not in our power to reject it, for
    there is no evidence–even more, no allegation–of anything different. The Court expresses
    dismay that “[t]hose opposite-sex couples who fill out the Affidavit in order to receive
    benefits may be shocked to think that they have in fact entered into a marriage that requires
    court action to dissolve . . . .” See ¶ 33. Whether or not they are shocked is not in the record,
    but more to the point, that is not the issue. For purposes of this case, they have signed an
    Affidavit which said that very thing: they were assuming the marital relationship with “all the
    responsibilities and duties which the law attached to such a relationship.” That is our record.
    It is unchallenged by pleading, briefing or evidence. Thus, as a factual matter, it is simply
    erroneous for the Court to find that any of the couples who signed the Affidavit “may choose
    not to marry.” Although intent is one element of common-law marriage (that is, the parties’
    mutual consent, discussed herein), the pleadings and the Affidavit clearly establish the
    couples’ mutual consent to their common-law marital relationship.11
    ¶124 On that factually-flawed premise, the Court then finds that such a policy “allows
    unmarried opposite-sex couples to sign an Affidavit.” See ¶ 24. This conclusion is also
    factually flawed because the University’s policy allows no such thing. To the contrary, the
    11
    I would offer an apology to any couple who may be offended by the Court’s
    description of them as perhaps “choos[ing] not to marry at all” or as having only “a
    fleeting relationship.” See ¶ 23. Although there is no evidence in the record to support
    these statements, I am sure it was not the Court’s intention to offend.
    57
    policy allows only married opposite-sex couples to obtain marital health benefits, including
    those opposite-sex couples who are married under the common law. The University’s policy
    requires these couples to sign the Affidavit attesting to their marital relationship. Likewise,
    the pleadings illustrate the Court’s clear error in stating that marital status “plays little if any
    role in determining who is eligible for benefits.” See ¶ 26. Again, to the contrary, marital
    status is the exclusive factor in determining partner benefits under the University’s policy.
    ¶125 Therefore, the Court has decided this matter on a basis which, I respectfully submit,
    is both procedurally and factually flawed. That notwithstanding, I turn to an analysis of the
    substance of the rationale regarding common-law marriage proffered by the Court, before
    turning to the issues pled by the Appellants.
    ¶126 The Court’s holding, which invalidates the common-law marriage claims of the
    couples who signed the Affidavit, is premised upon several policy observations and legal
    propositions which are either unsupported with authority, or which cite to authority which is
    inapposite. First, in ¶ 24, the Court offers an entirely new definition of common-law
    marriage, without citation to authority, as “an equitable doctrine used to ensure people are
    treated fairly once a relationship ends.” Second, the Court offers an entirely new rationale
    for common-law marriage, again without citation to authority except for a unspecified
    reference to our “typical cases,” as a concept “designed, in part, to prevent an unjust
    economic harm to couples who have held themselves out as husband and wife . . . .” Thirdly,
    the Court opines, with no reference to authority whatsoever, that “[a]t the very least . . .
    common law marriages are not automatically recognized by signing [an] Affidavit.” The
    58
    Court then concludes that a common-law marriage cannot be established “prospectively.” I
    respectfully submit that, in my opinion, none of these propositions comport with Montana
    law.
    ¶127 I concur with the Court’s citation to Ober and Hunsaker for the three elements of a
    common-law marriage which must be proven under our law–a couple’s competency, consent
    and confirmation. Regarding these elements, the party asserting that a common-law marriage
    exists has the burden of proving all three elements. Hunsaker, ¶ 32 (citing Matter of Estate
    of Vandenhook (1993), 
    259 Mont. 201
    , 204, 
    855 P.2d 518
    , 520). However, “public policy,
    as well as statutory law, favors the finding of a valid marriage.” Ober, ¶ 16. Further, the
    burden of proof is made lighter by § 26-1-602(30), MCA, which establishes a presumption
    that “[a] man and woman deporting themselves as husband and wife have entered into a
    lawful contract of marriage.” Although a disputable presumption, we have held in the
    common-law marriage context that “the presumption in favor of matrimony is one of the
    strongest known to the law and that every intendment of the law is in favor of matrimony
    . . . .” Estate of Murnion (1984), 
    212 Mont. 107
    , 113, 
    686 P.2d 893
    , 897. Indeed, this
    statutory presumption is “itself sufficient to establish the marriage unless overcome by other
    evidence.” Spradlin v. United States (D. Mont. 1967), 
    262 F. Supp. 502
    , 505. “The effect of
    [the marital] presumption, of course, is to place the burden on the other party to overcome the
    presumption.” Murnion, 212 Mont. at 113, 686 P.2d at 897.
    ¶128 Thus, the language of the Affidavit and the law’s presumption in favor of marriage
    clearly establish a prima facie claim of common-law marriage because the presumption is
    59
    “itself sufficient to establish the marriage.” Spradlin, 262 F.Supp. at 505. Consequently, the
    University acted properly under the law in recognizing the marriages based upon the
    Affidavit. Further, the pleadings did not challenge the marriage claims of couples signing the
    Affidavit, and therefore, there can be no argument that Appellants carried a burden to
    “overcome the presumption” that lies in favor of the couples’ claims. Murnion, 212 Mont.
    at 113, 686 P.2d at 897. Therefore, as a matter of proof (here, within the context of pleaded
    facts), the couples’ claims of common-law marriage have undeniably been established under
    Montana law.
    ¶129 For this reason, the Court’s reliance on Estate of McClelland, simply because the
    evidence in that case included an affidavit, is incorrect. In McClelland, the parties’ affidavit
    was but one piece of the “extensive evidence presented by both sides as to the existence or
    nonexistence of the common law marriage” at issue. McClelland, 168 Mont. at 162, 541 P.2d
    at 781-82. This Court decided that case, not on the sufficiency of the affidavit, but because:
    the facts establishing the common law marriage of appellant and deceased are
    conflicting. This Court has consistently held that where there is a conflict in
    the evidence, the findings of the trial court are presumed to be correct if
    supported by evidence most favorable to the prevailing party.
    McClelland, 168 Mont. at 165, 541 P.2d at 783. In its citation to McClelland, the Court
    mentions neither the other “extensive evidence” introduced in that case nor the basis for the
    McClelland court’s decision. In regard to the sufficiency of proof, McClelland is completely
    60
    irrelevant because, in this case, there are no pleaded facts which rebut the Affidavit and legal
    presumption in favor of marriage.12
    ¶130 The Court then states, without citation to any case, that “[o]ur case law consistently
    holds that one of the parties to the relationship must assert, through extrinsic evidence, that
    all of the common law marriage elements were met . . . .” See ¶ 33. The Court reiterates that
    it is “not aware” of any Montana case in which a common-law marriage was established
    without “extrinsic evidence.” This statement is erroneous, both as a matter of law and of fact,
    as demonstrated by the record in this case.
    ¶131 First, the law. Contrary to the Court’s new requirement of “extrinsic evidence,” we
    have held that “[t]he mutual consent of the parties [for a common-law marriage] does not need
    to be expressed in any particular form.” Hunsaker, ¶ 34 (citing In re Estate of Slavens (1973),
    
    162 Mont. 123
    , 126, 
    509 P.2d 293
    , 295). Thus, the Court errs in asserting that our law
    “clearly defines” what kind of evidence is necessary to establish a common-law marriage.
    See ¶ 33. To the contrary, we have allowed parties to demonstrate a common-law marriage
    by whatever form they are able.
    ¶132 Further, the Court ignores the presumption which the law imposes in favor of a
    marriage and the impact it has on evidentiary questions. In Spradlin, the Appeals Council of
    12
    For a case which illustrates the minimum proof necessary to establish a common-
    law marriage, see Matter of Estate of Alcorn (1994), 
    263 Mont. 353
    , 
    868 P.2d 629
    , where
    we upheld a marriage claim based upon a horseshoe-shaped ring, a horseshoe design
    within a walkway, and one party’s sworn assertion that they were married. Alcorn, 263
    Mont. at 357, 868 P.2d at 631. Here, superior to the proof in Alcorn, both parties have
    sworn to the marital relationship.
    61
    the Social Security Administration had concluded there was “no evidence” presented in
    support of the elements of a common-law marriage, and ruled against the party claiming the
    marriage. Spradlin, 262 F.Supp. at 504-05. The United States District Court reversed,
    concluding that the decision of the Appeals Council was contrary to Montana law, and
    explaining the nature of Montana’s statutory presumption on questions of proof:
    The [statutory] presumption itself was proof of a marriage, ceremonial or
    common-law. . . . If there was no ceremonial marriage, the presumption would
    be sufficient to establish both the capacity of the parties and the consent of the
    parties for the purposes of the common-law marriage. The statute creating the
    presumption, by the use of the words “lawful contract” embraces both the fact
    of the consent and the capacity to consent. . . . [T]he presumption of marriage
    should be weighed on the one side and on the other side [contrary evidence]
    should be weighed . . . . [H]owever, there is no requirement in the law that the
    capacity to marry should be conclusively established. The statutory
    presumption was itself sufficient to establish the marriage unless overcome by
    other evidence.
    Spradlin, 262 F.Supp. at 505. Thus, the statutory presumption alone is sufficient evidence
    to establish a common-law marriage–there is no other “extrinsic evidence” requirement in the
    law.
    ¶133 The Court’s error is further demonstrated by the practical realities of proving a
    common-law marriage. State, federal and private agencies routinely recognize common-law
    marriages by administrative declaration, and pay financial benefits based upon that
    administrative action. By law and by contract, these agencies defer to the law of the
    applicant’s domiciliary state in regard to the validity and establishment of a common-law
    marriage. This is particularly true of federal law governing eligibility for various federal
    benefits. “In deciding who is entitled to federal survivor benefits, [the United States Office
    62
    of Personnel Management] looks to state common law to define marriage and to determine
    who is the legal widow . . . .” Huff v. Director, United States Office of Pers. Mgmt. (3rd Cir.
    1994), 
    40 F.3d 35
    , 39 (citing 5 C.F.R. § 831.603). In LaRochelle v. Office of Pers. Mgmt.
    (Fed. Cir. 1985), 
    774 F.2d 1079
    , LaRochelle claimed to be a common-law spouse who was
    entitled to benefits. The court stated:
    Texas, the state of the LaRochelles’ domicile, recognizes common-law
    marriages. Tex.Fam.Code Ann. § 1.91(a)(2) (Vernon 1975). Because [the
    Office of Personnel Management] will consult state law where federal law is
    not determinative, this type of marriage satisfies the survivor annuity
    provisions.
    LaRochelle, 774 F.2d at 1080. The common-law marriage determination is an agency
    decision that does not require court involvement, unless a party seeks judicial review of the
    agency decision, see Slate v. OPM (1982), 10 M.S.P.R. 658, and Goldbach v. OPM (1989),
    42 M.S.P.R. 57, but which carefully applies the particular requirements of the law in the
    applicant’s jurisdiction. See Gainey v. Barnhart (8th Cir. 2002), 
    299 F.3d 1004
    , 1006-07, and
    McKenzie v. Harris (3rd Cir. 1982), 
    679 F.2d 8
    , 10-13 (analyzing elements and proof
    necessary under Michigan and Pennsylvania law, respectively, for determination of common-
    law marriage for purposes of Social Security benefits). An applicant from a state which does
    not recognize common-law marriages cannot qualify for benefits by claiming to be married
    under the common law. See Howard v. Keohane (E.D. Ky. 1995), 
    898 F. Supp. 459
    , 462-63
    (marriage claim could not be maintained under Louisiana law, which did not recognize
    common-law marriages). Thus, if state law denies common-law marriages without a court
    63
    order, that requirement will be enforced by the agencies applying the state law to determine
    eligibility.
    ¶134 Administrative determination of common-law marriage based upon the law of the
    applicant’s domicile occurs in a variety of other public and private benefit contexts as well,
    including Social Security, 20 C.F.R. § 404.344; ERISA plans, Iron Workers Mid-South
    Pension Fund v. Stoll (E.D. La. 1991), 
    771 F. Supp. 781
    , 783-84; Longshoremen’s and Harbor
    Workers’ Compensation Act benefits, Marcus v. Office of Workers’ Compensation (D.C. Cir.
    1976), 
    548 F.2d 1044
    , 1047 (citing 33 U.S.C. § 902(16)); trade union trust plans, Int’l
    Painters & Allied Trades Indus. Pension Fund v. Calabro (E.D. Pa. 2004), 
    312 F. Supp. 2d 697
    , 701-02; Department of Defense benefits, DOD Military Pay and Allowances
    Entitlements Manual, Rules for Determining Relationship and Dependency, ¶ 30233, Validity
    of Member’s Marriage; and property and casualty coverage, National Sec. Fire & Cas. Co.
    v. Minchew (Ala. 1979), 
    372 So. 2d 327
    . This is only a partial list. It has been said that
    marriage is “‘a unique gateway’ to hundreds of rights under state law and over 1,000 under
    federal law . . . .” Same-Sex Marriage, Duke Law Magazine, Fall 2004, p. 6.          Under 5
    C.F.R. § 831.603, which governs federal personnel plans, “[m]arriage means a marriage
    recognized in law or equity under the whole law of the jurisdiction . . . of the employee.”
    ¶135 Thus, administrative declarations of common-law marriage occur daily. Regarding
    necessary proof, the Social Security Administration, for example, will grant marital benefits
    under Montana law upon less convincing evidence than the University’s Affidavit:
    64
    (b) Preferred evidence. Preferred evidence of a common-law marriage
    is–
    (1) If both the husband and wife are alive, their signed statements and
    those of two blood relatives;
    ...
    (c) Other evidence of common-law marriage. If you cannot get
    preferred evidence of a common-law marriage, we will ask you to explain why
    and to give us other convincing evidence of the marriage. We may not ask you
    for statements from a blood relative or other person if we believe other
    evidence presented to us proves the common-law marriage.
    20 C.F.R. § 404.726(b)(1) and (c).
    ¶136 Thus, it can be seen that the Court’s new “extrinsic evidence” requirement, for which
    it can cite no authority, is not only inconsistent with our law, but, as a practical matter, will
    interfere with efforts of various agencies, applying Montana law, to make common-law
    marriage determinations.
    ¶137    Secondly, the Court is wrong on the “facts” of the matter. Even if it was appropriate
    to impose a new “extrinsic evidence” requirement, such evidence has been provided in this
    case. The Court belittles the University’s Affidavit process as simply “signing a piece of
    paper.”13 See ¶ 32. As a matter of evidence, however, it is uncontested that the couples who
    have signed the Affidavit have lived together since a past date, have consented and contracted
    to be husband and wife, are currently living together, and have assumed all responsibilities
    and duties under the law related to the marital relationship. This “extrinsic evidence” about
    their relationship has not been contested, and therefore, they have established a common-law
    13
    Demonstrating a marriage by way of a “piece of paper” is hardly a novel concept.
    Rejecting a marriage on the basis of a “piece of paper” is.
    65
    marriage as a matter of fact under the record in this case. The Court is simply closing its eyes
    to the pled, uncontested facts here.
    ¶138 The Court next faults the University’s Affidavit process because “no jurisdiction
    permits a statement of future intent to create a common law marriage” and because “[w]e are
    aware of no Montana case in which a common law marriage was established prospectively.”
    See ¶ 24. There are no such Montana cases because that is not the law. “The party asserting
    the existence of a common-law marriage must . . . prove that the three elements of common-
    law marriage all existed at one time.” Hunsaker, ¶ 43 (emphasis added). The law of
    common-law marriage does not recognize an element that is to occur in the future; all the
    elements must occur together. The elements of a common-law marriage “must take place at
    a set time.” Hunsaker, ¶ 43. However, this issue is a red herring, because there is no attempt
    here to prove the marriage prospectively. Rather, the Affidavit is evidence of both past
    intention and action (stating that the couple has previously mutually consented to be husband
    and wife, and have been living together and holding toward each other as husband and wife
    since a past date) and a present action and intention (stating the couple is now mutually
    consenting to be husband and wife, and is now living together and holding toward each other
    as husband and wife). No future intent is involved here.
    ¶139 The Court then attempts, without citation to authority, to explain that the application
    of the common-law marriage doctrine is limited to only those situations arising “after the
    death of one of the parties or separation of the relationship.” See ¶ 24. This is simply
    inaccurate. This Court, like other courts around the country, has addressed common-law
    66
    marriage in many contexts, including those in which both parties are alive and the relationship
    is continuing. See State v. Baldwin, 
    2003 MT 346
    , ¶ 37, 
    318 Mont. 489
    , ¶ 37, 
    81 P.3d 488
    ,
    ¶ 37 (defendant seeking application of spousal privilege); Howard (couple seeking marital
    communication rights within prison); Scott v. Bd. of Trustees of Mobile S.S. (Ala.1988), 
    540 So. 2d 657
    , 658 (couple seeking spousal welfare benefits); National Sec. Fire & Cas. Co.
    (couple seeking to establish insurable property interest by marriage). The Court cites no
    authority for its new rule limiting common-law marriage claims to post-death and post-
    relationship situations.
    ¶140 The Court then reasons that common-law marriage is an equitable doctrine “used to
    ensure people are treated fairly once a relationship ends.” ¶ 24. I would agree that Montana
    law protects people once a relationship ends, but not by a parsing of the common law
    doctrine. Rather, that is done by statute, which provides as follows:
    40-1-403. Validity of common-law marriage. Common-law marriages
    are not invalidated by this chapter.
    40-1-404. Putative spouse. Any person who has cohabited with
    another to whom he is not legally married in the good faith belief that he was
    married to that person is a putative spouse until knowledge of the fact that he
    is not legally married terminates his status and prevents acquisition of further
    rights. A putative spouse acquires the rights conferred upon a legal spouse,
    including the right to maintenance following termination of his status . . . .
    [Emphasis added.]
    We have held that “[t]he rights of putative spouses are protected in Section 40-1-404, MCA,
    where any person has cohabited with another to whom he is not legally married in the good
    faith belief that he was married.” Murnion, 212 Mont. at 118, 686 P.2d at 899 (emphasis
    67
    added). This provision specifically grants all rights of a legal spouse to a person who
    cohabited with another in the good faith belief they were married. Thus, it is not the
    common-law marriage doctrine which primarily protects a person following the end of the
    relationship. Indeed, a person is protected by this statute even if his or her claim of common-
    law marriage fails.
    ¶141 Finally, the Court asserts that should the couples who have signed the Affidavit wish
    to assure their marital status, there is “no need to resort to the ‘common law’ since Montana
    statutory law provides for a written declaration of marriage without solemnization and they
    may avail themselves of this informal statutory process as provided by the Legislature in §
    40-1-311, MCA.” ¶ 34. The Court’s premise is that there can be no common-law marriage
    here because there is no common law where the law is declared by statute, and thus, common-
    law marriage has been abrogated under these circumstances by operation of the statutes which
    provide for a written declaration of marriage. The Court errs here in two ways.
    ¶142 First, § 40-1-403, MCA, declares that “common-law marriages are not invalidated by
    this chapter.” In other words, the Legislature has specifically provided that nothing in the
    marriage statutes governing solemnization or declaration has done anything to affect the
    validity of common-law marriages. Thus, the marriage statutes which provide for other ways
    of marrying have not invalidated the law of common-law marriage for any circumstances,
    including those here. The Court can cite to no authority for its assertion to the contrary.
    ¶143 Likewise, the Court errs by concluding that “there is no need to resort to the ‘common
    law’” because the couples could have used a written declaration of marriage without
    68
    solemnization to establish their marriage. I do not disagree that marriage by declaration may
    also have worked and may even have been preferable.14 However, the failure to use a
    statutory marriage option, even one that may have been better under the circumstances, does
    not invalidate all other avenues which the law provides for marriage.
    ¶144 A summary of the Court’s various holdings here reveals the dramatic nature of the
    changes it has made to the substantive law of common-law marriage, beyond its procedural
    actions of entertaining new arguments on appeal. First, the Court has imposed, without
    citation to any case, the new requirement of “extrinsic evidence,” see ¶¶ 24, 33, and holds that
    an affidavit is insufficient, though both of these principles are inconsistent with our law
    providing that proof need not “be expressed in any particular form.” Hunsaker, ¶ 34. The
    Court overrules the law governing the marriage presumption, which, prior to this decision,
    “was itself sufficient to establish the marriage unless overcome by other evidence.” Spradlin,
    262 F.Supp. at 505. Although that presumption formerly held a position as “the strongest
    known to the law,” Murnion, 212 Mont. at 113, 686 P.2d at 897, the Court’s decision reduces
    it to nothing. The Court then prohibits, without citation to authority, claims to common-law
    marriage claims which it defines as “prospective.” See ¶¶ 24, 33. Although the evidence in
    this case demonstrates past and present actions of the couples, and therefore, the
    “prospective” rule is inapplicable here, this is, nonetheless, a limitation in the law of common-
    law marriage never before recognized. Then, in a dramatic holding, the Court prohibits
    14
    I fail to see, however, how couples signing a declaration of marriage would be
    any less “shocked” to discover they were married than couples who signed a declaration
    of common-law marriage, see ¶ 33, but I will stick to the actual record in this case.
    69
    common-law marriages in those situations in which the couples could have been married
    using a statutorily authorized method of marriage. See ¶ 34. Pursuant thereto, the Court
    directs federal, state and private agencies to use only the provisions of § 40-1-311, MCA,
    when seeking to recognize marriages, prohibiting them from considering marriage under the
    common law. See ¶ 36. This is accomplished without citation to a single Montana case
    which would support any of these holdings.
    ¶145 Despite all of this, the Court proclaims that its opinion simply “reaffirms existing
    common law marriage jurisprudence.” See ¶ 35. Reaching the dewpoint of duplicity, the
    Court then offers that “[w]e haven’t changed anything.” See ¶ 35. To the contrary, and as
    illustrated by the preceding paragraph, the Court has changed just about everything in regard
    to the law of common-law marriage and its application.
    ¶146 I submit, respectfully, that every piece of the rationale offered by the Court in support
    of its holding is inconsistent with the law. There is no basis to invalidate the University’s
    policy of granting marital benefits for those couples who are common-law married. The
    policy is fully justified under the law, both by proof and by process. Having so concluded,
    I turn to the issues actually pled by the Appellants in the District Court.
    ¶147 Appellants claim that the University’s policy of conditioning benefits upon marriage
    violates equal protection by impermissibly discriminating on the basis of sex, sexual
    orientation, and marital status, and further, that the policy’s reliance upon marriage violates
    their fundamental rights under the Montana Constitution, particularly, the right to dignity.
    Here, an important distinction must be made.
    70
    ¶148 The Court states that this case is “not about” a challenge to Montana’s marriage laws,
    noting that Appellants have not asked us to address the question of whether Montana’s
    marriage statutes discriminate against same-sex couples. See ¶ 13. This is true in the
    technical sense, but, without more, gives an incomplete picture about this case. The Court
    is correct that Appellants are not asking in this case for the right to marry. However, they are
    challenging the policy of granting partner benefits on the basis of marriage. In other words,
    Appellants, as unmarried same-sex couples, claim entitlement to the same benefits that are
    granted to married couples, arguing that the University’s policy of relying on marriage is
    impermissible discrimination. Thus, Appellants are challenging the right of government (and
    by extension, any entity) to define eligibility for benefits by reliance on the law’s recognition
    of legal marriage. If they prevail, defining eligibility for benefits for partners on the basis of
    marriage would no longer be permissible vis-a-vis unmarried couples. In this context,
    marriage would be rendered simply a societal option without exclusive legal significance.
    More accurately then, this case “is about” the legal status of marriage in our society,
    specifically, whether the law still recognizes marriage as the transcendent societal relationship
    upon which government may base its decisions.
    ¶149 Similarly, in my view, the concurrence mis-frames the issue before the Court. It states
    that “this is not a gay marriage case. This case is about providing equal financial benefits to
    similarly situated employees of the same employer.” See ¶ 105. I agree that this case is not
    about gay marriage. Rather, it is about legal, heterosexual marriage and its status under the
    law. The equal protection premise considered by the concurrence is that “heterosexual
    71
    couples are entitled to more and better employment benefits than are homosexual couples,”
    from which it concludes that this unequal treatment violates constitutional principle. See ¶ 87.
    That the concurrence has incorrectly analyzed this case as merely one about the treatment of
    heterosexual couples versus homosexual couples is apparent, not only from a review of the
    pled facts and the issues raised, but also from the logical outcome of its reasoning: unmarried
    heterosexual couples would be also entitled to partner benefits. In other words, the
    concurrence would require that all couples be equally treated, without regard to sex or marital
    status. Therefore, at its core, the concurrence’s analysis is flawed because it fails to consider
    that the heterosexual couples here are married, whether by solemnization, declaration, or
    common law, and then fails to consider whether the University’s reliance upon marriage is
    lawful in light of the Appellants’ challenges.15 Thus, neither the Court nor the concurrence
    has addressed the essential issue raised by the challenge: the legal status and effect of
    marriage.
    ¶150 Marriage between a man and a woman is based upon thousands of years of cultural
    experience. Its legal status is founded upon hundreds of years of legal precedent. We have
    stated that “[u]pon [marriage] depends the home, upon the preservation of which, in turn,
    depends good citizenship and the permanency of a republican form of government. The state
    15
    The concurrence offers, in three paragraphs, reasons why the “preserving-the-
    institution-of-marriage argument fails.” See ¶ 105. The reasons offered include that (1)
    this is not a gay marriage case, discussed above, (2) economic and social reasons that
    marriage will not be harmed by giving benefits to homosexual couples, and (3) why
    countering social opinions should not control the outcome here. The concurrence does
    not, however, offer a legal analysis of the status of marriage, and whether government
    may lawfully continue to base decisions thereon.
    72
    therefore favors the institution of marriage.” Franklin v. Franklin (1910), 
    40 Mont. 348
    , 350,
    
    106 P. 353
    , 354. The United States Supreme Court has held:
    It is also to be observed that, whilst marriage is often termed by text
    writers and in decisions of courts a civil contract–generally to indicate that it
    must be founded upon the agreement of the parties, and does not require any
    religious ceremony for its solemnization–it is something more than a mere
    contract. . . . It is an institution, in the maintenance of which in its purity the
    public is deeply interested, for it is the foundation of the family and of society,
    without which there would be neither civilization nor progress.
    Maynard v. Hill (1888), 
    125 U.S. 190
    , 210-11, 
    8 S. Ct. 723
    , 729, 
    31 L. Ed. 654
    , 659.
    ¶151 Given the status of marriage, it is hardly surprising that, as Respondent notes, courts
    on a national scale have routinely rejected constitutional challenges to state law limiting
    marriage to opposite-sex couples and have denied claims of same-sex couples to the benefits
    available to married couples. These cases recognize generally that the claims to unequal
    treatment cannot prevail against the simple, yet profound principle that marriage between a
    man and woman is fundamental to our society, that the state has a legitimate interest in
    promoting marriage, and that this relationship cannot be approximated, copied or equaled by
    any other without the collective will and action of the people. As stated by the Wisconsin
    Court of Appeals:
    [W]hether to allow extension of state employee health insurance benefits to
    companions of unmarried state employees of whatever gender or sexual
    orientation–is a legislative decision, not one for the courts. Indeed, the point is
    well made in the brief of the American Civil Liberties Union Foundation and
    the American Civil Liberties Union of Wisconsin Foundation, as amici curiae,
    when, urging us to rule that state insurance coverage be extended to employees’
    companions, they suggest that we can ensure responsible administration of such
    a program by “creat[ing] a scheme” to ensure that benefits are extended only
    to same-sex couples with adequate “indicia of commitment” to each other–or
    73
    a “registration scheme” that “is enforceable and guards against fraud.”
    “Creation” of verification and registration systems designed to facilitate
    the extension of state employee benefits to the employees’ unmarried
    companions–and an enforcement mechanism to ensure that only stable and
    committed same-sex couples are eligible for such benefits–is precisely the type
    of action committed to the legislature, as the policymaking branch of
    government. It is beyond all powers of this or any other court.
    Phillips v. Wisconsin Pers. Com’n (Wis. Ct. App. 1992), 
    482 N.W.2d 121
    , 124 n.1 (emphasis
    added).
    ¶152 Appellants contend that the University’s policy discriminates on the basis of marital
    status because it cannot be demonstrated that the policy “was rationally selected to advance
    an independent, legitimate governmental purpose.” However, the legitimate purpose is to
    provide benefits to the partners of University employees. As demonstrated by the above
    quote from Phillips, the use of marriage to define partner eligibility creates certainty and
    practicality in administration of a large benefit program because it incorporates existing state
    law regarding family relationships. As a matter of law, married couples are engaged in a
    permanent relationship because the relationship cannot be terminated except by operation of
    law. Thus, there is a legally presumptive stability that attends to the marital relationship that
    does not exist in other relationships, an important consideration in the administration of health
    plans. Further, the policy is “rationally related to a legitimate state purpose, the state’s
    interest in promoting marriage.” Hinman v. Dep’t of Pers. Admin. (Cal. Ct. App. 1985), 
    167 Cal. App. 3d 516
    , 523 (denying claim for dental benefits for same sex partners of state
    employees).
    74
    ¶153 Appellants contend that the University’s reliance on marriage is sex-based
    discrimination because the policy “den[ies] dependent benefits to a female employee with a
    female partner while offering them to a male employee with a female partner.” However, the
    policy itself rests upon state law which limits marriage to male-female couples, and which,
    with the passage of CI-96 on November 2, 2004, immediately effective, is constitutionally
    established. The law is not sex-based, but facially neutral, because it prohibits both men and
    women from marrying a person of the same sex. To the extent it could still be argued that the
    law is sex-based because it prohibits marriage based upon one’s sex, that classification is,
    nonetheless, now constitutionally sanctioned.
    ¶154 Appellants further contend that the University’s policy discriminates on the basis of
    sexual orientation. There is a dearth of authority that sexual orientation is a suspect class for
    equal protection purposes, but further, and again, the policy is based upon state law defining
    marriage as between a man and a woman. The marital relationship between a man and a
    woman is now a constitutionally-protected classification.          The University’s policy is
    consistent with that constitutional classification and therefore, the government’s reliance on
    that classification cannot result in unlawful discrimination. While these claims may neither
    have prevailed prior to the passage of CI-96 either, those arguments are now moot and need
    not be addressed.
    ¶155 Lastly, the Appellants claim the University’s policy violates their fundamental
    constitutional rights, particularly, the right to dignity.      The concurrence accepts the
    75
    Appellants’ argument, and concludes that the University’s policy should be invalidated by
    application of the dignity provision. See ¶ 97. I thus turn to this final claim.
    ¶156 I would note at this juncture that I respect the personal concern that drives the
    concurrence. I would not question the author’s sincerity nor his desire to render decisions he
    believes will improve the lives of people. Thus, my disagreement with the concurrence is not
    with its empathy, but with its legal analysis.
    ¶157 The concurrence would hold that “[h]uman dignity may not be violated–no
    exceptions.” See ¶ 77. It suggests that various principles emanate from the Constitution’s
    dignity provision that this Court should encase as law. While admirable in thought, such an
    expansive reading and rendering of the dignity provision would easily subsume concrete
    constitutional principles. There is nothing within constitutional jurisprudence, for example,
    of equal protection, due process or cruel and unusual punishment, that would not be
    superseded by the mandate that all people be treated with “dignity.” Indeed, the offered
    model purports “to declare one way in which human dignity can be violated–by denying
    someone the equal protection of the law based on some sort of arbitrary classification . . . .”
    See ¶ 72. Thus, instead of a constitution embodying numerous principles interpreted and
    understood in accordance with their respective jurisprudence, ultimately we would have a
    constitution embodying a single, overriding and encompassing principle–dignity.
    ¶158 Of course, dignity undergirds the Constitution and is part of the philosophical
    foundation of our Constitution. We would desire that all would be treated with dignity and
    work toward such end under the law, but that is something far different than interpreting the
    76
    law to require all outcomes be consistent with dignity–whatever that would mean, and that
    is the problem. Elevating the dignity provision to such a place would inevitably require that
    a judges’ subjective feelings about how a person should be treated be enshrined as law, and
    that without limits, because “human dignity may not be violated–no exceptions.” The
    concurrence itself is illustrative of this concern.
    ¶159 The concurrence reaches its implied conclusion–that marriage can no longer be used
    as a basis for governmental decision and action–without any evidence. This is an appeal from
    the granting of a motion to dismiss, and there are no facts of record beyond those asserted in
    the pleadings. Instead, the concurrence is fueled by sociological research. While research
    is important and is occasionally referenced in court opinions, it is notable here that none of
    the sociological information relied upon by the concurrence was introduced as part of the
    District Court record, and thus, no opportunity to rebut or defend those assertions was ever
    given to the Respondents. Evidence is not critical in order for judges to decide cases on the
    basis of their personal concept of dignity.
    ¶160 The concurrence’s analysis of the dignity provision is comprehensive.                The
    Constitution’s language and history is finely combed. However, not a single word can be
    found therein which would give even a clue that the dignity provision was intended by the
    constitutional convention delegates, or could be extrapolated, to re-order the exclusive nature
    of marriage or otherwise expand marital or related rights to those who did not have them at
    the time the Constitution was adopted. The concurrence asserts such rights are included with
    those “retained by the people.” However, the rights which the concurrence would grant had
    77
    not been granted anywhere in the country at the time of the Constitution’s adoption.
    Discussion about such a fundamental altering of society cannot be found or implied in our
    constitutional history. Would anyone deny, that had Montanans been advised that the word
    “dignity” in our Constitution could be interpreted by judges as legitimizing or benefitting
    homosexual relationships, the Constitution would never have been approved in 1972? Would
    anyone disagree with the same proposition concerning an election today? No one would,
    because it cannot be denied. Thus, the very document which sets forth the word “dignity”
    would not exist under philosophical assumptions offered by the concurrence.
    ¶161 This underscores the authority that judges would need to take to themselves in order
    to do what the concurrence suggests. It would require judges to read into the Constitution,
    either in a manner never contemplated by the people, or, as illustrated by the passage of CI-
    96, directly opposed by the people. To undertake such power would require judges to deny
    the rights of the people which are more fundamental than the right to dignity: the right of the
    people to define their society and to govern themselves. Although the concurrence calls up
    Madison’s “tyranny of the majority,” rendering the conclusion it advocates would require
    judges to act as a “tyranny of the few,” depriving the people of their sovereign rights:
    What goes on in other people’s bedrooms is a question that has intrigued
    me since reaching puberty, but it is none of my business. I thus find it
    distasteful to uphold the denial of health insurance to the dependents of a
    deserving segment of the workforce merely because of their sexual
    predilections.
    ....
    78
    . . . [However, w]e must take care not to read the constitution to embrace
    subjects never thought to be within its reach. The more the state constitution
    is found to be intolerant of disagreement, the deadlier becomes the grip upon
    the people’s inventiveness.
    The most cherished principle in our system is that government rests on
    the consent of the governed. The central idea is that in the meandering course
    of history, there is time for vision and revisions–for mistakes to be made by the
    people and rectified by the people. Democracy has its price. . . . But, surely,
    the judiciary does not have a monopoly on justice. Appellants must seek
    redress in another forum.
    Rutgers Council of AAUP v. Rutgers State Univ. (N.J. Super. 1997), 
    689 A.2d 828
    , 838-39
    (J.A.D. Baime, concurring).
    ¶162 The concurrence taunts the will of the people with repeated criticisms of majoritarian
    morality. It is this very “majoritarian morality” that has placed into law those principles upon
    which society rests. By law, “we the people” feed the hungry, care for the sick, build schools
    and hospitals, educate the population, protect workers’ safety and wages, define and prosecute
    crime, punish the criminal without cruelty, defend the country, rescue the abused child, and
    recompense for damages inflicted, to name a few. Without majoritarian morality, we would
    not be having this discussion today, because a civil society would not exist. For that reason
    it is incorrect to define this issue as a violation of liberty. Liberty is not a license to do what
    is right in one’s own eyes. That is anarchy. Liberty in a free society is the right to pursue
    one’s own life within the solemn principles that “we the people” have established for
    governance of the society. As the delegates stated, referenced within the concurrence’s quote
    in ¶ 54, “the guidelines and protections for the exercise of liberty in a free society come not
    from government but from the people who create the government.”
    79
    ¶163 The Montana Constitution’s opening phrase of “We the people” mirrors the words of
    the United States Constitution. “The United States was then the only country in the world
    with a government founded explicitly on the consent of its people, given in a distinct and
    identifiable act, and the people who gave that consent were intensely, profoundly conscious
    of the fact.” Larry D. Kramer, The People Themselves (2004), p. 5, Oxford University Press.
    The phrase means many things obvious, but more than the obvious is revealed when the
    history of the phrase is studied carefully. Included therein are deep feelings about the nature
    of the Constitution, and the people’s role in its application:
    It means refusing to be deflected by arguments that constitutional law is too
    complex or difficult for ordinary citizens. Constitutional law is indeed
    complex, for legitimating judicial authority has offered an excuse to emphasize
    technical requirements of precedent and legal argument that necessarily
    complicated matters. But this complexity was created by the [United States
    Supreme] Court for the Court and is itself a product of judicializing
    constitutional law.     In reclaiming the Constitution, we reclaim the
    Constitution’s legacy as, in Franklin D. Roosevelt’s words, “a layman’s
    instrument of government” and not “a lawyer’s contract.” Above all, it means
    insisting that the Supreme Court is our servant and not our master: a servant
    whose seriousness and knowledge deserves much deference, but who is
    ultimately supposed to yield to our judgments about what the Constitution
    means and not the reverse. The Supreme Court is not the highest authority in
    the land on constitutional law. We are.
    Kramer, The People Themselves, p. 248.
    ¶164 “We the people” in the Preamble to the Montana Constitution means that the
    Constitution is the people’s–its creation, its adoption, its interpretation–and further means that
    it is the people who determine how their state shall be governed. It does not mean “We the
    judges.”
    80
    ¶165 I would affirm the District Court.
    /S/ JIM RICE
    Justice John Warner joins in the foregoing dissent of Justice Rice.
    /S/ JOHN WARNER
    81
    Chief Justice Karla M. Gray, dissenting.
    ¶166 I respectfully dissent from the Court's opinion. I agree with part--but not all--of
    Justice Rice’s dissent, and feel compelled to comment on several matters.
    ¶167 Most basically and most importantly, it is critical to remember that this case is before
    us on appeal from a decision entered by the First Judicial District Court, Lewis and Clark
    County. It is not an original proceeding in this Court. The issue, therefore, is not as stated
    by the Court. The issue is whether the District Court erred in granting the University
    System's motion to dismiss. Other than several passing references to the District Court's
    granting of that motion and a statement that the District Court erred--on the basis of an issue
    not presented to it--in the first step of its equal protection analysis, even a brief reading of
    the Court's opinion clarifies that it has totally ignored the District Court's legal analysis of
    the issues presented to it by the parties. One can only speculate about why the Court has
    chosen to do so.
    ¶168 The fact remains that the Court resolves the present case, and reverses the trial court,
    on the basis of an issue not presented to the trial court. Our cases holding that we do not
    consider new issues--or changed theories--on appeal are so legion as to require no citation
    to authority. The reason is mentioned above: as a reviewing Court, it is fundamentally
    unfair for us to reverse a district court on the basis of arguments not presented to it. In
    addition, of course, doing so essentially makes this Court the court of first--rather than last--
    resort in an appeal. The Court's statement that we may address the issue because the parties
    briefed it totally misses the essence of our "will not consider" rule, which focuses not on
    82
    what the parties argue, but on this Court's proper role as a reviewing court.         Absent a
    reasoned and correct legal analysis by this Court establishing some error of law in the
    District Court's resolution of the case before it, I would affirm that court. Because the Court
    addresses the new issue, however, I feel compelled to respond.
    ¶169 I disagree strongly with the Court's discussion and analysis of common law marriage,
    which is the basis on which it determines that this is a case about unmarried opposite-sex
    couples versus unmarried same-sex couples, rather than about married couples versus non-
    married couples. Indeed, the inherent flaw--both logically and legally--in both appellants'
    arguments and the Court's opinion can be seen early on when the Court relates that the
    appellant couples "consider themselves married and hold themselves out to their families and
    their community as a couple in a committed, marital relationship." There is no question that
    these couples consider themselves married in their hearts and souls; nor do I doubt for a
    moment that they hold themselves out as such and, hopefully, are accepted as such in the
    hearts of their communities. The problem is that Montana does not recognize same-sex
    marriages. Under the law--whether we like it or not--these couples are not eligible for
    marriage in the state of Montana whether by solemnization, declaration or common law.
    I cannot join in the Court's creation of the artificial construct of "unmarried opposite-sex and
    unmarried same-sex couples" for purposes of resolving this appeal.
    ¶170   I do join the Court in acknowledging the extraordinary number of amici curiae who
    appeared in this case. Our legal analyses are often illuminated by such amici, which is as
    it should be. Indeed, the facts set forth by the Court from amicus Northwest Women's Law
    83
    Center regarding the numerous entities which have allowed same-sex domestic partners to
    qualify for benefits are interesting and, perhaps, indicative of a trend. These facts, however,
    are of no relevance to the legal issues before us. That many may choose to provide such
    benefits to same-sex domestic partners bears no relationship to the legal question of whether
    the law requires such an action. Indeed, I wonder whether all of the amici siding with the
    appellants in the present case have chosen to provide health benefits to same-sex domestic
    partners. The fact remains, contrary to the Court's "restatement" of the University System's
    policy, that by its terms the policy permits all University System employees who have
    spouses recognized by Montana law--whether via solemnization, declaration or common
    law--to purchase health benefits for their marital partners. Thus, I turn briefly to the Court's
    discussion of the University System's Affidavit.
    ¶171 The University System's Affidavit of Common-Law Marriage is a sworn statement
    by couples eligible for marriage under Montana law. When sworn and subscribed to, and
    duly notarized, it is a clear statement that the couple has--since a past date--lived together
    as husband and wife and taken on the responsibilities and duties of marriage. The Court
    apparently believes University System employees will swear to untruths. I cannot join the
    Court in such an unsupported perception of University System employees.
    ¶172 The Court also cites to a law review article on the subject of the continued viability
    of common law marriage (a proposition unrelated to the present case) which observes that
    no jurisdiction permits a statement of future intent to create a common law marriage. While
    the observation is undoubtedly true, the Affidavit at issue here is not a statement of future
    84
    intent, as discussed above. The Court goes on to interpret the Affidavit as being one by a
    couple "who declines to sign a statutory written declaration." Such a negative connotation
    is totally unwarranted in a state which recognizes common law marriage. The fact is that
    the sworn Affidavit used by the University System evidences that the couple has married
    under the common law. Most assuredly, the Affidavit does not create the marriage. In my
    view, however, the Affidavit is not reasonably susceptible to a determination by this Court
    that the sworn statements are made by those who "may not choose to marry at all, but rather
    may choose to sign a document in order to receive employment benefits." Not surprisingly,
    nothing of record supports such a determination.
    ¶173 Nor does the Court's statement that we are "not aware of any Montana 'case' in which
    a common law marriage has been established without one of the parties involved in the
    relationship using extrinsic evidence to prove" the existence of the elements of a common
    law marriage advance its theory in any substantive way. That this Court sees very few cases
    involving common law marriage does not mean there are not thousands of such marriages
    in Montana which never require a court determination regarding the marriage at all, even on
    the death of one of the spouses. Moreover, I daresay that district courts across the state have
    conducted any number of dissolution proceedings involving spouses in a common law
    marriage where the validity of the marriage never arises and need not be determined. I
    personally know of a situation in which a common law marriage was dissolved in the usual
    way under the laws applicable to the dissolution of marriages, without any issue being
    raised--or resolved by the trial court--about the existence of the common law marriage. It
    85
    is disingenuous for this Court to rely on a mere lack of "awareness" of any common law
    marriage "case" not involving extrinsic evidence while ignoring the certainty that the issue
    of the existence of a common law marriage thankfully does not always result in litigation at
    all, much less litigation which makes its way to this Court.
    ¶174 For equal protection purposes, and notwithstanding the Court's statement to the
    contrary, there is nothing "illusory" about the marital versus non-marital nature of the
    University System's policy. Indeed, the appellants argued in the District Court, and argue
    here, a marital versus non-marital classification. The classes created by the policy are based
    entirely on the kinds of marriages recognized by Montana law, not sexual orientation. For
    purposes of this case, the difference between the "classes" is that one class involves a spouse
    in a legally recognized marital relationship and the other class involves a committed partner
    in a relationship which under current Montana law does not--and cannot--constitute a
    marriage in any legal sense. Thus, the present case is readily distinguishable from both the
    Court's and former Chief Justice Turnage's opinions in Gryczan, which did not involve a
    marital classification. Moreover, expressly unlike the present case, Gryczan presented a
    challenge to the constitutionality of a statute criminalizing sexual acts between same-sex
    people. Here, we all agree the appellants are not directly challenging Montana's laws
    relating to the definition of marriage. For those reasons, I submit Gryczan has no application
    here.
    ¶175 With regard to the Court's statement that it is unconvinced the policy at issue is
    justified based on administrative efficiency, surely the Court cannot mean administrative
    86
    efficiency is not a legitimate governmental interest. Perhaps the Court merely means that
    it disagrees the policy advances administrative efficiency. If so, I suggest that this Court is
    not in a position to make such a determination for the University System; nor could we
    properly conclude that a marital versus non-marital classification is not a rational means of
    making health benefits available to "dependents" of University System employees.
    "Rational" does not equate to what this Court might have chosen to do.
    ¶176 In any event, it is true--as the Court states--that the University System could adopt
    other policies. Those policies conceivably could make health benefits available to any and
    all individuals chosen by University System employees. They conceivably could exclude
    health benefits for any spouses or children of University System employees. But the issue
    here is whether the policy actually adopted by the University System denies equal protection
    of the law. In my view, it does not, at least as discussed and resolved by the Court.
    ¶177     It is difficult to close without addressing, in some way, Justice Nelson's passionate
    and scholarly concurring opinion which correctly notes the historic discrimination against
    gay and lesbian citizens, cites to much sociological and academic literature and other
    materials, and provides a number of analytical approaches based on various articles and
    books. We all have passions that run deep and strong, and the nice thing about either
    authoring or responding to a concurring opinion is that one is more free to express
    her/himself outside the strictures that generally apply to a Court opinion. For myself,
    however, the closer I stay to the law and away from personal passions, the better I perform
    this very difficult job. Moreover, concurring opinions and responses thereto sometimes are
    87
    viewed by others--whether intended by the author or not--as taking positions in advance on
    matters that need not be addressed in the context of the present case. Again, for myself, I
    would rather await a case or controversy presenting a clear issue, based on a record, which
    necessarily requires resolution of an issue.
    ¶178     In sum, I dissent from the Court's opinion and, since no error is established by the
    Court in the District Court's resolution of the issues before it, I would affirm the District
    Court.
    /S/ KARLA M. GRAY
    88
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 03-238

Citation Numbers: 2004 MT 390, 325 Mont. 148, 104 P.3d 445, 2004 Mont. LEXIS 675

Judges: Regnier, Nelson, Rice, Warner, Gray, Cotter, Leaphart

Filed Date: 12/30/2004

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 11/11/2024

Authorities (53)

Lofton v. Kearney , 157 F. Supp. 2d 1372 ( 2001 )

State v. Martinez , 2003 MT 65 ( 2003 )

Commonwealth v. Bonadio , 490 Pa. 91 ( 1980 )

San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez , 93 S. Ct. 1278 ( 1973 )

Spradlin v. United States , 262 F. Supp. 502 ( 1967 )

International Painters and Allied Trades Industry Pension ... , 312 F. Supp. 2d 697 ( 2004 )

Phillips v. Wisconsin Personnel Commission , 167 Wis. 2d 205 ( 1992 )

State v. Baldwin , 318 Mont. 489 ( 2003 )

McKenzie Mary E. v. Harris, Patricia, Secretary of Health & ... , 679 F.2d 8 ( 1982 )

In Re the Mental Health of K.G.F. , 306 Mont. 1 ( 2001 )

Walker v. State , 316 Mont. 103 ( 2003 )

State v. Lucero , 322 Mont. 42 ( 2004 )

Gryczan v. State , 283 Mont. 433 ( 1997 )

People v. Garcia , 77 Cal. App. 4th 1269 ( 2000 )

Weaver v. Nebo School District , 29 F. Supp. 2d 1279 ( 1998 )

Ella Mae Larochelle v. Office of Personnel Management , 774 F.2d 1079 ( 1985 )

Henry v. State Compensation Insurance Fund , 294 Mont. 449 ( 1999 )

Alphonso Marcus v. Director, Office of Workers' ... , 548 F.2d 1044 ( 1976 )

Matter of Estate of Murnion , 1984 Mont. LEXIS 1020 ( 1984 )

Boutilier v. Immigration & Naturalization Service , 87 S. Ct. 1563 ( 1967 )

View All Authorities »

Cited By (17)

Adoption of A.W.S. and K.R.S. , 377 Mont. 234 ( 2014 )

AJB and OF v. 18th Judicial District ( 2023 )

State v. Guill , 359 Mont. 225 ( 2011 )

Benefis Healthcare v. GREAT FALLS CLINIC, LLP. , 334 Mont. 86 ( 2006 )

Kulstad v. Maniaci , 352 Mont. 513 ( 2009 )

Baxter v. State , 354 Mont. 234 ( 2009 )

Brown v. YELLOWSTONE CLUB OPERATIONS, LLC , 361 Mont. 124 ( 2011 )

Montana Cannabis Industry Ass'n v. State , 366 Mont. 224 ( 2012 )

State v. Holm , 552 Utah Adv. Rep. 3 ( 2006 )

MONTANA SHOOTING SPORTS ASS'N v. State , 355 Mont. 49 ( 2010 )

Rohlfs v. KLEMENHAGEN, LLC , 354 Mont. 133 ( 2009 )

Jones v. County of Missoula , 330 Mont. 205 ( 2006 )

Wilkes v. Montana State Fund , 341 Mont. 292 ( 2008 )

Hamlin v. DOT ( 2022 )

S. Hensley v. State Fund ( 2020 )

Donaldson v. State of Montana , 2012 MT 288 ( 2012 )

Northern Plains Resource Council, Inc. v. Montana Board of ... , 366 Mont. 399 ( 2012 )

View All Citing Opinions »