-
(Slip Opinion) OCTOBER TERM, 2013 1 Syllabus NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued. The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader. See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co.,
200 U. S. 321, 337. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES Syllabus MCCUTCHEON ET AL. v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA No. 12–536. Argued October 8, 2013—Decided April 2, 2014 The right to participate in democracy through political contributions is protected by the First Amendment, but that right is not absolute. Congress may regulate campaign contributions to protect against corruption or the appearance of corruption. See, e.g., Buckley v. Valeo,
424 U. S. 1, 26–27. It may not, however, regulate contribu- tions simply to reduce the amount of money in politics, or to restrict the political participation of some in order to enhance the relative in- fluence of others. See, e.g., Arizona Free Enterprise Club’s Freedom Club PAC v. Bennett, 564 U. S. ___, ___. The Federal Election Campaign Act of 1971 (FECA), as amended by the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002 (BCRA), imposes two types of limits on campaign contributions. Base limits restrict how much money a donor may contribute to a particular candidate or committee while aggregate limits restrict how much money a donor may contribute in total to all candidates or committees. 2 U. S. C. §441a. In the 2011–2012 election cycle, appellant McCutcheon contributed to 16 different federal candidates, complying with the base limits ap- plicable to each. He alleges that the aggregate limits prevented him from contributing to 12 additional candidates and to a number of noncandidate political committees. He also alleges that he wishes to make similar contributions in the future, all within the base limits. McCutcheon and appellant Republican National Committee filed a complaint before a three-judge District Court, asserting that the ag- gregate limits were unconstitutional under the First Amendment. The District Court denied their motion for a preliminary injunction and granted the Government’s motion to dismiss. Assuming that the 2 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Syllabus base limits appropriately served the Government’s anticorruption in- terest, the District Court concluded that the aggregate limits sur- vived First Amendment scrutiny because they prevented evasion of the base limits. Held: The judgment is reversed, and the case is remanded.
893 F. Supp. 2d 133, reversed and remanded. CHIEF JUSTICE ROBERTS, joined by JUSTICE SCALIA, JUSTICE KENNE- DY, and JUSTICE ALITO, concluded that the aggregate limits are inva- lid under the First Amendment. Pp. 7–40. (a) Appellants’ substantial First Amendment challenge to the cur- rent system of aggregate limits merits plenary consideration. Pp. 7– 14. (1) In Buckley, this Court evaluated the constitutionality of the original contribution and expenditure limits in FECA. Buckley dis- tinguished the two types of limits based on the degree to which each encroaches upon protected First Amendment interests. It subjected expenditure limits to “the exacting scrutiny applicable to limitations on core First Amendment rights of political expression.”
424 U. S., at44–45. But it concluded that contribution limits impose a lesser re- straint on political speech and thus applied a lesser but still “rigorous standard of review,”
id., at 29, under which such limits “may be sus- tained if the State demonstrates a sufficiently important interest and employs means closely drawn to avoid unnecessary abridgement of associational freedoms,”
id., at 25. Because the Court found that the primary purpose of FECA—preventing quid pro quo corruption and its appearance—was a “sufficiently important” governmental inter- est,
id.,at 26–27, it upheld the base limit under the “closely drawn” test,
id., at 29. After doing so, the Court devoted only one paragraph of its 139-page opinion to the aggregate limit then in place under FECA, noting that the provision “ha[d] not been separately addressed at length by the parties.”
Id., at 38. It concluded that the aggregate limit served to prevent circumvention of the base limit and was “no more than a corollary” of that limit.
Id., at 38. Pp. 7–9. (2) There is no need in this case to revisit Buckley’s distinction between contributions and expenditures and the corresponding dis- tinction in standards of review. Regardless whether strict scrutiny or the “closely drawn” test applies, the analysis turns on the fit between the stated governmental objective and the means selected to achieve that objective. Here, given the substantial mismatch between the Government’s stated objective and the means selected to achieve it, the aggregate limits fail even under the “closely drawn” test. Buckley’s ultimate conclusion about the constitutionality of the ag- gregate limit in place under FECA does not control here. Buckley spent just three sentences analyzing that limit, which had not been Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 3 Syllabus separately addressed by the parties. Appellants here, by contrast, have directly challenged the aggregate limits in place under BCRA, a different statutory regime whose limits operate against a distinct le- gal backdrop. Most notably, statutory safeguards against circumven- tion have been considerably strengthened since Buckley. The 1976 FECA Amendments added another layer of base limits—capping con- tributions from individuals to political committees—and an antipro- liferation rule prohibiting donors from creating or controlling multi- ple affiliated political committees. Since Buckley, the Federal Election Commission has also enacted an intricate regulatory scheme that further limits the opportunities for circumvention of the base limits through “unearmarked contributions to political committees likely to contribute” to a particular candidate.
424 U. S., at 38. In addition to accounting for such statutory and regulatory changes, ap- pellants raise distinct legal arguments not considered in Buckley, in- cluding an overbreadth challenge to the aggregate limit. Pp. 10–14. (b) Significant First Amendment interests are implicated here. Contributing money to a candidate is an exercise of an individual’s right to participate in the electoral process through both political ex- pression and political association. A restriction on how many candi- dates and committees an individual may support is hardly a “modest restraint” on those rights. The Government may no more restrict how many candidates or causes a donor may support than it may tell a newspaper how many candidates it may endorse. In its simplest terms, the aggregate limits prohibit an individual from fully contrib- uting to the primary and general election campaigns of ten or more candidates, even if all contributions fall within the base limits. And it is no response to say that the individual can simply contribute less than the base limits permit: To require one person to contribute at lower levels because he wants to support more candidates or causes is to penalize that individual for “robustly exercis[ing]” his First Amendment rights. Davis v. Federal Election Comm’n,
554 U. S. 724, 739. In assessing the First Amendment interests at stake, the proper fo- cus is on an individual’s right to engage in political speech, not a col- lective conception of the public good. The whole point of the First Amendment is to protect individual speech that the majority might prefer to restrict, or that legislators or judges might not view as use- ful to the democratic process. Pp. 14–18. (c) The aggregate limits do not further the permissible governmen- tal interest in preventing quid pro quo corruption or its appearance. Pp. 18–36. (1) This Court has identified only one legitimate governmental interest for restricting campaign finances: preventing corruption or 4 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Syllabus the appearance of corruption. See Davis,
supra, at 741. Moreover, the only type of corruption that Congress may target is quid pro quo corruption. Spending large sums of money in connection with elec- tions, but not in connection with an effort to control the exercise of an officeholder’s official duties, does not give rise to quid pro quo corrup- tion. Nor does the possibility that an individual who spends large sums may garner “influence over or access to” elected officials or po- litical parties. Citizens United v. Federal Election Comm’n,
558 U. S. 310, 359. The line between quid pro quo corruption and general in- fluence must be respected in order to safeguard basic First Amend- ment rights, and the Court must “err on the side of protecting politi- cal speech rather than suppressing it.” Federal Election Comm’n v. Wisconsin Right to Life,
551 U. S. 449, 457 (opinion of ROBERTS, C. J.). Pp. 18–21. (2) The Government argues that the aggregate limits further the permissible objective of preventing quid pro quo corruption. The dif- ficulty is that once the aggregate limits kick in, they ban all contribu- tions of any amount, even though Congress’s selection of a base limit indicates its belief that contributions beneath that amount do not create a cognizable risk of corruption. The Government must thus defend the aggregate limits by demonstrating that they prevent cir- cumvention of the base limits, a function they do not serve in any meaningful way. Given the statutes and regulations currently in ef- fect, Buckley’s fear that an individual might “contribute massive amounts of money to a particular candidate through . . . unear- marked contributions” to entities likely to support the candidate,
424 U. S., at 38, is far too speculative. Even accepting Buckley’s circum- vention theory, it is hard to see how a candidate today could receive “massive amounts of money” that could be traced back to a particular donor uninhibited by the aggregate limits. The Government’s scenar- ios offered in support of that possibility are either illegal under cur- rent campaign finance laws or implausible. Pp. 21–30. (3) The aggregate limits also violate the First Amendment be- cause they are not “closely drawn to avoid unnecessary abridgment of associational freedoms.” Buckley,
supra, at 25. The Government ar- gues that the aggregate limits prevent an individual from giving to too many initial recipients who might then recontribute a donation, but experience suggests that the vast majority of contributions are retained and spent by their recipients. And the Government has pro- vided no reason to believe that candidates or party committees would dramatically shift their priorities if the aggregate limits were lifted. The indiscriminate ban on all contributions above the aggregate lim- its is thus disproportionate to the Government’s interest in prevent- ing circumvention. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 5 Syllabus Importantly, there are multiple alternatives available to Congress that would serve the Government’s interest in preventing circumven- tion while avoiding “unnecessary abridgment” of First Amendment rights. Buckley, supra, at 25. Such alternatives might include tar- geted restrictions on transfers among candidates and political com- mittees, or tighter earmarking rules. Transfers, after all, are the key to the Government’s concern about circumvention, but they can be addressed without such a direct and broad interference with First Amendment rights. Pp. 30–35. (4) Disclosure of contributions also reduces the potential for abuse of the campaign finance system. Disclosure requirements, which are justified by “a governmental interest in ‘provid[ing] the electorate with information’ about the sources of election-related spending,” Citizens United, supra, at 367, may deter corruption “by exposing large contributions and expenditures to the light of publici- ty,” Buckley,
supra at 67. Disclosure requirements may burden speech, but they often represent a less restrictive alternative to flat bans on certain types or quantities of speech. Particularly with mod- ern technology, disclosure now offers more robust protections against corruption than it did when Buckley was decided. Pp. 35–36. (d) The Government offers an additional rationale for the aggregate limits, arguing that the opportunity for corruption exists whenever a legislator is given a large check, even if the check consists of contri- butions within the base limits to be divided among numerous candi- dates or committees. That rationale dangerously broadens the cir- cumscribed definition of quid pro quo corruption articulated in prior cases. Buckley confined its analysis to the possibility that “massive amounts of money” could be funneled to a particular candidate in ex- cess of the base limits.
424 U. S., at 38. Recasting as corruption a donor’s widely distributed support for a political party would dramat- ically expand government regulation of the political process. And though the Government suggests that solicitation of large contribu- tions poses the corruption danger, the aggregate limits are not lim- ited to any direct solicitation by an officeholder or candidate. Pp. 36– 39. JUSTICE THOMAS agreed that the aggregate limits are invalid under the First Amendment, but would overrule Buckley v. Valeo,
424 U. S. 1, and subject BCRA’s aggregate limits to strict scrutiny, which they would surely fail. Buckley’s “analytic foundation . . . was tenuous from the very beginning and has only continued to erode in the inter- vening years.” Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC,
528 U. S. 377, 412 (THOMAS, J., dissenting). Contributions and expenditures are simply “two sides of the same First Amendment coin,” and this Court’s efforts to distinguish the two have produced mere “word 6 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Syllabus games” rather than any cognizable constitutional law principle. Buckley,
supra, at 241, 244(Burger, C. J., concurring in part and dis- senting in part). Pp. 1–5. ROBERTS, C. J., announced the judgment of the Court and delivered an opinion, in which SCALIA, KENNEDY, and ALITO, JJ., joined. THOMAS, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment. BREYER, J., filed a dis- senting opinion, in which GINSBURG, SOTOMAYOR, and KAGAN, JJ., joined. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 1 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Wash- ington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 12–536 _________________ SHAUN MCCUTCHEON, ET AL., APPELLANTS v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION ON APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA [April 2, 2014] CHIEF JUSTICE ROBERTS announced the judgment of the Court and delivered an opinion, in which JUSTICE SCALIA, JUSTICE KENNEDY, and JUSTICE ALITO join. There is no right more basic in our democracy than the right to participate in electing our political leaders. Citi- zens can exercise that right in a variety of ways: They can run for office themselves, vote, urge others to vote for a particular candidate, volunteer to work on a campaign, and contribute to a candidate’s campaign. This case is about the last of those options. The right to participate in democracy through political contributions is protected by the First Amendment, but that right is not absolute. Our cases have held that Con- gress may regulate campaign contributions to protect against corruption or the appearance of corruption. See, e.g., Buckley v. Valeo,
424 U. S. 1, 26–27 (1976) (per curiam). At the same time, we have made clear that Congress may not regulate contributions simply to reduce the amount of money in politics, or to restrict the political participation of some in order to enhance the relative influence of others. See, e.g., Arizona Free Enterprise 2 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. Club’s Freedom Club PAC v. Bennett, 564 U. S. ___, ___ (2011) (slip op., at 24–25). Many people might find those latter objectives attrac- tive: They would be delighted to see fewer television com- mercials touting a candidate’s accomplishments or dispar- aging an opponent’s character. Money in politics may at times seem repugnant to some, but so too does much of what the First Amendment vigorously protects. If the First Amendment protects flag burning, funeral protests, and Nazi parades—despite the profound offense such spectacles cause—it surely protects political campaign speech despite popular opposition. See Texas v. Johnson,
491 U. S. 397(1989); Snyder v. Phelps, 562 U. S. ___ (2011); National Socialist Party of America v. Skokie,
432 U. S. 43(1977) (per curiam). Indeed, as we have empha- sized, the First Amendment “has its fullest and most urgent application precisely to the conduct of campaigns for political office.” Monitor Patriot Co. v. Roy,
401 U. S. 265, 272 (1971). In a series of cases over the past 40 years, we have spelled out how to draw the constitutional line between the permissible goal of avoiding corruption in the political process and the impermissible desire simply to limit polit- ical speech. We have said that government regulation may not target the general gratitude a candidate may feel toward those who support him or his allies, or the political access such support may afford. “Ingratiation and access . . . are not corruption.” Citizens United v. Federal Elec- tion Comm’n,
558 U. S. 310, 360 (2010). They embody a central feature of democracy—that constituents support candidates who share their beliefs and interests, and candidates who are elected can be expected to be respon- sive to those concerns. Any regulation must instead target what we have called “quid pro quo” corruption or its appearance. See
id., at 359. That Latin phrase captures the notion of a direct Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 3 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. exchange of an official act for money. See McCormick v. United States,
500 U. S. 257, 266 (1991). “The hallmark of corruption is the financial quid pro quo: dollars for po- litical favors.” Federal Election Comm’n v. National Con- servative Political Action Comm.,
470 U. S. 480, 497 (1985). Campaign finance restrictions that pursue other objectives, we have explained, impermissibly inject the Government “into the debate over who should govern.” Bennett, supra, at ___ (slip op., at 25). And those who govern should be the last people to help decide who should govern. The statute at issue in this case imposes two types of limits on campaign contributions. The first, called base limits, restricts how much money a donor may contribute to a particular candidate or committee. 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(1). The second, called aggregate limits, restricts how much money a donor may contribute in total to all candidates or committees. §441a(a)(3). This case does not involve any challenge to the base limits, which we have previously upheld as serving the permissible objective of combatting corruption. The Gov- ernment contends that the aggregate limits also serve that objective, by preventing circumvention of the base limits. We conclude, however, that the aggregate limits do little, if anything, to address that concern, while seriously re- stricting participation in the democratic process. The aggregate limits are therefore invalid under the First Amendment. I A For the 2013–2014 election cycle, the base limits in the Federal Election Campaign Act of 1971 (FECA), as amended by the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002 (BCRA), permit an individual to contribute up to $2,600 per election to a candidate ($5,200 total for the primary 4 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. and general elections); $32,400 per year to a national party committee;1 $10,000 per year to a state or local party committee; and $5,000 per year to a political action com- mittee, or “PAC.” 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(1);
78 Fed. Reg. 8532(2013).2 A national committee, state or local party com- mittee, or multicandidate PAC may in turn contribute up to $5,000 per election to a candidate. §441a(a)(2).3 The base limits apply with equal force to contributions that are “in any way earmarked or otherwise directed through an intermediary or conduit” to a candidate. §441a(a)(8). If, for example, a donor gives money to a party committee but directs the party committee to pass the contribution along to a particular candidate, then the transaction is treated as a contribution from the original donor to the specified candidate. For the 2013–2014 election cycle, the aggregate limits in BCRA permit an individual to contribute a total of $48,600 to federal candidates and a total of $74,600 to other politi- cal committees. Of that $74,600, only $48,600 may be contributed to state or local party committees and PACs, —————— 1 Thereare six authorized national party committees: the Republican National Committee, the Democratic National Committee, the National Republican Senatorial Committee, the Democratic Senatorial Cam- paign Committee, the National Republican Congressional Committee, and the Democratic Congressional Campaign Committee. See
2 U. S. C. §431(14). 2 A PAC is a business, labor, or interest group that raises or spends money in connection with a federal election, in some cases by contrib- uting to candidates. A so-called “Super PAC” is a PAC that makes only independent expenditures and cannot contribute to candidates. The base and aggregate limits govern contributions to traditional PACs, but not to independent expenditure PACs. See SpeechNow.org v. Federal Election Comm’n,
599 F. 3d 686, 695–696 (CADC 2010) (en banc). 3 A multicandidate PAC is a PAC with more than 50 contributors that has been registered for at least six months and has made contributions to five or more candidates for federal office.
11 CFR §100.5(e)(3) (2012). PACs that do not qualify as multicandidate PACs must abide by the base limit applicable to individual contributions. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 5 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. as opposed to national party committees. §441a(a)(3);
78 Fed. Reg. 8532. All told, an individual may contribute up to $123,200 to candidate and noncandidate committees during each two-year election cycle. The base limits thus restrict how much money a donor may contribute to any particular candidate or committee; the aggregate limits have the effect of restricting how many candidates or committees the donor may support, to the extent permitted by the base limits. B In the 2011–2012 election cycle, appellant Shaun McCutcheon contributed a total of $33,088 to 16 different federal candidates, in compliance with the base limits applicable to each. He alleges that he wished to contribute $1,776 to each of 12 additional candidates but was pre- vented from doing so by the aggregate limit on contribu- tions to candidates. McCutcheon also contributed a total of $27,328 to several noncandidate political committees, in compliance with the base limits applicable to each. He alleges that he wished to contribute to various other polit- ical committees, including $25,000 to each of the three Republican national party committees, but was prevented from doing so by the aggregate limit on contributions to political committees. McCutcheon further alleges that he plans to make similar contributions in the future. In the 2013–2014 election cycle, he again wishes to contribute at least $60,000 to various candidates and $75,000 to non-candidate political committees. Brief for Appellant McCutcheon 11–12. Appellant Republican National Committee is a national political party committee charged with the general man- agement of the Republican Party. The RNC wishes to receive the contributions that McCutcheon and similarly situated individuals would like to make—contributions otherwise permissible under the base limits for national 6 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. party committees but foreclosed by the aggregate limit on contributions to political committees. In June 2012, McCutcheon and the RNC filed a com- plaint before a three-judge panel of the U. S. District Court for the District of Columbia. See BCRA §403(a),
116 Stat. 113–114. McCutcheon and the RNC asserted that the aggregate limits on contributions to candidates and to noncandidate political committees were unconstitutional under the First Amendment. They moved for a prelimi- nary injunction against enforcement of the challenged provisions, and the Government moved to dismiss the case. The three-judge District Court denied appellants’ mo- tion for a preliminary injunction and granted the Govern- ment’s motion to dismiss. Assuming that the base limits appropriately served the Government’s anticorruption interest, the District Court concluded that the aggregate limits survived First Amendment scrutiny because they prevented evasion of the base limits.
893 F. Supp. 2d 133, 140 (2012). In particular, the District Court imagined a hypothetical scenario that might occur in a world without aggregate limits. A single donor might contribute the maximum amount under the base limits to nearly 50 separate com- mittees, each of which might then transfer the money to the same single committee.
Ibid.That committee, in turn, might use all the transferred money for coordinated expenditures on behalf of a particular candidate, allowing the single donor to circumvent the base limit on the amount he may contribute to that candidate.
Ibid.The District Court acknowledged that “it may seem unlikely that so many separate entities would willingly serve as conduits” for the single donor’s interests, but it concluded that such a scenario “is not hard to imagine.”
Ibid.It thus rejected a constitutional challenge to the aggregate limits, characterizing the base limits and the aggregate Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 7 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. limits “as a coherent system rather than merely a collec- tion of individual limits stacking prophylaxis upon prophy- laxis.”
Ibid.McCutcheon and the RNC appealed directly to this Court, as authorized by law.
28 U. S. C. §1253. In such a case, “we ha[ve] no discretion to refuse adjudication of the case on its merits,” Hicks v. Miranda,
422 U. S. 332, 344 (1975), and accordingly we noted probable jurisdiction. 568 U. S. ___ (2013). II A Buckley v. Valeo,
424 U. S. 1, presented this Court with its first opportunity to evaluate the constitutionality of the original contribution and expenditure limits set forth in FECA. FECA imposed a $1,000 per election base limit on contributions from an individual to a federal candidate. It also imposed a $25,000 per year aggregate limit on all contributions from an individual to candidates or political committees.
18 U. S. C. §§608(b)(1), 608(b)(3) (1970 ed., Supp. IV). On the expenditures side, FECA imposed limits on both independent expenditures and candidates’ overall campaign expenditures. §§608(e)(1), 608(c). Buckley recognized that “contribution and expenditure limitations operate in an area of the most fundamental First Amendment activities.”
424 U. S., at 14. But it distinguished expenditure limits from contribution limits based on the degree to which each encroaches upon pro- tected First Amendment interests. Expenditure limits, the Court explained, “necessarily reduce[ ] the quantity of expression by restricting the number of issues discussed, the depth of their exploration, and the size of the audience reached.”
Id., at 19. The Court thus subjected expendi- ture limits to “the exacting scrutiny applicable to lim- itations on core First Amendment rights of political expression.”
Id.,at 44–45. Under exacting scrutiny, the 8 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. Government may regulate protected speech only if such regulation promotes a compelling interest and is the least restrictive means to further the articulated interest. See Sable Communications of Cal., Inc. v. FCC,
492 U. S. 115, 126 (1989). By contrast, the Court concluded that contribution limits impose a lesser restraint on political speech because they “permit[ ] the symbolic expression of support evi- denced by a contribution but do[ ] not in any way infringe the contributor’s freedom to discuss candidates and is- sues.” Buckley,
424 U. S., at 21. As a result, the Court focused on the effect of the contribution limits on the freedom of political association and applied a lesser but still “rigorous standard of review.”
Id., at 29. Under that standard, “[e]ven a ‘ “significant interference” with pro- tected rights of political association’ may be sustained if the State demonstrates a sufficiently important interest and employs means closely drawn to avoid unnecessary abridgement of associational freedoms.”
Id., at 25(quot- ing Cousins v. Wigoda,
419 U. S. 477, 488 (1975)). The primary purpose of FECA was to limit quid pro quo corruption and its appearance; that purpose satisfied the requirement of a “sufficiently important” governmental interest.
424 U. S., at26–27. As for the “closely drawn” component, Buckley concluded that the $1,000 base limit “focuses precisely on the problem of large campaign con- tributions . . . while leaving persons free to engage in independent political expression, to associate actively through volunteering their services, and to assist to a limited but nonetheless substantial extent in supporting candidates and committees with financial resources.”
Id., at 28. The Court therefore upheld the $1,000 base limit under the “closely drawn” test.
Id., at 29. The Court next separately considered an overbreadth challenge to the base limit. See
id.,at 29–30. The chal- lengers argued that the base limit was fatally overbroad Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 9 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. because most large donors do not seek improper influence over legislators’ actions. Although the Court accepted that premise, it nevertheless rejected the overbreadth chal- lenge for two reasons: First, it was too “difficult to isolate suspect contributions” based on a contributor’s subjective intent.
Id., at 30. Second, “Congress was justified in concluding that the interest in safeguarding against the appearance of impropriety requires that the opportunity for abuse inherent in the process of raising large monetary contributions be eliminated.”
Ibid.Finally, in one paragraph of its 139-page opinion, the Court turned to the $25,000 aggregate limit under FECA. As a preliminary matter, it noted that the constitution- ality of the aggregate limit “ha[d] not been separately addressed at length by the parties.”
Id., at 38. Then, in three sentences, the Court disposed of any constitutional objections to the aggregate limit that the challengers might have had: “The overall $25,000 ceiling does impose an ultimate restriction upon the number of candidates and com- mittees with which an individual may associate him- self by means of financial support. But this quite modest restraint upon protected political activity serves to prevent evasion of the $1,000 contribution limitation by a person who might otherwise contribute massive amounts of money to a particular candidate through the use of unearmarked contributions to po- litical committees likely to contribute to that candi- date, or huge contributions to the candidate’s political party. The limited, additional restriction on associa- tional freedom imposed by the overall ceiling is thus no more than a corollary of the basic individual con- tribution limitation that we have found to be constitu- tionally valid.”
Ibid.10 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. B 1 The parties and amici curiae spend significant energy debating whether the line that Buckley drew between contributions and expenditures should remain the law. Notwithstanding the robust debate, we see no need in this case to revisit Buckley’s distinction between contributions and expenditures and the corollary distinction in the applicable standards of review. Buckley held that the Government’s interest in preventing quid pro quo corrup- tion or its appearance was “sufficiently important,”
id.,at 26–27; we have elsewhere stated that the same interest may properly be labeled “compelling,” see National Con- servative Political Action Comm.,
470 U. S., at496–497, so that the interest would satisfy even strict scrutiny. More- over, regardless whether we apply strict scrutiny or Buck- ley’s “closely drawn” test, we must assess the fit between the stated governmental objective and the means selected to achieve that objective. See, e.g., National Conservative Political Action Comm., supra, at 496–501; Randall v. Sorrell,
548 U. S. 230, 253–262 (2006) (opinion of BREYER, J.). Or to put it another way, if a law that restricts politi- cal speech does not “avoid unnecessary abridgement” of First Amendment rights, Buckley,
424 U. S., at 25, it cannot survive “rigorous” review. Because we find a substantial mismatch between the Government’s stated objective and the means selected to achieve it, the aggregate limits fail even under the “closely drawn” test. We therefore need not parse the differences between the two standards in this case. 2 Buckley treated the constitutionality of the $25,000 aggregate limit as contingent upon that limit’s ability to prevent circumvention of the $1,000 base limit, describing the aggregate limit as “no more than a corollary” of the Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 11 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. base limit.
Id., at 38. The Court determined that circum- vention could occur when an individual legally contributes “massive amounts of money to a particular candidate through the use of unearmarked contributions” to entities that are themselves likely to contribute to the candidate.
Ibid.For that reason, the Court upheld the $25,000 ag- gregate limit. Although Buckley provides some guidance, we think that its ultimate conclusion about the constitutionality of the aggregate limit in place under FECA does not control here. Buckley spent a total of three sentences analyzing that limit; in fact, the opinion pointed out that the consti- tutionality of the aggregate limit “ha[d] not been separately addressed at length by the parties.”
Ibid.We are now asked to address appellants’ direct challenge to the aggre- gate limits in place under BCRA. BCRA is a different statutory regime, and the aggregate limits it imposes operate against a distinct legal backdrop. Most notably, statutory safeguards against circumven- tion have been considerably strengthened since Buckley was decided, through both statutory additions and the introduction of a comprehensive regulatory scheme. With more targeted anticircumvention measures in place today, the indiscriminate aggregate limits under BCRA appear particularly heavy-handed. The 1976 FECA Amendments, for example, added an- other layer of base contribution limits. The 1974 version of FECA had already capped contributions from political committees to candidates, but the 1976 version added limits on contributions to political committees. This change was enacted at least “in part to prevent circumven- tion of the very limitations on contributions that this Court upheld in Buckley.” California Medical Assn. v. Federal Election Comm’n,
453 U. S. 182, 197–198 (1981) (plurality opinion); see also
id., at 203(Blackmun, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment). Because 12 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. a donor’s contributions to a political committee are now limited, a donor cannot flood the committee with “huge” amounts of money so that each contribution the committee makes is perceived as a contribution from him. Buckley,
supra, at 38. Rather, the donor may contribute only $5,000 to the committee, which hardly raises the specter of abuse that concerned the Court in Buckley. Limits on contributions to political committees consequently create an additional hurdle for a donor who seeks both to channel a large amount of money to a particular candidate and to ensure that he gets the credit for doing so. The 1976 Amendments also added an antiprolifera- tion rule prohibiting donors from creating or controlling multiple affiliated political committees. See 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(5);
11 CFR §100.5(g)(4). The Government ac- knowledges that this antiproliferation rule “forecloses what would otherwise be a particularly easy and effective means of circumventing the limits on contributions to any particular political committee.” Brief for Appellee 46. In effect, the rule eliminates a donor’s ability to create and use his own political committees to direct funds in excess of the individual base limits. It thus blocks a straightfor- ward method of achieving the circumvention that was the underlying concern in Buckley. The intricate regulatory scheme that the Federal Elec- tion Commission has enacted since Buckley further limits the opportunities for circumvention of the base limits via “unearmarked contributions to political committees likely to contribute” to a particular candidate.
424 U. S., at 38. Although the earmarking provision, 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(8), was in place when Buckley was decided, the FEC has since added regulations that define earmarking broadly. For example, the regulations construe earmarking to include any designation, “whether direct or indirect, express or implied, oral or written.”
11 CFR §110.6(b)(1). The regu- lations specify that an individual who has contributed to a Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 13 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. particular candidate may not also contribute to a single- candidate committee for that candidate. §110.1(h)(1). Nor may an individual who has contributed to a candidate also contribute to a political committee that has supported or anticipates supporting the same candidate, if the individ- ual knows that “a substantial portion [of his contribution] will be contributed to, or expended on behalf of,” that candidate. §110.1(h)(2). In addition to accounting for statutory and regulatory changes in the campaign finance arena, appellants’ chal- lenge raises distinct legal arguments that Buckley did not consider. For example, presumably because of its cursory treatment of the $25,000 aggregate limit, Buckley did not separately address an overbreadth challenge with respect to that provision. The Court rejected such a challenge to the base limits because of the difficulty of isolating suspect contributions. The propriety of large contributions to in- dividual candidates turned on the subjective intent of donors, and the Court concluded that there was no way to tell which donors sought improper influence over legisla- tors’ actions. See
424 U. S., at 30. The aggregate limit, on the other hand, was upheld as an anticircumvention measure, without considering whether it was possible to discern which donations might be used to circumvent the base limits. See
id., at 38. The Court never addressed overbreadth in the specific context of aggregate limits, where such an argument has far more force. Given the foregoing, this case cannot be resolved merely by pointing to three sentences in Buckley that were writ- ten without the benefit of full briefing or argument on the issue. See Toucey v. New York Life Ins. Co.,
314 U. S. 118, 139–140 (1941) (departing from “[l]oose language and a sporadic, ill-considered decision” when asked to resolve a question “with our eyes wide open and in the light of full consideration”); Hohn v. United States,
524 U. S. 236, 251 (1998) (departing from a prior decision where it 14 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. “was rendered without full briefing or argument”). We are confronted with a different statute and different legal arguments, at a different point in the development of campaign finance regulation. Appellants’ sub- stantial First Amendment challenge to the system of aggregate limits currently in place thus merits our plenary consideration.4 III The First Amendment “is designed and intended to remove governmental restraints from the arena of public discussion, putting the decision as to what views shall be voiced largely into the hands of each of us, . . . in the belief that no other approach would comport with the premise of individual dignity and choice upon which our political system rests.” Cohen v. California,
403 U. S. 15, 24 (1971). As relevant here, the First Amendment safe- guards an individual’s right to participate in the public debate through political expression and political associa- tion. See Buckley,
424 U. S., at 15. When an individual contributes money to a candidate, he exercises both of those rights: The contribution “serves as a general expres- sion of support for the candidate and his views” and “serves to affiliate a person with a candidate.”
Id.,at 21–22. Those First Amendment rights are important regardless whether the individual is, on the one hand, a “lone pam- phleteer[ ] or street corner orator[ ] in the Tom Paine mold,” or is, on the other, someone who spends “substan- —————— 4 The dissent contends that we should remand for development of an evidentiary record before answering the question with which we were presented. See post, at 28–30 (opinion of BREYER, J). But the parties have treated the question as a purely legal one, and the Government has insisted that the aggregate limits can be upheld under the existing record alone. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 43, 55–56. We take the case as it comes to us. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 15 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. tial amounts of money in order to communicate [his] polit- ical ideas through sophisticated” means. National Con- servative Political Action Comm.,
470 U. S., at 493. Either way, he is participating in an electoral debate that we have recognized is “integral to the operation of the system of government established by our Constitution.” Buckley,
supra, at 14. Buckley acknowledged that aggregate limits at least diminish an individual’s right of political association. As the Court explained, the “overall $25,000 ceiling does impose an ultimate restriction upon the number of candi- dates and committees with which an individual may asso- ciate himself by means of financial support.”
424 U. S., at 38. But the Court characterized that restriction as a “quite modest restraint upon protected political activity.”
Ibid.We cannot agree with that characterization. An aggregate limit on how many candidates and committees an individual may support through contributions is not a “modest restraint” at all. The Government may no more restrict how many candidates or causes a donor may support than it may tell a newspaper how many candi- dates it may endorse. To put it in the simplest terms, the aggregate limits prohibit an individual from fully contributing to the pri- mary and general election campaigns of ten or more can- didates, even if all contributions fall within the base limits Congress views as adequate to protect against corruption. The individual may give up to $5,200 each to nine candi- dates, but the aggregate limits constitute an outright ban on further contributions to any other candidate (beyond the additional $1,800 that may be spent before reaching the $48,600 aggregate limit). At that point, the limits deny the individual all ability to exercise his expressive and associational rights by contributing to someone who will advocate for his policy preferences. A donor must limit the number of candidates he supports, and may have 16 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. to choose which of several policy concerns he will ad- vance—clear First Amendment harms that the dissent never acknowledges. It is no answer to say that the individual can simply contribute less money to more people. To require one person to contribute at lower levels than others because he wants to support more candidates or causes is to impose a special burden on broader participation in the democratic process. And as we have recently admonished, the Gov- ernment may not penalize an individual for “robustly exercis[ing]” his First Amendment rights. Davis v. Federal Election Comm’n,
554 U. S. 724, 739 (2008). The First Amendment burden is especially great for individuals who do not have ready access to alternative avenues for supporting their preferred politicians and policies. In the context of base contribution limits, Buck- ley observed that a supporter could vindicate his associa- tional interests by personally volunteering his time and energy on behalf of a candidate. See
424 U. S., at 22, 28. Such personal volunteering is not a realistic alternative for those who wish to support a wide variety of candidates or causes. Other effective methods of supporting preferred candidates or causes without contributing money are reserved for a select few, such as entertainers capable of raising hundreds of thousands of dollars in a single even- ing. Cf. Davis,
supra, at 742.5 The dissent faults this focus on “the individual’s right to engage in political speech,” saying that it fails to take into account “the public’s interest” in “collective speech.” Post, at 6 (opinion of BREYER, J). This “collective” interest is —————— 5 See, e.g., Felsenthal, Obama Attends Fundraiser Hosted by Jay-Z, Beyonce, Reuters, Sept. 18, 2012; Coleman, Kid Rock Supports Paul Ryan at Campaign Fundraiser, Rolling Stone, Aug. 25, 2012; Mason, Robert Duvall to Host Romney Fundraiser, L. A. Times, July 25, 2012; Piazza, Hillary Lands 2.5M with Rocket Man, N. Y. Daily News, Apr. 10, 2008, p. 2. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 17 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. said to promote “a government where laws reflect the very thoughts, views, ideas, and sentiments, the expression of which the First Amendment protects.” Post, at 7. But there are compelling reasons not to define the boundaries of the First Amendment by reference to such a generalized conception of the public good. First, the dis- sent’s “collective speech” reflected in laws is of course the will of the majority, and plainly can include laws that restrict free speech. The whole point of the First Amend- ment is to afford individuals protection against such in- fringements. The First Amendment does not protect the government, even when the government purports to act through legislation reflecting “collective speech.” Cf. United States v. Alvarez, 567 U. S. ___ (2012); Wooley v. Maynard,
430 U. S. 705(1977); West Virginia Bd. of Ed. v. Barnette,
319 U. S. 624(1943). Second, the degree to which speech is protected cannot turn on a legislative or judicial determination that partic- ular speech is useful to the democratic process. The First Amendment does not contemplate such “ad hoc balancing of relative social costs and benefits.” United States v. Stevens,
559 U. S. 460, 470 (2010); see also United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc.,
529 U. S. 803, 818 (2000) (“What the Constitution says is that” value judg- ments “are for the individual to make, not for the Gov- ernment to decree, even with the mandate or approval of a majority”). Third, our established First Amendment analysis al- ready takes account of any “collective” interest that may justify restrictions on individual speech. Under that accepted analysis, such restrictions are measured against the asserted public interest (usually framed as an im- portant or compelling governmental interest). As ex- plained below, we do not doubt the compelling nature of the “collective” interest in preventing corruption in the electoral process. But we permit Congress to pursue that 18 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. interest only so long as it does not unnecessarily infringe an individual’s right to freedom of speech; we do not trun- cate this tailoring test at the outset. IV A With the significant First Amendment costs for individ- ual citizens in mind, we turn to the governmental inter- ests asserted in this case. This Court has identified only one legitimate governmental interest for restricting cam- paign finances: preventing corruption or the appearance of corruption. See Davis,
supra, at 741; National Conserva- tive Political Action Comm.,
470 U. S., at496–497. We have consistently rejected attempts to suppress campaign speech based on other legislative objectives. No matter how desirable it may seem, it is not an acceptable govern- mental objective to “level the playing field,” or to “level electoral opportunities,” or to “equaliz[e] the financial resources of candidates.” Bennett, 564 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 22–23); Davis,
supra,at 741–742; Buckley,
supra, at 56. The First Amendment prohibits such legislative at- tempts to “fine-tun[e]” the electoral process, no matter how well intentioned. Bennett, supra, at ___ (slip op., at 21). As we framed the relevant principle in Buckley, “the concept that government may restrict the speech of some elements of our society in order to enhance the relative voice of others is wholly foreign to the First Amendment.”
424 U. S., at48–49. The dissent’s suggestion that Buckley supports the opposite proposition, see post, at 6, simply ignores what Buckley actually said on the matter. See also Citizens Against Rent Control/Coalition for Fair Housing v. Berkeley,
454 U. S. 290, 295 (1981) (“Buckley . . . made clear that contributors cannot be protected from the possibility that others will make larger contributions”). Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 19 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. Moreover, while preventing corruption or its appearance is a legitimate objective, Congress may target only a specific type of corruption—“quid pro quo” corruption. As Buckley explained, Congress may permissibly seek to rein in “large contributions [that] are given to secure a political quid pro quo from current and potential office holders.”
424 U. S., at 26. In addition to “actual quid pro quo arrangements,” Congress may permissibly limit “the ap- pearance of corruption stemming from public awareness of the opportunities for abuse inherent in a regime of large individual financial contributions” to particular candi- dates.
Id., at 27; see also Citizens United,
558 U. S., at 359(“When Buckley identified a sufficiently important governmental interest in preventing corruption or the appearance of corruption, that interest was limited to quid pro quo corruption”). Spending large sums of money in connection with elec- tions, but not in connection with an effort to control the exercise of an officeholder’s official duties, does not give rise to such quid pro quo corruption. Nor does the possi- bility that an individual who spends large sums may garner “influence over or access to” elected officials or political parties.
Id., at 359; see McConnell v. Federal Election Comm’n,
540 U. S. 93, 297 (2003) (KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part). And because the Government’s interest in preventing the appearance of corruption is equally confined to the ap- pearance of quid pro quo corruption, the Government may not seek to limit the appearance of mere influence or access. See Citizens United,
558 U. S., at 360. The dissent advocates a broader conception of corrup- tion, and would apply the label to any individual contribu- tions above limits deemed necessary to protect “collective speech.” Thus, under the dissent’s view, it is perfectly fine to contribute $5,200 to nine candidates but somehow corrupt to give the same amount to a tenth. 20 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. It is fair to say, as Justice Stevens has, “that we have not always spoken about corruption in a clear or con- sistent voice.”
Id., at 447(opinion concurring in part and dissenting in part). The definition of corruption that we apply today, however, has firm roots in Buckley itself. The Court in that case upheld base contribution limits because they targeted “the danger of actual quid pro quo arrange- ments” and “the impact of the appearance of corruption stemming from public awareness” of such a system of unchecked direct contributions.
424 U. S., at 27. Buckley simultaneously rejected limits on spending that was less likely to “be given as a quid pro quo for improper commit- ments from the candidate.”
Id., at 47. In any event, this case is not the first in which the debate over the proper breadth of the Government’s anticorruption interest has been engaged. Compare Citizens United,
558 U. S., at356–361 (majority opinion), with
id.,at 447–460 (opinion of Stevens, J.). The line between quid pro quo corruption and general influence may seem vague at times, but the distinction must be respected in order to safeguard basic First Amendment rights. In addition, “[i]n drawing that line, the First Amendment requires us to err on the side of protecting political speech rather than suppressing it.” Federal Election Comm’n v. Wisconsin Right to Life,
551 U. S. 449, 457 (2007) (opinion of ROBERTS, C. J.). The dissent laments that our opinion leaves only rem- nants of FECA and BCRA that are inadequate to combat corruption. See post, at 2. Such rhetoric ignores the fact that we leave the base limits undisturbed.6 Those base —————— 6 The fact that this opinion does not address the base limits also be- lies the dissent’s concern that we have silently overruled the Court’s holding in McConnell v. Federal Election Comm’n,
540 U. S. 93(2003). See post, at 12–13. At issue in McConnell was BCRA’s extension of the base limits to so-called “soft money”—previously unregulated contribu- tions to national party committees. See
540 U. S., at 142; see also post, Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 21 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. limits remain the primary means of regulating campaign contributions—the obvious explanation for why the aggre- gate limits received a scant few sentences of attention in Buckley.7 B “When the Government restricts speech, the Govern- ment bears the burden of proving the constitutionality of its actions.” United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc.,
529 U. S., at 816. Here, the Government seeks to carry that burden by arguing that the aggregate limits further the permissible objective of preventing quid pro quo corruption. The difficulty is that once the aggregate limits kick in, they ban all contributions of any amount. But Congress’s selection of a $5,200 base limit indicates its belief that contributions of that amount or less do not create a cog- nizable risk of corruption. If there is no corruption con- cern in giving nine candidates up to $5,200 each, it is difficult to understand how a tenth candidate can be re- garded as corruptible if given $1,801, and all others cor- —————— at 31–38 (appendix A to opinion of BREYER, J.) (excerpts from McConnell record discussing unregulated “soft money”). Our holding about the constitutionality of the aggregate limits clearly does not overrule McConnell’s holding about “soft money.” 7 It would be especially odd to regard aggregate limits as essential to enforce base limits when state campaign finance schemes typically include base limits but not aggregate limits. Just eight of the 38 States that have imposed base limits on contributions from individuals to candidates have also imposed aggregate limits (excluding restrictions on a specific subset of donors). See
Conn. Gen. Stat. §9–611(c) (2013); Me. Rev. Stat. Ann., Tit. 21–A, §1015(3) (Supp. 2013); Md. Elec. Law Code Ann. §13–226(b) (Lexis Supp. 2013); Mass. Gen. Laws, ch. 55, §7A(a)(5) (West 2012); N. Y. Elec. Law Ann. §14–114(8) (West Supp. 2013); R. I. Gen. Laws §17–25–10.1(a)(1) (Lexis 2013);
Wis. Stat. §11.26(4) (2007–2008);
Wyo. Stat. Ann. §22–25–102(c)(ii) (2013). The Government presents no evidence concerning the circumvention of base limits from the 30 States with base limits but no aggregate limits. 22 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. ruptible if given a dime. And if there is no risk that addi- tional candidates will be corrupted by donations of up to $5,200, then the Government must defend the aggregate limits by demonstrating that they prevent circumvention of the base limits. The problem is that they do not serve that function in any meaningful way. In light of the various statutes and regulations currently in effect, Buckley’s fear that an individual might “contribute massive amounts of money to a particular candidate through the use of unearmarked contributions” to entities likely to support the candi- date,
424 U. S., at 38, is far too speculative. And— importantly—we “have never accepted mere conjecture as adequate to carry a First Amendment burden.” Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC,
528 U. S. 377, 392 (2000). As an initial matter, there is not the same risk of quid pro quo corruption or its appearance when money flows through independent actors to a candidate, as when a donor contributes to a candidate directly. When an indi- vidual contributes to a candidate, a party committee, or a PAC, the individual must by law cede control over the funds. See 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(8);
11 CFR §110.6. The Government admits that if the funds are subsequently re- routed to a particular candidate, such action occurs at the initial recipient’s discretion—not the donor’s. See Brief for Appellee 37. As a consequence, the chain of attribution grows longer, and any credit must be shared among the various actors along the way. For those reasons, the risk of quid pro quo corruption is generally applicable only to “the narrow category of money gifts that are directed, in some manner, to a candidate or officeholder.” McConnell,
540 U. S., at 310(opinion of KENNEDY, J.). Buckley nonetheless focused on the possibility that “unearmarked contributions” could eventually find their way to a candidate’s coffers.
424 U. S., at 38. Even ac- Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 23 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. cepting the validity of Buckley’s circumvention theory, it is hard to see how a candidate today could receive a “massive amount[ ] of money” that could be traced back to a particu- lar contributor uninhibited by the aggregate limits.
Ibid.The Government offers a series of scenarios in support of that possibility. But each is sufficiently implausible that the Government has not carried its burden of demonstrat- ing that the aggregate limits further its anticircumvention interest. The primary example of circumvention, in one form or another, envisions an individual donor who contributes the maximum amount under the base limits to a particu- lar candidate, say, Representative Smith. Then the donor also channels “massive amounts of money” to Smith through a series of contributions to PACs that have stated their intention to support Smith. See, e.g., Brief for Appel- lee 35–37; Tr. of Oral Arg. 4, 6. Various earmarking and antiproliferation rules disarm this example. Importantly, the donor may not contribute to the most obvious PACs: those that support only Smith. See
11 CFR §110.1(h)(1); see also §102.14(a). Nor may the donor contribute to the slightly less obvious PACs that he knows will route “a substantial portion” of his contribution to Smith. §110.1(h)(2). The donor must instead turn to other PACs that are likely to give to Smith. When he does so, however, he discovers that his contribution will be significantly diluted by all the contributions from others to the same PACs. After all, the donor cannot give more than $5,000 to a PAC and so cannot dominate the PAC’s total receipts, as he could when Buckley was decided. 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(1)(C). He cannot retain control over his contribution,
11 CFR §110.1(h)(3), direct his money “in any way” to Smith, 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(8), or even imply that he would like his money to be recontributed to Smith,
11 CFR §110.6(b)(1). His salience as a Smith supporter has been 24 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. diminished, and with it the potential for corruption. It is not clear how many candidates a PAC must support before our dedicated donor can avoid being tagged with the impermissible knowledge that “a substantial portion” of his contribution will go to Smith. But imagine that the donor is one of ten equal donors to a PAC that gives the highest possible contribution to Smith.8 The PAC may give no more than $2,600 per election to Smith. Of that sum, just $260 will be attributable to the donor intent on circumventing the base limits. Thus far he has hardly succeeded in funneling “massive amounts of money” to Smith. Buckley, supra, at 38. But what if this donor does the same thing via, say, 100 different PACs? His $260 contribution will balloon to $26,000, ten times what he may contribute directly to Smith in any given election. This 100-PAC scenario is highly implausible. In the first instance, it is not true that the individual donor will necessarily have access to a sufficient number of PACs to effectuate such a scheme. There are many PACs, but they are not limitless. For the 2012 election cycle, the FEC reported about 2,700 nonconnected PACs (excluding PACs that finance independent expenditures only). And not every PAC that supports Smith will work in this scheme: For our donor’s pro rata share of a PAC’s contribution to Smith to remain meaningful, the PAC must be funded by only a small handful of donors. The antiproliferation rules, which were not in effect when Buckley was decided, prohibit our donor from creating 100 pro-Smith PACs of his own, or collaborating with the nine other donors to do —————— 8 Even those premises are generous because they assume that the donor contributes to non-multicandidate PACs, which are relatively rare. Multicandidate PACs, by contrast, must have more than 50 contributors.
11 CFR §100.5(e)(3). The more contributors, of course, the more the donor’s share in any eventual contribution to Smith is diluted. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 25 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. so. See 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(5) (“all contributions made by political committees established or financed or maintained or controlled by . . . any other person, or by any group of such persons, shall be considered to have been made by a single political committee”). Moreover, if 100 PACs were to contribute to Smith and few other candidates, and if specific individuals like our ardent Smith supporter were to contribute to each, the FEC could weigh those “circumstantial factors” to deter- mine whether to deem the PACs affiliated.
11 CFR §100.5(g)(4)(ii). The FEC’s analysis could take account of a “common or overlapping membership” and “similar patterns of contributions or contributors,” among other considerations. §§100.5(g)(4)(ii)(D), (J). The FEC has in the past initiated enforcement proceedings against con- tributors with such suspicious patterns of PAC donations. See, e.g., Conciliation Agreement, In re Riley, Matters Under Review 4568, 4633, 4634, 4736 (FEC, Dec. 19, 2001). On a more basic level, it is hard to believe that a rational actor would engage in such machinations. In the example described, a dedicated donor spent $500,000—donating the full $5,000 to 100 different PACs—to add just $26,000 to Smith’s campaign coffers. That same donor, mean- while, could have spent unlimited funds on independent expenditures on behalf of Smith. See Buckley,
424 U. S., at44–51. Indeed, he could have spent his entire $500,000 advocating for Smith, without the risk that his selected PACs would choose not to give to Smith, or that he would have to share credit with other contributors to the PACs. We have said in the context of independent expenditures that “ ‘[t]he absence of prearrangement and coordination of an expenditure with the candidate or his agent . . . un- dermines the value of the expenditure to the candidate.’ ” Citizens United,
558 U. S., at 357(quoting Buckley,
supra, at 47). But probably not by 95 percent. And at least from 26 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. the donor’s point of view, it strikes us as far more likely that he will want to see his full $500,000 spent on behalf of his favored candidate—even if it must be spent inde- pendently—rather than see it diluted to a small fraction so that it can be contributed directly by someone else.9 Another circumvention example is the one that appar- ently motivated the District Court. As the District Court crafted the example, a donor gives a $500,000 check to a joint fundraising committee composed of a candidate, a national party committee, and “most of the party’s state party committees” (actually, 47 of the 50). 893 F. Supp. 2d, at 140. The committees divide up the money so that each one receives the maximum contribution permissible under the base limits, but then each transfers its allocated portion to the same single committee. That committee uses the money for coordinated expenditures on behalf of a particular candidate. If that scenario “seem[s] unlikely,” the District Court thought so, too. Ibid. But because the District Court could “imagine” that chain of events, it held that the example substantiated the Government’s circum- vention concerns. Ibid. One problem, however, is that the District Court’s spec- ulation relies on illegal earmarking. Lest there be any confusion, a joint fundraising committee is simply a mech- anism for individual committees to raise funds collectively, not to circumvent base limits or earmarking rules. See 11 —————— 9 The Justice Department agrees. As Acting Assistant Attorney Gen- eral Mythili Raman recently testified before Congress: “We anticipate seeing fewer cases of conduit contributions directly to campaign com- mittees or parties, because individuals or corporations who wish to influence elections or officials will no longer need to attempt to do so through conduit contribution schemes that can be criminally prosecut- ed. Instead, they are likely to simply make unlimited contributions to Super PACs or 501(c)s.” Hearing on Current Issues in Campaign Finance Law Enforcement before the Subcommittee on Crime and Terrorism of the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 113th Cong., 1st Sess., 3 (2013). Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 27 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. CFR §102.17(c)(5). Under no circumstances may a contri- bution to a joint fundraising committee result in an alloca- tion that exceeds the contribution limits applicable to its constituent parts; the committee is in fact required to return any excess funds to the contributor. See §102.17(c)(6)(i). The District Court assumed compliance with the specific allocation rules governing joint fundraising committees, but it expressly based its example on the premise that the donor would telegraph his desire to support one candidate and that “many separate entities would willingly serve as conduits for a single contributor’s interests.” 893 F. Supp. 2d, at 140. Regardless whether so many distinct entities would cooperate as a practical matter, the earmarking provision prohibits an individual from directing funds “through an intermediary or conduit” to a particular can- didate. 2 U. S. C. §441a(8). Even the “implicit[ ]” agree- ment imagined by the District Court, 893 F. Supp. 2d, at 140, would trigger the earmarking provision. See
11 CFR §110.6(b)(1). So this circumvention scenario could not succeed without assuming that nearly 50 separate party committees would engage in a transparent violation of the earmarking rules (and that they would not be caught if they did). Moreover, the District Court failed to acknowledge that its $500,000 example cannot apply to most candidates. It crafted the example around a presidential candidate, for whom donations in the thousands of dollars may not seem remarkable—especially in comparison to the nearly $1.4 billion spent by the 2012 presidential candidates. The same example cannot, however, be extrapolated to most House and Senate candidates. Like contributions, coordi- nated expenditures are limited by statute, with different limits based on the State and the office. See 2 U. S. C. §441a(d)(3). The 2013 coordinated expenditure limit for most House races is $46,600, well below the $500,000 in 28 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. coordinated expenditures envisioned by the District Court. The limit for Senate races varies significantly based on state population. See
78 Fed. Reg. 8531(2013). A scheme of the magnitude imagined by the District Court would be possible even in theory for no House candidates and the Senate candidates from just the 12 most populous States.
Ibid.Further, to the extent that the law does not foreclose the scenario described by the District Court, experience and common sense do. The Government provides no reason to believe that many state parties would willingly participate in a scheme to funnel money to another State’s candidates. A review of FEC data of Republican and Democratic state party committees for the 2012 election cycle reveals just 12 total instances in which a state party committee con- tributed to a House or Senate candidate in another State. No surprise there. The Iowa Democratic Party, for exam- ple, has little reason to transfer money to the California Democratic Party, especially when the Iowa Democratic Party would be barred for the remainder of the election cycle from receiving another contribution for its own activ- ities from the particular donor. These scenarios, along with others that have been sug- gested, are either illegal under current campaign finance laws or divorced from reality. The three examples posed by the dissent are no exception. The dissent does not explain how the large sums it postulates can be legally rerouted to a particular candidate, why most state com- mittees would participate in a plan to redirect their dona- tions to a candidate in another State, or how a donor or group of donors can avoid regulations prohibiting con- tributions to a committee “with the knowledge that a substantial portion” of the contribution will support a candidate to whom the donor has already contributed,
11 CFR §110.1(h)(2). The dissent argues that such knowledge may be difficult Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 29 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. to prove, pointing to eight FEC cases that did not proceed because of insufficient evidence of a donor’s incriminating knowledge. See post, at 24–25. It might be that such guilty knowledge could not be shown because the donors were not guilty—a possibility that the dissent does not entertain. In any event, the donors described in those eight cases were typically alleged to have exceeded the base limits by $5,000 or less. The FEC’s failure to find the requisite knowledge in those cases hardly means that the agency will be equally powerless to prevent a scheme in which a donor routes millions of dollars in excess of the base limits to a particular candidate, as in the dissent’s “Example Two.” And if an FEC official cannot establish knowledge of circumvention (or establish affiliation) when the same ten donors contribute $10,000 each to 200 newly created PACs, and each PAC writes a $10,000 check to the same ten candidates—the dissent’s “Example Three”— then that official has not a heart but a head of stone. See post, at 19–20, 25. The dissent concludes by citing three briefs for the proposition that, even with the aggregate limits in place, individuals “have transferred large sums of money to specific candidates” in excess of the base limits. Post, at 26. But the cited sources do not provide any real-world examples of circumvention of the base limits along the lines of the various hypotheticals. The dearth of FEC prosecutions, according to the dissent, proves only that people are getting away with it. And the violations that surely must be out there elude detection “because in the real world, the methods of achieving circumvention are more subtle and more complex” than the hypothetical examples.
Ibid.This sort of speculation, however, cannot justify the substantial intrusion on First Amendment rights at issue in this case. Buckley upheld aggregate limits only on the ground that they prevented channeling money to candidates beyond 30 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. the base limits. The absence of such a prospect today belies the Government’s asserted objective of preventing corruption or its appearance. The improbability of cir- cumvention indicates that the aggregate limits instead further the impermissible objective of simply limiting the amount of money in political campaigns. C Quite apart from the foregoing, the aggregate limits violate the First Amendment because they are not “closely drawn to avoid unnecessary abridgment of associational freedoms.” Buckley,
424 U. S., at 25. In the First Amendment context, fit matters. Even when the Court is not applying strict scrutiny, we still require “a fit that is not necessarily perfect, but reasonable; that represents not necessarily the single best disposition but one whose scope is ‘in proportion to the interest served,’ . . . that employs not necessarily the least restrictive means but . . . a means narrowly tailored to achieve the desired objective.” Board of Trustees of State Univ. of N. Y. v. Fox,
492 U. S. 469, 480 (1989) (quoting In re R. M. J.,
455 U. S. 191, 203 (1982)). Here, because the statute is poorly tailored to the Government’s interest in preventing circumvention of the base limits, it impermissibly restricts participation in the political process. 1 The Government argues that the aggregate limits are justified because they prevent an individual from giving to too many initial recipients who might subsequently recon- tribute a donation. After all, only recontributed funds can conceivably give rise to circumvention of the base limits. Yet all indications are that many types of recipients have scant interest in regifting donations they receive. Some figures might be useful to put the risk of circum- vention in perspective. We recognize that no data can be Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 31 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. marshaled to capture perfectly the counterfactual world in which aggregate limits do not exist. But, as we have noted elsewhere, we can nonetheless ask “whether experience under the present law confirms a serious threat of abuse.” Federal Election Comm’n v. Colorado Republican Federal Campaign Comm.,
533 U. S. 431, 457 (2001). It does not. Experience suggests that the vast majority of contri- butions made in excess of the aggregate limits are likely to be retained and spent by their recipients rather than rerouted to candidates. In the 2012 election cycle, federal candidates, political parties, and PACs spent a total of $7 billion, according to the FEC. In particular, each national political party’s spending ran in the hundreds of millions of dollars. The National Republican Senatorial Committee (NRSC), Na- tional Republican Congressional Committee (NRCC), Democratic Senatorial Campaign Committee (DSCC), and Democratic Congressional Campaign Committee (DCCC), however, spent less than $1 million each on direct candi- date contributions and less than $10 million each on coor- dinated expenditures. Brief for NRSC et al. as Amici Curiae 23, 25 (NRSC Brief). Including both coordinated expenditures and direct candidate contributions, the NRSC and DSCC spent just 7% of their total funds on contributions to candidates and the NRCC and DCCC spent just 3%. Likewise, as explained previously, state parties rarely contribute to candidates in other States. In the 2012 election cycle, the Republican and Democratic state party committees in all 50 States (and the District of Columbia) contributed a paltry $17,750 to House and Senate candi- dates in other States. The state party committees spent over half a billion dollars over the same time period, of which the $17,750 in contributions to other States’ candi- dates constituted just 0.003%. As with national and state party committees, candidates 32 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. contribute only a small fraction of their campaign funds to other candidates. Authorized candidate committees may support other candidates up to a $2,000 base limit.
2 U. S. C. §432(e)(3)(B). In the 2012 election, House candi- dates spent a total of $1.1 billion. Candidate-to-candidate contributions among House candidates totaled $3.65 million, making up just 0.3% of candidates’ overall spend- ing. NRSC Brief 29. The most that any one individual candidate received from all other candidates was around $100,000. Brief for Appellee 39. The fact is that candi- dates who receive campaign contributions spend most of the money on themselves, rather than passing along dona- tions to other candidates. In this arena at least, charity begins at home.10 Based on what we can discern from experience, the indiscriminate ban on all contributions above the aggre- gate limits is disproportionate to the Government’s inter- est in preventing circumvention. The Government has not given us any reason to believe that parties or candidates would dramatically shift their priorities if the aggregate limits were lifted. Absent such a showing, we cannot conclude that the sweeping aggregate limits are appropri- ately tailored to guard against any contributions that might implicate the Government’s anticircumvention interest. A final point: It is worth keeping in mind that the base limits themselves are a prophylactic measure. As we have —————— 10 In addition, the percentage of contributions above the aggregate limits that even could be used for circumvention is limited by the fact that many of the modes of potential circumvention can be used only once each election. For example, if one donor gives $2,600 to 100 candidates with safe House seats in the hopes that each candidate will reroute $2,000 to Representative Smith, a candidate in a contested district, no other donor can do the same, because the candidates in the safe seats will have exhausted their permissible contributions to Smith. So there is no risk that the circumvention scheme will repeat itself with multiple other would-be donors to Smith. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 33 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. explained, “restrictions on direct contributions are preven- tative, because few if any contributions to candidates will involve quid pro quo arrangements.” Citizens United,
558 U. S., at 357. The aggregate limits are then layered on top, ostensibly to prevent circumvention of the base limits. This “prophylaxis-upon-prophylaxis approach” requires that we be particularly diligent in scrutinizing the law’s fit. Wisconsin Right to Life,
551 U. S., at 479(opinion of ROBERTS, C. J.); see McConnell,
540 U. S., at268–269 (opinion of THOMAS, J.). 2 Importantly, there are multiple alternatives available to Congress that would serve the Government’s anticircum- vention interest, while avoiding “unnecessary abridgment” of First Amendment rights. Buckley,
424 U. S., at 25. The most obvious might involve targeted restrictions on transfers among candidates and political committees. There are currently no such limits on transfers among party committees and from candidates to party commit- tees. See 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(4);
11 CFR §113.2(c). Per- haps for that reason, a central concern of the District Court, the Government, multiple amici curiae, and the dissent has been the ability of party committees to trans- fer money freely. If Congress agrees that this is problem- atic, it might tighten its permissive transfer rules. Doing so would impose a lesser burden on First Amendment rights, as compared to aggregate limits that flatly ban contributions beyond certain levels. And while the Gov- ernment has not conceded that transfer restrictions would be a perfect substitute for the aggregate limits, it has recognized that they would mitigate the risk of circumven- tion. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 29. One possible option for restricting transfers would be to require contributions above the current aggregate limits to be deposited into segregated, nontransferable accounts 34 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. and spent only by their recipients. Such a solution would address the same circumvention possibilities as the cur- rent aggregate limits, while not completely barring contri- butions beyond the aggregate levels. In addition (or as an alternative), if Congress believes that circumvention is especially likely to occur through creation of a joint fund- raising committee, it could require that funds received through those committees be spent by their recipients (or perhaps it could simply limit the size of joint fundraising committees). Such alternatives to the aggregate limits properly refocus the inquiry on the delinquent actor: the recipient of a contribution within the base limits, who then routes the money in a manner that undermines those limits. See Citizens United, supra, at 360–361; cf. Bart- nicki v. Vopper,
532 U. S. 514, 529–530 (2001). Indeed, Congress has adopted transfer restrictions, and the Court has upheld them, in the context of state party spending. See 2 U. S. C. §441i(b). So-called “Levin funds” are donations permissible under state law that may be spent on certain federal election activity—namely, voter registration and identification, get-out-the-vote efforts, or generic campaign activities. Levin funds are raised directly by the state or local party committee that ultimately spends them. §441i(b)(2)(B)(iv). That means that other party committees may not transfer Levin funds, solicit Levin funds on behalf of the particular state or local com- mittee, or engage in joint fundraising of Levin funds. See McConnell,
540 U. S., at171–173. McConnell upheld those transfer restrictions as “justifiable anticircumven- tion measures,” though it acknowledged that they posed some associational burdens.
Id., at 171. Here, a narrow transfer restriction on contributions that could otherwise be recontributed in excess of the base limits could rely on a similar justification. Other alternatives might focus on earmarking. Many of the scenarios that the Government and the dissent hy- Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 35 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. pothesize involve at least implicit agreements to circum- vent the base limits—agreements that are already prohib- ited by the earmarking rules. See
11 CFR §110.6. The FEC might strengthen those rules further by, for exam- ple, defining how many candidates a PAC must support in order to ensure that “a substantial portion” of a do- nor’s contribution is not rerouted to a certain candidate. §110.1(h)(2). Congress might also consider a modified version of the aggregate limits, such as one that prohibits donors who have contributed the current maximum sums from further contributing to political committees that have indicated they will support candidates to whom the donor has already contributed. To be sure, the existing earmark- ing provision does not define “the outer limit of accept- able tailoring.” Colorado Republican Federal Campaign Comm.,
533 U. S., at 462. But tighter rules could have a significant effect, especially when adopted in concert with other measures. We do not mean to opine on the validity of any particu- lar proposal. The point is that there are numerous al- ternative approaches available to Congress to prevent circumvention of the base limits. D Finally, disclosure of contributions minimizes the poten- tial for abuse of the campaign finance system. Disclosure requirements are in part “justified based on a governmen- tal interest in ‘provid[ing] the electorate with information’ about the sources of election-related spending.” Citizens United,
558 U. S., at 367(quoting Buckley,
supra, at 66). They may also “deter actual corruption and avoid the appearance of corruption by exposing large contributions and expenditures to the light of publicity.”
Id., at 67. Disclosure requirements burden speech, but—unlike the aggregate limits—they do not impose a ceiling on speech. Citizens United, supra, at 366; but see McConnell,
supra,36 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. at 275–277 (opinion of THOMAS, J.). For that reason, disclosure often represents a less restrictive alternative to flat bans on certain types or quantities of speech. See, e.g., Federal Election Comm’n v. Massachusetts Citizens for Life, Inc.,
479 U. S. 238, 262 (1986). With modern technology, disclosure now offers a partic- ularly effective means of arming the voting public with information. In 1976, the Court observed that Congress could regard disclosure as “only a partial measure.” Buck- ley,
424 U. S., at 28. That perception was understandable in a world in which information about campaign contribu- tions was filed at FEC offices and was therefore virtually inaccessible to the average member of the public. See Brief for Cause of Action Institute as Amicus Curiae 15– 16. Today, given the Internet, disclosure offers much more robust protections against corruption. See Citizens United, supra, at 370–371. Reports and databases are availa- ble on the FEC’s Web site almost immediately after they are filed, supplemented by private entities such as Open- Secrets.org and FollowTheMoney.org. Because massive quantities of information can be accessed at the click of a mouse, disclosure is effective to a degree not possible at the time Buckley, or even McConnell, was decided. The existing aggregate limits may in fact encourage the movement of money away from entities subject to dis- closure. Because individuals’ direct contributions are limited, would-be donors may turn to other avenues for political speech. See Citizens United, supra, at 364. Indi- viduals can, for example, contribute unlimited amounts to 501(c) organizations, which are not required to publicly disclose their donors. See
26 U. S. C. §6104(d)(3). Such organizations spent some $300 million on independent expenditures in the 2012 election cycle. V At oral argument, the Government shifted its focus from Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 37 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. Buckley’s anticircumvention rationale to an argument that the aggregate limits deter corruption regardless of their ability to prevent circumvention of the base limits. See Tr. of Oral Arg. 29–30, 50–52. The Government argued that there is an opportunity for corruption whenever a large check is given to a legislator, even if the check consists of contributions within the base limits to be appropriately divided among numerous candidates and committees. The aggregate limits, the argument goes, ensure that the check amount does not become too large. That new rationale for the aggregate limits—embraced by the dissent, see post, at 15–17—does not wash. It dangerously broadens the cir- cumscribed definition of quid pro quo corruption articu- lated in our prior cases, and targets as corruption the general, broad-based support of a political party. In analyzing the base limits, Buckley made clear that the risk of corruption arises when an individual makes large contributions to the candidate or officeholder him- self. See
424 U. S., at26–27. Buckley’s analysis of the aggregate limit under FECA was similarly confined. The Court noted that the aggregate limit guarded against an individual’s funneling—through circumvention—“massive amounts of money to a particular candidate.”
Id., at 38(emphasis added). We have reiterated that understanding several times. See, e.g., National Conservative Political Action Comm.,
470 U. S., at 497(quid pro quo corruption occurs when “[e]lected officials are influenced to act con- trary to their obligations of office by the prospect of finan- cial gain to themselves or infusions of money into their campaigns” (emphasis added)); Citizens Against Rent Control/Coalition for Fair Housing v. Berkeley,
454 U. S. 290, 297 (1981) (Buckley’s holding that contribution limits are permissible “relates to the perception of undue influ- ence of large contributors to a candidate”); McConnell,
540 U. S., at 296(opinion of KENNEDY, J.) (quid pro quo cor- ruption in Buckley involved “contributions that flowed to a 38 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. particular candidate’s benefit” (emphasis added)). Of course a candidate would be pleased with a donor who contributed not only to the candidate himself, but also to other candidates from the same party, to party commit- tees, and to PACs supporting the party. But there is a clear, administrable line between money beyond the base limits funneled in an identifiable way to a candidate—for which the candidate feels obligated—and money within the base limits given widely to a candidate’s party—for which the candidate, like all other members of the party, feels grateful. When donors furnish widely distributed support within all applicable base limits, all members of the party or supporters of the cause may benefit, and the leaders of the party or cause may feel particular gratitude. That grati- tude stems from the basic nature of the party system, in which party members join together to further common political beliefs, and citizens can choose to support a party because they share some, most, or all of those beliefs. See Tashjian v. Republican Party of Conn.,
479 U. S. 208, 214– 216 (1986). To recast such shared interest, standing alone, as an opportunity for quid pro quo corruption would dramatically expand government regulation of the politi- cal process. Cf. California Democratic Party v. Jones,
530 U. S. 567, 572–573 (2000) (recognizing the Government’s “role to play in structuring and monitoring the election process,” but rejecting “the proposition that party affairs are public affairs, free of First Amendment protections”). The Government suggests that it is the solicitation of large contributions that poses the danger of corruption, see Tr. of Oral Arg. 29–30, 38–39, 50–51; see also post, at 15–16, 20, but the aggregate limits are not limited to any direct solicitation by an officeholder or candidate. Cf. McConnell,
supra,at 298–299, 308 (opinion of KENNEDY, J.) (rejecting a ban on “soft money” contributions to na- tional parties, but approving a ban on the solicitation of Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 39 Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. such contributions as “a direct and necessary regulation of federal candidates’ and officeholders’ receipt of quids”). We have no occasion to consider a law that would specifi- cally ban candidates from soliciting donations—within the base limits—that would go to many other candidates, and would add up to a large sum. For our purposes here, it is enough that the aggregate limits at issue are not directed specifically to candidate behavior. * * * For the past 40 years, our campaign finance jurispru- dence has focused on the need to preserve authority for the Government to combat corruption, without at the same time compromising the political responsiveness at the heart of the democratic process, or allowing the Gov- ernment to favor some participants in that process over others. As Edmund Burke explained in his famous speech to the electors of Bristol, a representative owes constitu- ents the exercise of his “mature judgment,” but judgment informed by “the strictest union, the closest correspond- ence, and the most unreserved communication with his constituents.” The Speeches of the Right Hon. Edmund Burke 129–130 (J. Burke ed. 1867). Constituents have the right to support candidates who share their views and concerns. Representatives are not to follow constituent orders, but can be expected to be cognizant of and respon- sive to those concerns. Such responsiveness is key to the very concept of self-governance through elected officials. The Government has a strong interest, no less critical to our democratic system, in combatting corruption and its appearance. We have, however, held that this interest must be limited to a specific kind of corruption—quid pro quo corruption—in order to ensure that the Government’s efforts do not have the effect of restricting the First Amendment right of citizens to choose who shall govern them. For the reasons set forth, we conclude that the 40 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Opinion of ROBERTS, C. J. aggregate limits on contributions do not further the only governmental interest this Court accepted as legitimate in Buckley. They instead intrude without justification on a citizen’s ability to exercise “the most fundamental First Amendment activities.” Buckley,
424 U. S., at 14. The judgment of the District Court is reversed, and the case is remanded for further proceedings. It is so ordered. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 1 THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 12–536 _________________ SHAUN MCCUTCHEON, ET AL., APPELLANTS v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION ON APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA [April 2, 2014] JUSTICE THOMAS, concurring in the judgment. I adhere to the view that this Court’s decision in Buckley v. Valeo,
424 U. S. 1(1976) (per curiam), denigrates core First Amendment speech and should be overruled. See Randall v. Sorrell,
548 U. S. 230, 265–267 (2006) (THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment); Federal Election Comm’n v. Beaumont,
539 U. S. 146, 164–165 (2003) (THOMAS, J., dissenting); Federal Election Comm’n v. Colorado Republican Federal Campaign Comm.,
533 U. S. 431, 465–466 (2001) (Colorado II) (THOMAS, J., dissent- ing); Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC,
528 U. S. 377, 412–420 (2000) (THOMAS, J., dissenting); Colorado Republican Federal Campaign Comm. v. Federal Election Comm’n,
518 U. S. 604, 635–640 (1996) (Colorado I ) (THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment and dissenting in part). Political speech is “ ‘the primary object of First Amend- ment protection’ ” and “the lifeblood of a self-governing people.” Colorado II, supra, at 465–466 (THOMAS, J., dissenting). Contributions to political campaigns, no less than direct expenditures, “generate essential political speech” by fostering discussion of public issues and can- didate qualifications. Shrink Missouri,
supra, at 412(THOMAS, J., dissenting); see also
id.,at 410–411. Buckley itself recognized that both contribution and expenditure 2 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment limits “operate in an area of the most fundamental First Amendment activities” and “implicate fundamental First Amendment interests.”
424 U. S., at 14, 23. But instead of treating political giving and political spending alike, Buckley distinguished the two, embracing a bifurcated standard of review under which contribution limits receive less rigorous scrutiny.
Id., at 25. As I have explained before, “[t]he analytic foundation of Buckley . . . was tenuous from the very beginning and has only continued to erode in the intervening years.” Shrink Missouri,
supra, at 412(THOMAS, J., dissenting). To justify a lesser standard of review for contribution limits, Buckley relied on the premise that contributions are dif- ferent in kind from direct expenditures. None of the Court’s bases for that premise withstands careful review. The linchpin of the Court’s analysis was its assertion that “[w]hile contributions may result in political expression if spent by a candidate or an association to present views to the voters, the transformation of contributions into politi- cal debate involves speech by someone other than the contributor.”
424 U. S., at 21. But that “ ‘speech by proxy’ ” rationale quickly breaks down, given that “[e]ven in the case of a direct expenditure, there is usually some go-between that facilitates the dissemination of the spender’s message—for instance, an advertising agency or a television station.” Colorado I, supra, at 638–639 (opin- ion of THOMAS, J.). Moreover, we have since rejected the “ ‘proxy speech’ ” approach as affording insufficient First Amendment protection to “the voices of those of modest means as opposed to those sufficiently wealthy to be able to buy expensive media ads with their own resources.” Federal Election Comm’n v. National Conservative Politi- cal Action Comm.,
470 U. S. 480, 495 (1985); see Shrink Missouri,
supra,at 413–414 (THOMAS, J., dissenting). The remaining justifications Buckley provided are also flawed. For example, Buckley claimed that contribution Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 3 THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment limits entail only a “marginal” speech restriction because “[a] contribution serves as a general expression of support for the candidate and his views, but does not communicate the underlying basis for the support.”
424 U. S., at 20, 21. But this Court has never required a speaker to explain the reasons for his position in order to obtain full First Amendment protection. Instead, we have consistently held that speech is protected even “when the underlying basis for a position is not given.” Shrink Missouri,
supra, at 415, n. 3(THOMAS, J., dissenting); see, e.g., City of Ladue v. Gilleo,
512 U. S. 43, 46 (1994) (sign reading “For Peace in the Gulf ”); Texas v. Johnson,
491 U. S. 397, 415– 416 (1989) (flag burning); Tinker v. Des Moines Independ- ent Community School Dist.,
393 U. S. 503, 510–511 (1969) (black armband signifying opposition to Vietnam War); see also Colorado I, supra, at 640 (opinion of THOMAS, J.) (“Even a pure message of support, unadorned with reasons, is valuable to the democratic process”) Equally unpersuasive is Buckley’s suggestion that con- tribution limits warrant less stringent review because “[t]he quantity of communication by the contributor does not increase perceptibly with the size of his contribution,” and “[a]t most, the size of the contribution provides a very rough index of the intensity of the contributor’s support for the candidate.”
424 U. S., at 21. Contributions do in- crease the quantity of communication by “amplifying the voice of the candidate” and “help[ing] to ensure the dis- semination of the messages that the contributor wishes to convey.” Shrink Missouri,
supra, at 415(THOMAS, J., dissenting). They also serve as a quantifiable metric of the intensity of a particular contributor’s support, as demonstrated by the frequent practice of giving different amounts to different candidates. Buckley simply failed to recognize that “we have accorded full First Amendment protection to expressions of intensity.”
Id., at 415, n. 3; see also Cohen v. California,
403 U. S. 15, 25–26 (1971) 4 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment (protecting the use of an obscenity for emphasis). Although today’s decision represents a faithful applica- tion of our precedents, the plurality’s discussion of Buckley omits any reference to these discarded rationales. In- stead, the plurality alludes only to Buckley’s last remain- ing reason for devaluing political contributions relative to expenditures. See ante, at 8 (quoting Buckley,
424 U. S., at 21). The relevant sentence from Buckley reads as follows: “A limitation on the amount of money a person may give to a candidate or campaign organization thus in- volves little direct restraint on his political commu- nication, for it permits the symbolic expression of support evidenced by a contribution but does not in any way infringe the contributor’s freedom to discuss candidates and issues.”
Ibid.That proposition, read in full, cannot be squared with a key premise of today’s decision. Among the Government’s justifications for the aggregate limits set forth in the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002 (BCRA) is that “an individual can engage in the ‘symbolic act of contributing’ to as many entities as he wishes.” Brief for Appellee 20. That is, the Government contends that aggregate limits are constitutional as long as an individual can still contribute some token amount (a dime, for example) to each of his preferred candidates. The plurality, quite correctly, rejects that argument, noting that “[i]t is no answer to say that the individual can simply contribute less money to more people.” Ante, at 16. That is so because “[t]o require one person to contribute at lower levels than others because he wants to support more candidates or causes is to impose a special burden on broader participation in the democratic process.”
Ibid.What the plurality does not recognize is that the same logic also defeats the reasoning from Buckley on which the Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 5 THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment plurality purports to rely. Under the plurality’s analysis, limiting the amount of money a person may give to a candidate does impose a direct restraint on his political communication; if it did not, the aggregate limits at issue here would not create “a special burden on broader partic- ipation in the democratic process.”
Ibid.I am wholly in agreement with the plurality’s conclusion on this point: “[T]he Government may not penalize an individual for ‘robustly exercis[ing]’ his First Amendment rights.”
Ibid.(quoting Davis v. Federal Election Comm’n,
554 U. S. 724, 739 (2008)). I regret only that the plurality does not acknowledge that today’s decision, although purporting not to overrule Buckley, continues to chip away at its footings. In sum, what remains of Buckley is a rule without a rationale. Contributions and expenditures are simply “two sides of the same First Amendment coin,” and our ef- forts to distinguish the two have produced mere “word games” rather than any cognizable principle of constitu- tional law. Buckley, supra, at 241, 244 (Burger, C. J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). For that rea- son, I would overrule Buckley and subject the aggregate limits in BCRA to strict scrutiny, which they would surely fail. See Colorado I,
518 U. S., at640–641 (opinion of THOMAS, J.) (“I am convinced that under traditional strict scrutiny, broad prophylactic caps on both spending and giving in the political process . . . are unconstitutional”). This case represents yet another missed opportunity to right the course of our campaign finance jurisprudence by restoring a standard that is faithful to the First Amend- ment. Until we undertake that reexamination, we remain in a “halfway house” of our own design. Shrink Missouri,
528 U. S., at 410(KENNEDY, J., dissenting). For these reasons, I concur only in the judgment. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 1 BREYER, J., dissenting SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 12–536 _________________ SHAUN MCCUTCHEON, ET AL., APPELLANTS v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMMISSION ON APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA [April 2, 2014] JUSTICE BREYER, with whom JUSTICE GINSBURG, JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR, and JUSTICE KAGAN join, dissenting. Nearly 40 years ago in Buckley v. Valeo,
424 U. S. 1(1976) (per curiam), this Court considered the constitu tionality of laws that imposed limits upon the overall amount a single person can contribute to all federal candi dates, political parties, and committees taken together. The Court held that those limits did not violate the Con stitution.
Id., at 38; accord, McConnell v. Federal Election Comm’n,
540 U. S. 93, 138, n. 40, 152–153, n. 48 (2003) (citing with approval Buckley’s aggregate limits holding). The Buckley Court focused upon the same problem that concerns the Court today, and it wrote: “The overall $25,000 ceiling does impose an ultimate restriction upon the number of candidates and com mittees with which an individual may associate him self by means of financial support. But this quite modest restraint upon protected political activity serves to prevent evasion of the $1,000 contribution limitation by a person who might otherwise contribute massive amounts of money to a particular candidate through the use of unearmarked contributions to po litical committees likely to contribute to that candi date, or huge contributions to the candidate’s political party. The limited, additional restriction on associa 2 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting tional freedom imposed by the overall ceiling is thus no more than a corollary of the basic individual con tribution limitation that we have found to be constitu tionally valid.”
424 U. S., at 38. Today a majority of the Court overrules this holding. It is wrong to do so. Its conclusion rests upon its own, not a record-based, view of the facts. Its legal analysis is faulty: It misconstrues the nature of the competing constitutional interests at stake. It understates the importance of pro tecting the political integrity of our governmental insti- tutions. It creates a loophole that will allow a single individual to contribute millions of dollars to a political party or to a candidate’s campaign. Taken together with Citi- zens United v. Federal Election Comm’n,
558 U. S. 310(2010), today’s decision eviscerates our Nation’s campaign finance laws, leaving a remnant incapable of dealing with the grave problems of democratic legitimacy that those laws were intended to resolve. I The plurality concludes that the aggregate contribution limits “ ‘unnecessar[ily] abridg[e]’ ” First Amendment rights. Ante, at 8, 30 (quoting Buckley, supra, at 25). It notes that some individuals will wish to “spen[d] ‘substan tial amounts of money in order to communicate [their] political ideas through sophisticated’ means.” Ante, at 14– 15 (quoting Federal Election Comm’n v. National Con- servative Political Action Comm.,
470 U. S. 480, 493 (1985) (NCPAC)). Aggregate contribution ceilings limit an indi vidual’s ability to engage in such “broader participation in the democratic process,” while insufficiently advancing any legitimate governmental objective. Ante, at 16, 21–29. Hence, the plurality finds, they violate the Constitution. The plurality’s conclusion rests upon three separate but related claims. Each is fatally flawed. First, the plurality says that given the base limits on contributions to candi Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 3 BREYER, J., dissenting dates and political committees, aggregate limits do not further any independent governmental objective worthy of protection. And that is because, given the base limits, “[s]pending large sums of money in connection with elec tions” does not “give rise to . . . corruption.” Ante, at 19. In making this argument, the plurality relies heavily upon a narrow definition of “corruption” that excludes efforts to obtain “ ‘influence over or access to’ elected officials or political parties. ”
Ibid.(quoting Citizens United, supra, at 359); accord, ante, at 18–20, 22–29. Second, the plurality assesses the instrumental objec tive of the aggregate limits, namely, safeguarding the base limits. It finds that they “do not serve that function in any meaningful way.” Ante, at 22. That is because, even without the aggregate limits, the possibilities for circum venting the base limits are “implausible” and “divorced from reality.” Ante, at 23, 24, 28. Third, the plurality says the aggregate limits are not a “ ‘reasonable’ ” policy tool. Rather, they are “poorly tailored to the Government’s interest in preventing circumvention of the base limits.” Ante, at 30 (quoting Board of Trustees of State Univ. of N. Y. v. Fox,
492 U. S. 469, 480 (1989)). The plurality imagines several alternative regulations that it says might just as effectively thwart circumvention. Accordingly, it finds, the aggregate caps are out of “ ‘pro portion to the [anticorruption] interest served.’ ” Ante, at 30 (quoting Fox,
supra, at 480). II The plurality’s first claim—that large aggregate contri butions do not “give rise” to “corruption”—is plausible only because the plurality defines “corruption” too narrowly. The plurality describes the constitutionally permissible objective of campaign finance regulation as follows: “Con gress may target only a specific type of corruption—‘quid pro quo’ corruption.” Ante, at 19. It then defines quid pro 4 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting quo corruption to mean no more than “a direct exchange of an official act for money”—an act akin to bribery. Ante, at 2–3. It adds specifically that corruption does not include efforts to “garner ‘influence over or access to’ elected offi cials or political parties.” Ante, at 19 (quoting Citizens United, supra, at 359). Moreover, the Government’s ef forts to prevent the “appearance of corruption” are “equally confined to the appearance of quid pro quo corruption,” as narrowly defined. Ante, at 19. In the plurality’s view, a federal statute could not prevent an individual from writ ing a million dollar check to a political party (by donating to its various committees), because the rationale for any limit would “dangerously broade[n] the circumscribed definition of quid pro quo corruption articulated in our prior cases.” Ante, at 37. This critically important definition of “corruption” is inconsistent with the Court’s prior case law (with the possible exception of Citizens United, as I will explain below). It is virtually impossible to reconcile with this Court’s decision in McConnell, upholding the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002 (BCRA). And it misun- derstands the constitutional importance of the interests at stake. In fact, constitutional interests—indeed, First Amendment interests—lie on both sides of the legal equation. A In reality, as the history of campaign finance reform shows and as our earlier cases on the subject have recog nized, the anticorruption interest that drives Congress to regulate campaign contributions is a far broader, more important interest than the plurality acknowledges. It is an interest in maintaining the integrity of our public governmental institutions. And it is an interest rooted in the Constitution and in the First Amendment itself. Consider at least one reason why the First Amendment Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 5 BREYER, J., dissenting protects political speech. Speech does not exist in a vac- uum. Rather, political communication seeks to secure government action. A politically oriented “marketplace of ideas” seeks to form a public opinion that can and will influence elected representatives. This is not a new idea. Eighty-seven years ago, Justice Brandeis wrote that the First Amendment’s protection of speech was “essential to effective democracy.” Whitney v. California,
274 U. S. 357, 377 (1927) (concurring opinion). Chief Justice Hughes reiterated the same idea shortly thereafter: “A fundamental principle of our constitutional system” is the “maintenance of the opportunity for free political discussion to the end that government may be responsive to the will of the people.” Stromberg v. Cali- fornia,
283 U. S. 359, 369 (1931) (emphasis added). In Citizens United, the Court stated that “[s]peech is an essential mechanism of democracy, for it is the means to hold officials accountable to the people.”
558 U. S., at 339(emphasis added). The Framers had good reason to emphasize this same connection between political speech and governmental action. An influential 18th-century continental philoso pher had argued that in a representative democracy, the people lose control of their representatives between elec tions, during which interim periods they were “in chains.” J. Rousseau, An Inquiry Into the Nature of the Social Contract 265–266 (transl. 1791). The Framers responded to this criticism both by requir ing frequent elections to federal office, and by enacting a First Amendment that would facilitate a “chain of com munication between the people, and those, to whom they have committed the exercise of the powers of government.” J. Wilson, Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States of America 30–31 (1792). This “chain” would establish the necessary “communion of interests and sympathy of sentiments” between the people and their 6 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting representatives, so that public opinion could be channeled into effective governmental action. The Federalist No. 57, p. 386 (J. Cooke ed. 1961) (J. Madison); accord, T. Benton, 1 Abridgement of the Debates of Congress, from 1789 to 1856, p. 141 (1857) (explaining that the First Amendment will strengthen American democracy by giving “ ‘the peo ple’ ” a right to “ ‘publicly address their representatives,’ ” “ ‘privately advise them,’ ” or “ ‘declare their sentiments by petition to the whole body’ ” (quoting James Madison)). Accordingly, the First Amendment advances not only the individual’s right to engage in political speech, but also the public’s interest in preserving a democratic order in which collective speech matters. What has this to do with corruption? It has everything to do with corruption. Corruption breaks the constitution ally necessary “chain of communication” between the people and their representatives. It derails the essential speech-to-government-action tie. Where enough money calls the tune, the general public will not be heard. Inso far as corruption cuts the link between political thought and political action, a free marketplace of political ideas loses its point. That is one reason why the Court has stressed the constitutional importance of Congress’ con cern that a few large donations not drown out the voices of the many. See, e.g., Buckley,
424 U. S., at26–27. That is also why the Court has used the phrase “subver sion of the political process” to describe circumstances in which “[e]lected officials are influenced to act contrary to their obligations of office by the prospect of financial gain to themselves or infusions of money into their campaigns.” NCPAC,
470 U. S., at 497. See also Federal Election Comm’n v. National Right to Work Comm.,
459 U. S. 197, 208 (1982) (the Government’s interests in preventing corruption “directly implicate the integrity of our electoral process” (internal quotation marks and citation omitted)). See generally R. Post, Citizens Divided: Campaign Fi Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 7 BREYER, J., dissenting nance Reform and the Constitution 7–16, 80–94 (forthcom ing 2014) (arguing that the efficacy of American democ- racy depends on “electoral integrity” and the responsiveness of public officials to public opinion). The “appearance of corruption” can make matters worse. It can lead the public to believe that its efforts to com municate with its representatives or to help sway public opinion have little purpose. And a cynical public can lose interest in political participation altogether. See Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC,
528 U. S. 377, 390 (2000) (“[T]he cynical assumption that large donors call the tune could jeopardize the willingness of voters to take part in democratic governance”). Democracy, the Court has often said, cannot work unless “the people have faith in those who govern.” United States v. Mississippi Valley Generating Co.,
364 U. S. 520, 562 (1961). The upshot is that the interests the Court has long described as preventing “corruption” or the “appearance of corruption” are more than ordinary factors to be weighed against the constitutional right to political speech. Rather, they are interests rooted in the First Amendment it- self. They are rooted in the constitutional effort to create a democracy responsive to the people—a government where laws reflect the very thoughts, views, ideas, and sentiments, the expression of which the First Amendment protects. Given that end, we can and should understand campaign finance laws as resting upon a broader and more significant constitutional rationale than the plural- ity’s limited definition of “corruption” suggests. We should see these laws as seeking in significant part to strengthen, rather than weaken, the First Amendment. To say this is not to deny the potential for conflict between (1) the need to permit contributions that pay for the diffusion of ideas, and (2) the need to limit payments in order to help main tain the integrity of the electoral process. But that conflict takes place within, not outside, the First Amendment’s 8 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting boundaries. B Since the kinds of corruption that can destroy the link between public opinion and governmental action extend well beyond those the plurality describes, the plurality’s notion of corruption is flatly inconsistent with the basic constitutional rationale I have just described. Thus, it should surprise no one that this Court’s case law (Citizens United excepted) insists upon a considerably broader definition. In Buckley, for instance, the Court said explicitly that aggregate limits were constitutional because they helped “prevent evasion . . . [through] huge contributions to the candidate’s political party,”
424 U. S., at 26(the contrary to what the plurality today seems to believe, see ante, at 36–39). Moreover, Buckley upheld the base limits in significant part because they helped thwart “the appear ance of corruption stemming from public awareness of the opportunities for abuse inherent in a regime of large indi- vidual financial contributions.”
424 U. S., at 27(emphasis added). And it said that Congress could reasonably con clude that criminal laws forbidding “the giving and taking of bribes” did not adequately “deal with the reality or appearance of corruption.”
Id., at 28. Bribery laws, the Court recognized, address “only the most blatant and specific attempts of those with money to influence gov ernmental action.”
Ibid.The concern with corruption extends further. Other cases put the matter yet more strongly. In Beaumont, for example, the Court found constitutional a ban on direct contributions by corporations because of the need to prevent corruption, properly “understood not only as quid pro quo agreements, but also as undue influence on an officeholder’s judgment.” Federal Election Comm’n v. Beaumont,
539 U. S. 146, 155–156 (2003). In Federal Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 9 BREYER, J., dissenting Election Comm’n v. Colorado Republican Federal Cam- paign Comm.,
533 U. S. 431, 441, 457–460 (2001) (Colo- rado II ), the Court upheld limits imposed upon coordinated expenditures among parties and candidates because it found they thwarted corruption and its appearance, again understood as including “undue influence” by wealthy donors. In Shrink Missouri, the Court upheld limitations imposed by the Missouri Legislature upon contributions to state political candidates, not only because of the need to prevent bribery, but also because of “the broader threat from politicians too compliant with the wishes of large contributors.”
528 U. S., at 389. C Most important, in McConnell, this Court considered the constitutionality of the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002, an Act that set new limits on “soft money” contri butions to political parties. “Soft money” referred to funds that, prior to BCRA, were freely donated to parties for activities other than directly helping elect a federal candi date—activities such as voter registration, “get out the vote” drives, and advertising that did not expressly advo cate a federal candidate’s election or defeat.
540 U. S., at122–124. BCRA imposed a new ban on soft money contri butions to national party committees, and greatly cur tailed them in respect to state and local parties.
Id.,at 133–134, 161–164. The Court in McConnell upheld these new contribution restrictions under the First Amendment for the very rea son the plurality today discounts or ignores. Namely, the Court found they thwarted a significant risk of cor ruption—understood not as quid pro quo bribery, but as privileged access to and pernicious influence upon elected representatives. In reaching its conclusion in McConnell, the Court relied upon a vast record compiled in the District Court. That 10 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting record consisted of over 100,000 pages of material and included testimony from more than 200 witnesses. See
251 F. Supp. 2d 176, 209 (DC 2003) (per curiam). What it showed, in detail, was the web of relationships and un- derstandings among parties, candidates, and large donors that underlies privileged access and influence. See McConnell,
540 U. S., at146–152, 154–157, 167–171, 182– 184. The District Judges in McConnell made clear that the record did “not contain any evidence of bribery or vote buying in exchange for donations of nonfederal money.”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 481(opinion of Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (emphasis added). Indeed, no one had identified a “single discrete instance of quid pro quo corruption” due to soft money. Id., at 395 (opinion of Henderson, J.). But what the record did demonstrate was that enormous soft money contributions, ranging between $1 million and $5 million among the largest donors, enabled wealthy contributors to gain disproportionate “access to federal lawmakers” and the ability to “influenc[e] legislation.” Id., at 481 (opinion of Kollar-Kotelly, J.). There was an indisputable link between generous political donations and opportunity after opportunity to make one’s case directly to a Member of Congress. Testimony by elected officials supported this conclusion. See, e.g., ibid. (“ ‘Large donors of both hard and soft money receive special treatment’ ” (Sen. Simpson)); id., at 482 (“ ‘Donations, including soft money donations to political parties, do affect how Congress operates. It’s only natural, and happens all too often, that a busy Senator with 10 minutes to spare will spend those minutes returning the call of a large soft money donor’ ” (Sen. Boren)); id., at 496 (“ ‘At a minimum, large soft money donations purchase an opportunity for the donors to make their case to elected officials . . .’ ” (Sen. McCain)). Furthermore, testimony from party operatives showed that national political par ties had created “major donor programs,” through which Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 11 BREYER, J., dissenting they openly “offer[ed] greater access to federal office hold ers as the donations gr[e]w larger.” Id., at 502. I have placed in Appendix A more examples of the kind of evi dence that filled the District Court record in McConnell. This Court upheld BCRA’s limitations on soft money contributions by relying on just the kind of evidence I have described. We wrote: “The evidence in the record shows that candidates and donors alike have in fact exploited the soft-money loophole, the former to increase their prospects of election and the latter to create debt on the part of of ficeholders . . . . Plaintiffs argue that without concrete evidence of an instance in which a federal officeholder has actually switched a vote [in exchange for soft money] . . . , Congress has not shown that there exists real or apparent corruption. . . . [P]laintiffs conceive of corruption too narrowly. Our cases have firmly estab lished that Congress’ legitimate interest extends be yond preventing simple cash-for-votes corruption to curbing ‘undue influence on an officeholder’s judg ment, and the appearance of such influence.’ ”
540 U. S., at 146, 149–150 (quoting Colorado II,
533 U. S., at 441; emphasis added; paragraphs and paragraph breaks omitted). We specifically rejected efforts to define “corruption” in ways similar to those the plurality today accepts. We added: “Just as troubling to a functioning democracy as clas sic quid pro quo corruption is the danger that office holders will decide issues not on the merits or the desires of their constituencies, but according to the wishes of those who have made large financial contri butions valued by the officeholder.”
540 U. S., at 153. Insofar as today’s decision sets forth a significantly nar 12 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting rower definition of “corruption,” and hence of the public’s interest in political integrity, it is flatly inconsistent with McConnell. D One case, however, contains language that offers the plurality support. That case is Citizens United. There, as the plurality points out, ante, at 19, the Court said that “[w]hen Buckley identified a sufficiently important gov ernmental interest in preventing corruption or the ap pearance of corruption, that interest was limited to quid pro quo corruption.”
558 U. S., at 359. Further, the Court said that quid pro quo corruption does not include “influ ence over or access to elected officials,” because “ ‘generic favoritism or influence theory . . . is at odds with standard First Amendment analyses.’ ”
Ibid.(quoting McConnell, supra, at 296 (KENNEDY, J., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part)). How should we treat these statements from Citizens United now? They are not essential to the Court’s holding in the case—at least insofar as it can be read to require federal law to treat corporations and trade unions like individuals when they independently pay for, e.g., televi sion advertising during the last 60 days of a federal elec tion. Citizens United, supra, at 365. Taken literally, the statements cited simply refer to and characterize still earlier Court cases. They do not require the more absolute reading that the plurality here gives them. More than that. Read as the plurality reads them to day, the statements from Citizens United about the proper contours of the corruption rationale conflict not just with language in the McConnell opinion, but with McConnell’s very holding. See supra, at 9–11. Did the Court in Citi- zens United intend to overrule McConnell? I doubt it, for if it did, the Court or certainly the dissent would have said something about it. The total silence of all opinions in Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 13 BREYER, J., dissenting Citizens United with respect to this matter argues strongly in favor of treating the language quoted above as dic- tum, as an overstatement, or as limited to the context in which it appears. Citizens United itself contains language that supports the last mentioned reading, for it says that “[Buckley] did not extend this rationale [about the reality or appearance of corruption] to independent expenditures, and the Court does not do so here.”
558 U. S., at 357(emphasis added). And it adds that, while “[t]he BCRA record establishes that certain donations to political par ties, called ‘soft money,’ were made to gain access to elected officials,” “[t]his case, however, is about independent expenditures, not soft money.”
Id.,at 360–361 (emphasis added). The plurality’s use of Citizens United’s narrow definition of corruption here, however, is a different matter. That use does not come accompanied with a limiting context (independent expenditures by corporations and unions) or limiting language. It applies to the whole of campaign finance regulation. And, as I have pointed out, it is flatly inconsistent with the broader definition of corruption upon which McConnell’s holding depends. So: Does the Court intend today to overrule McConnell? Or does it intend to leave McConnell and BCRA in place? The plurality says the latter. Ante, at 20–21, n. 6 (“Our holding about the constitutionality of the aggregate limits clearly does not overrule McConnell’s holding about ‘soft money’ ”). But how does the plurality explain its rejection of the broader definition of corruption, upon which McConnell’s holding depends? Compare ante, at 18–21, with McConnell,
540 U. S., at 146, 149–153. III The plurality invalidates the aggregate contribution limits for a second reason. It believes they are no longer needed to prevent contributors from circumventing federal 14 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting limits on direct contributions to individuals, political parties, and political action committees. Ante, at 22–29. Cf. Buckley,
424 U. S., at 38(aggregate limits “prevent evasion” of base contribution limits). Other “campaign finance laws,” combined with “experience” and “common sense,” foreclose the various circumvention scenarios that the Government hypothesizes. Ante, at 28. Accordingly, the plurality concludes, the aggregate limits provide no added benefit. The plurality is wrong. Here, as in Buckley, in the absence of limits on aggregate political contributions, donors can and likely will find ways to channel millions of dollars to parties and to individual candidates, producing precisely the kind of “corruption” or “appearance of cor ruption” that previously led the Court to hold aggregate limits constitutional. Those opportunities for circumven tion will also produce the type of corruption that concerns the plurality today. The methods for using today’s opinion to evade the law’s individual contribution limits are com plex, but they are well known, or will become well known, to party fundraisers. I shall describe three. A Example One: Gifts for the Benefit of the Party. Cam paign finance law permits each individual to give $64,800 over two years to a national party committee. 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(1)(B);
78 Fed. Reg. 8532(2013). The two major political parties each have three national committees. Ante, at 4, n. 1. Federal law also entitles an individual to give $20,000 to a state party committee over two years. §441a(a)(1)(D). Each major political party has 50 such committees. Those individual limits mean that, in the absence of any aggregate limit, an individual could legally give to the Republican Party or to the Democratic Party about $1.2 million over two years. See Appendix B, Table 1, infra, at 39. To make it easier for contributors to give Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 15 BREYER, J., dissenting gifts of this size, each party could create a “Joint Party Committee,” comprising all of its national and state party committees. The titular heads could be the Speaker of the House of Representatives and the Minority Leader of the House. A contributor could then write a single check to the Joint Party Committee—and its staff would divide the funds so that each constituent unit receives no more than it could obtain from the contributor directly ($64,800 for a national committee over two years, $20,000 for a state committee over the same). Before today’s decision, the total size of Rich Donor’s check to the Joint Party Commit tee was capped at $74,600—the aggregate limit for dona tions to political parties over a 2-year election cycle. See §441a(a)(3)(B);
78 Fed. Reg. 8532. After today’s decision, Rich Donor can write a single check to the Joint Party Committee in an amount of about $1.2 million. Will political parties seek these large checks? Why not? The recipient national and state committees can spend the money to buy generic party advertisements, say television commercials or bumper stickers saying “Support Republi cans,” “Support Democrats,” or the like. They also can transfer the money to party committees in battleground States to increase the chances of winning hotly contested seats. See §441a(a)(4) (permitting national or state po- litical committees to make unlimited “transfers” to other committees “of the same political party”). Will party officials and candidates solicit these large contributions from wealthy donors? Absolutely. Such con- tributions will help increase the party’s power, as well as the candidate’s standing among his colleagues. Will elected officials be particularly grateful to the large donor, feeling obliged to provide him special access and influence, and perhaps even a quid pro quo legislative favor? That is what we have previously believed. See McConnell,
540 U. S., at 182(“Large soft-money donations at a candidate’s or officeholder’s behest give rise to all of 16 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting the same corruption concerns posed by contributions made directly to the candidate or officeholder”); id., at 308 (opin ion of KENNEDY, J.) (“The making of a solicited gift is a quid both to the recipient of the money and to the one who solicits the payment”); Colorado II,
533 U. S., at 460, n. 23(explaining how a candidate can “become a player [in his party] beyond his own race” by “directing donations to the party and making sure that the party knows who raised the money,” and that “the donor’s influence is multiplied” in such instances). And, as the statements collected in Appendix A, infra, make clear, we have believed this with good reason. Example Two: Donations to Individual Candidates (The $3.6 Million Check). The first example significantly un- derstates the problem. That is because federal election law also allows a single contributor to give $5,200 to each party candidate over a 2-year election cycle (assuming the candidate is running in both a primary and a general election). §441a(a)(1)(A);
78 Fed. Reg. 8532. There are 435 party candidates for House seats and 33 party candi dates for Senate seats in any given election year. That makes an additional $2.4 million in allowable contribu tions. Thus, without an aggregate limit, the law will permit a wealthy individual to write a check, over a 2-year election cycle, for $3.6 million—all to benefit his political party and its candidates. See Appendix B, Table 2(a), infra, at 39. To make it easier for a wealthy donor to make a contri bution of this size, the parties can simply enlarge the composition of the Joint Party Committee described in Example One, so that it now includes party candidates. And a party can proliferate such joint entities, perhaps calling the first the “Smith Victory Committee,” the second the “Jones Victory Committee,” and the like. See
11 CFR §102.17(c)(5) (2012). (I say “perhaps” because too trans parent a name might call into play certain earmarking Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 17 BREYER, J., dissenting rules. But the Federal Election Commission’s (FEC) database of joint fundraising committees in 2012 shows similarly named entities, e.g., “Landrieu Wyden Victory Fund,” etc.). As I have just said, without any aggregate limit, the law will allow Rich Donor to write a single check to, say, the Smith Victory Committee, for up to $3.6 million. This check represents “the total amount that the contributor could contribute to all of the participants” in the Commit tee over a 2-year cycle. §102.17(c)(5). The Committee would operate under an agreement that provides a “for- mula for the allocation of fundraising proceeds” among its constituent units. §102.17(c)(1). And that “formula” would divide the proceeds so that no committee or can- didate receives more than it could have received from Rich Donor directly—$64,800, $20,000, or $5,200. See §102.17(c)(6). So what is wrong with that? The check is considerably larger than Example One’s check. But is there anything else wrong? The answer is yes, absolutely. The law will also permit a party and its candidates to shift most of Rich Donor’s contributions to a single candidate, say Smith. Here is how: The law permits each candidate and each party commit tee in the Smith Victory Committee to write Candidate Smith a check directly. For his primary and general elections combined, they can write checks of up to $4,000 (from each candidate’s authorized campaign committee) and $10,000 (from each state and national committee).
2 U. S. C. §§432(e)(3)(B), 441a(a)(2)(A);
11 CFR §110.3(b). This yields a potential $1,872,000 (from candidates) plus $530,000 (from party committees). Thus, the law permits the candidates and party entities to redirect $2.37 million of Rich Donor’s $3.6 million check to Candidate Smith. It also permits state and national committees to contribute to Smith’s general election campaign through making 18 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting coordinated expenditures—in amounts that range from $46,600 to $2.68 million for a general election (depending upon the size of Smith’s State and whether he is running for a House or Senate seat).
78 Fed. Reg. 8530–8532. See Appendix B, Table 2(b), infra, at 40. The upshot is that Candidate Smith can receive at least $2.37 million and possibly the full $3.6 million contributed by Rich Donor to the Smith Victory Committee, even though the funds must first be divided up among the constituent units before they can be rerouted to Smith. Nothing requires the Smith Victory Committee to explain in advance to Rich Donor all of the various transfers that will take place, and nothing prevents the entities in the Committee from informing the donor and the receiving candidate after the fact what has transpired. Accordingly, the money can be donated and rerouted to Candidate Smith without the donor having violated the base limits or any other FEC regulation. And the evidence in the McConnell record reprinted in Appendix A, infra—with respect to soft money contributions—makes clear that Candidate Smith will almost certainly come to learn from whom he has received this money. The parties can apply the same procedure to other large donations, channeling money from Rich Donor Two to Candidate Jones. If 10 or 20 candidates face particularly tight races, party committees and party candidates may work together to channel Rich Donor One’s multimillion dollar contribution to the Most Embattled Candidate (e.g., Candidate Smith), Rich Donor Two’s multimillion dollar contribution to the Second Most Embattled Candidate (e.g., Candidate Jones), and so on down the line. If this does not count as evasion of the base limits, what does? Present aggregate limits confine the size of any individual gift to $123,200. Today’s opinion creates a loophole meas ured in the millions. Example Three: Proliferating Political Action Commit- Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 19 BREYER, J., dissenting tees (PACs). Campaign finance law prohibits an individual from contributing (1) more than $5,200 to any candidate in a federal election cycle, and (2) more than $5,000 to a PAC in a calendar year. 2 U. S. C. §§441a(a)(1)(A), (C);
78 Fed. Reg. 8532. It also prohibits (3) any PAC from contributing more than $10,000 to any candidate in an election cycle. §441(a)(2)(A). But the law does not prohibit an individual from contributing (within the current $123,200 biannual aggregate limit) $5,000 to each of an unlimited total num ber of PACs. And there, so to speak, lies the rub. Here is how, without any aggregate limits, a party will be able to channel $2 million from each of ten Rich Do- nors to each of ten Embattled Candidates. Groups of party supporters—individuals, corporations, or trade unions— create 200 PACs. Each PAC claims it will use the funds it raises to support several candidates from the party, though it will favor those who are most endangered. (Each PAC qualifies for “multicandidate” status because it has received contributions from more than 50 persons and has made contributions to five federal candidates at some point previously. §441a(a)(4);
11 CFR §100.5(e)(3)). Over a 2-year election cycle, Rich Donor One gives $10,000 to each PAC ($5,000 per year)—yielding $2 million total. Rich Donor 2 does the same. So, too, do the other eight Rich Donors. This brings their total donations to $20 million, disbursed among the 200 PACs. Each PAC will have collected $100,000, and each can use its money to write ten checks of $10,000—to each of the ten most Em battled Candidates in the party (over two years). See Appendix B, Table 3, infra, at 41. Every Embattled Can didate, receiving a $10,000 check from 200 PACs, will have collected $2 million. The upshot is that ten Rich Donors will have contrib- uted $2 million each, and ten Embattled Candidates will have collected $2 million each. In this example, unlike Example Two, the recipient candidates may not know 20 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting which of the ten Rich Donors is personally responsible for the $2 million he or she receives. But the recipient candi date is highly likely to know who the ten Rich Donors are, and to feel appropriately grateful. Moreover, the ability of a small group of donors to contribute this kind of money to threatened candidates is not insignificant. In the example above—with ten Rich Donors giving $2 million each, and ten Embattled Candidates receiving $2 million each—the contributions would have been enough to finance a consid erable portion of, and perhaps all of, the candidates’ races in the 2012 elections. See Appendix C, Table 1, infra, at 42 (showing that in 2012, the average winning House candidate spent $1.6 million and the average winning Senate candidate spent $11.5 million). B The plurality believes that the three scenarios I have just depicted either pose no threat, or cannot or will not take place. It does not believe the scenario depicted in Example One is any cause for concern, because it involves only “general, broad-based support of a political party.” Ante, at 37. Not so. A candidate who solicits a multimil lion dollar check for his party will be deeply grateful to the checkwriter, and surely could reward him with a quid pro quo favor. The plurality discounts the scenarios depicted in Example Two and Example Three because it finds such circumvention tactics “illegal under current campaign finance laws,” “implausible,” or “divorced from reality.” Ante, at 23, 24, 28. But they are not. The plurality’s view depends in large part upon its claim that since this Court decided Buckley in 1976, changes in either statutory law or in applicable regulations have come to make it difficult, if not impossible, for these cir cumvention scenarios to arise. Hence, it concludes, there is no longer a need for aggregate contribution limits. See ante, at 11–13, 22–29. But a closer examination of the five Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 21 BREYER, J., dissenting legal changes to which the plurality points makes clear that those changes cannot effectively stop the abuses that I have depicted. First, the plurality points out that in 1976 (a few months after this Court decided Buckley) Congress “added limits on contributions to political committees,” i.e., to PACs. Ante, at 11; accord,
90 Stat. 487(codified at 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(1)(C)). But Example Three, the here relevant example, takes account of those limits, namely, $5,000 to a PAC in any given year. And it shows that the per-PAC limit does not matter much when it comes to the potential for circumvention, as long as party supporters can create dozens or hundreds of PACs. Federal law places no upper limit on the number of PACs supporting a party or a group of party candidates that can be estab lished. And creating a PAC is primarily a matter of pa perwork, a knowledgeable staff person, and a little time. Second, the plurality points out that in 1976, Congress “also added an antiproliferation rule prohibiting donors from creating or controlling multiple affiliated political committees.” Ante, at 12. The rule provides that “all contributions made by political committees established or financed or maintained or controlled” by the same corpora tion, labor organization, person, or group of persons, “shall be considered to have been made by a single political committee.” §441a(a)(5). But different supporters can create different PACs. Indeed, there were roughly 2,700 “nonconnected” PACs (i.e., PACs not connected to a spe- cific corporation or labor union) operating during the 2012 elections. Ante, at 24. In a future without aggregate contribution limits, far more nonconnected PACs will likely appear. The plurality also notes that the FEC can examine certain “ ‘circumstantial factors,’ ” such as “ ‘com mon or overlapping membership’ ” or “ ‘similar patterns of contributions,’ ” to determine whether a group of PACs are affiliated. Ante, at 25 (quoting
11 CFR §100.5(g)(4)(ii)). 22 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting But the ultimate question in the affiliation inquiry is whether “one committee or organization [has] been estab lished, financed, maintain or controlled by another com mittee or sponsoring organization.”
Ibid.Just because a group of multicandidate PACs all support the same party and all decide to donate funds to a group of endangered candidates in that party does not mean they will qualify as “affiliated” under the relevant definition. This rule appears inadequate to stop the sort of circumvention depicted in Example Three. Third, the plurality says that a post-Buckley regulation has strengthened the statute’s earmarking provision. Ante, at 12. Namely, the plurality points to a rule pro- mulgated by the FEC in 1976, specifying that earmarking includes any “designation ‘whether direct or indirect, express or implied, oral or written.’ ”
Ibid.(quoting
11 CFR §110.6(b)); accord,
41 Fed. Reg. 35950(1976). This means that if Rich Donor were to give $5,000 to a PAC while “designat[ing]” (in any way) that the money go to Candidate Smith, those funds must count towards Rich Donor’s total allowable contributions to Smith—$5,200 per election cycle. But the virtually identical earmarking provision in effect when this Court decided Buckley would have required the same thing. That provision also counted, when applying the base contribution limits, “all contri- butions made by a person, either directly or indirectly, on behalf of a particular candidate, including contributions which are in any way earmarked or otherwise directed through an intermediary or conduit to a candidate.”
88 Stat. 1264; accord, 2 U. S. C. §441a(a)(8) (same). What is the difference? Fourth, the plurality points out that the FEC’s regula tions “specify that an individual who has contributed to a particular candidate committee may not also contribute to a single-candidate committee for that candidate.” Ante, at 12–13 (citing
11 CFR §110.1(h)(1); emphasis added). The Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 23 BREYER, J., dissenting regulations, however, do not prevent a person who has contributed to a candidate from also contributing to multi- candidate committees that support the candidate. Indeed, the rules specifically authorize such contributions. See §110.1(h) (“A person may contribute to a candidate . . . and also contribute to a political committee which has sup- ported, or anticipates supporting, the same candidate in the same election,” as long as the political committee is “not the candidate’s principal campaign committee” or a “single candidate committee” (emphasis added)). Example Three illustrates the latter kind of contribution. And briefs before us make clear that the possibility for circumventing the base limits through making such contributions is a realistic, not an illusory, one. See Brief for Appellee 36 (demonstrating that many PACs today explain in their public materials just what fairly small group of candidates they intend to support); Brief for Americans for Campaign Reform as Amicus Curiae 14–15 (similar). Fifth, the plurality points to another FEC regulation (also added in 1976), which says that “an individual who has contributed to a candidate” may not “also contribute to a political committee that has supported or anticipates supporting the same candidate if the individual knows that ‘a substantial portion [of his contribution] will be contributed to, or expended on behalf of,’ that candidate.” Ante, at 13 (quoting
11 CFR §110.1(h)(2); brackets in original); accord,
41 Fed. Reg. 35948. This regulation is important, for in principle, the FEC might use it to pre vent the circumstances that Examples Two and Three set forth from arising. And it is not surprising that the plu rality relies upon the existence of this rule when it de scribes those circumstances as “implausible,” “illegal,” or “divorced from reality.” Ante, at 23, 24, 28. In fact, however, this regulation is not the strong anti circumvention weapon that the plurality imagines. De spite the plurality’s assurances, it does not “disarm” the 24 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting possibilities for circumvention. Ante, at 23. That is be cause the regulation requires a showing that donors have “knowledge that a substantial portion” of their contribu tions will be used by a PAC to support a candidate to whom they have already contributed. §110.1(h)(2) (em phasis added). And “knowledge” is hard to prove. I have found nine FEC cases decided since the year 2000 that refer to this regulation. In all but one, the FEC failed to find the requisite “knowledge”—despite the presence of Example Two or Example Three circumstances. See Fac tual and Legal Analysis, In re: Transfund PAC, Matter Under Review (MUR) 6221, p. 11 (FEC, June 7, 2010) (although the donor “might reasonably infer that some portion of his contribution” to a candidate’s Leadership PAC would be used to support the candidate, “such an inference alone does not suggest that [he] had ‘actual knowledge’ ” of such); Factual and Legal Analysis, In re: John Shadegg’s Friends, MUR 5968, pp. 3, 6–7 (FEC, Nov. 10, 2008) (“[T]here is no basis on which to conclude that [the donors] knew that the funds they contributed to LEAD PAC would be used to support the Shadegg Com mittee” even though Congressman Shadegg solicited the donations and LEAD PAC was Congressman Shadegg’s Leadership PAC); Factual and Legal Analysis, In re: Wal- berg for Congress, MUR 5881, pp. 6, 9–11 (FEC, Aug. 15, 2007) (finding seven contributors, who gave to a candidate and to a PAC that provided 86% of the candidate’s financ ing, had not shown “knowledge”); Factual and Legal Anal ysis, In re: Matt Brown for Senate, MUR 5732, p. 11 (FEC, Apr. 4, 2007) (“Though it may be reasonable to infer that the individual donors solicited by Brown gave to the State Parties under the assumption that some portion of their contribution might then be donated to the Brown Commit tee, such an inference alone is insufficient to find reason to believe
11 CFR §110.1(h) has been violated”); First Gen eral Counsel’s Report, In re: Liffrig for Senate, MUR 5678, Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 25 BREYER, J., dissenting pp. 8–9 (FEC, Nov. 27, 2006) (similar); First General Counsel’s Report, In re: Nesbitt, MUR 5445, pp. 11–12 (FEC, Feb. 2, 2005) (similar); First General Counsel’s Report, In re: Keystone Corp., MUR 5019, pp. 23–29 (FEC, Feb. 5, 2001) (similar); General Counsel’s Report #2, In re: Boston Capital Corp., MUR 4538, pp. 17–18 (FEC, Mar. 10, 2000) (recommending the FEC take no action with respect to the §110.1(h) issue). Given this record of FEC (in)activity, my reaction to the plurality’s reliance upon agency enforcement of this rule (as an adequate substitute for Congress’ aggregate limits) is like Oscar Wilde’s after reading Dickens’ account of the death of Little Nell: “One must have a heart of stone,” said Wilde, “to read [it] with out laughing.” Oxford Dictionary of Humorous Quotations 86 (N. Sherrin 2d ed. 2001). I have found one contrary example—the single example to which the plurality refers. Ante, at 25 (citing Concilia tion Agreement, In re Riley, MURs 4568, 4633, 4634, 4736 (FEC, Dec. 19, 2001)). In that case, the FEC found prob able cause to believe that three individual contributors to several PACs had the requisite “knowledge” that the PACs would use a “substantial portion” of their contributions to support a candidate to whom they had already contributed— Sam Brownback, a candidate for the Senate (for two of the contributors), and Robert Riley, a candidate for the House (for the third). The individuals had made donations to several PACs operating as a network, under the direc tion of a single political consulting firm. The two contribu tors to Sam Brownback were his parents-in-law, and the FEC believed they might be using the PAC network to channel extra support to him. The contributor to Robert Riley was his son, and the FEC believed he might be doing the same. The facts in this case are unusual, for individ- ual contributors are not typically relatives of the candidates they are seeking to support, and ordinary PACs do not tend to work in coordination under the direction of a con 26 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting sulting firm. In any event, this single swallow cannot make the plurality’s summer. Thus, it is not surprising that throughout the many years this FEC regulation has been in effect, political parties and candidates have established ever more joint fundraising committees (numbering over 500 in the last federal elections); candidates have established ever more “Leadership PACs” (numbering over 450 in the last elec tions); and party supporters have established ever more multicandidate PACs (numbering over 3,000 in the last elections). See Appendix C, Tables 2–3, infra, at 42–43; FEC, 2014 Committee Summary (reporting the number of “qualified” (or multicandidate) PACs in 2012), online at http://www.fec.gov/data/CommitteeSummary.do (all Inter net materials as visited Mar. 28, 2014, and available in Clerk of Court’s case file). Using these entities, candidates, parties, and party supporters can transfer and, we are told, have transferred large sums of money to specific candidates, thereby avoid ing the base contribution limits in ways that Examples Two and Three help demonstrate. See Brief for Appellee 38–39, 53–54; Brief for Campaign Legal Center, et al. as Amici Curiae 12–15; Brief of Democratic Members of the United States House of Representatives as Amici Curiae 28–29. They have done so without drawing FEC prosecu tion—at least not according to my (and apparently the plurality’s) search of publicly available records. That is likely because in the real world, the methods of achieving circumvention are more subtle and more complex than our stylized Examples Two and Three depict. And persons have used these entities to channel money to candidates without any individual breaching the current aggregate $123,200 limit. The plurality now removes that limit, thereby permitting wealthy donors to make aggregate contributions not of $123,200, but of several millions of dollars. If the FEC regulation has failed to plug a small Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 27 BREYER, J., dissenting hole, how can it possibly plug a large one? IV The plurality concludes that even if circumvention were a threat, the aggregate limits are “poorly tailored” to ad- dress it. Ante, at 30. The First Amendment requires “ ‘a fit that is . . . reasonable,’ ” and there is no such “fit” here because there are several alternative ways Congress could prevent evasion of the base limits. Ibid. (quoting Fox,
492 U. S., at 480). For instance, the plurality posits, Congress (or the FEC) could “tighten . . . transfer rules”; it could require “contributions above the current aggregate limits to be deposited into segregated, nontransferable accounts and spent only by their recipients”; it could define “how many candidates a PAC must support in order to ensure that ‘a substantial portion’ of a donor’s contribution is not rerouted to a certain candidate”; or it could prohibit “do nors who have contributed the current maximum sums from further contributing to political committees that have indicated they will support candidates to whom the donor has already contributed.” Ante, at 33–35 (quoting
11 CFR §110.1(h)(2)). The plurality, however, does not show, or try to show, that these hypothetical alternatives could effectively replace aggregate contribution limits. Indeed, it does not even “opine on the validity of any particular proposal,” ante, at 35—presumably because these proposals them selves could be subject to constitutional challenges. For the most part, the alternatives the plurality mentions were similarly available at the time of Buckley. Their hypothetical presence did not prevent the Court from upholding aggregate limits in 1976. How can their con tinued hypothetical presence lead the plurality now to conclude that aggregate limits are “poorly tailored?” See ante, at 30. How can their continued hypothetical pres ence lead the Court to overrule Buckley now? 28 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting In sum, the explanation of why aggregate limits are needed is complicated, as is the explanation of why other methods will not work. But the conclusion is simple: There is no “substantial mismatch” between Congress’ legitimate objective and the “means selected to achieve it.” Ante, at 10. The Court, as in Buckley, should hold that aggregate contribution limits are constitutional. V The District Court in this case, holding that Buckley foreclosed McCutcheon’s constitutional challenge to the aggregate limits, granted the Government’s motion to dismiss the complaint prior to a full evidentiary hearing. See
893 F. Supp. 2d 133, 140–141 (DC 2012). If the plu rality now believes the District Court was wrong, then why does it not return the case for the further evidentiary development which has not yet taken place? In the past, when evaluating the constitutionality of campaign finance restrictions, we have typically relied upon an evidentiary record amassed below to determine whether the law served a compelling governmental objec tive. And, typically, that record contained testimony from Members of Congress (or state legislators) explaining why Congress (or the legislature) acted as it did. See, e.g., McConnell,
540 U. S., at147–154 (upholding federal re strictions on soft money by drawing on an extensive Dis trict Court record that contained declarations from current and former Members of Congress); Colorado II,
533 U. S., at457–465 (upholding federal limits on coordinated ex penditures between parties and candidates on the basis of a summary judgment record that contained declarations from party operatives, fundraisers, and Members of Con gress); Shrink Missouri,
528 U. S., at 393(upholding Missouri’s contribution limits on the basis of the lower court record, which contained similar declarations). If we are to overturn an act of Congress here, we should do so on Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 29 BREYER, J., dissenting the basis of a similar record. For one thing, an evidentiary record can help us deter mine whether or the extent to which we should defer to Congress’ own judgments, particularly those reflecting a balance of the countervailing First Amendment interests I have described. Determining whether anticorruption objectives justify a particular set of contribution limits requires answering empirically based questions, and ap- plying significant discretion and judgment. To what ex tent will unrestricted giving lead to corruption or its appearance? What forms will any such corruption take? To what extent will a lack of regulation undermine public confidence in the democratic system? To what extent can regulation restore it? These kinds of questions, while not easily answered, are questions that Congress is far better suited to resolve than are judges. Thus, while court review of contribution limits has been and should be “rigorous,” Buckley,
424 U. S., at 29, we have also recognized that “deference to legislative choice is warranted.” Beaumont,
539 U. S., at 155. And that deference has taken account of facts and circum stances set forth in an evidentiary record. For another thing, a comparison of the plurality’s opin ion with this dissent reveals important differences of opinion on fact-related matters. We disagree, for example, on the possibilities for circumvention of the base limits in the absence of aggregate limits. We disagree about how effectively the plurality’s “alternatives” could prevent evasion. An evidentiary proceeding would permit the parties to explore these matters, and it would permit the courts to reach a more accurate judgment. The plurality rationalizes its haste to forgo an evidentiary record by noting that “the parties have treated the question as a purely legal one.” Ante, at 14, n. 4. But without a doubt, the legal question—whether the aggregate limits are closely drawn to further a compelling governmental inter 30 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N BREYER, J., dissenting est—turns on factual questions about whether corruption, in the absence of such limits, is a realistic threat to our democracy. The plurality itself spends pages citing figures about campaign spending to defend its “legal” conclusion. Ante, at 24–26, 27–28, 30–32. The problem with such reasoning is that this Court’s expertise does not lie in marshaling facts in the primary instance. That is why in the past, when answering similar questions about the constitutionality of restrictions on campaign contributions, we have relied on an extensive evidentiary record pro duced below to inform our decision. Without further development of the record, however, I fail to see how the plurality can now find grounds for overturning Buckley. The justification for aggregate con tribution restrictions is strongly rooted in the need to assure political integrity and ultimately in the First Amendment itself. Part II, supra. The threat to that integrity posed by the risk of special access and influence remains real. Part III, supra. Even taking the plurality on its own terms and considering solely the threat of quid pro quo corruption (i.e., money-for-votes exchanges), the aggregate limits are a necessary tool to stop circumven tion. Ibid. And there is no basis for finding a lack of “fit” between the threat and the means used to combat it, namely the aggregate limits. Part IV, supra. The plurality reaches the opposite conclusion. The re sult, as I said at the outset, is a decision that substitutes judges’ understandings of how the political process works for the understanding of Congress; that fails to recognize the difference between influence resting upon public opin ion and influence bought by money alone; that overturns key precedent; that creates huge loopholes in the law; and that undermines, perhaps devastates, what remains of campaign finance reform. With respect, I dissent. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 31 Appendix A to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting APPENDIXES A Existence of Large Donations Expert Report: “During the 1996 election cycle, the top 50 nonfederal money donors made contributions ranging from $530,000 to $3,287,175. . . . Soft money financing of party campaigning exploded in the 2000 election cycle. Soft money spending by the national parties reached $498 million, now 42% of their total spending. Raising a half billion dollars in soft money [in 2000] took a major effort by the national parties and elected officials, but they had the advantage of focusing their efforts on large donors. . . . The top 50 soft money donors . . . each contributed be tween $955,695 and $5,949,000.”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 440(opinion of Kollar-Kotelly, J.) (citing T. Mann Expert Report, pp. 22, 24–25) Candidate Solicitation of Large Donations Judicial Finding of Fact: “It is a common practice for Members of Congress to be involved in raising both federal and non-federal dollars for the national party committees, sometimes at the parties’ request. The personal involve ment of high-ranking Members of Congress is a major component of raising federal and nonfederal funds.”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 471. Senator Paul Simon: “ ‘While I was in Congress, the Demo cratic Congressional Campaign Committee (DCCC) and the Democratic Senatorial Campaign Committee (DSCC) would ask Members to make phone calls seeking contribu tions to the party. They would assign me a list of names, people I had not known previously, and I would just go 32 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Appendix A to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting down the list. I am certain they did this because they found it more effective to have Members make calls.’ ”
Ibid.(quoting Simon Decl. ¶7). Senator John McCain: “ ‘[T]he parties encourage Members of Congress to raise large amounts of soft money to benefit their own and others’ re-election. At one recent caucus meeting, a Member of Congress was praised for raising $1.3 million dollars for the party. James Greenwood, a Republican Congressman from Pennsylvania, recently told the New York Times that House leaders consider soft money fundraising prowess in assigning chairmanships and other sought-after jobs. . . . I share Mr. Greenwood’s concerns.’ ” Id., at 476 (quoting McCain Decl. ¶7). Representative Christopher Shays: “ ‘Soft money is raised directly by federal candidates, officeholders, and national political party leaders. National party officials often raise these funds by promising donors access to elected officials. The national parties and national congressional campaign committees also request that Members of Congress make the calls to soft money donors to solicit more funds.’ ” Id., at 471 (quoting Shays Decl. ¶18). Representative Marty Meehan: “ ‘Members of Congress raise money for the national party committees, and I have been involved in such fund-raising for the Democratic Party. At the request of the Party Members of Congress go to the [DCCC] and call prospective donors from lists provided by the Party to ask them to participate in Party events, such as DCCC dinners or Democratic National Committee (DNC) dinners. These lists typically consist of persons who have contributed to the Democratic Party in the past.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 471(quoting Meehan Decl. in Republican National Committee v. FEC, No. 98–CV– 1207 (DC), ¶6). Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 33 Appendix A to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting Lobbyist: “ ‘Even though soft money contributions often go to political parties, the money is given so that the contrib utors can be close to, and recognized by, Members, Presi dents, and Administration officials who have power. Mem bers, not party staffers or party chairs, raise much of the large soft money contributions.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 472(quoting Robert Rozen Decl. ¶15, a partner in a lobby ing firm). Senator Fred Thompson: “ ‘We have gone from basically a small donor system . . . where the average person believed they had a stake, believed they had a voice, to one of ex tremely large amounts of money, where you are not a player unless you are in the $100,000 or $200,000 range [or more] . . . .’ ” Id., at 433 (quoting 147 Cong. Rec. 4622 (2001)). Former DNC official: “Former DNC and DSCC official and current lobbyist Robert Hickmott testifies that even in cumbents with safe seats have incentives to raise money for the parties. He explains: ‘Incumbents who were not raising money for themselves because they were not up for reelection would sometimes raise money for other Sena tors, or for challengers. They would send $20,000 to the DSCC and ask that it be entered on another candidate’s tally. They might do this, for example, if they were plan ning to run for a leadership position and wanted to obtain support from the Senators they assisted. This would personally benefit them, in addition to doing their part to help retain Democratic control of the Senate, which would preserve the legislative power of all Democratic senators.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at475–476 (quoting Hickmott Decl., Exh. A ¶18). Judicial Finding of Fact: “The DSCC maintains a ‘credit’ 34 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Appendix A to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting program that credits nonfederal money raised by a Sena tor or candidate to that Senator or candidate’s state party. Amounts credited to a state party can reflect that the Senator or candidate solicited the donation, or can serve as a donor’s sign of tacit support for the state party or the Senate candidate.”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 477(cita tion omitted). Judicial Finding of Fact: “Federal candidates also raise nonfederal money through joint fundraising committees formed with national committees. One common method of joint fundraising is for a national congressional committee to form a separate joint fundraising committee with a federal candidate committee. . . . Two experts characterize the joint fundraising system as one ‘in which Senate can didates in effect raise[ ] soft money for use in their own races.’ ” Id., at 478 (quoting J. Krasno and F. Sorauf Ex pert Report, p. 13; citation omitted). Donor Access and Influence Judicial Finding of Fact: “The fact that Members of Con gress are intimately involved in the raising of money for the political parties, particularly unlimited nonfederal money donations, creates opportunities for corruption. The record does not contain any evidence of bribery or vote buying in exchange for donations of nonfederal money; however, the evidence presented in this case convincingly demonstrates that large contributions, particularly those nonfederal contributions surpassing the federal limits, provide donors access to federal lawmakers which is a critical ingredient for influencing legislation, and which the Supreme Court has determined constitutes corrup tion.”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 481. Judicial Finding of Fact: “Individual donors testify that Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 35 Appendix A to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting contributions provide access to influence federal office holders on issue of concern to them.” Id., at 498. Political donor: “ ‘I’ve been involved in political fundraising long enough to remember when soft money had little value to federal candidates. . . . [I]n recent election cycles, Members and national committees have asked soft money donors to write soft money checks to state and national parties solely in order to assist federal campaigns. Most soft money donors don’t ask and don’t care why the money is going to a particular state party, a party with which they may have no connection. What matters is that the donor has done what the Member asked.’ ” Id., at 472 (quoting Wade Randlett, Chief Executive Officer, Dash board Technology, Decl. ¶¶6–9). Political donor: “ ‘As a result of my $500,000 soft money donation to the DNC, I was offered the chance to at- tend events with the President, including events at the White House, a number of times. I was offered special ac cess. . . .’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 499(quoting Arnold Hiatt Decl. ¶9). Senator Alan Simpson: “ ‘Too often, Members’ first thought is not what is right or wrong or what they believe, but how will it affect fundraising. Who, after all, can seriously contend that a $100,000 donation does not alter the way one thinks about—and quite possibly votes on—an issue? . . . When you don’t pay the piper that finances your cam paigns, you will never get any more money from that piper. Since money is the mother’s milk of politics, you never want to be in that situation.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 481(quoting Simpson Decl. ¶10). Senator Alan Simpson: “ ‘Large donors of both hard and soft money receive special treatment. No matter how busy 36 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Appendix A to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting a politician may be during the day, he or she will always make time to see donors who gave large amounts of money. Staffers who work for Members know who the big donors are, and those people always get their phone calls returned first and are allowed to see the Member when others are not.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at481–482 (quoting Simpson Decl. ¶9). Senator David Boren: “ ‘Donations, including soft money donations to political parties, do affect how Congress operates. It’s only natural, and happens all too often, that a busy Senator with 10 minutes to spare will spend those minutes returning the call of a large soft money donor rather than the call of any other constituent. . . . I know from my first-hand experience and from my interactions with other Senators that they did feel beholden to large donors.”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 482(quoting Boren Decl. ¶¶7–8). Senator Dale Bumpers: “[Senator Bumpers] had ‘heard that some Members even keep lists of big donors in their offices,’ and [stated] that ‘you cannot be a good Democratic or good Republican Member and not be aware of who gave money to the party.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 487(quoting Bumpers Decl. ¶¶18, 20). Representative Christopher Shays: “ ‘The candidates know who makes these huge contributions and what these donors expect. Candidates not only solicit these funds themselves, they meet with big donors who have im portant issues pending before the government; and some times, the candidates’ or the party’s position appear to change after such meetings.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 487(quoting 148 Cong Rec. 1305 (2002)). Senator Warren Rudman: “ ‘Large soft money contri Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 37 Appendix A to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting butions in fact distort the legislative process. They affect what gets done and how it gets done. They affect whom Senators and House members see, whom they spend their time with, what input they get . . . .’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 496(quoting Rudman Decl. ¶¶7, 9). Senator Paul Simon: “ ‘While I realize some argue donors don’t buy favors, they buy access. That access is the abuse and it affects all of us. . . . You feel a sense of gratitude for their support. . . . Because few people can afford to give over $20,000 or $25,000 to a party committee, those people who can will receive substantially better access to elected federal leaders than people who can only afford smaller contributions or can not afford to make any contributions. When you increase the amount that people are allowed to give, or let people give without limit to the parties, you increase the danger of unfair access.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 496(quoting Simon Decl. ¶16). Senator John McCain: “ ‘At a minimum, large soft money donations purchase an opportunity for the donors to make their case to elected officials . . . in a way average citizens cannot.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 496(quoting McCain Decl. ¶6). Senator Warren Rudman: “ ‘I understand that those who opposed passage of the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act, and those who now challenge its constitutionality in Court, dare elected officials to point to specific [instances of vote buying]. I think this misses the point altogether. [The access and influence accorded large donors] is inher ently, endemically, and hopelessly corrupting. You can’t swim in the ocean without getting wet; you can’t be part of this system without getting dirty.’ ”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 481(quoting Rudman Decl. ¶10). 38 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Appendix A to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting Judicial Finding of Fact: “Lobbyists state that their clients make donations to political parties to achieve access.”
251 F. Supp. 2d, at 489. Letter from Republican National Committee (RNC) staffer: “ ‘As you know, [this executive] has been very generous to the RNC. If there is any way you can assist [in obtain ing an appointment with an important Senator], it would be greatly appreciated.’ ” Id., at 501 (quoting Memoran dum from Tim Barnes, RNC, to Royal Roth). Letter from RNC: “[The] letter from RNC to Senator Hagel staffer [asks] Senator Hagel to meet with a donor for four ‘key’ reasons including: . . . ‘[h]e just contributed $100,000 to the RNC.’ ” Ibid. (quoting a letter in the judicial record). Judicial Finding of Fact: “The political parties have struc tured their donation programs so that donors are encour aged to contribute larger amounts in order to get access to more exclusive and intimate events at which Members or Congress are present. The evidence also shows that the parties use the enticement of access to secure larger dona tions. ” Id., at 502 (quoting a document in the judicial record). Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 39 Appendix B to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting B Table 1: Donations to Support the Party Base Total Contri- Limit Number Years butions (per 2- (per (committees) year cycle) year) National Party Committees $32,400 3 2 $194,400 State Party Committees $10,000 50 2 $1,000,000 Total $1,194,400 Source: See 2 U. S. C. §§441a(a)(1)(B), (D);
78 Fed. Reg. 8532. Table 2(a): The $3.6 Million Check Total Base Number Years Contribu- Limit (committees/ or Elec- tions (per year/ candidates) tions (per 2-year election) cycle) National Party Com mittees $32,400 3 2 $194,400 State Party Committees $10,000 50 2 $1,000,000 Candidates (Senate) $2,600 33 2 $171,600 Candidates (House) $2,600 435 2 $2,262,000 Total $3,628,000 Source: See 2 U. S. C. §§441a(a)(1)(A), (B), (D);
78 Fed. Reg. 8532. 40 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Appendix B to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting Table 2(b): Circumvention of the $3.6 Million Check Direct Total Contribu- Direct Number tions to Elec- Contribu- (committees/ Candidate tions tions (per candidates) (per 2-year election) cycle) National Party Committees $5,000 3 2 $30,0001 State Party Committees $5,000 50 2 $500,000 Candidates (Senate) $2,000 33 2 $132,000 Candidates (House) $2,000 435 2 $1,740,000 Total Direct Contributions $2,372,000 Total IEs Independent Expendi- Elec- (per tures (IEs) tions general (per general election) election) House Senate Candidate Candidate $46,600– National Party $46,600 $94,100 $93,100 Committees (min)2 (min)3 1 (min) $46,600– State Party $46,600 $94,100 $93,100 Committees (min)2 (min)3 1 (min) $46,600– $46,600 $94,100 $93,100 Total IEs (min)2 (min)3 (min) 1 $45,400 for a Senate candidate. §441a(h);
78 Fed. Reg. 8532. 2 If the State has more than one House seat, this figure is $46,600. If it has one House seat, this figure is $93,100. Id., at 8531. 3 This figure ranges from $93,100 (Del.) to $2,68 million (Cal.), depending on the State’s population. Ibid. Source: See
2 U. S. C. §§432(e)(3)(B), 441a(a)(2)(A);
11 CFR §110.3(b);
78 Fed. Reg. 8530–8532. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 41 Appendix B to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting Table 3: Proliferating PACs Total Contribu- Base Limit Number Years tions (per year) (PACs) (per 2-year cycle) Rich Donor One $5,000 200 2 $2,000,000 Rich Donor Two $5,000 200 2 $2,000,000 Rich Donor Three $5,000 200 2 $2,000,000 Rich Donor Four $5,000 200 2 $2,000,000 Rich Donor Five $5,000 200 2 $2,000,000 Rich Donor Six $5,000 200 2 $2,000,000 Rich Donor Seven $5,000 200 2 $2,000,000 Rich Donor Eight $5,000 200 2 $2,000,000 Rich Donor Nine $5,000 200 2 $2,000,000 Rich Donor Ten $5,000 200 2 $2,000,000 Total Contribu- tions to PACs (by 10 Donors) $20,000,000 Total Contribu- tions by Each Donor $2,000,000 Base Limit Number Elec- (per (candi- tions election) dates) PAC One $5,000 10 2 $100,000 PAC Two $5,000 10 2 $100,000 PAC Three $5,000 10 2 $100,000 ... etc. etc. etc. etc. PAC 200 $5,000 10 2 $100,000 Total Contribu- tions by PACs (to 10 Candi- dates) $20,000,000 Total Contribu- tions to Each Candidate $2,000,000 Source: 2 U. S. C. §§441a(a)(1)(C), 441a(a)(2)(A). 42 MCCUTCHEON v. FEDERAL ELECTION COMM’N Appendix C to ,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting C Table 1: Costs of a Federal Seat 2012 Elections House Average House Winner Spent $1,567,293 Average House Loser Spent $496,637 Average Winner's Receipts from PACs $665,728 Senate Average Senate Winner Spent $11,474,077 Average Senate Loser Spent $7,435,446 Average Winner's Receipts from PACs $2,185,650 Source: Center for Responsive Politics, Election Stats, online at http://www.opensecrets.org/bigpicture/elec_stats.php. Table 2: Leadership PACs Number of Leadership PACs Total Contributed (contributing to federal (to federal candidates) candidates) 2000 Elections 175 $17,000,000 2002 Elections 228 $25,000,000 2004 Elections 274 $30,700,000 2006 Elections 336 $44,700,000 2008 Elections 378 $40,600,000 2010 Elections 396 $44,000,000 2012 Elections 456 $46,400,000 Source: Center for Responsive Politics, Leadership PACs, online at http://www.opensecrets.org/pacs. Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014) 43 Appendix C to,opinion of BREYER, J. BREYER J., dissenting Table 3: Joint Fundraising Committees Number of Joint “Senate” “House” Fundraising Related Related Committees 2008 Elections 269 31 34 2010 Elections 367 37 60 2012 Elections 508 67 89 Source: Federal Election Commission, online at http://www.fec.gov/data/CommitteeSummary.do.
Document Info
Docket Number: 12–536.
Citation Numbers: 188 L. Ed. 2d 468, 134 S. Ct. 1434, 2014 U.S. LEXIS 2391, 82 U.S.L.W. 4217, 572 U.S. 185, 24 Fla. L. Weekly Fed. S 639, 2014 WL 1301866
Filed Date: 4/2/2014
Precedential Status: Precedential
Modified Date: 10/19/2024