Schuette v. Coal. to Defend Affirmative Action , 134 S. Ct. 1623 ( 2014 )


Menu:
  • (Slip Opinion)              OCTOBER TERM, 2013                                       1
    Syllabus
    NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is
    being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued.
    The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been
    prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader.
    See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 
    200 U.S. 321
    , 337.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    Syllabus
    SCHUETTE, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MICHIGAN v.
    COALITION TO DEFEND AFFIRMATIVE ACTION,
    INTEGRATION AND IMMIGRATION RIGHTS AND
    FIGHT FOR EQUALITY BY ANY MEANS NECESSARY
    (BAMN) ET AL.
    CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR
    THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    No. 12–682.      Argued October 15, 2013—Decided April 22, 2014
    After this Court decided that the University of Michigan’s undergradu-
    ate admissions plan’s use of race-based preferences violated the
    Equal Protection Clause, Gratz v. Bollinger, 
    539 U.S. 244
    , 270, but
    that the law school admission plan’s more limited use did not, Grutter
    v. Bollinger, 
    539 U.S. 306
    , 343, Michigan voters adopted Proposal 2,
    now Art. I, §26, of the State Constitution, which, as relevant here,
    prohibits the use of race-based preferences as part of the admissions
    process for state universities. In consolidated challenges, the District
    Court granted summary judgment to Michigan, thus upholding Pro-
    posal 2, but the Sixth Circuit reversed, concluding that the proposal
    violated the principles of Washington v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1,
    
    458 U.S. 457
    .
    Held: The judgment is reversed.
    
    701 F.3d 466
    , reversed.
    JUSTICE KENNEDY, joined by THE CHIEF JUSTICE and JUSTICE ALITO,
    concluded that there is no authority in the Federal Constitution or in
    this Court’s precedents for the Judiciary to set aside Michigan laws
    that commit to the voters the determination whether racial prefer-
    ences may be considered in governmental decisions, in particular
    with respect to school admissions. Pp. 4–18.
    (a) This case is not about the constitutionality, or the merits, of
    race-conscious admissions policies in higher education. Here, the
    principle that the consideration of race in admissions is permissible
    2                          SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Syllabus
    when certain conditions are met is not being challenged. Rather, the
    question concerns whether, and in what manner, voters in the States
    may choose to prohibit the consideration of such racial preferences.
    Where States have prohibited race-conscious admissions policies,
    universities have responded by experimenting “with a wide variety of
    alternative approaches.” 
    Grutter, supra, at 342
    . The decision by
    Michigan voters reflects the ongoing national dialogue about such
    practices. Pp. 4–5.
    (b) The Sixth Circuit’s determination that Seattle controlled here
    extends Seattle’s holding in a case presenting quite different issues to
    reach a mistaken conclusion. Pp. 5–18.
    (1) It is necessary to consider first the relevant cases preceding
    Seattle and the background against which Seattle arose. Both Reit­
    man v. Mulkey, 
    387 U.S. 369
    , and Hunter v. Erickson, 
    393 U.S. 385
    ,
    involved demonstrated injuries on the basis of race that, by reasons
    of state encouragement or participation, became more aggravated. In
    Mulkey, a voter-enacted amendment to the California Constitution
    prohibiting state legislative interference with an owner’s prerogative
    to decline to sell or rent residential property on any basis barred the
    challenging parties, on account of race, from invoking the protection
    of California’s statutes, thus preventing them from leasing residen-
    tial property. In Hunter, voters overturned an Akron ordinance that
    was enacted to address widespread racial discrimination in housing
    sales and rentals had forced many to live in “ ‘unhealthful, unsafe,
    unsanitary and overcrowded’ ” segregated 
    housing, 393 U.S., at 391
    .
    In Seattle, after the school board adopted a mandatory busing pro-
    gram to alleviate racial isolation of minority students in local schools,
    voters passed a state initiative that barred busing to desegregate.
    This Court found that the state initiative had the “practical effect” of
    removing “the authority to address a racial problem . . . from the ex-
    isting decisionmaking body, in such a way as to burden minority in-
    terests” of busing advocates who must now “seek relief from the state
    legislature, or from the statewide 
    electorate.” 458 U.S., at 474
    .
    Pp. 5–8.
    (2) Seattle is best understood as a case in which the state action
    had the serious risk, if not purpose, of causing specific injuries on ac-
    count of race as had been the case in Mulkey and Hunter. While
    there had been no judicial finding of de jure segregation with respect
    to Seattle’s school district, a finding that would be required today, see
    Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1,
    
    551 U.S. 701
    , 720–721, Seattle must be understood as Seattle under-
    stood itself, as a case in which neither the State nor the United
    States “challenge[d] the propriety of race-conscious student assign-
    ments for the purpose of achieving integration, even absent a finding
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)                      3
    Syllabus
    of prior de jure 
    segregation.” 458 U.S. at 472
    , n. 15.
    Seattle’s broad language, however, went well beyond the analysis
    needed to resolve the case. Seizing upon the statement in Justice
    Harlan’s concurrence in Hunter that the procedural change in that
    case had “the clear purpose of making it more difficult for certain ra-
    cial and religious minorities to achieve legislation that is in their in-
    
    terest,” 385 U.S., at 395
    , the Seattle Court established a new and far-
    reaching rationale: Where a government policy “inures primarily to
    the benefit of the minority” and “minorities . . . consider” the policy to
    be “ ‘in their interest,’ ” then any state action that “place[s] effective
    decisionmaking authority over” that policy “at a different level of
    government” is subject to strict 
    scrutiny. 458 U.S., at 472
    , 474.
    Pp. 8–11.
    (3) To the extent Seattle is read to require the Court to determine
    and declare which political policies serve the “interest” of a group de-
    fined in racial terms, that rationale was unnecessary to the decision
    in Seattle; it has no support in precedent; and it raises serious equal
    protection concerns. In cautioning against “impermissible racial ste-
    reotypes,” this Court has rejected the assumption that all individuals
    of the same race think alike, see Shaw v. Reno, 
    509 U.S. 630
    , 647,
    but that proposition would be a necessary beginning point were the
    Seattle formulation to control. And if it were deemed necessary to
    probe how some races define their own interest in political matters,
    still another beginning point would be to define individuals according
    to race. Such a venture would be undertaken with no clear legal
    standards or accepted sources to guide judicial decision. It would al-
    so result in, or impose a high risk of, inquiries and categories de-
    pendent upon demeaning stereotypes, classifications of questionable
    constitutionality on their own terms. Assuming these steps could be
    taken, the court would next be required to determine the policy
    realms in which groups defined by race had a political interest. That
    undertaking, again without guidance from accepted legal standards,
    would risk the creation of incentives for those who support or oppose
    certain policies to cast the debate in terms of racial advantage or dis-
    advantage. Adoption of the Seattle formulation could affect any
    number of laws or decisions, involving, e.g., tax policy or housing sub-
    sidies. And racial division would be validated, not discouraged.
    It can be argued that objections to the larger consequences of the
    Seattle formulation need not be confronted here, for race was an un-
    doubted subject of the ballot issue. But other problems raised by Se­
    attle, such as racial definitions, still apply. And the principal flaw in
    the Sixth Circuit’s decision remains: Here there was no infliction of a
    specific injury of the kind at issue in Mulkey and Hunter and in the
    history of the Seattle schools, and there is no precedent for extending
    4                          SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Syllabus
    these cases to restrict the right of Michigan voters to determine that
    race-based preferences granted by state entities should be ended.
    The Sixth Circuit’s judgment also calls into question other States’
    long-settled rulings on policies similar to Michigan’s.
    Unlike the injuries in Mulkey, Hunter, and Seattle, the question
    here is not how to address or prevent injury caused on account of race
    but whether voters may determine whether a policy of race-based
    preferences should be continued. By approving Proposal 2 and there-
    by adding §26 to their State Constitution, Michigan voters exercised
    their privilege to enact laws as a basic exercise of their democratic
    power, bypassing public officials they deemed not responsive to their
    concerns about a policy of granting race-based preferences. The
    mandate for segregated schools, Brown v. Board of Education, 
    347 U.S. 483
    , and scores of other examples teach that individual liberty
    has constitutional protection. But this Nation’s constitutional system
    also embraces the right of citizens to speak and debate and learn and
    then, as a matter of political will, to act through a lawful electoral
    process, as Michigan voters have done here. These precepts are not
    inconsistent with the well-established principle that when hurt or in-
    jury is inflicted on racial minorities by the encouragement or com-
    mand of laws or other state action, the Constitution requires redress
    by the courts. Such circumstances were present in Mulkey, Hunter,
    and Seattle, but they are not present here. Pp. 11–18.
    JUSTICE SCALIA, joined by JUSTICE THOMAS, agreed that §26 rightly
    stands, though not because it passes muster under the political-
    process doctrine. It likely does not, but the cases establishing that
    doctrine should be overruled. They are patently atextual, unadmin-
    istrable, and contrary to this Court’s traditional equal protection ju-
    risprudence. The question here, as in every case in which neutral
    state action is said to deny equal protection on account of race, is
    whether the challenged action reflects a racially discriminatory pur-
    pose. It plainly does not. Pp. 1–18.
    (a) The Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit held §26 unconstitu-
    tional under the so-called political-process doctrine, derived from
    Washington v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 
    458 U.S. 457
    , and Hunter v.
    Erickson, 
    393 U.S. 385
    . In those cases, one level of government ex-
    ercised borrowed authority over an apparently “racial issue” until a
    higher level of government called the loan. This Court deemed each
    revocation an equal-protection violation, without regard to whether
    there was evidence of an invidious purpose to discriminate. The re-
    lentless, radical logic of Hunter and Seattle would point to a similar
    conclusion here, as in so many other cases. Pp. 3–7.
    (b) The problems with the political-process doctrine begin with its
    triggering prong, which assigns to a court the task of determining
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)                      5
    Syllabus
    whether a law that reallocates policymaking authority concerns a
    “racial issue,” 
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 473
    , i.e., whether adopting one
    position on the question would “at bottom inur[e] primarily to the
    benefit of the minority, and is designed for that purpose,” 
    id., at 472.
    Such freeform judicial musing into ethnic and racial “interests” in-
    volves judges in the dirty business of dividing the Nation “into racial
    blocs,” Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v. FCC, 
    497 U.S. 547
    , 603, 610
    (O’Connor, J., dissenting), and promotes racial stereotyping, see
    Shaw v. Reno, 
    509 U.S. 630
    , 647. More fundamentally, the analysis
    misreads the Equal Protection Clause to protect particular groups, a
    construction that has been repudiated in a “long line of cases under-
    standing equal protection as a personal right.” Adarand Construc­
    tors, Inc. v. Peña, 
    515 U.S. 200
    , 224, 230. Pp. 7–12.
    (c) The second part of the Hunter-Seattle analysis directs a court to
    determine whether the challenged act “place[s] effective decisionmak-
    ing authority over [the] racial issue at a different level of govern-
    ment,” 
    Seattle, supra, at 474
    ; but, in another line of cases, the Court
    has emphasized the near-limitless sovereignty of each State to design
    its governing structure as it sees fit, see, e.g., Holt Civic Club v. Tus­
    caloosa, 
    439 U.S. 60
    , 71. Taken to the limits of its logic, Hunter-
    Seattle is the gaping exception that nearly swallows the rule of struc-
    tural state sovereignty, which would seem to permit a State to give
    certain powers to cities, later assign the same powers to counties, and
    even reclaim them for itself. Pp. 12–15.
    (d) Hunter and Seattle also endorse a version of the proposition
    that a facially neutral law may deny equal protection solely because
    it has a disparate racial impact. That equal-protection theory has
    been squarely and soundly rejected by an “unwavering line of cases”
    holding “that a violation of the Equal Protection Clause requires
    state action motivated by discriminatory intent,” Hernandez v. New
    York, 
    500 U.S. 352
    , 372–373 (O’Connor, J., concurring in judgment),
    and that “official action will not be held unconstitutional solely be-
    cause it results in a racially disproportionate impact,” Arlington
    Heights v. Metropolitan Housing Development Corp., 
    429 U.S. 252
    ,
    264–265. Respondents cannot prove that the action here reflects a
    racially discriminatory purpose, for any law expressly requiring state
    actors to afford all persons equal protection of the laws does not—
    cannot—deny “to any person . . . equal protection of the laws,” U. S.
    Const., Amdt. 14, §1. Pp. 15–17.
    JUSTICE BREYER agreed that the amendment is consistent with the
    Equal Protection Clause, but for different reasons. First, this case
    addresses the amendment only as it applies to, and forbids, race-
    conscious admissions programs that consider race solely in order to
    obtain the educational benefits of a diverse student body. Second, the
    6                          SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Syllabus
    Constitution permits, but does not require, the use of the kind of
    race-conscious programs now barred by the Michigan Constitution.
    It foresees the ballot box, not the courts, as the normal instrument
    for resolving debates about the merits of these programs. Third,
    Hunter v. Erickson, 
    393 U.S. 385
    , and Washington v. Seattle School
    Dist. No. 1, 
    458 U.S. 457
    , which reflect the important principle that
    an individual’s ability to participate meaningfully in the political pro-
    cess should be independent of his race, do not apply here. Those cas-
    es involved a restructuring of the political process that changed the
    political level at which policies were enacted, while this case involves
    an amendment that took decisionmaking authority away from une-
    lected actors and placed it in the hands of the voters. Hence, this
    case does not involve a diminution of the minority’s ability to partici-
    pate in the political process. Extending the holding of Hunter and
    Seattle to situations where decisionmaking authority is moved from
    an administrative body to a political one would also create significant
    difficulties, given the nature of the administrative process. Further-
    more, the principle underlying Hunter and Seattle runs up against a
    competing principle favoring decisionmaking through the democratic
    process. Pp. 1–6.
    KENNEDY, J., announced the judgment of the Court and delivered an
    opinion, in which ROBERTS, C. J., and ALITO, J., joined. ROBERTS, C. J.,
    filed a concurring opinion. SCALIA, J., filed an opinion concurring in the
    judgment, in which THOMAS, J., joined. BREYER, J., filed an opinion
    concurring in the judgment. SOTOMAYOR, J., filed a dissenting opinion,
    in which GINSBURG, J., joined. KAGAN, J., took no part in the considera-
    tion or decision of the case.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)                              1
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the
    preliminary print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested to
    notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Wash-
    ington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order
    that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 12–682
    _________________
    BILL SCHUETTE, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MICHI-
    GAN, PETITIONER v. COALITION TO DEFEND AF-
    FIRMATIVE ACTION, INTEGRATION AND IMMI-
    GRANT RIGHTS AND FIGHT FOR EQUALITY
    BY ANY MEANS NECESSARY (BAMN), ET AL.
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    [April 22, 2014]
    JUSTICE KENNEDY announced the judgment of the Court
    and delivered an opinion, in which THE CHIEF JUSTICE
    and JUSTICE ALITO join.
    The Court in this case must determine whether an
    amendment to the Constitution of the State of Michigan,
    approved and enacted by its voters, is invalid under the
    Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to
    the Constitution of the United States.
    In 2003 the Court reviewed the constitutionality of two
    admissions systems at the University of Michigan, one for
    its undergraduate class and one for its law school. The
    undergraduate admissions plan was addressed in Gratz v.
    Bollinger, 
    539 U.S. 244
    . The law school admission plan
    was addressed in Grutter v. Bollinger, 
    539 U.S. 306
    . Each
    admissions process permitted the explicit consideration of
    an applicant’s race. In Gratz, the Court invalidated the
    undergraduate plan as a violation of the Equal Protection
    
    Clause. 539 U.S., at 270
    . In Grutter, the Court found no
    2                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    constitutional flaw in the law school admission plan’s
    more limited use of race-based 
    preferences. 539 U.S., at 343
    .
    In response to the Court’s decision in Gratz, the univer-
    sity revised its undergraduate admissions process, but the
    revision still allowed limited use of race-based preferences.
    After a statewide debate on the question of racial prefer-
    ences in the context of governmental decisionmaking, the
    voters, in 2006, adopted an amendment to the State Con-
    stitution prohibiting state and other governmental entities
    in Michigan from granting certain preferences, including
    race-based preferences, in a wide range of actions and
    decisions. Under the terms of the amendment, race-based
    preferences cannot be part of the admissions process for
    state universities. That particular prohibition is central to
    the instant case.
    The ballot proposal was called Proposal 2 and, after it
    passed by a margin of 58 percent to 42 percent, the result-
    ing enactment became Article I, §26, of the Michigan
    Constitution. As noted, the amendment is in broad terms.
    Section 26 states, in relevant part, as follows:
    “(1) The University of Michigan, Michigan State
    University, Wayne State University, and any other
    public college or university, community college, or
    school district shall not discriminate against, or grant
    preferential treatment to, any individual or group on
    the basis of race, sex, color, ethnicity, or national
    origin in the operation of public employment, public
    education, or public contracting.
    “(2) The state shall not discriminate against, or
    grant preferential treatment to, any individual or
    group on the basis of race, sex, color, ethnicity, or na-
    tional origin in the operation of public employment,
    public education, or public contracting.
    “(3) For the purposes of this section ‘state’ includes,
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)             3
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    but is not necessarily limited to, the state itself, any
    city, county, any public college, university, or commu-
    nity college, school district, or other political subdivi-
    sion or governmental instrumentality of or within the
    State of Michigan not included in sub-section 1.”
    Section 26 was challenged in two cases. Among the
    plaintiffs in the suits were the Coalition to Defend Affirm-
    ative Action, Integration and Immigrant Rights and Fight
    for Equality By Any Means Necessary (BAMN); students;
    faculty; and prospective applicants to Michigan public
    universities.     The named defendants included then-
    Governor Jennifer Granholm, the Board of Regents of the
    University of Michigan, the Board of Trustees of Michigan
    State University, and the Board of Governors of Wayne
    State University. The Michigan Attorney General was
    granted leave to intervene as a defendant. The United
    States District Court for the Eastern District of Michigan
    consolidated the cases.
    In 2008, the District Court granted summary judgment
    to Michigan, thus upholding Proposal 2. BAMN v. Regents
    of Univ. of Mich., 
    539 F. Supp. 2d 924
    . The District Court
    denied a motion to reconsider the grant of summary judg-
    ment. 
    592 F. Supp. 2d 948
    . A panel of the United States
    Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit reversed the grant
    of summary judgment. 
    652 F.3d 607
    (2011). Judge Gib-
    bons dissented from that holding. 
    Id., at 633–646.
    The
    panel majority held that Proposal 2 had violated the prin-
    ciples elaborated by this Court in Washington v. Seattle
    School Dist. No. 1, 
    458 U.S. 457
    (1982), and in the cases
    that Seattle relied upon.
    The Court of Appeals, sitting en banc, agreed with the
    panel decision. 
    701 F.3d 466
    (CA6 2012). The majority
    opinion determined that Seattle “mirrors the [case] before
    us.” 
    Id., at 475.
    Seven judges dissented in a number of
    opinions. The Court granted certiorari. 568 U. S. ___
    4                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    (2013).
    Before the Court addresses the question presented, it is
    important to note what this case is not about. It is not
    about the constitutionality, or the merits, of race-conscious
    admissions policies in higher education. The considera-
    tion of race in admissions presents complex questions, in
    part addressed last Term in Fisher v. University of Texas
    at Austin, 570 U. S. ––– (2013). In Fisher, the Court did
    not disturb the principle that the consideration of race in
    admissions is permissible, provided that certain conditions
    are met. In this case, as in Fisher, that principle is not
    challenged. The question here concerns not the permissi-
    bility of race-conscious admissions policies under the
    Constitution but whether, and in what manner, voters in
    the States may choose to prohibit the consideration of
    racial preferences in governmental decisions, in particular
    with respect to school admissions.
    This Court has noted that some States have decided to
    prohibit race-conscious admissions policies. In Grutter,
    the Court noted: “Universities in California, Florida, and
    Washington State, where racial preferences in admissions
    are prohibited by state law, are currently engaged in
    experimenting with a wide variety of alternative ap-
    proaches. Universities in other States can and should
    draw on the most promising aspects of these race-neutral
    alternatives as they 
    develop.” 539 U.S., at 342
    (citing
    United States v. Lopez, 
    514 U.S. 549
    , 581 (1995)
    (KENNEDY, J., concurring) (“[T]he States may perform
    their role as laboratories for experimentation to devise
    various solutions where the best solution is far from
    clear”)). In this way, Grutter acknowledged the signifi-
    cance of a dialogue regarding this contested and complex
    policy question among and within States. There was
    recognition that our federal structure “permits ‘ innovation
    and experimentation’ ” and “enables greater citizen ‘ in-
    volvement in democratic processes.’ ” Bond v. United
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)            5
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    States, 564 U. S. –––, ––– (2011) (slip op., at 9) (quoting
    Gregory v. Ashcroft, 
    501 U.S. 452
    , 458 (1991)). While this
    case arises in Michigan, the decision by the State’s voters
    reflects in part the national dialogue regarding the wis-
    dom and practicality of race-conscious admissions policies
    in higher education. See, e.g., Coalition for Economic
    Equity v. Wilson, 
    122 F.3d 692
    (CA9 1997).
    In Michigan, the State Constitution invests independent
    boards of trustees with plenary authority over public
    universities, including admissions policies. Mich. Const.,
    Art. VIII, §5; see also Federated Publications, Inc. v. Board
    of Trustees of Mich. State Univ., 
    460 Mich. 75
    , 86–87, 
    594 N.W.2d 491
    , 497 (1999). Although the members of the
    boards are elected, some evidence in the record suggests
    they delegated authority over admissions policy to the
    faculty. But whether the boards or the faculty set the
    specific policy, Michigan’s public universities did consider
    race as a factor in admissions decisions before 2006.
    In holding §26 invalid in the context of student admis-
    sions at state universities, the Court of Appeals relied in
    primary part on 
    Seattle, supra
    , which it deemed to control
    the case. But that determination extends Seattle’s holding
    in a case presenting quite different issues to reach a con-
    clusion that is mistaken here. Before explaining this
    further, it is necessary to consider the relevant cases that
    preceded Seattle and the background against which Seat-
    tle itself arose.
    Though it has not been prominent in the arguments of
    the parties, this Court’s decision in Reitman v. Mulkey,
    
    387 U.S. 369
    (1967), is a proper beginning point for dis-
    cussing the controlling decisions.       In Mulkey, voters
    amended the California Constitution to prohibit any state
    legislative interference with an owner’s prerogative to
    decline to sell or rent residential property on any basis.
    Two different cases gave rise to Mulkey. In one a couple
    could not rent an apartment, and in the other a couple
    6                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    were evicted from their apartment. Those adverse actions
    were on account of race. In both cases the complaining
    parties were barred, on account of race, from invoking the
    protection of California’s statutes; and, as a result, they
    were unable to lease residential property. This Court
    concluded that the state constitutional provision was a
    denial of equal protection. The Court agreed with the
    California Supreme Court that the amendment operated
    to insinuate the State into the decision to discriminate by
    encouraging that practice. The Court noted the “immedi-
    ate design and intent” of the amendment was to “estab-
    lis[h] a purported constitutional right to privately discrim-
    inate.” 
    Id., at 374
    (internal quotation marks omitted and
    emphasis deleted). The Court agreed that the amendment
    “expressly authorized and constitutionalized the private
    right to discriminate.” 
    Id., at 376.
    The effect of the state
    constitutional amendment was to “significantly encourage
    and involve the State in private racial discriminations.”
    
    Id., at 381.
    In a dissent joined by three other Justices,
    Justice Harlan disagreed with the majority’s holding. 
    Id., at 387.
    The dissent reasoned that California, by the action
    of its voters, simply wanted the State to remain neutral in
    this area, so that the State was not a party to discrimina-
    tion. 
    Id., at 389.
    That dissenting voice did not prevail
    against the majority’s conclusion that the state action in
    question encouraged discrimination, causing real and
    specific injury.
    The next precedent of relevance, Hunter v. Erickson, 
    393 U.S. 385
    (1969), is central to the arguments the respond-
    ents make in the instant case. In Hunter, the Court for
    the first time elaborated what the Court of Appeals here
    styled the “political process” doctrine. There, the Akron
    City Council found that the citizens of Akron consisted of
    “ ‘people of different race[s], . . . many of whom live in
    circumscribed and segregated areas, under sub-standard
    unhealthful, unsafe, unsanitary and overcrowded condi-
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)            7
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    tions, because of discrimination in the sale, lease, rental
    and financing of housing.’ ” 
    Id., at 391.
    To address the
    problem, Akron enacted a fair housing ordinance to pro-
    hibit that sort of discrimination. In response, voters
    amended the city charter to overturn the ordinance and to
    require that any additional antidiscrimination housing
    ordinance be approved by referendum. But most other
    ordinances “regulating the real property market” were not
    subject to those threshold requirements. 
    Id., at 390.
    The
    plaintiff, a black woman in Akron, Ohio, alleged that her
    real estate agent could not show her certain residences
    because the owners had specified they would not sell to
    black persons.
    Central to the Court’s reasoning in Hunter was that the
    charter amendment was enacted in circumstances where
    widespread racial discrimination in the sale and rental of
    housing led to segregated housing, forcing many to live in
    “ ‘unhealthful, unsafe, unsanitary and overcrowded condi-
    tions.’ ” 
    Id., at 391.
    The Court stated: “It is against this
    background that the referendum required by [the charter
    amendment] must be assessed.” 
    Ibid. Akron attempted to
    characterize the charter amendment “simply as a public
    decision to move slowly in the delicate area of race rela-
    tions” and as a means “to allow the people of Akron to
    participate” in the decision. 
    Id., at 392.
    The Court rejected
    Akron’s flawed “justifications for its discrimination,”
    justifications that by their own terms had the effect of
    acknowledging the targeted nature of the charter amend-
    ment. 
    Ibid. The Court noted,
    furthermore, that the char-
    ter amendment was unnecessary as a general means of
    public control over the city council; for the people of Akron
    already were empowered to overturn ordinances by refer-
    endum. 
    Id., at 390,
    n. 6. The Court found that the city
    charter amendment, by singling out antidiscrimination
    ordinances, “places special burden on racial minorities
    within the governmental process,” thus becoming as im-
    8                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    permissible as any other government action taken with
    the invidious intent to injure a racial minority. 
    Id., at 391.
    Justice Harlan filed a concurrence. He argued the city
    charter amendment “has the clear purpose of making it
    more difficult for certain racial and religious minorities to
    achieve legislation that is in their interest.” 
    Id., at 395.
    But without regard to the sentence just quoted, Hunter
    rests on the unremarkable principle that the State may
    not alter the procedures of government to target racial
    minorities. The facts in Hunter established that invidious
    discrimination would be the necessary result of the proce-
    dural restructuring. Thus, in Mulkey and Hunter, there
    was a demonstrated injury on the basis of race that, by
    reasons of state encouragement or participation, became
    more aggravated.
    Seattle is the third case of principal relevance here.
    There, the school board adopted a mandatory busing
    program to alleviate racial isolation of minority students
    in local schools. Voters who opposed the school board’s
    busing plan passed a state initiative that barred busing to
    desegregate. The Court first determined that, although
    “white as well as Negro children benefit from” diversity,
    the school board’s plan “inures primarily to the benefit of
    the 
    minority.” 458 U.S., at 472
    . The Court next found
    that “the practical effect” of the state initiative was to
    “remov[e] the authority to address a racial problem—and
    only a racial problem—from the existing decisionmaking
    body, in such a way as to burden minority interests” be-
    cause advocates of busing “now must seek relief from the
    state legislature, or from the statewide electorate.” 
    Id., at 474.
    The Court therefore found that the initiative had
    “explicitly us[ed] the racial nature of a decision to deter-
    mine the decisionmaking process.” 
    Id., at 470
    (emphasis
    deleted).
    Seattle is best understood as a case in which the state
    action in question (the bar on busing enacted by the
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)              9
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    State’s voters) had the serious risk, if not purpose, of
    causing specific injuries on account of race, just as had
    been the case in Mulkey and Hunter. Although there had
    been no judicial finding of de jure segregation with respect
    to Seattle’s school district, it appears as though school
    segregation in the district in the 1940’s and 1950’s may
    have been the partial result of school board policies that
    “permitted white students to transfer out of black schools
    while restricting the transfer of black students into white
    schools.” Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seat-
    tle School Dist. No. 1, 
    551 U.S. 701
    , 807–808 (2007)
    (BREYER, J., dissenting). In 1977, the National Associa-
    tion for the Advancement of Colored People (NAACP) filed
    a complaint with the Office for Civil Rights, a federal
    agency. The NAACP alleged that the school board had
    maintained a system of de jure segregation. Specifically,
    the complaint alleged “that the Seattle School Board had
    created or perpetuated unlawful racial segregation
    through, e.g., certain school-transfer criteria, a construc-
    tion program that needlessly built new schools in white
    areas, district line-drawing criteria, the maintenance of
    inferior facilities at black schools, the use of explicit racial
    criteria in the assignment of teachers and other staff, and
    a general pattern of delay in respect to the implementa-
    tion of promised desegregation efforts.” 
    Id., at 810.
    As
    part of a settlement with the Office for Civil Rights, the
    school board implemented the “Seattle Plan,” which used
    busing and mandatory reassignments between elementary
    schools to reduce racial imbalance and which was the
    subject of the state initiative at issue in Seattle. 
    See 551 U.S., at 807
    –812.
    As this Court held in Parents Involved, the school
    board’s purported remedial action would not be permissi-
    ble today absent a showing of de jure segregation. 
    Id., at 720–721.
    That holding prompted JUSTICE BREYER to
    observe in dissent, as noted above, that one permissible
    10                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    reading of the record was that the school board had main-
    tained policies to perpetuate racial segregation in the
    schools. In all events we must understand Seattle as
    Seattle understood itself, as a case in which neither the
    State nor the United States “challenge[d] the propriety of
    race-conscious student assignments for the purpose of
    achieving integration, even absent a finding of prior
    de jure 
    segregation.” 458 U.S. at 472
    , n. 15. In other
    words the legitimacy and constitutionality of the remedy
    in question (busing for desegregation) was assumed, and
    Seattle must be understood on that basis. 
    Ibid. Seattle involved a
    state initiative that “was carefully tailored to
    interfere only with desegregative busing.” 
    Id., at 471.
    The
    Seattle Court, accepting the validity of the school board’s
    busing remedy as a predicate to its analysis of the consti-
    tutional question, found that the State’s disapproval of the
    school board’s busing remedy was an aggravation of the
    very racial injury in which the State itself was complicit.
    The broad language used in Seattle, however, went well
    beyond the analysis needed to resolve the case. The Court
    there seized upon the statement in Justice Harlan’s con-
    currence in Hunter that the procedural change in that case
    had “the clear purpose of making it more difficult for
    certain racial and religious minorities to achieve legisla-
    tion that is in their 
    interest.” 385 U.S., at 395
    . That
    language, taken in the context of the facts in Hunter, is
    best read simply to describe the necessity for finding an
    equal protection violation where specific injuries from
    hostile discrimination were at issue. The Seattle Court,
    however, used the language from the Hunter concurrence
    to establish a new and far-reaching rationale. Seattle
    stated that where a government policy “inures primarily
    to the benefit of the minority” and “minorities . . . con-
    sider” the policy to be “ ‘in their interest,’ ” then any state
    action that “place[s] effective decisionmaking authority
    over” that policy “at a different level of government” must
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)             11
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    be reviewed under strict 
    scrutiny. 458 U.S., at 472
    , 474.
    In essence, according to the broad reading of Seattle, any
    state action with a “racial focus” that makes it “more
    difficult for certain racial minorities than for other groups”
    to “achieve legislation that is in their interest” is subject to
    strict scrutiny. It is this reading of Seattle that the Court
    of Appeals found to be controlling here. And that reading
    must be rejected.
    The broad rationale that the Court of Appeals adopted
    goes beyond the necessary holding and the meaning of the
    precedents said to support it; and in the instant case
    neither the formulation of the general rule just set forth
    nor the precedents cited to authenticate it suffice to inval-
    idate Proposal 2. The expansive reading of Seattle has no
    principled limitation and raises serious questions of com-
    patibility with the Court’s settled equal protection juris-
    prudence. To the extent Seattle is read to require the
    Court to determine and declare which political policies
    serve the “interest” of a group defined in racial terms, that
    rationale was unnecessary to the decision in Seattle; it has
    no support in precedent; and it raises serious constitu-
    tional concerns. That expansive language does not provide
    a proper guide for decisions and should not be deemed
    authoritative or controlling. The rule that the Court of
    Appeals elaborated and respondents seek to establish here
    would contradict central equal protection principles.
    In cautioning against “impermissible racial stereotypes,”
    this Court has rejected the assumption that “members of
    the same racial group—regardless of their age, education,
    economic status, or the community in which they live—
    think alike, share the same political interests, and will
    prefer the same candidates at the polls.” Shaw v. Reno,
    
    509 U.S. 630
    , 647 (1993); see also Metro Broadcasting,
    Inc. v. FCC, 
    497 U.S. 547
    , 636 (1990) (KENNEDY, J., dis-
    senting) (rejecting the “demeaning notion that members of
    . . . defined racial groups ascribe to certain ‘minority views’
    12                  SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    that must be different from those of other citizens”). It
    cannot be entertained as a serious proposition that all
    individuals of the same race think alike. Yet that proposi-
    tion would be a necessary beginning point were the Seattle
    formulation to control, as the Court of Appeals held it did
    in this case. And if it were deemed necessary to probe how
    some races define their own interest in political matters,
    still another beginning point would be to define individu-
    als according to race. But in a society in which those lines
    are becoming more blurred, the attempt to define race-
    based categories also raises serious questions of its own.
    Government action that classifies individuals on the basis
    of race is inherently suspect and carries the danger of
    perpetuating the very racial divisions the polity seeks to
    transcend. Cf. Ho v. San Francisco Unified School Dist.,
    
    147 F.3d 854
    , 858 (CA9 1998) (school district delineating
    13 racial categories for purposes of racial balancing).
    Were courts to embark upon this venture not only would it
    be undertaken with no clear legal standards or accepted
    sources to guide judicial decision but also it would result
    in, or at least impose a high risk of, inquiries and catego-
    ries dependent upon demeaning stereotypes, classifica-
    tions of questionable constitutionality on their own terms.
    Even assuming these initial steps could be taken in a
    manner consistent with a sound analytic and judicial
    framework, the court would next be required to determine
    the policy realms in which certain groups—groups defined
    by race—have a political interest. That undertaking,
    again without guidance from any accepted legal stand-
    ards, would risk, in turn, the creation of incentives for
    those who support or oppose certain policies to cast the
    debate in terms of racial advantage or disadvantage. Thus
    could racial antagonisms and conflict tend to arise in the
    context of judicial decisions as courts undertook to an-
    nounce what particular issues of public policy should be
    classified as advantageous to some group defined by race.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)           13
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    This risk is inherent in adopting the Seattle formulation.
    There would be no apparent limiting standards defining
    what public policies should be included in what Seattle
    called policies that “inur[e] primarily to the benefit of the
    minority” and that “minorities . . . consider” to be “ ‘in
    their interest.’ 
    458 U.S., at 472
    , 474. Those who seek to
    represent the interests of particular racial groups could
    attempt to advance those aims by demanding an equal
    protection ruling that any number of matters be foreclosed
    from voter review or participation. In a nation in which
    governmental policies are wide ranging, those who seek to
    limit voter participation might be tempted, were this
    Court to adopt the Seattle formulation, to urge that a
    group they choose to define by race or racial stereotypes
    are advantaged or disadvantaged by any number of laws
    or decisions. Tax policy, housing subsidies, wage regula-
    tions, and even the naming of public schools, highways,
    and monuments are just a few examples of what could
    become a list of subjects that some organizations could
    insist should be beyond the power of voters to decide, or
    beyond the power of a legislature to decide when enacting
    limits on the power of local authorities or other govern-
    mental entities to address certain subjects. Racial division
    would be validated, not discouraged, were the Seattle
    formulation, and the reasoning of the Court of Appeals in
    this case, to remain in force.
    Perhaps, when enacting policies as an exercise of demo-
    cratic self-government, voters will determine that race-
    based preferences should be adopted. The constitutional
    validity of some of those choices regarding racial prefer-
    ences is not at issue here. The holding in the instant case
    is simply that the courts may not disempower the voters
    from choosing which path to follow. In the realm of policy
    discussions the regular give-and-take of debate ought to be
    a context in which rancor or discord based on race are
    avoided, not invited. And if these factors are to be inter-
    14                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    jected, surely it ought not to be at the invitation or insist-
    ence of the courts.
    One response to these concerns may be that objections
    to the larger consequences of the Seattle formulation need
    not be confronted in this case, for here race was an un-
    doubted subject of the ballot issue. But a number of prob-
    lems raised by Seattle, such as racial definitions, still
    apply. And this principal flaw in the ruling of the Court of
    Appeals does remain: Here there was no infliction of a
    specific injury of the kind at issue in Mulkey and Hunter
    and in the history of the Seattle schools. Here there is no
    precedent for extending these cases to restrict the right of
    Michigan voters to determine that race-based preferences
    granted by Michigan governmental entities should be
    ended.
    It should also be noted that the judgment of the Court of
    Appeals in this case of necessity calls into question other
    long-settled rulings on similar state policies. The Califor-
    nia Supreme Court has held that a California constitu-
    tional amendment prohibiting racial preferences in public
    contracting does not violate the rule set down by Seattle.
    Coral Constr., Inc. v. City and County of San Francisco, 
    50 Cal. 4th 315
    , 
    235 P.3d 947
    (2010). The Court of Appeals
    for the Ninth Circuit has held that the same amendment,
    which also barred racial preferences in public education,
    does not violate the Equal Protection Clause. Wilson, 
    122 F.3d 692
    (1997). If the Court were to affirm the essential
    rationale of the Court of Appeals in the instant case, those
    holdings would be invalidated, or at least would be put in
    serious question. The Court, by affirming the judgment
    now before it, in essence would announce a finding that
    the past 15 years of state public debate on this issue have
    been improper. And were the argument made that Coral
    might still stand because it involved racial preferences in
    public contracting while this case concerns racial prefer-
    ences in university admissions, the implication would be
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)           15
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    that the constitutionality of laws forbidding racial prefer-
    ences depends on the policy interest at stake, the concern
    that, as already explained, the voters deem it wise to avoid
    because of its divisive potential. The instant case presents
    the question involved in Coral and Wilson but not involved
    in Mulkey, Hunter, and Seattle. That question is not how
    to address or prevent injury caused on account of race but
    whether voters may determine whether a policy of race-
    based preferences should be continued.
    By approving Proposal 2 and thereby adding §26 to their
    State Constitution, the Michigan voters exercised their
    privilege to enact laws as a basic exercise of their demo-
    cratic power. In the federal system States “respond,
    through the enactment of positive law, to the initiative of
    those who seek a voice in shaping the destiny of their own
    times.” Bond, 564 U. S., at ––– (slip op., at 9). Michigan
    voters used the initiative system to bypass public officials
    who were deemed not responsive to the concerns of a
    majority of the voters with respect to a policy of granting
    race-based preferences that raises difficult and delicate
    issues.
    The freedom secured by the Constitution consists, in one
    of its essential dimensions, of the right of the individual
    not to be injured by the unlawful exercise of governmental
    power. The mandate for segregated schools, Brown v.
    Board of Education, 
    347 U.S. 483
    (1954); a wrongful
    invasion of the home, Silverman v. United States, 
    365 U.S. 505
    (1961); or punishing a protester whose views
    offend others, Texas v. Johnson, 
    491 U.S. 397
    (1989); and
    scores of other examples teach that individual liberty has
    constitutional protection, and that liberty’s full extent and
    meaning may remain yet to be discovered and affirmed.
    Yet freedom does not stop with individual rights. Our
    constitutional system embraces, too, the right of citizens to
    debate so they can learn and decide and then, through the
    political process, act in concert to try to shape the course
    16                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    of their own times and the course of a nation that must
    strive always to make freedom ever greater and more
    secure.     Here Michigan voters acted in concert and
    statewide to seek consensus and adopt a policy on a diffi-
    cult subject against a historical background of race in
    America that has been a source of tragedy and persisting
    injustice. That history demands that we continue to learn,
    to listen, and to remain open to new approaches if we are
    to aspire always to a constitutional order in which all
    persons are treated with fairness and equal dignity. Were
    the Court to rule that the question addressed by Michigan
    voters is too sensitive or complex to be within the grasp of
    the electorate; or that the policies at issue remain too
    delicate to be resolved save by university officials or facul-
    ties, acting at some remove from immediate public scru-
    tiny and control; or that these matters are so arcane that
    the electorate’s power must be limited because the people
    cannot prudently exercise that power even after a full
    debate, that holding would be an unprecedented re-
    striction on the exercise of a fundamental right held not
    just by one person but by all in common. It is the right to
    speak and debate and learn and then, as a matter of polit-
    ical will, to act through a lawful electoral process.
    The respondents in this case insist that a difficult ques-
    tion of public policy must be taken from the reach of the
    voters, and thus removed from the realm of public discus-
    sion, dialogue, and debate in an election campaign. Quite
    in addition to the serious First Amendment implications of
    that position with respect to any particular election, it is
    inconsistent with the underlying premises of a responsi-
    ble, functioning democracy. One of those premises is that
    a democracy has the capacity—and the duty—to learn
    from its past mistakes; to discover and confront persisting
    biases; and by respectful, rationale deliberation to rise
    above those flaws and injustices. That process is impeded,
    not advanced, by court decrees based on the proposition
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)          17
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    that the public cannot have the requisite repose to discuss
    certain issues. It is demeaning to the democratic process
    to presume that the voters are not capable of deciding an
    issue of this sensitivity on decent and rational grounds.
    The process of public discourse and political debate should
    not be foreclosed even if there is a risk that during a pub-
    lic campaign there will be those, on both sides, who seek to
    use racial division and discord to their own political ad-
    vantage. An informed public can, and must, rise above
    this. The idea of democracy is that it can, and must,
    mature. Freedom embraces the right, indeed the duty, to
    engage in a rational, civic discourse in order to determine
    how best to form a consensus to shape the destiny of the
    Nation and its people. These First Amendment dynamics
    would be disserved if this Court were to say that the ques-
    tion here at issue is beyond the capacity of the voters to
    debate and then to determine.
    These precepts are not inconsistent with the well-
    established principle that when hurt or injury is inflicted
    on racial minorities by the encouragement or command of
    laws or other state action, the Constitution requires re-
    dress by the courts. Cf. Johnson v. California, 
    543 U.S. 499
    , 511–512 (2005) (“[S]earching judicial review . . . is
    necessary to guard against invidious discrimination”);
    Edmonson v. Leesville Concrete Co., 
    500 U.S. 614
    , 619
    (1991) (“Racial discrimination” is “invidious in all con-
    texts”). As already noted, those were the circumstances
    that the Court found present in Mulkey, Hunter, and
    Seattle. But those circumstances are not present here.
    For reasons already discussed, Mulkey, Hunter, and
    Seattle are not precedents that stand for the conclusion
    that Michigan’s voters must be disempowered from acting.
    Those cases were ones in which the political restriction in
    question was designed to be used, or was likely to be used,
    to encourage infliction of injury by reason of race. What is
    at stake here is not whether injury will be inflicted but
    18                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    Opinion of KENNEDY, J.
    whether government can be instructed not to follow a
    course that entails, first, the definition of racial categories
    and, second, the grant of favored status to persons in some
    racial categories and not others. The electorate’s instruc-
    tion to governmental entities not to embark upon the
    course of race-defined and race-based preferences was
    adopted, we must assume, because the voters deemed a
    preference system to be unwise, on account of what voters
    may deem its latent potential to become itself a source of
    the very resentments and hostilities based on race that
    this Nation seeks to put behind it. Whether those adverse
    results would follow is, and should be, the subject of de-
    bate. Voters might likewise consider, after debate and
    reflection, that programs designed to increase diversity—
    consistent with the Constitution—are a necessary part of
    progress to transcend the stigma of past racism.
    This case is not about how the debate about racial pref-
    erences should be resolved. It is about who may resolve it.
    There is no authority in the Constitution of the United
    States or in this Court’s precedents for the Judiciary to set
    aside Michigan laws that commit this policy determination
    to the voters. See Sailors v. Board of Ed. of County of
    Kent, 
    387 U.S. 105
    , 109 (1967) (“Save and unless the
    state, county, or municipal government runs afoul of a
    federally protected right, it has vast leeway in the man-
    agement of its internal affairs”). Deliberative debate on
    sensitive issues such as racial preferences all too often
    may shade into rancor. But that does not justify removing
    certain court-determined issues from the voters’ reach.
    Democracy does not presume that some subjects are either
    too divisive or too profound for public debate.
    The judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Sixth
    Circuit is reversed.
    It is so ordered.
    JUSTICE KAGAN took no part in the consideration or
    decision of this case.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)           1
    ROBERTS, C. J., concurring
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 12–682
    _________________
    BILL SCHUETTE, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MICHI-
    GAN, PETITIONER v. COALITION TO DEFEND AF-
    FIRMATIVE ACTION, INTEGRATION AND IMMI-
    GRANT RIGHTS AND FIGHT FOR EQUALITY
    BY ANY MEANS NECESSARY (BAMN), ET AL.
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    [April 22, 2014]
    CHIEF JUSTICE ROBERTS, concurring.
    The dissent devotes 11 pages to expounding its own
    policy preferences in favor of taking race into account in
    college admissions, while nonetheless concluding that it
    “do[es] not mean to suggest that the virtues of adopting
    race-sensitive admissions policies should inform the legal
    question before the Court.” Post, at 57 (opinion of
    SOTOMAYOR, J.). The dissent concedes that the governing
    boards of the State’s various universities could have im-
    plemented a policy making it illegal to “discriminate
    against, or grant preferential treatment to,” any individ-
    ual on the basis of race. See post, at 3, 34–35. On the
    dissent’s view, if the governing boards conclude that draw-
    ing racial distinctions in university admissions is undesir-
    able or counterproductive, they are permissibly exercising
    their policymaking authority. But others who might reach
    the same conclusion are failing to take race seriously.
    The dissent states that “[t]he way to stop discrimination
    on the basis of race is to speak openly and candidly on the
    subject of race.” Post, at 46. And it urges that “[r]ace
    matters because of the slights, the snickers, the silent
    judgments that reinforce that most crippling of thoughts:
    2                         SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    ROBERTS, C. J., concurring
    ‘I do not belong here.’ ” 
    Ibid. But it is
    not “out of touch
    with reality” to conclude that racial preferences may
    themselves have the debilitating effect of reinforcing
    precisely that doubt, and—if so—that the preferences do
    more harm than good. Post, at 45. To disagree with the
    dissent’s views on the costs and benefits of racial prefer-
    ences is not to “wish away, rather than confront” racial
    inequality. Post, at 46. People can disagree in good faith
    on this issue, but it similarly does more harm than good to
    question the openness and candor of those on either side of
    the debate.*
    ——————
    * JUSTICE SCALIA and JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR question the relationship
    between Washington v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 
    458 U.S. 457
    (1982),
    and Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No.
    1, 
    551 U.S. 701
    (2007). See post, at 6, n. 2 (SCALIA, J., concurring in
    judgment); post, at 23, n. 9 (SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting). The plurality
    today addresses that issue, explaining that the race-conscious action in
    Parents Involved was unconstitutional given the absence of a showing
    of prior de jure segregation. Parents 
    Involved, supra, at 720
    –721
    (majority opinion), 736 (plurality opinion); see ante, at 9. Today’s
    plurality notes that the Court in Seattle “assumed” the constitutionality
    of the busing remedy at issue there, “ ‘even absent a finding of prior
    de jure segregation.’ ” Ante, at 10 (quoting 
    Seattle, supra
    , at 472, n. 15).
    The assumption on which Seattle proceeded did not constitute a finding
    sufficient to justify the race-conscious action in Parents Involved,
    though it is doubtless pertinent in analyzing Seattle. “As this Court
    held in Parents Involved, the [Seattle] school board’s purported remedial
    action would not be permissible today absent a showing of de jure
    segregation,” but “we must understand Seattle as Seattle understood
    itself.” Ante, at 9–10 (emphasis added).
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)           1
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 12–682
    _________________
    BILL SCHUETTE, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MICHI-
    GAN, PETITIONER v. COALITION TO DEFEND AF-
    FIRMATIVE ACTION, INTEGRATION AND IMMI-
    GRANT RIGHTS AND FIGHT FOR EQUALITY
    BY ANY MEANS NECESSARY (BAMN), ET AL.
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    [April 22, 2014]
    JUSTICE SCALIA, with whom JUSTICE THOMAS joins,
    concurring in the judgment.
    It has come to this. Called upon to explore the jurispru-
    dential twilight zone between two errant lines of prece-
    dent, we confront a frighteningly bizarre question: Does
    the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amend-
    ment forbid what its text plainly requires? Needless to say
    (except that this case obliges us to say it), the question
    answers itself. “The Constitution proscribes government
    discrimination on the basis of race, and state-provided
    education is no exception.” Grutter v. Bollinger, 
    539 U.S. 306
    , 349 (2003) (SCALIA, J., concurring in part and dis-
    senting in part). It is precisely this understanding—the
    correct understanding—of the federal Equal Protection
    Clause that the people of the State of Michigan have
    adopted for their own fundamental law. By adopting it,
    they did not simultaneously offend it.
    Even taking this Court’s sorry line of race-based-
    admissions cases as a given, I find the question presented
    only slightly less strange: Does the Equal Protection
    Clause forbid a State from banning a practice that the
    Clause barely—and only provisionally—permits? React-
    2                       SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    ing to those race-based-admissions decisions, some
    States—whether deterred by the prospect of costly litiga-
    tion; aware that Grutter’s bell may soon toll, 
    see 539 U.S., at 343
    ; or simply opposed in principle to the notion of
    “benign” racial discrimination—have gotten out of the
    racial-preferences business altogether. And with our
    express encouragement: “Universities in California, Flor-
    ida, and Washington State, where racial preferences in
    admissions are prohibited by state law, are currently
    engaging in experimenting with a wide variety of alterna-
    tive approaches. Universities in other States can and
    should draw on the most promising aspects of these race-
    neutral alternatives as they develop.” 
    Id., at 342
    (empha-
    sis added). Respondents seem to think this admonition
    was merely in jest.1 The experiment, they maintain, is not
    only over; it never rightly began. Neither the people of the
    States nor their legislatures ever had the option of direct-
    ing subordinate public-university officials to cease consid-
    ering the race of applicants, since that would deny mem-
    bers of those minority groups the option of enacting a
    policy designed to further their interest, thus denying
    them the equal protection of the laws. Never mind that it
    is hotly disputed whether the practice of race-based ad-
    missions is ever in a racial minority’s interest. Cf. 
    id., at 371–373
    (THOMAS, J., concurring in part and dissenting in
    part). And never mind that, were a public university to
    stake its defense of a race-based-admissions policy on the
    ground that it was designed to benefit primarily minorities
    (as opposed to all students, regardless of color, by enhanc-
    ing diversity), we would hold the policy unconstitutional.
    See 
    id., at 322–325.
       But the battleground for this case is not the constitu-
    ——————
    1 For simplicity’s sake, I use “respondent” or “respondents” through-
    out the opinion to describe only those parties who are adverse to
    petitioner, not Eric Russell, a respondent who supports petitioner.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)             3
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    tionality of race-based admissions—at least, not quite.
    Rather, it is the so-called political-process doctrine, de-
    rived from this Court’s opinions in Washington v. Seattle
    School Dist. No. 1, 
    458 U.S. 457
    (1982), and Hunter v.
    Erickson, 
    393 U.S. 385
    (1969). I agree with those parts of
    the plurality opinion that repudiate this doctrine. But I do
    not agree with its reinterpretation of Seattle and Hunter,
    which makes them stand in part for the cloudy and doctri-
    nally anomalous proposition that whenever state action
    poses “the serious risk . . . of causing specific injuries on
    account of race,” it denies equal protection. Ante, at 9. I
    would instead reaffirm that the “ordinary principles of our
    law [and] of our democratic heritage” require “plaintiffs
    alleging equal protection violations” stemming from fa-
    cially neutral acts to “prove intent and causation and not
    merely the existence of racial disparity.” Freeman v. Pitts,
    
    503 U.S. 467
    , 506 (1992) (SCALIA, J., concurring) (citing
    Washington v. Davis, 
    426 U.S. 229
    (1976)). I would fur-
    ther hold that a law directing state actors to provide equal
    protection is (to say the least) facially neutral, and cannot
    violate the Constitution. Section 26 of the Michigan Con-
    stitution (formerly Proposal 2) rightly stands.
    I
    A
    The political-process doctrine has its roots in two of our
    cases. The first is Hunter. In 1964, the Akron City Coun-
    cil passed a fair-housing ordinance “ ‘assur[ing] equal
    opportunity to all persons to live in decent housing facili-
    ties regardless of race, color, religion, ancestry or national
    origin.’ 
    393 U.S., at 386
    . Soon after, the city’s voters
    passed an amendment to the Akron City Charter stating
    that any ordinance enacted by the council that “ ‘regu-
    lates’ ” commercial transactions in real property “ ‘on the
    basis of race, color, religion, national origin or ancestry’ ”—
    including the already enacted 1964 ordinance—“must first
    4                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    be approved by a majority of the electors voting on the
    question” at a later referendum. 
    Id., at 387.
    The question
    was whether the charter amendment denied equal protec-
    tion. Answering yes, the Court explained that “although
    the law on its face treats Negro and white, Jew and gentile
    in an identical manner, the reality is that the law’s impact
    falls on the minority. The majority needs no protection
    against discrimination.” 
    Id., at 391.
    By placing a “special
    burden on racial minorities within the governmental
    processes,” the amendment “disadvantage[d]” a racial
    minority “by making it more difficult to enact legislation
    in its behalf.” 
    Id., at 391,
    393.
    The reasoning in Seattle is of a piece. Resolving to
    “eliminate all [racial] imbalance from the Seattle public
    schools,” the city school board passed a mandatory busing
    and pupil-reassignment plan of the sort typically imposed
    on districts guilty of de jure 
    segregation. 458 U.S., at 460
    –461. A year later, the citizens of the State of Wash-
    ington passed Initiative 350, which directed (with excep-
    tions) that “ ‘no school . . . shall directly or indirectly re-
    quire any student to attend a school other than the school
    which is geographically nearest or next nearest the stu-
    dent’s place of residence . . . and which offers the course of
    study pursued by such student,’ ” permitting only court-
    ordered race-based busing. 
    Id., at 462.
    The lower courts
    held Initiative 350 unconstitutional, and we affirmed,
    announcing in the prelude of our analysis—as though it
    were beyond debate—that the Equal Protection Clause
    forbade laws that “subtly distor[t] governmental processes
    in such a way as to place special burdens on the ability of
    minority groups to achieve beneficial legislation.” 
    Id., at 467.
       The first question in Seattle was whether the subject
    matter of Initiative 350 was a “ ‘racial’ issue,” triggering
    Hunter and its process 
    doctrine. 458 U.S., at 471
    –472. It
    was “undoubtedly. . . true” that whites and blacks were
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)            5
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    “counted among both the supporters and the opponents of
    Initiative 350.” 
    Id., at 472.
    It was “equally clear” that
    both white and black children benefited from desegre-
    gated schools. 
    Ibid. Nonetheless, we concluded
    that desegre-
    gation “inures primarily to the benefit of the minority, and
    is designed for that purpose.” 
    Ibid. (emphasis added). In
    any event, it was “enough that minorities may consider
    busing for integration to be ‘legislation that is in their
    interest.’ ” 
    Id., at 474
    (quoting 
    Hunter, supra, at 395
    (Harlan, J., concurring)).
    So we proceeded to the heart of the political-process
    analysis. We held Initiative 350 unconstitutional, since it
    removed “the authority to address a racial problem—and
    only a racial problem—from the existing decisionmaking
    body, in such a way as to burden minority interests.”
    
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 474
    . Although school boards in
    Washington retained authority over other student-
    assignment issues and over most matters of educational
    policy generally, under Initiative 350, minorities favoring
    race-based busing would have to “surmount a considerably
    higher hurdle” than the mere petitioning of a local assem-
    bly: They “now must seek relief from the state legislature,
    or from the statewide electorate,” a “different level of
    government.” 
    Ibid. The relentless logic
    of Hunter and Seattle would point to
    a similar conclusion in this case. In those cases, one level
    of government exercised borrowed authority over an ap-
    parently “racial issue,” until a higher level of government
    called the loan. So too here. In those cases, we deemed
    the revocation an equal-protection violation regardless of
    whether it facially classified according to race or reflected
    an invidious purpose to discriminate. Here, the Court of
    Appeals did the same.
    The plurality sees it differently. Though it, too, dis-
    avows the political-process-doctrine basis on which Hunter
    and Seattle were decided, ante, at 10–14, it does not take
    6                        SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    the next step of overruling those cases. Rather, it reinter-
    prets them beyond recognition. Hunter, the plurality
    suggests, was a case in which the challenged act had
    “target[ed] racial minorities.” Ante, at 8. Maybe, but the
    Hunter Court neither found that to be so nor considered it
    relevant, bypassing the question of intent entirely, satis-
    fied that its newly minted political-process theory sufficed
    to invalidate the charter amendment.
    As for Seattle, what was really going on, according to the
    plurality, was that Initiative 350 had the consequence (if
    not the purpose) of preserving the harms effected by prior
    de jure segregation. Thus, “the political restriction in
    question was designed to be used, or was likely to be used,
    to encourage infliction of injury by reason of race.” Ante,
    at 17. That conclusion is derived not from the opinion but
    from recently discovered evidence that the city of Seattle
    had been a cause of its schools’ racial imbalance all along:
    “Although there had been no judicial finding of de jure
    segregation with respect to Seattle’s school district, it
    appears as though school segregation in the district in the
    1940’s and 1950’s may have been the partial result of
    school board policies.” Ante, at 9.2 That the district’s
    effort to end racial imbalance had been stymied by Initia-
    tive 350 meant that the people, by passing it, somehow
    had become complicit in Seattle’s equal-protection-denying
    status quo, whether they knew it or not. Hence, there
    was in Seattle a government-furthered “infliction of a
    ——————
    2 The plurality cites evidence from JUSTICE BREYER’s dissent in Par­
    ents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 
    551 U.S. 701
    (2007), to suggest that the city had been a “partial” cause of
    its segregation problem. Ante, at 9. The plurality in Parents Involved
    criticized that dissent for relying on irrelevant evidence, for “elid[ing
    the] distinction between de jure and de facto segregation,” and for
    “casually intimat[ing] that Seattle’s school attendance patterns re-
    flect[ed] illegal 
    segregation.” 551 U.S., at 736
    –737, and n. 15. Today’s
    plurality sides with the dissent and repeats its errors.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)                  7
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    specific”—and, presumably, constitutional—“injury.” Ante,
    at 14.
    Once again this describes what our opinion in Seattle
    might have been, but assuredly not what it was. The
    opinion assumes throughout that Seattle’s schools suffered
    at most from de facto segregation, see, 
    e.g., 458 U.S., at 474
    , 475—that is, segregation not the “product . . . of state
    action but of private choices,” having no “constitutional
    implications,” 
    Freeman, 503 U.S., at 495
    –496. Nor did it
    anywhere state that the current racial imbalance was the
    (judicially remediable) effect of prior de jure segregation.
    Absence of de jure segregation or the effects of de jure
    segregation was a necessary premise of the Seattle opin-
    ion. That is what made the issue of busing and pupil
    reassignment a matter of political choice rather than
    judicial mandate.3 And precisely because it was a question
    for the political branches to decide, the manner—which is
    to say, the process—of its resolution implicated the Court’s
    new process theory. The opinion itself says this: “[I]n the
    absence of a constitutional violation, the desirability and
    efficacy of school desegregation are matters to be resolved
    through the political process. For present purposes, it is
    enough [to hold reallocation of that political decision to a
    higher level unconstitutional] that minorities may consider
    busing for integration to be legislation that is in their
    
    interest.” 458 U.S., at 474
    (internal quotation marks
    omitted).
    B
    Patently atextual, unadministrable, and contrary to our
    traditional equal-protection jurisprudence, Hunter and
    ——————
    3 Or so the Court assumed. 
    See 458 U.S., at 472
    , n. 15 (“Appellants
    and the United States do not challenge the propriety of race-conscious
    student assignments for the purpose of achieving integration, even
    absent a finding of prior de jure segregation. We therefore do not
    specifically pass on that issue”).
    8                        SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    Seattle should be overruled.
    The problems with the political-process doctrine begin
    with its triggering prong, which assigns to a court the task
    of determining whether a law that reallocates policy-
    making authority concerns a “racial issue.” 
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 473
    . Seattle takes a couple of dissatisfying cracks at
    defining this crucial term. It suggests that an issue is
    racial if adopting one position on the question would “at
    bottom inur[e] primarily to the benefit of the minority, and
    is designed for that purpose.” 
    Id., at 472.
    It is irrelevant
    that, as in Hunter and 
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 472
    , both the
    racial minority and the racial majority benefit from the
    policy in question, and members of both groups favor it.
    Judges should instead focus their guesswork on their own
    juridical sense of what is primarily for the benefit of mi-
    norities. Cf. 
    ibid. (regarding as dispositive
    what “our
    cases” suggest is beneficial to minorities). On second
    thought, maybe judges need only ask this question: Is it
    possible “that minorities may consider” the policy in ques-
    tion to be “in their interest”? 
    Id., at 474.
    If so, you can be
    sure that you are dealing with a “racial issue.”4
    ——————
    4 The dissent’s version of this test is just as scattershot. Since, ac-
    cording to the dissent, the doctrine forbids “reconfigur[ing] the political
    process in a manner that burdens only a racial minority,” post, at 5
    (opinion of SOTOMAYOR, J.) (emphasis added), it must be that the reason
    the underlying issue (that is, the issue concerning which the process
    has been reconfigured) is “racial” is that the policy in question benefits
    only a racial minority (if it also benefited persons not belonging to a
    racial majority, then the political-process reconfiguration would burden
    them as well). On second thought: The issue is “racial” if the policy
    benefits primarily a racial minority and “ ‘[is] designed for that pur-
    pose,’ ” post, at 44. This is the standard Seattle purported to apply. But
    under that standard, §26 does not affect a “racial issue,” because under
    Grutter v. Bollinger, 
    539 U.S. 306
    (2003), race-based admissions
    policies may not constitutionally be “designed for [the] purpose,”
    
    Seattle, supra
    , at 472, of benefiting primarily racial minorities, but
    must be designed for the purpose of achieving educational benefits for
    students of all races, 
    Grutter, supra, at 322
    –325. So the dissent must
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)                    9
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    No good can come of such random judicial musing. The
    plurality gives two convincing reasons why. For one thing,
    it involves judges in the dirty business of dividing the
    Nation “into racial blocs,” Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v.
    FCC, 
    497 U.S. 547
    , 603, 610 (1990) (O’Connor, J., dissent-
    ing); ante, at 11–13. That task is as difficult as it is unap-
    pealing. (Does a half-Latino, half–American Indian have
    Latino interests, American-Indian interests, both, half of
    both?5) What is worse, the exercise promotes the noxious
    fiction that, knowing only a person’s color or ethnicity, we
    can be sure that he has a predetermined set of policy
    “interests,” thus “reinforc[ing] the perception that mem-
    bers of the same racial group—regardless of their age,
    education, economic status, or the community in which
    they live—think alike, [and] share the same political
    interests.”6 Shaw v. Reno, 
    509 U.S. 630
    , 647 (1993).
    Whether done by a judge or a school board, such “racial
    stereotyping [is] at odds with equal protection mandates.”
    Miller v. Johnson, 
    515 U.S. 900
    , 920 (1995).
    But that is not the “racial issue” prong’s only defect.
    More fundamentally, it misreads the Equal Protection
    Clause to protect “particular group[s],” a construction that
    we have tirelessly repudiated in a “long line of cases
    understanding equal protection as a personal right.”
    ——————
    mean that an issue is “racial” so long as the policy in question has the
    incidental effect (an effect not flowing from its design) of benefiting
    primarily racial minorities.
    5 And how many members of a particular racial group must take the
    same position on an issue before we suppose that the position is in the
    entire group’s interest? Not every member, the dissent suggests, post,
    at 44. Beyond that, who knows? Five percent? Eighty-five percent?
    6 The dissent proves my point.     After asserting—without citation,
    though I and many others of all races deny it—that it is “common-sense
    reality” that affirmative action benefits racial minorities, post, at 16,
    the dissent suggests throughout, e.g., post, at 30, that that view of
    “reality” is so necessarily shared by members of racial minorities that
    they must favor affirmative action.
    10                       SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña, 
    515 U.S. 200
    , 224,
    230 (1995). It is a “basic principle that the Fifth and
    Fourteenth Amendments to the Constitution protect per­
    sons, not groups.” 
    Id., at 227;
    Metro 
    Broadcasting, supra, at 636
    (KENNEDY, J., dissenting).7 Yet Seattle insists that
    only those political-process alterations that burden racial
    minorities deny equal protection. “The majority,” after all,
    “needs no protection against 
    discrimination.” 458 U.S., at 468
    (quoting 
    Hunter, 393 U.S., at 391
    ). In the years since
    Seattle, we have repeatedly rejected “a reading of the
    guarantee of equal protection under which the level of
    scrutiny varies according to the ability of different groups
    to defend their interests in the representative process.”
    Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co., 
    488 U.S. 469
    , 495 (1989).
    Meant to obliterate rather than endorse the practice of
    racial classifications, the Fourteenth Amendment’s guar-
    antees “obtai[n] with equal force regardless of ‘the race of
    those burdened or benefited.’ ” 
    Miller, supra, at 904
    (quoting 
    Croson, supra, at 494
    (plurality opinion));
    
    Adarand, supra, at 223
    , 227. The Equal Protection Clause
    “cannot mean one thing when applied to one individual
    and something else when applied to a person of another
    color. If both are not accorded the same protection it is not
    equal.” Regents of Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke, 
    438 U.S. 265
    ,
    289–290 (1978) (opinion of Powell, J.).
    The dissent trots out the old saw, derived from dictum
    in a footnote, that legislation motivated by “ ‘prejudice
    ——————
    7 The dissent contends, post, at 39, that this point “ignores the obvi-
    ous: Discrimination against an individual occurs because of that indi-
    vidual’s membership in a particular group.” No, I do not ignore the
    obvious; it is the dissent that misses the point. Of course discrimina-
    tion against a group constitutes discrimination against each member of
    that group. But since it is persons and not groups that are protected,
    one cannot say, as the dissent would, that the Constitution prohibits
    discrimination against minority groups, but not against majority
    groups.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)                  11
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    against discrete and insular minorities’ ” merits “ ‘more
    exacting judicial scrutiny.’ ” Post, at 31 (quoting United
    States v. Carolene Products, 
    304 U.S. 144
    , 152–153, n. 4).
    I say derived from that dictum (expressed by the four-
    Justice majority of a seven-Justice Court) because the
    dictum itself merely said “[n]or need we enquire . . .
    whether prejudice against discrete and insular minorities
    may be a special condition,” 
    id., at 153,
    n. 4 (emphasis
    added). The dissent does not argue, of course, that such
    “prejudice” produced §26. Nor does it explain why certain
    racial minorities in Michigan qualify as “ ‘insular,’ ” mean-
    ing that “other groups will not form coalitions with them—
    and, critically, not because of lack of common interests but
    because of ‘prejudice.’ ” Strauss, Is Carolene Products
    Obsolete? 2010 U. Ill. L. Rev. 1251, 1257. Nor does it even
    make the case that a group’s “discreteness” and “insu-
    larity” are political liabilities rather than political
    strengths8—a serious question that alone demonstrates
    the prudence of the Carolene Products dictumizers in
    leaving the “enquir[y]” for another day. As for the ques-
    tion whether “legislation which restricts those political
    processes which can ordinarily be expected to bring about
    repeal of undesirable legislation . . . is to be subjected to
    more exacting judicial scrutiny,” the Carolene Products
    Court found it “unnecessary to consider [that] 
    now.” 304 U.S., at 152
    , n. 4. If the dissent thinks that worth consid-
    ering today, it should explain why the election of a univer-
    sity’s governing board is a “political process which can
    ——————
    8 Cf., e.g., Ackerman, Beyond Carolene Products, 98 Harv. L. Rev.
    713, 723–724 (1985) (“Other things being equal, ‘discreteness and
    insularity’ will normally be a source of enormous bargaining advantage,
    not disadvantage, for a group engaged in pluralist American politics.
    Except for special cases, the concerns that underlie Carolene should
    lead judges to protect groups that possess the opposite characteristic
    from the ones Carolene emphasizes—groups that are ‘anonymous and
    diffuse’ rather than ‘discrete and insular’ ”).
    12                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    ordinarily be expected to bring about repeal of undesirable
    legislation,” but Michigan voters’ ability to amend their
    Constitution is not. It seems to me quite the opposite.
    Amending the Constitution requires the approval of only
    “a majority of the electors voting on the question.” Mich.
    Const., Art. XII, §2. By contrast, voting in a favorable
    board (each of which has eight members) at the three
    major public universities requires electing by majority
    vote at least 15 different candidates, several of whom
    would be running during different election cycles. See
    BAMN v. Regents of Univ. of Mich., 
    701 F.3d 466
    , 508
    (CA6 2012) (Sutton, J., dissenting). So if Michigan voters,
    instead of amending their Constitution, had pursued the
    dissent’s preferred path of electing board members promis-
    ing to “abolish race-sensitive admissions policies,” post, at
    3, it would have been harder, not easier, for racial minori-
    ties favoring affirmative action to overturn that decision.
    But the more important point is that we should not design
    our jurisprudence to conform to dictum in a footnote in a
    four-Justice opinion.
    C
    Moving from the appalling to the absurd, I turn now to
    the second part of the Hunter-Seattle analysis—which is
    apparently no more administrable than the first, compare
    post, at 4–6 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment) (“This
    case . . . does not involve a reordering of the political
    process”), with post, at 25–29 (SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting)
    (yes, it does). This part of the inquiry directs a court to
    determine whether the challenged act “place[s] effective
    decisionmaking authority over [the] racial issue at a dif-
    ferent level of government.” 
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 474
    .
    The laws in both Hunter and Seattle were thought to fail
    this test. In both cases, “the effect of the challenged
    action was to redraw decisionmaking authority over racial
    matters—and only over racial matters—in such a way as
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)           13
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    to place comparative burdens on 
    minorities.” 458 U.S., at 475
    , n. 17. This, we said, a State may not do.
    By contrast, in another line of cases, we have empha-
    sized the near-limitless sovereignty of each State to design
    its governing structure as it sees fit. Generally, “a State is
    afforded wide leeway when experimenting with the appro-
    priate allocation of state legislative power” and may create
    “political subdivisions such as cities and counties . . . ‘as
    convenient agencies for exercising such of the governmen-
    tal powers of the state as may be entrusted to them.’ ”
    Holt Civic Club v. Tuscaloosa, 
    439 U.S. 60
    , 71 (1978)
    (quoting Hunter v. Pittsburgh, 
    207 U.S. 161
    , 178 (1907)).
    Accordingly, States have “absolute discretion” to deter-
    mine the “number, nature and duration of the powers
    conferred upon [municipal] corporations and the territory
    over which they shall be exercised.” Holt Civic 
    Club, supra, at 71
    . So it would seem to go without saying that a
    State may give certain powers to cities, later assign the
    same powers to counties, and even reclaim them for itself.
    Taken to the limits of its logic, Hunter-Seattle is the
    gaping exception that nearly swallows the rule of struc-
    tural state sovereignty. If indeed the Fourteenth Amend-
    ment forbids States to “place effective decisionmaking
    authority over” racial issues at “different level[s] of gov-
    ernment,” then it must be true that the Amendment’s
    ratification in 1868 worked a partial ossification of each
    State’s governing structure, rendering basically irrevoca-
    ble the power of any subordinate state official who, the
    day before the Fourteenth Amendment’s passage, hap-
    pened to enjoy legislatively conferred authority over a
    “racial issue.” Under the Fourteenth Amendment, that
    subordinate entity (suppose it is a city council) could itself
    take action on the issue, action either favorable or unfa-
    vorable to minorities. It could even reverse itself later.
    What it could not do, however, is redelegate its power to
    an even lower level of state government (such as a city-
    14                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    council committee) without forfeiting it, since the neces-
    sary effect of wresting it back would be to put an additional
    obstacle in the path of minorities. Likewise, no entity
    or official higher up the state chain (e.g., a county board)
    could exercise authority over the issue. Nor, even, could
    the state legislature, or the people by constitutional
    amendment, revoke the legislative conferral of power to
    the subordinate, whether the city council, its subcommit-
    tee, or the county board. Seattle’s logic would create
    affirmative-action safe havens wherever subordinate offi-
    cials in public universities (1) traditionally have enjoyed
    “effective decisionmaking authority” over admissions
    policy but (2) have not yet used that authority to prohibit
    race-conscious admissions decisions. The mere existence
    of a subordinate’s discretion over the matter would work a
    kind of reverse pre-emption. It is “a strange notion—alien
    to our system—that local governmental bodies can forever
    pre-empt the ability of a State—the sovereign power—to
    address a matter of compelling concern to the 
    State.” 458 U.S., at 495
    (Powell, J., dissenting). But that is precisely
    what the political-process doctrine contemplates.
    Perhaps the spirit of Seattle is especially disquieted by
    enactments of constitutional amendments. That appears
    to be the dissent’s position. The problem with §26, it
    suggests, is that amending Michigan’s Constitution is
    simply not a part of that State’s “existing” political pro-
    cess. E.g., post, at 4, 41. What a peculiar notion: that a
    revision of a State’s fundamental law, made in precisely
    the manner that law prescribes, by the very people who
    are the source of that law’s authority, is not part of the
    “political process” which, but for those people and that
    law, would not exist. This will surely come as news to the
    people of Michigan, who, since 1914, have amended their
    Constitution 20 times. Brief for Gary Segura et al. as
    Amici Curiae 12. Even so, the dissent concludes that the
    amendment attacked here worked an illicit “chang[ing]
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)                  15
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    [of ] the basic rules of the political process in that State” in
    “the middle of the game.” Post, at 2, 4. Why, one might
    ask, is not the amendment provision of the Michigan
    Constitution one (perhaps the most basic one) of the rules
    of the State’s political process? And why does democratic
    invocation of that provision not qualify as working
    through the “existing political process,” post, at 41?9
    II
    I part ways with Hunter, Seattle, and (I think) the plu-
    rality for an additional reason: Each endorses a version of
    the proposition that a facially neutral law may deny equal
    protection solely because it has a disparate racial impact.
    Few equal-protection theories have been so squarely and
    soundly rejected. “An unwavering line of cases from this
    Court holds that a violation of the Equal Protection Clause
    requires state action motivated by discriminatory intent,”
    Hernandez v. New York, 
    500 U.S. 352
    , 372–373 (1991)
    (O’Connor, J., concurring in judgment), and that “official
    action will not be held unconstitutional solely because it
    results in a racially disproportionate impact,” Arlington
    Heights v. Metropolitan Housing Development Corp., 
    429 U.S. 252
    , 264–265 (1977). Indeed, we affirmed this prin-
    ciple the same day we decided Seattle: “[E]ven when a
    neutral law has a disproportionately adverse effect on a
    racial minority, the Fourteenth Amendment is violated
    only if a discriminatory purpose can be shown.” Crawford
    v. Board of Ed. of Los Angeles, 
    458 U.S. 527
    , 537–538
    ——————
    9 The dissent thinks I do not understand its argument. Only when
    amending Michigan’s Constitution violates Hunter-Seattle, it says, is
    that constitutionally prescribed activity necessarily not part of the
    State’s existing political process. Post, at 21, n. 7. I understand the
    argument quite well; and see quite well that it begs the question. Why
    is Michigan’s action here unconstitutional? Because it violates Hunter-
    Seattle. And why does it violate Hunter-Seattle? Because it is not part
    of the State’s existing political process. And why is it not part of the
    State’s existing political process? Because it violates Hunter-Seattle.
    16                        SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    (1982).
    Notwithstanding our dozens of cases confirming the
    exception-less nature of the Washington v. Davis rule, the
    plurality opinion leaves ajar an effects-test escape hatch
    modeled after Hunter and Seattle, suggesting that state
    action denies equal protection when it “ha[s] the serious
    risk, if not purpose, of causing specific injuries on account
    of race,” or is either “designed to be used, or . . . likely to be
    used, to encourage infliction of injury by reason of race.”
    Ante, at 9, 17 (emphasis added). Since these formulations
    enable a determination of an equal-protection violation
    where there is no discriminatory intent, they are incon-
    sistent with the long Washington v. Davis line of cases.10
    Respondents argue that we need not bother with the
    discriminatory-purpose test, since §26 may be struck more
    straightforwardly as a racial “classification.” Admitting
    (as they must) that §26 does not on its face “distribut[e]
    burdens or benefits on the basis of individual racial classi-
    fications,” Parents Involved in Community Schools v.
    Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 
    551 U.S. 701
    , 720 (2007), re-
    spondents rely on Seattle’s statement that “when the
    political process or the decisionmaking mechanism used to
    address racially conscious legislation—and only such
    legislation—is singled out for peculiar and disadvanta-
    geous treatment,” then that “singling out” is a racial clas-
    
    sification. 458 U.S., at 485
    , 486, n. 30. But this is just
    the political-process theory bedecked in different doctrinal
    ——————
    10 According to the dissent, Hunter-Seattle fills an important doctrinal
    gap left open by Washington v. Davis, since Hunter-Seattle’s rule—
    unique among equal-protection principles—makes clear that “the
    majority” may not alter a political process with the goal of “prevent[ing]
    minority groups from partaking in that process on equal footing.” Post,
    at 33. Nonsense. There is no gap. To “manipulate the ground rules,”
    post, at 34, or to “ri[g] the contest,” post, at 35, in order to harm persons
    because of their race is to deny equal protection under Washington v.
    Davis.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)           17
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    dress. A law that “neither says nor implies that persons
    are to be treated differently on account of their race” is not
    a racial classification. 
    Crawford, supra, at 537
    . That is
    particularly true of statutes mandating equal treatment.
    “[A] law that prohibits the State from classifying individu-
    als by race . . . a fortiori does not classify individuals by
    race.” Coalition for Economic Equity v. Wilson, 
    122 F.3d 692
    , 702 (CA9 1997) (O’Scannlain, J.).
    Thus, the question in this case, as in every case in which
    neutral state action is said to deny equal protection on
    account of race, is whether the action reflects a racially
    discriminatory purpose. Seattle stresses that “singling out
    the political processes affecting racial issues for uniquely
    disadvantageous treatment inevitably raises dangers of
    impermissible 
    motivation.” 458 U.S., at 486
    , n. 30. True
    enough, but that motivation must be proved. And re-
    spondents do not have a prayer of proving it here. The
    District Court noted that, under “conventional equal
    protection” doctrine, the suit was “doom[ed].” 
    539 F. Supp. 2d
    924, 951 (ED Mich. 2008). Though the Court of Ap-
    peals did not opine on this question, I would not leave it
    for them on remand. In my view, any law expressly re-
    quiring state actors to afford all persons equal protection
    of the laws (such as Initiative 350 in Seattle, though not
    the charter amendment in Hunter) does not—cannot—
    deny “to any person . . . equal protection of the laws,” U. S.
    Const., Amdt. 14, §1, regardless of whatever evidence of
    seemingly foul purposes plaintiffs may cook up in the trial
    court.
    *    *    *
    As Justice Harlan observed over a century ago, “[o]ur
    Constitution is color-blind, and neither knows nor toler-
    ates classes among citizens.” Plessy v. Ferguson, 
    163 U.S. 537
    , 559 (1896) (dissenting opinion). The people of Michi-
    gan wish the same for their governing charter. It would
    18                      SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment
    be shameful for us to stand in their way.11
    ——————
    11 And doubly shameful to equate “the majority” behind §26 with “the
    majority” responsible for Jim Crow. Post, at 1–2 (SOTOMAYOR, J.,
    dissenting).
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)              1
    BREYER, J., concurring in judgment
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 12–682
    _________________
    BILL SCHUETTE, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MICHI-
    GAN, PETITIONER v. COALITION TO DEFEND AF-
    FIRMATIVE ACTION, INTEGRATION AND IMMI-
    GRANT RIGHTS AND FIGHT FOR EQUALITY
    BY ANY MEANS NECESSARY (BAMN), ET AL.
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    [April 22, 2014]
    JUSTICE BREYER, concurring in the judgment.
    Michigan has amended its Constitution to forbid state
    universities and colleges to “discriminate against, or grant
    preferential treatment to, any individual or group on the
    basis of race, sex, color, ethnicity, or national origin in the
    operation of public employment, public education, or
    public contracting.” Mich. Const., Art. I, §26. We here
    focus on the prohibition of “grant[ing] . . . preferential
    treatment . . . on the basis of race . . . in . . . public educa-
    tion.” I agree with the plurality that the amendment is
    consistent with the Federal Equal Protection Clause.
    U. S. Const., Amdt. 14. But I believe this for different
    reasons.
    First, we do not address the amendment insofar as it
    forbids the use of race-conscious admissions programs
    designed to remedy past exclusionary racial discrimina-
    tion or the direct effects of that discrimination. Applica-
    tion of the amendment in that context would present
    different questions which may demand different answers.
    Rather, we here address the amendment only as it applies
    to, and forbids, programs that, as in Grutter v. Bollinger,
    
    539 U.S. 306
    (2003), rest upon “one justification”: using
    2                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    BREYER, J., concurring in judgment
    “race in the admissions process” solely in order to “obtai[n]
    the educational benefits that flow from a diverse student
    body,” 
    id., at 328
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    Second, dissenting in Parents Involved in Community
    Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 
    551 U.S. 701
    (2007),
    I explained why I believe race-conscious programs of this
    kind are constitutional, whether implemented by law
    schools, universities, high schools, or elementary schools.
    I concluded that the Constitution does not “authorize
    judges” either to forbid or to require the adoption of diver-
    sity-seeking race-conscious “solutions” (of the kind at issue
    here) to such serious problems as “how best to administer
    America’s schools” to help “create a society that includes
    all Americans.” 
    Id., at 862.
       I continue to believe that the Constitution permits,
    though it does not require, the use of the kind of race-
    conscious programs that are now barred by the Michigan
    Constitution. The serious educational problems that faced
    Americans at the time this Court decided Grutter endure.
    See, e.g., I. Mullis, M. Martin, P. Foy, & K. Drucker,
    Progress in International Reading Literacy Study, 2011
    International Results in Reading 38, Exh. 1.1 (2012)
    (elementary-school students in numerous other countries
    outperform their counterparts in the United States in
    reading); I. Mullis, M. Martin, P. Foy, & A. Arora, Trends
    in International Mathematics and Science Study (TIMSS),
    2011 International Results in Mathematics 40, Exh. 1.1
    (2012) (same in mathematics); M. Martin, I. Mullis, P.
    Foy, & G. Stanco, TIMSS, 2011 International Results in
    Science, 38, Exh. 1.1 (2012) (same in science); Organisa-
    tion of Economic Co-operation Development (OECD),
    Education at a Glance 2013: OECD Indicators 50 (Table
    A2.1a) (secondary-school graduation rate lower in the
    United States than in numerous other countries); McKin-
    sey & Co., The Economic Impact of the Achievement Gap
    in America’s Schools 8 (Apr. 2009) (same; United States
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)            3
    BREYER, J., concurring in judgment
    ranks 18th of 24 industrialized nations). And low educa-
    tional achievement continues to be correlated with income
    and race. See, e.g., National Center for Education Statis-
    tics, Digest of Education Statistics, Advance Release of
    Selected 2013 Digest Tables (Table 104.20) (White Ameri-
    cans more likely to have completed high school than
    African-Americans or Hispanic-Americans), online at
    http://nces.ed.gov/programs/digest (as visited Apr. 15,
    2014, and available in Clerk of Court’s case file); 
    id., Table 219.75
    (Americans in bottom quartile of income most
    likely to drop out of high school); 
    id., Table 302.60
    (White
    Americans more likely to enroll in college than African-
    Americans or Hispanic-Americans); 
    id., Table 302.30
    (middle- and high-income Americans more likely to enroll
    in college than low-income Americans).
    The Constitution allows local, state, and national com-
    munities to adopt narrowly tailored race-conscious pro-
    grams designed to bring about greater inclusion and di-
    versity. But the Constitution foresees the ballot box, not
    the courts, as the normal instrument for resolving differ-
    ences and debates about the merits of these programs.
    Compare Parents 
    Involved, 551 U.S., at 839
    (BREYER, J.,
    dissenting) (identifying studies showing the benefits of
    racially integrated education), with 
    id., at 761–763
    (THOMAS, J., concurring) (identifying studies suggesting
    racially integrated schools may not confer educational
    benefits). In short, the “Constitution creates a democratic
    political system through which the people themselves
    must together find answers” to disagreements of this kind.
    
    Id., at 862
    (BREYER, J., dissenting).
    Third, cases such as Hunter v. Erickson, 
    393 U.S. 385
    (1969), and Washington v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 
    458 U.S. 457
    (1982), reflect an important principle, namely,
    that an individual’s ability to participate meaningfully in
    the political process should be independent of his race.
    Although racial minorities, like other political minorities,
    4                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    BREYER, J., concurring in judgment
    will not always succeed at the polls, they must have the
    same opportunity as others to secure through the ballot
    box policies that reflect their preferences. In my view,
    however, neither Hunter nor Seattle applies here. And the
    parties do not here suggest that the amendment violates
    the Equal Protection Clause if not under the Hunter-
    Seattle doctrine.
    Hunter and Seattle involved efforts to manipulate the
    political process in a way not here at issue. Both cases
    involved a restructuring of the political process that
    changed the political level at which policies were enacted.
    In Hunter, decisionmaking was moved from the elected
    city council to the local electorate at 
    large. 393 U.S., at 389
    –390. And in Seattle, decisionmaking by an elected
    school board was replaced with decisionmaking by the
    state legislature and electorate at 
    large. 458 U.S., at 466
    .
    This case, in contrast, does not involve a reordering of
    the political process; it does not in fact involve the move-
    ment of decisionmaking from one political level to another.
    Rather, here, Michigan law delegated broad policymaking
    authority to elected university boards, see Mich. Const.,
    Art. VIII, §5, but those boards delegated admissions-
    related decisionmaking authority to unelected university
    faculty members and administrators, see, e.g., Bylaws of
    Univ. of Mich. Bd. of Regents §8.01; Mich. State Univ.
    Bylaws of Bd. of Trustees, Preamble; Mich. State Univ.
    Bylaws for Academic Governance §4.4.3; Wayne State
    Univ. Stat. §§2–34–09, 2–34–12. Although the boards
    unquestionably retained the power to set policy regarding
    race-conscious     admissions,    see    post,   at    25–29
    (SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting), in fact faculty members and
    administrators set the race-conscious admissions policies
    in question.     (It is often true that elected bodies—
    including, for example, school boards, city councils, and
    state legislatures—have the power to enact policies, but in
    fact delegate that power to administrators.) Although at
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ____ (2014)            5
    BREYER, J., concurring in judgment
    limited times the university boards were advised of the
    content of their race-conscious admissions policies, see 
    701 F.3d 466
    , 481–482 (CA6 2012), to my knowledge no board
    voted to accept or reject any of those policies. Thus, un-
    elected faculty members and administrators, not voters or
    their elected representatives, adopted the race-conscious
    admissions programs affected by Michigan’s constitutional
    amendment. The amendment took decisionmaking au-
    thority away from these unelected actors and placed it in
    the hands of the voters.
    Why does this matter? For one thing, considered con-
    ceptually, the doctrine set forth in Hunter and Seattle does
    not easily fit this case. In those cases minorities had
    participated in the political process and they had won.
    The majority’s subsequent reordering of the political
    process repealed the minority’s successes and made it
    more difficult for the minority to succeed in the future.
    The majority thereby diminished the minority’s ability to
    participate meaningfully in the electoral process. But one
    cannot as easily characterize the movement of the deci-
    sionmaking mechanism at issue here—from an adminis-
    trative process to an electoral process—as diminishing the
    minority’s ability to participate meaningfully in the politi-
    cal process. There is no prior electoral process in which
    the minority participated.
    For another thing, to extend the holding of Hunter and
    Seattle to reach situations in which decisionmaking au-
    thority is moved from an administrative body to a political
    one would pose significant difficulties. The administrative
    process encompasses vast numbers of decisionmakers
    answering numerous policy questions in hosts of different
    fields. See Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Ac-
    counting Oversight Bd., 
    561 U.S. 477
    , ___ (2010) (BREYER,
    J., dissenting). Administrative bodies modify programs in
    detail, and decisionmaking authority within the adminis-
    trative process frequently moves around—due to amend-
    6                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    BREYER, J., concurring in judgment
    ments to statutes, new administrative rules, and evolving
    agency practice. It is thus particularly difficult in this
    context for judges to determine when a change in the locus
    of decisionmaking authority places a comparative struc-
    tural burden on a racial minority. And to apply Hunter
    and Seattle to the administrative process would, by tend-
    ing to hinder change, risk discouraging experimentation,
    interfering with efforts to see when and how race-
    conscious policies work.
    Finally, the principle that underlies Hunter and Seattle
    runs up against a competing principle, discussed above.
    This competing principle favors decisionmaking through
    the democratic process. Just as this principle strongly
    supports the right of the people, or their elected repre-
    sentatives, to adopt race-conscious policies for reasons of
    inclusion, so must it give them the right to vote not to do
    so.
    As I have said, my discussion here is limited to circum-
    stances in which decisionmaking is moved from an un-
    elected administrative body to a politically responsive one,
    and in which the targeted race-conscious admissions
    programs consider race solely in order to obtain the educa-
    tional benefits of a diverse student body. We need now
    decide no more than whether the Federal Constitution
    permits Michigan to apply its constitutional amendment
    in those circumstances. I would hold that it does. There-
    fore, I concur in the judgment of the Court.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)            1
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 12–682
    _________________
    BILL SCHUETTE, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF MICHI-
    GAN, PETITIONER v. COALITION TO DEFEND AF-
    FIRMATIVE ACTION, INTEGRATION AND IMMI-
    GRANT RIGHTS AND FIGHT FOR EQUALITY
    BY ANY MEANS NECESSARY (BAMN), ET AL.
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    [April 22, 2014]
    JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR, with whom JUSTICE GINSBURG
    joins, dissenting.
    We are fortunate to live in a democratic society. But
    without checks, democratically approved legislation can
    oppress minority groups. For that reason, our Constitu-
    tion places limits on what a majority of the people may do.
    This case implicates one such limit: the guarantee of equal
    protection of the laws. Although that guarantee is tradi-
    tionally understood to prohibit intentional discrimination
    under existing laws, equal protection does not end there.
    Another fundamental strand of our equal protection juris-
    prudence focuses on process, securing to all citizens the
    right to participate meaningfully and equally in self-
    government. That right is the bedrock of our democracy,
    for it preserves all other rights.
    Yet to know the history of our Nation is to understand
    its long and lamentable record of stymieing the right of
    racial minorities to participate in the political process. At
    first, the majority acted with an open, invidious purpose.
    Notwithstanding the command of the Fifteenth Amend-
    ment, certain States shut racial minorities out of the
    political process altogether by withholding the right to
    2                        SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    vote. This Court intervened to preserve that right. The
    majority tried again, replacing outright bans on voting
    with literacy tests, good character requirements, poll
    taxes, and gerrymandering. The Court was not fooled; it
    invalidated those measures, too. The majority persisted.
    This time, although it allowed the minority access to the
    political process, the majority changed the ground rules of
    the process so as to make it more difficult for the minority,
    and the minority alone, to obtain policies designed to
    foster racial integration. Although these political restruc-
    turings may not have been discriminatory in purpose, the
    Court reaffirmed the right of minority members of our
    society to participate meaningfully and equally in the
    political process.
    This case involves this last chapter of discrimination: A
    majority of the Michigan electorate changed the basic
    rules of the political process in that State in a manner that
    uniquely disadvantaged racial minorities.1 Prior to the
    enactment of the constitutional initiative at issue here,
    all of the admissions policies of Michigan’s public colleges
    and universities—including race-sensitive admissions poli-
    cies2—were in the hands of each institution’s governing
    ——————
    1 I of course do not mean to suggest that Michigan’s voters acted with
    anything like the invidious intent, see n. 8, infra, of those who histori-
    cally stymied the rights of racial minorities. Contra, ante, at 18, n. 11
    (SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment). But like earlier chapters of
    political restructuring, the Michigan amendment at issue in this case
    changed the rules of the political process to the disadvantage of minor-
    ity members of our society.
    2 Although the term “affirmative action” is commonly used to describe
    colleges’ and universities’ use of race in crafting admissions policies, I
    instead use the term “race-sensitive admissions policies.” Some com-
    prehend the term “affirmative action” as connoting intentional prefer-
    ential treatment based on race alone—for example, the use of a quota
    system, whereby a certain proportion of seats in an institution’s incom-
    ing class must be set aside for racial minorities; the use of a “points”
    system, whereby an institution accords a fixed numerical advantage to
    an applicant because of her race; or the admission of otherwise unquali-
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)                     3
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    board. The members of those boards are nominated by
    political parties and elected by the citizenry in statewide
    elections. After over a century of being shut out of Michi-
    gan’s institutions of higher education, racial minorities in
    Michigan had succeeded in persuading the elected board
    representatives to adopt admissions policies that took into
    account the benefits of racial diversity. And this Court
    twice blessed such efforts—first in Regents of Univ. of Cal.
    v. Bakke, 
    438 U.S. 265
    (1978), and again in Grutter v.
    Bollinger, 
    539 U.S. 306
    (2003), a case that itself concerned
    a Michigan admissions policy.
    In the wake of Grutter, some voters in Michigan set out
    to eliminate the use of race-sensitive admissions policies.
    Those voters were of course free to pursue this end in any
    number of ways. For example, they could have persuaded
    existing board members to change their minds through
    individual or grassroots lobbying efforts, or through gen-
    eral public awareness campaigns. Or they could have
    mobilized efforts to vote uncooperative board members out
    of office, replacing them with members who would share
    their desire to abolish race-sensitive admissions policies.
    When this Court holds that the Constitution permits a
    particular policy, nothing prevents a majority of a State’s
    ——————
    fied students to an institution solely on account of their race. None of
    this is an accurate description of the practices that public universities
    are permitted to adopt after this Court’s decision in Grutter v. Bol­
    linger, 
    539 U.S. 306
    (2003). There, we instructed that institutions of
    higher education could consider race in admissions in only a very
    limited way in an effort to create a diverse student body. To comport
    with Grutter, colleges and universities must use race flexibly, 
    id., at 334,
    and must not maintain a quota, 
    ibid. And even this
    limited
    sensitivity to race must be limited in time, 
    id., at 341–343,
    and must be
    employed only after “serious, good faith consideration of workable race-
    neutral alternatives,” 
    id., at 339.
    Grutter-compliant admissions plans,
    like the ones in place at Michigan’s institutions, are thus a far cry from
    affirmative action plans that confer preferential treatment intention-
    ally and solely on the basis of race.
    4                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    voters from choosing not to adopt that policy. Our system
    of government encourages—and indeed, depends on—that
    type of democratic action.
    But instead, the majority of Michigan voters changed
    the rules in the middle of the game, reconfiguring the
    existing political process in Michigan in a manner that
    burdened racial minorities. They did so in the 2006 elec-
    tion by amending the Michigan Constitution to enact Art.
    I, §26, which provides in relevant part that Michigan’s
    public universities “shall not discriminate against, or
    grant preferential treatment to, any individual or group on
    the basis of race, sex, color, ethnicity, or national origin in
    the operation of public employment, public education, or
    public contracting.”
    As a result of §26, there are now two very different
    processes through which a Michigan citizen is permitted to
    influence the admissions policies of the State’s universi-
    ties: one for persons interested in race-sensitive admis-
    sions policies and one for everyone else. A citizen who is a
    University of Michigan alumnus, for instance, can advo-
    cate for an admissions policy that considers an applicant’s
    legacy status by meeting individually with members of the
    Board of Regents to convince them of her views, by joining
    with other legacy parents to lobby the Board, or by voting
    for and supporting Board candidates who share her posi-
    tion. The same options are available to a citizen who
    wants the Board to adopt admissions policies that consider
    athleticism, geography, area of study, and so on. The one
    and only policy a Michigan citizen may not seek through
    this long-established process is a race-sensitive admissions
    policy that considers race in an individualized manner
    when it is clear that race-neutral alternatives are not
    adequate to achieve diversity. For that policy alone, the
    citizens of Michigan must undertake the daunting task of
    amending the State Constitution.
    Our precedents do not permit political restructurings
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)             5
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    that create one process for racial minorities and a sepa-
    rate, less burdensome process for everyone else. This
    Court has held that the Fourteenth Amendment does not
    tolerate “a political structure that treats all individuals as
    equals, yet more subtly distorts governmental processes in
    such a way as to place special burdens on the ability of
    minority groups to achieve beneficial legislation.” Wash­
    ington v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 
    458 U.S. 457
    , 467
    (1982) (internal quotation marks omitted). Such restruc-
    turing, the Court explained, “is no more permissible than
    denying [the minority] the [right to] vote, on an equal
    basis with others.” Hunter v. Erickson, 
    393 U.S. 385
    , 391
    (1969). In those cases—Hunter and Seattle—the Court
    recognized what is now known as the “political-process
    doctrine”: When the majority reconfigures the political
    process in a manner that burdens only a racial minority,
    that alteration triggers strict judicial scrutiny.
    Today, disregarding stare decisis, a majority of the
    Court effectively discards those precedents. The plurality
    does so, it tells us, because the freedom actually secured
    by the Constitution is the freedom of self-government—
    because the majority of Michigan citizens “exercised their
    privilege to enact laws as a basic exercise of their demo-
    cratic power.” Ante, at 15. It would be “demeaning to the
    democratic process,” the plurality concludes, to disturb
    that decision in any way. Ante, at 17. This logic embraces
    majority rule without an important constitutional limit.
    The plurality’s decision fundamentally misunderstands
    the nature of the injustice worked by §26. This case is not,
    as the plurality imagines, about “who may resolve” the
    debate over the use of race in higher education admis-
    sions. Ante, at 18. I agree wholeheartedly that nothing
    vests the resolution of that debate exclusively in the courts
    or requires that we remove it from the reach of the elec-
    torate. Rather, this case is about how the debate over the
    use of race-sensitive admissions policies may be resolved,
    6                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    contra, ibid.—that is, it must be resolved in constitution-
    ally permissible ways. While our Constitution does not
    guarantee minority groups victory in the political process,
    it does guarantee them meaningful and equal access to
    that process. It guarantees that the majority may not win
    by stacking the political process against minority groups
    permanently, forcing the minority alone to surmount
    unique obstacles in pursuit of its goals—here, educational
    diversity that cannot reasonably be accomplished through
    race-neutral measures. Today, by permitting a majority of
    the voters in Michigan to do what our Constitution forbids,
    the Court ends the debate over race-sensitive admissions
    policies in Michigan in a manner that contravenes consti-
    tutional protections long recognized in our precedents.
    Like the plurality, I have faith that our citizenry will
    continue to learn from this Nation’s regrettable history;
    that it will strive to move beyond those injustices towards
    a future of equality. And I, too, believe in the importance
    of public discourse on matters of public policy. But I part
    ways with the plurality when it suggests that judicial
    intervention in this case “impede[s]” rather than “ad-
    vance[s]” the democratic process and the ultimate hope of
    equality. Ante, at 16. I firmly believe that our role as
    judges includes policing the process of self-government
    and stepping in when necessary to secure the constitu-
    tional guarantee of equal protection. Because I would do
    so here, I respectfully dissent.
    I
    For much of its history, our Nation has denied to many
    of its citizens the right to participate meaningfully and
    equally in its politics. This is a history we strive to put
    behind us. But it is a history that still informs the society
    we live in, and so it is one we must address with candor.
    Because the political-process doctrine is best understood
    against the backdrop of this history, I will briefly trace its
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)           7
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    course.
    The Fifteenth Amendment, ratified after the Civil War,
    promised to racial minorities the right to vote. But many
    States ignored this promise. In addition to outright tactics
    of fraud, intimidation, and violence, there are countless
    examples of States categorically denying to racial minori-
    ties access to the political process. Consider Texas; there,
    a 1923 statute prevented racial minorities from participat-
    ing in primary elections. After this Court declared that
    statute unconstitutional, Nixon v. Herndon, 
    273 U.S. 536
    ,
    540–541 (1927), Texas responded by changing the rules.
    It enacted a new statute that gave political parties them-
    selves the right to determine who could participate in
    their primaries. Predictably, the Democratic Party speci-
    fied that only white Democrats could participate in its
    primaries. Nixon v. Condon, 
    286 U.S. 73
    , 81–82 (1932).
    The Court invalidated that scheme, too. 
    Id., at 89;
    see
    also Smith v. Allwright, 
    321 U.S. 649
    (1944); Terry v.
    Adams, 
    345 U.S. 461
    (1953).
    Some States were less direct. Oklahoma was one of
    many that required all voters to pass a literacy test. But
    the test did not apply equally to all voters. Under a
    “grandfather clause,” voters were exempt if their grand-
    fathers had been voters or had served as soldiers before
    1866. This meant, of course, that black voters had to pass
    the test, but many white voters did not. The Court held
    the scheme unconstitutional. Guinn v. United States, 
    238 U.S. 347
    (1915). In response, Oklahoma changed the
    rules. It enacted a new statute under which all voters who
    were qualified to vote in 1914 (under the unconstitutional
    grandfather clause) remained qualified, and the remaining
    voters had to apply for registration within a 12-day period.
    Lane v. Wilson, 
    307 U.S. 268
    , 270–271 (1939). The Court
    struck down that statute as well. 
    Id., at 275.
       Racial minorities were occasionally able to surmount the
    hurdles to their political participation. Indeed, in some
    8                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    States, minority citizens were even able to win elective
    office. But just as many States responded to the Fifteenth
    Amendment by subverting minorities’ access to the polls,
    many States responded to the prospect of elected minority
    officials by undermining the ability of minorities to win
    and hold elective office. Some States blatantly removed
    black officials from local offices. See, e.g., H. Rabinowitz,
    Race Relations in the Urban South, 1865–1890, pp. 267,
    269–270 (1978) (describing events in Tennessee and Vir-
    ginia). Others changed the processes by which local offi-
    cials were elected. See, e.g., Extension of the Voting
    Rights Act, Hearings before the Subcommittee on Civil
    and Constitutional Rights of the House Committee on the
    Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st Sess., pt. 1, pp. 2016–2017
    (1981) (hereinafter 1981 Hearings) (statement of Professor
    J. Morgan Kousser) (after a black judge refused to resign
    in Alabama, the legislature abolished the court on which
    he served and replaced it with one whose judges were
    appointed by the Governor); 
    Rabinowitz, supra, at 269
    –
    270 (the North Carolina Legislature divested voters of
    the right to elect justices of the peace and county commis-
    sioners, then arrogated to itself the authority to select
    justices of the peace and gave them the power to select
    commissioners).
    This Court did not stand idly by. In Alabama, for exam-
    ple, the legislature responded to increased black voter
    registration in the city of Tuskegee by amending the State
    Constitution to authorize legislative abolition of the county
    in which Tuskegee was located, Ala. Const. Amdt. 132
    (1957), repealed by Ala. Const. Amdt. 406 (1982), and by
    redrawing the city’s boundaries to remove all the black
    voters “while not removing a single white voter,” Gomil­
    lion v. Lightfoot, 
    364 U.S. 339
    , 341 (1960). The Court
    intervened, finding it “inconceivable that guaranties em-
    bedded in the Constitution” could be “manipulated out of
    existence” by being “cloaked in the garb of [political] rea-
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)           9
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    lignment.” 
    Id., at 345
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    This Court’s landmark ruling in Brown v. Board of
    Education, 
    347 U.S. 483
    (1954), triggered a new era of
    political restructuring, this time in the context of educa-
    tion. In Virginia, the General Assembly transferred con-
    trol of student assignment from local school districts to a
    State Pupil Placement Board. See B. Muse, Virginia’s
    Massive Resistance 34, 74 (1961). And when the legisla-
    ture learned that the Arlington County school board had
    prepared a desegregation plan, the General Assembly
    “swiftly retaliated” by stripping the county of its right to
    elect its school board by popular vote and instead making
    the board an appointed body. 
    Id., at 24;
    see also B. Smith,
    They Closed Their Schools 142–143 (1965).
    Other States similarly disregarded this Court’s mandate
    by changing their political process. See, e.g., Bush v.
    Orleans Parish School Bd., 
    187 F. Supp. 42
    , 44–45 (ED La.
    1960) (the Louisiana Legislature gave the Governor the
    authority to supersede any school board’s decision to
    integrate); Extension of the Voting Rights Act, Hearings
    on H. R. 4249 et al. before Subcommittee No. 5 of the
    House Committee on the Judiciary, 91st Cong., 1st Sess.,
    146–149 (1969) (statement of Thomas E. Harris, Assoc.
    Gen. Counsel, American Federation of Labor and Congress
    of Industrial Organizations) (the Mississippi Legislature
    removed from the people the right to elect superintendents
    of education in 11 counties and instead made those posi-
    tions appointive).
    The Court remained true to its command in Brown. In
    Arkansas, for example, it enforced a desegregation order
    against the Little Rock school board. Cooper v. Aaron, 
    358 U.S. 1
    , 5 (1958). On the very day the Court announced
    that ruling, the Arkansas Legislature responded by chang-
    ing the rules. It enacted a law permitting the Governor to
    close any public school in the State, and stripping local
    school districts of their decisionmaking authority so long
    10                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    as the Governor determined that local officials could not
    maintain “ ‘a general, suitable, and efficient educational
    system.’ ” Aaron v. Cooper, 
    261 F.2d 97
    , 99 (CA8 1958)
    (per curiam) (quoting Arkansas statute).           The then-
    Governor immediately closed all of Little Rock’s high
    schools. 
    Id., at 99–100;
    see also S. Breyer, Making Our
    Democracy Work 49–67 (2010) (discussing the events in
    Little Rock).
    The States’ political restructuring efforts in the 1960’s
    and 1970’s went beyond the context of education. Many
    States tried to suppress the political voice of racial minori-
    ties more generally by reconfiguring the manner in which
    they filled vacancies in local offices, often transferring
    authority from the electorate (where minority citizens had
    a voice at the local level) to the States’ executive branch
    (where minorities wielded little if any influence). See, e.g.,
    1981 Hearings, pt. 1, at 815 (report of J. Cox & A. Turner)
    (the Alabama Legislature changed all municipal judge-
    ships from elective to appointive offices); 
    id., at 1955
    (report of R. Hudlin & K. Brimah, Voter Educ. Project,
    Inc.) (the Georgia Legislature eliminated some elective
    offices and made others appointive when it appeared that
    a minority candidate would be victorious); 
    id., at 501
    (statement of Frank R. Parker, Director, Lawyers’ Comm.
    for Civil Rights Under Law) (the Mississippi Legislature
    changed the manner of filling vacancies for various public
    offices from election to appointment).
    II
    It was in this historical context that the Court inter-
    vened in Hunter v. Erickson, 
    393 U.S. 385
    (1969), and
    Washington v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 
    458 U.S. 457
    (1982). Together, Hunter and Seattle recognized a funda-
    mental strand of this Court’s equal protection jurispru-
    dence: the political-process doctrine. To understand that
    doctrine fully, it is necessary to set forth in detail precisely
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)           11
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    what the Court had before it, and precisely what it said.
    For to understand Hunter and Seattle is to understand
    why those cases straightforwardly resolve this one.
    A
    In Hunter, the City Council of Akron, Ohio, enacted a
    fair housing ordinance to “assure equal opportunity to all
    persons to live in decent housing facilities regardless of
    race, color, religion, ancestry, or national origin.
    393 U.S., at 386
    (internal quotation marks omitted). A major-
    ity of the citizens of Akron disagreed with the ordinance
    and overturned it. But the majority did not stop there; it
    also amended the city charter to prevent the City Council
    from implementing any future ordinance dealing with
    racial, religious, or ancestral discrimination in housing
    without the approval of the majority of the Akron elec-
    torate. 
    Ibid. That amendment changed
    the rules of the
    political process in Akron. The Court described the result
    of the change as follows:
    “[T]o enact an ordinance barring housing discrimina-
    tion on the basis of race or religion, proponents had to
    obtain the approval of the City Council and of a major-
    ity of the voters citywide. To enact an ordinance pre-
    venting housing discrimination on other grounds, or
    to enact any other type of housing ordinance, propo-
    nents needed the support of only the City Council.”
    
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 468
    (describing Hunter; empha-
    sis deleted).
    The Court invalidated the Akron charter amendment
    under the Equal Protection Clause. It concluded that the
    amendment unjustifiably “place[d] special burdens on
    racial minorities within the governmental process,” thus
    effecting “a real, substantial, and invidious denial of the
    equal protection of the laws.” 
    Hunter, 393 U.S., at 391
    ,
    393. The Court characterized the amendment as “no more
    12                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    permissible” than denying racial minorities the right to
    vote on an equal basis with the majority. 
    Id., at 391.
    For
    a “State may no more disadvantage any particular group
    by making it more difficult to enact legislation in its behalf
    than it may dilute any person’s vote or give any group a
    smaller representation than another of comparable size.”
    
    Id., at 392–393.
    The vehicle for the change—a popular
    referendum—did not move the Court: “The sovereignty of
    the people,” it explained, “is itself subject to . . . constitu-
    tional limitations.” 
    Id., at 392.
       Justice Harlan, joined by Justice Stewart, wrote in his
    concurrence that although a State can normally allocate
    political power according to any general principle, it bears
    a “far heavier burden of justification” when it reallocates
    political power based on race, because the selective reallo-
    cation necessarily makes it far more difficult for racial
    minorities to “achieve legislation that is in their interest.”
    
    Id., at 395
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    In Seattle, a case that mirrors the one before us, the
    Court applied Hunter to invalidate a statute, enacted by a
    majority of Washington State’s citizens, that prohibited
    racially integrative busing in the wake of Brown. As early
    as 1963, Seattle’s School District No. 1 began taking steps
    to cure the de facto racial segregation in its 
    schools. 458 U.S., at 460
    –461. Among other measures, it enacted a
    desegregation plan that made extensive use of busing and
    mandatory assignments. 
    Id., at 461.
    The district was
    under no obligation to adopt the plan; Brown charged
    school boards with a duty to integrate schools that were
    segregated because of de jure racial discrimination, but
    there had been no finding that the de facto segregation in
    Seattle’s schools was the product of de jure 
    discrimination. 458 U.S., at 472
    , n. 15. Several residents who opposed
    the desegregation efforts formed a committee and sued to
    enjoin implementation of the plan. 
    Id., at 461.
    When
    these efforts failed, the committee sought to change the
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)              13
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    rules of the political process. It drafted a statewide initia-
    tive “designed to terminate the use of mandatory busing
    for purposes of racial integration.” 
    Id., at 462.
    A major-
    ity of the State’s citizens approved the initiative. 
    Id., at 463–464.
       The Court invalidated the initiative under the Equal
    Protection Clause. It began by observing that equal pro-
    tection of the laws “guarantees racial minorities the right
    to full participation in the political life of the community.”
    
    Id., at 467.
    “It is beyond dispute,” the Court explained,
    “that given racial or ethnic groups may not be denied the
    franchise, or precluded from entering into the political
    process in a reliable and meaningful manner.” 
    Ibid. But the Equal
    Protection Clause reaches further, the Court
    stated, reaffirming the principle espoused in Hunter—that
    while “laws structuring political institutions or allocating
    political power according to neutral principles” do not
    violate the Constitution, “a different analysis is required
    when the State allocates governmental power nonneutrally,
    by explicitly using the racial nature of a decision to de-
    termine the decisionmaking 
    process.” 458 U.S., at 470
    .
    That kind of state action, it observed, “places special bur-
    dens on racial minorities within the governmental pro-
    cess,” by making it “more difficult for certain racial and
    religious minorities” than for other members of the com-
    munity “to achieve legislation . . . in their interest.” 
    Ibid. Rejecting the argument
    that the initiative had no racial
    focus, the Court found that the desegregation of public
    schools, like the Akron housing ordinance, “inure[d] pri-
    marily to the benefit of the minority, and [was] designed
    for that purpose.” 
    Id., at 472.
    Because minorities had
    good reason to “consider busing for integration to be ‘legis-
    lation that is in their interest,’ ” the Court concluded that
    the “racial focus of [the initiative] . . . suffice[d] to trigger
    application of the Hunter doctrine.” 
    Id., at 474
    (quoting
    
    Hunter, 393 U.S., at 395
    ) (Harlan, J. concurring)).
    14                        SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    The Court next concluded that “the practical effect of
    [the initiative was] to work a reallocation of power of the
    kind condemned in Hunter.” 
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 474
    . It
    explained: “Those favoring the elimination of de facto
    school segregation now must seek relief from the state
    legislature, or from the statewide electorate. Yet authority
    over all other student assignment decisions, as well as
    over most other areas of educational policy, remains vested
    in the local school board.” 
    Ibid. Thus, the initiative
    re-
    quired those in favor of racial integration in public schools
    to “surmount a considerably higher hurdle than persons
    seeking comparable legislative action” in different con-
    texts. 
    Ibid. The Court reaffirmed
    that the “ ‘simple repeal or modifi-
    cation of desegregation or antidiscrimination laws, without
    more, never has been viewed as embodying a presump-
    tively invalid racial classification.’ ” 
    Id., at 483
    (quoting
    Crawford v. Board of Ed. of Los Angeles, 
    458 U.S. 527
    ,
    539 (1982)). But because the initiative burdened future
    attempts to integrate by lodging the decisionmaking au-
    thority at a “new and remote level of government,” it was
    more than a “mere repeal”; it was an unconstitutionally
    discriminatory change to the political process.3 Seattle,
    ——————
    3 In Crawford, the Court confronted an amendment to the California
    Constitution prohibiting state courts from mandating pupil assign-
    ments unless a federal court would be required to do so under the
    Equal Protection Clause. We upheld the amendment as nothing more
    than a repeal of existing legislation: The standard previously required
    by California went beyond what was federally required; the amendment
    merely moved the standard back to the federal baseline. The Court
    distinguished the amendment from the one in Seattle because it left the
    rules of the political game unchanged. Racial minorities in Crawford,
    unlike racial minorities in Seattle, could still appeal to their local school
    districts for relief.
    The Crawford Court distinguished Hunter v. Erickson, 
    393 U.S. 385
    (1969), by clarifying that the charter amendment in Hunter was “some-
    thing more than a mere repeal” because it altered the framework of the
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)                   15
    SOTOMAYOR, J., 
    dissenting 458 U.S., at 483
    –484.
    B
    Hunter and Seattle vindicated a principle that is as
    elementary to our equal protection jurisprudence as it is
    essential: The majority may not suppress the minority’s
    right to participate on equal terms in the political process.
    Under this doctrine, governmental action deprives minor-
    ity groups of equal protection when it (1) has a racial focus,
    targeting a policy or program that “inures primarily to the
    benefit of the minority,” 
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 472
    ; and
    (2) alters the political process in a manner that uniquely
    burdens racial minorities’ ability to achieve their goals
    through that process. A faithful application of the doc-
    trine resoundingly resolves this case in respondents’ favor.
    1
    Section 26 has a “racial focus.” 
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 474
    . That is clear from its text, which prohibits Michi-
    gan’s public colleges and universities from “grant[ing]
    preferential treatment to any individual or group on the
    basis of race.” Mich. Const., Art. I, §26. Like desegrega-
    tion of public schools, race-sensitive admissions policies
    “inur[e] primarily to the benefit of the minority,
    458 U.S., at 472
    , as they are designed to increase minorities’
    access to institutions of higher education.4
    ——————
    political 
    process. 458 U.S., at 540
    . And the Seattle Court drew the
    same distinction when it held that the initiative “work[ed] something
    more than the ‘mere repeal’ of a desegregation law by the political
    entity that created 
    it.” 458 U.S., at 483
    .
    4 JUSTICE SCALIA accuses me of crafting my own version (or versions)
    of the racial-focus prong. See ante, at 8–9, n. 4 (opinion concurring in
    judgment). I do not. I simply apply the test announced in Seattle:
    whether the policy in question “inures primarily to the benefit of the
    
    minority.” 458 U.S., at 472
    . JUSTICE SCALIA ignores this analysis, see
    Part 
    II–B–1, supra
    , and instead purports to identify three versions of
    the test that he thinks my opinion advances. The first—whether “ ‘the
    policy in question benefits only a racial minority, ’ ” ante, at 8, n. 4
    16                       SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    Petitioner argues that race-sensitive admissions policies
    cannot “inur[e] primarily to the benefit of the minority,”
    ibid., as the Court has upheld such policies only insofar as
    they further “the educational benefits that flow from a
    diverse student body,” 
    Grutter, 539 U.S., at 343
    . But
    there is no conflict between this Court’s pronouncement in
    Grutter and the common-sense reality that race-sensitive
    admissions policies benefit minorities.       Rather, race-
    sensitive admissions policies further a compelling state
    interest in achieving a diverse student body precisely
    because they increase minority enrollment, which neces-
    sarily benefits minority groups. In other words, constitu-
    tionally permissible race-sensitive admissions policies can
    both serve the compelling interest of obtaining the educa-
    tional benefits that flow from a diverse student body, and
    inure to the benefit of racial minorities. There is nothing
    mutually exclusive about the two. Cf. 
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 472
    (concluding that the desegregation plan had a racial
    focus even though “white as well as Negro children bene-
    fit from exposure to ‘ethnic and racial diversity in the
    classroom’ ”).
    It is worth emphasizing, moreover, that §26 is relevant
    ——————
    
    (quoting supra, at 5
    )—misunderstands the doctrine and misquotes my
    opinion. The racial-focus prong has never required a policy to benefit
    only a minority group. The sentence from which JUSTICE SCALIA
    appears to quote makes the altogether different point that the political-
    process doctrine is obviously not implicated in the first place by a
    restructuring that burdens members of society equally. This is the
    second prong of the political-process doctrine. 
    See supra, at 5
    (explain-
    ing that the political-process doctrine is implicated “[w]hen the majority
    reconfigures the political process in a manner that burdens only a
    racial minority”). The second version—which asks whether a policy
    “benefits primarily a racial minority,” ante, at 8, n. 4—is the one
    articulated by the Seattle Court and, as I have explained, 
    see supra, at 15
    and this page, it is easily met in this case. And the third—whether
    the policy has “the incidental effect” of benefitting racial minorities,”
    ante, at 8–9, n. 4—is not a test I advance at all.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)           17
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    only to admissions policies that have survived strict scru-
    tiny under Grutter; other policies, under this Court’s
    rulings, would be forbidden with or without §26. A Grutter-
    compliant admissions policy must use race flexibly, not
    maintain a quota; must be limited in time; and must be
    employed only after “serious, good faith consideration of
    workable race-neutral 
    alternatives,” 539 U.S., at 339
    .
    The policies banned by §26 meet all these requirements
    and thus already constitute the least restrictive ways to
    advance Michigan’s compelling interest in diversity in
    higher education.
    2
    Section 26 restructures the political process in Michigan
    in a manner that places unique burdens on racial minori-
    ties. It establishes a distinct and more burdensome politi-
    cal process for the enactment of admissions plans that
    consider racial diversity.
    Long before the enactment of §26, the Michigan Consti-
    tution granted plenary authority over all matters relating
    to Michigan’s public universities, including admissions
    criteria, to each university’s eight-member governing
    board. See Mich. Const., Art. VIII, §5 (establishing the
    Board of Regents of the University of Michigan, the Board
    of Trustees of Michigan State University, and the Board of
    Governors of Wayne State University). The boards have
    the “power to enact ordinances, by-laws and regulations
    for the government of the university.” Mich. Comp. Laws
    Ann. §390.5 (West 2010); see also §390.3 (“The govern-
    ment of the university is vested in the board of regents”).
    They are “ ‘constitutional corporation[s] of independent
    authority, which, within the scope of [their] functions,
    [are] co-ordinate with and equal to . . . the legislature.’ ”
    Federated Publications, Inc. v. Board of Trustees of Mich.
    State Univ., 
    460 Mich. 75
    , 84, n. 8, 
    594 N.W.2d 491
    , 496,
    n. 8 (1999).
    18                      SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    The boards are indisputably a part of the political pro-
    cess in Michigan. Each political party nominates two
    candidates for membership to each board, and board
    members are elected to 8-year terms in the general
    statewide election.        See Mich. Comp. Laws Ann.
    §§168.282, 168.286 (West 2008); Mich. Const., Art. VIII,
    §5. Prior to §26, board candidates frequently included
    their views on race-sensitive admissions in their cam-
    paigns. For example, in 2005, one candidate pledged to
    “work to end so-called ‘Affirmative-Action,’ a racist, de-
    grading system.” See League of Women Voters, 2005
    General Election Voter Guide, online at http://
    www.lwvka.org/guide04/regents/html (all Internet materi-
    als as visited Apr. 18, 2014, and available in Clerk of
    Court’s case file); see also George, U-M Regents Race Tests
    Policy, Detroit Free Press, Oct. 26, 2000, p. 2B (noting that
    one candidate “opposes affirmative action admissions
    policies” because they “ ‘basically sa[y] minority students
    are not qualified’ ”).
    Before the enactment of §26, Michigan’s political struc-
    ture permitted both supporters and opponents of race-
    sensitive admissions policies to vote for their candidates of
    choice and to lobby the elected and politically accountable
    boards. Section 26 reconfigured that structure. After §26,
    the boards retain plenary authority over all admissions
    criteria except for race-sensitive admissions policies.5 To
    change admissions policies on this one issue, a Michigan
    citizen must instead amend the Michigan Constitution.
    That is no small task. To place a proposed constitutional
    ——————
    5 By stripping the governing boards of the authority to decide whether
    to adopt race-sensitive admissions policies, the majority removed the
    decision from bodies well suited to make that decision: boards engaged
    in the arguments on both sides of a matter, which deliberate and
    then make and refine “considered judgment[s]” about racial diversity
    and admissions policies, see 
    Grutter, 539 U.S., at 387
    (KENNEDY, J.,
    dissenting).
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)            19
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    amendment on the ballot requires either the support of
    two-thirds of both Houses of the Michigan Legislature or a
    vast number of signatures from Michigan voters—10
    percent of the total number of votes cast in the preceding
    gubernatorial election. See Mich. Const., Art. XII, §§1, 2.
    Since more than 3.2 million votes were cast in the 2010
    election for Governor, more than 320,000 signatures are
    currently needed to win a ballot spot. See Brief for Gary
    Segura et al. as Amici Curiae 9 (hereinafter Segura Brief).
    Moreover, “[t]o account for invalid and duplicative signa-
    tures, initiative sponsors ‘need to obtain substantially
    more than the actual required number of signatures,
    typically by a 25% to 50% margin.’ ” 
    Id., at 10
    (quoting
    Tolbert, Lowenstein, & Donovan, Election Law and Rules
    for Using Initiatives, in Citizens as Legislators: Direct
    Democracy in the United States 27, 37 (S. Bowler, T.
    Donovan, & C. Tolbert eds., 1998)).
    And the costs of qualifying an amendment are signifi-
    cant. For example, “[t]he vast majority of petition ef-
    forts . . . require initiative sponsors to hire paid petition
    circulators, at significant expense.” Segura Brief 10; see
    also T. Donovan, C. Mooney, & D. Smith, State and Local
    Politics: Institutions and Reform 96 (2012) (hereinafter
    Donovan) (“In many states, it is difficult to place a meas-
    ure on the ballot unless professional petition firms are
    paid to collect some or all the signatures required for
    qualification”); 
    Tolbert, supra, at 35
    (“ ‘Qualifying an
    initiative for the statewide ballot is . . . no longer so much
    a measure of general citizen interest as it is a test of fund-
    raising ability’ ”). In addition to the cost of collecting
    signatures, campaigning for a majority of votes is an
    expensive endeavor, and “organizations advocating on
    behalf of marginalized groups remain . . . outmoneyed by
    corporate, business, and professional organizations.”
    Strolovitch & Forrest, Social and Economic Justice Move-
    ments and Organizations, in The Oxford Handbook of
    20                       SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    American Political Parties and Interest Groups 468, 471
    (L. Maisel & J. Berry eds., 2010). In 2008, for instance,
    over $800 million was spent nationally on state-level
    initiative and referendum campaigns, nearly $300 million
    more than was spent in the 2006 cycle. Donovan 98. “In
    several states, more money [is] spent on ballot initiative
    campaigns than for all other races for political office com-
    bined.” 
    Ibid. Indeed, the amount
    spent on state-level
    initiative and referendum campaigns in 2008 eclipsed the
    $740.6 million spent by President Obama in his 2008
    presidential campaign, Salant, Spending Doubled as
    Obama Led Billion-Dollar Campaign, Bloomberg News,
    Dec. 27, 2008, online at http://www.bloomberg.com/apps/
    news?pid=newsarchive&sid=anLDS9WWPQW8.
    Michigan’s Constitution has only rarely been amended
    through the initiative process. Between 1914 and 2000,
    voters have placed only 60 statewide initiatives on the
    Michigan ballot, of which only 20 have passed. See Segura
    Brief 12. Minority groups face an especially uphill battle.
    See Donovan 106 (“[O]n issues dealing with racial and
    ethnic matters, studies show that racial and ethnic minor-
    ities do end up more on the losing side of the popular
    vote”). In fact, “[i]t is difficult to find even a single
    statewide initiative in any State in which voters approved
    policies that explicitly favor racial or ethnic minority
    groups.”6 Segura Brief 13.
    ——————
    6 In the face of this overwhelming evidence, JUSTICE SCALIA claims
    that it is actually easier, not harder, for minorities to effectuate change
    at the constitutional amendment level than at the board level. See
    ante, at 11–12 (opinion concurring in judgment) (“voting in a favorable
    board (each of which has eight members) at the three major public
    universities requires electing by majority vote at least 15 different
    candidates, several of whom would be running during different election
    cycles”). This claim minimizes just how difficult it is to amend the
    State Constitution. 
    See supra, at 18
    –20. It is also incorrect in its
    premise that minorities must elect an entirely new slate of board
    members in order to effectuate change at the board level. JUSTICE
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)                      21
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    This is the onerous task that §26 forces a Michigan
    citizen to complete in order to change the admissions
    policies of Michigan’s public colleges and universities with
    respect to racial sensitivity. While substantially less
    grueling paths remain open to those advocating for any
    other admissions policies, a constitutional amendment is
    the only avenue by which race-sensitive admissions poli-
    cies may be obtained. The effect of §26 is that a white
    graduate of a public Michigan university who wishes to
    pass his historical privilege on to his children may freely
    lobby the board of that university in favor of an expanded
    legacy admissions policy, whereas a black Michigander
    who was denied the opportunity to attend that very uni-
    versity cannot lobby the board in favor of a policy that
    might give his children a chance that he never had and
    that they might never have absent that policy.
    Such reordering of the political process contravenes
    Hunter and Seattle.7 See 
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 467
    (the
    Equal Protection Clause prohibits “ ‘a political structure
    that treats all individuals as equals,’ yet more subtly
    distorts governmental processes in such a way as to place
    special burdens on the ability of minority groups to
    ——————
    SCALIA overlooks the fact that minorities need not elect any new board
    members in order to effect change; they may instead seek to persuade
    existing board members to adopt changes in their interests.
    7 I do not take the position, as JUSTICE SCALIA asserts, that the pro-
    cess of amending the Michigan Constitution is not a part of Michigan’s
    existing political process. See ante, at 13–14 (opinion concurring in
    judgment). It clearly is. The problem with §26 is not that “amending
    Michigan’s Constitution is simply not a part of that State’s ‘existing
    political process.’ ” Ante, at 14. It is that §26 reconfigured the political
    process in Michigan such that it is now more difficult for racial minori-
    ties, and racial minorities alone, to achieve legislation in their interest.
    Section 26 elevated the issue of race-sensitive admissions policies,
    and not any other kinds of admissions policies, to a higher plane of
    the existing political process in Michigan: that of a constitutional
    amendment.
    22                       SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    achieve beneficial legislation” (citation omitted)). Where,
    as here, the majority alters the political process to the
    detriment of a racial minority, the governmental action is
    subject to strict scrutiny. See 
    id., at 485,
    n. 28. Michigan
    does not assert that §26 satisfies a compelling state inter-
    est. That should settle the matter.
    C
    1
    The plurality sees it differently. Disregarding the lan-
    guage used in Hunter, the plurality asks us to contort that
    case into one that “rests on the unremarkable principle
    that the State may not alter the procedures of government
    to target racial minorities.” Ante, at 8. And the plurality
    recasts Seattle “as a case in which the state action in
    question . . . had the serious risk, if not purpose, of causing
    specific injuries on account of race.” Ante, at 8–9. Accord-
    ing to the plurality, the Hunter and Seattle Courts were
    not concerned with efforts to reconfigure the political
    process to the detriment of racial minorities; rather, those
    cases invalidated governmental actions merely because
    they reflected an invidious purpose to discriminate. This
    is not a tenable reading of those cases.
    The plurality identifies “invidious discrimination” as the
    “necessary result” of the restructuring in Hunter. Ante, at
    8. It is impossible to assess whether the housing amend-
    ment in Hunter was motivated by discriminatory purpose,
    for the opinion does not discuss the question of intent.8
    ——————
    8 It certainly is fair to assume that some voters may have supported
    the Hunter amendment because of discriminatory animus. But others
    may have been motivated by their strong beliefs in the freedom of
    contract or the freedom to alienate property. Similarly, here, although
    some Michiganders may have voted for §26 out of racial animus, some
    may have been acting on a personal belief, like that of some of my
    colleagues today, that using race-sensitive admissions policies in higher
    education is unwise. The presence (or absence) of invidious discrimina-
    tion has no place in the current analysis. That is the very purpose of
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)                    23
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    What is obvious, however, is that the possibility of invidi-
    ous discrimination played no role in the Court’s reasoning.
    We ordinarily understand our precedents to mean what
    they actually say, not what we later think they could or
    should have said. The Hunter Court was clear about why
    it invalidated the Akron charter amendment: It was im-
    permissible as a restructuring of the political process, not
    as an action motivated by discriminatory intent. 
    See 393 U.S., at 391
    (striking down the Akron charter amendment
    because it “places a special burden on racial minorities
    within the governmental process”).
    Similarly, the plurality disregards what Seattle actually
    says and instead opines that “the political restriction in
    question was designed to be used, or was likely to be used,
    to encourage infliction of injury by reason of race.” Ante,
    at 17. Here, the plurality derives its conclusion not from
    Seattle itself, but from evidence unearthed more than a
    quarter-century later in Parents Involved in Community
    Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 
    551 U.S. 701
    (2007):
    “Although there had been no judicial finding of de jure
    segregation with respect to Seattle’s school district, it
    appears as though school desegregation in the district in
    the 1940’s and 1950’s may have been the partial result of
    school board policies that ‘permitted white students to
    transfer out of black schools while restricting the transfer
    of black students into white schools.’ ”9 Ante, at 9 (quoting
    Parents 
    Involved, 551 U.S., at 807
    –808 (BREYER, J., dis-
    senting) (emphasis added). It follows, according to the
    ——————
    the political-process doctrine; it operates irrespective of discriminatory
    intent, for it protects a process-based right.
    9 The plurality relies on JUSTICE BREYER’s dissent in Parents Involved
    to conclude that “one permissible reading of the record was that the
    school board had maintained policies to perpetuate racial segregation
    in the schools.” Ante, at 9–10. Remarkably, some Members of today’s
    plurality criticized JUSTICE BREYER’s reading of the record in Parents
    Involved itself. 
    See 551 U.S., at 736
    .
    24                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    plurality, that Seattle’s desegregation plan was constitu-
    tionally required, so that the initiative halting the plan
    was an instance of invidious discrimination aimed at
    inflicting a racial injury.
    Again, the plurality might prefer that the Seattle Court
    had said that, but it plainly did not. Not once did the
    Court suggest the presence of de jure segregation in Seat-
    tle. Quite the opposite: The opinion explicitly suggested
    the desegregation plan was adopted to remedy de facto
    rather than de jure segregation. 
    See 458 U.S., at 472
    ,
    n. 15 (referring to the “absen[ce]” of “a finding of prior de
    jure segregation”). The Court, moreover, assumed that no
    “constitutional violation” through de jure segregation had
    occurred. 
    Id., at 474.
    And it unmistakably rested its
    decision on Hunter, holding Seattle’s initiative invalid
    because it “use[d] the racial nature of an issue to define
    the governmental decisionmaking structure, and thus
    impose[d] substantial and unique burdens on racial minor-
    
    ities.” 458 U.S., at 470
    .
    It is nothing short of baffling, then, for the plurality to
    insist—in the face of clear language in Hunter and Seattle
    saying otherwise—that those cases were about nothing
    more than the intentional and invidious infliction of a
    racial injury. Ante, at 8 (describing the injury in Hunter
    as “a demonstrated injury on the basis of race”); ante, at
    8–9 (describing the injury in Seattle as an “injur[y] on
    account of race”). The plurality’s attempt to rewrite
    Hunter and Seattle so as to cast aside the political-process
    doctrine sub silentio is impermissible as a matter of stare
    decisis. Under the doctrine of stare decisis, we usually
    stand by our decisions, even if we disagree with them,
    because people rely on what we say, and they believe they
    can take us at our word.
    And what now of the political-process doctrine? After
    the plurality’s revision of Hunter and Seattle, it is unclear
    what is left. The plurality certainly does not tell us. On
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)            25
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    this point, and this point only, I agree with JUSTICE
    SCALIA that the plurality has rewritten those precedents
    beyond recognition. See ante, at 5–7 (opinion concurring
    in judgment).
    2
    JUSTICE BREYER concludes that Hunter and Seattle do
    not apply. Section 26, he reasons, did not move the rele-
    vant decisionmaking authority from one political level to
    another; rather, it removed that authority from “unelected
    actors and placed it in the hands of the voters.” Ante, at 5
    (opinion concurring in judgment). He bases this conclu-
    sion on the premise that Michigan’s elected boards “dele-
    gated admissions-related decisionmaking authority to
    unelected university faculty members and administra-
    tors.” 
    Ibid. But this premise
    is simply incorrect.
    For one thing, it is undeniable that prior to §26, board
    candidates often pledged to end or carry on the use of race-
    sensitive admissions policies at Michigan’s public univer-
    sities. 
    See supra, at 18
    . Surely those were not empty
    promises. Indeed, the issue of race-sensitive admissions
    policies often dominated board elections. See, e.g., George,
    Detroit Free Press, at 2B (observing that “[t]he race for
    the University of Michigan Board of Regents could deter-
    mine . . . the future of [the University’s] affirmative action
    policies”); Kosseff, UM Policy May Hang On Election,
    Crain’s Detroit Business, Sept. 18, 2000, p. 1 (noting that
    an upcoming election could determine whether the Uni-
    versity would continue to defend its affirmative action
    policies); University of Michigan’s Admissions Policy Still
    an Issue for Regents’ Election, Black Issues in Higher
    Education, Oct. 21, 2004, p. 17 (commenting that although
    “the Supreme Court struck down the University of Michi-
    gan’s undergraduate admissions policy as too formulaic,”
    the issue “remains an important [one] to several peo-
    ple running” in an upcoming election for the Board of
    26                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    Regents).
    Moreover, a careful examination of the boards and their
    governing structure reveals that they remain actively
    involved in setting admissions policies and procedures.
    Take Wayne State University, for example. Its Board of
    Governors has enacted university statutes that govern the
    day-to-day running of the institution. See Wayne State
    Univ. Stat., online at http://bog.wayne.edu/code. A num-
    ber of those statutes establish general admissions proce-
    dures, see §2.34.09 (establishing undergraduate admis-
    sions procedures); §2.34.12 (establishing graduate
    admissions procedures), and some set out more specific
    instructions for university officials, see, e.g., §2.34.09.030
    (“Admissions decisions will be based on a full evaluation of
    each student’s academic record, and on empirical data
    reflecting the characteristics of students who have suc-
    cessfully graduated from [the university] within the four
    years prior to the year in which the student applies”);
    §§2.34.12.080, 2.34.12.090 (setting the requisite grade
    point average for graduate applicants).
    The Board of Governors does give primary responsibility
    over day-to-day admissions matters to the university’s
    President. §2.34.09.080. But the President is “elected by
    and answerable to the Board.” Brief for Respondent Board
    of Governors of Wayne State University et al. 15. And
    while university officials and faculty members “serv[e] an
    important advisory role in recommending educational
    policy,” 
    id., at 14,
    the Board alone ultimately controls
    educational policy and decides whether to adopt (or reject)
    program-specific admissions recommendations. For ex-
    ample, the Board has voted on recommendations “to revise
    guidelines for establishment of honors curricula, including
    admissions criteria”; “to modify the honor point criteria for
    graduate admission”; and “to modify the maximum num-
    ber of transfer credits that the university would allow in
    certain cases where articulation agreements rendered
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)           27
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    modification appropriate.” 
    Id., at 17;
    see also 
    id., at 18–20
    (providing examples of the Board’s “review[ing] and
    pass[ing] upon admissions requirements in the course of
    voting on broader issues, such as the implementation of
    new academic programs”). The Board also “engages in
    robust and regular review of administrative actions in-
    volving admissions policy and related matters.” 
    Id., at 16.
       Other public universities more clearly entrust admis-
    sions policy to university officials. The Board of Regents
    of the University of Michigan, for example, gives primary
    responsibility for admissions to the Associate Vice Provost,
    Executive Director of Undergraduate Admissions, and
    Directors of Admissions. Bylaws §8.01, online at http://
    www.regents.umich.edu/bylaws. And the Board of Trus-
    tees of Michigan State University relies on the President
    to make recommendations regarding admissions policies.
    Bylaws, Art. 8, online at http://www.trustees.msu.edu/
    bylaws. But the bylaws of the Board of Regents and the
    Board of Trustees “make clear that all university opera-
    tions remain subject to their control.” Brief for Respond-
    ents Regents of the University of Michigan, the Board of
    Trustees of Michigan State University et al. 13–14.
    The boards retain ultimate authority to adopt or reject
    admissions policies in at least three ways. First, they
    routinely meet with university officials to review admis-
    sions policies, including race-sensitive admissions policies.
    For example, shortly after this Court’s decisions in Gratz
    v. Bollinger, 
    539 U.S. 244
    (2003), and 
    Grutter, 539 U.S., at 306
    , the President of the University of Michigan ap-
    peared before the University’s Board of Regents to discuss
    the impact of those decisions on the University. See
    Proceedings 2003–2004, pp. 10–12 (July 2003), online
    at http://name.umdl.umich.edu/ACW7513.2003.001. Six
    members of the Board voiced strong support for the Uni-
    versity’s use of race as a factor in admissions. 
    Id., at 11–
    12. In June 2004, the President again appeared before the
    28                      SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    Board to discuss changes to undergraduate admissions
    policies. 
    Id., at 301
    (June 2004). And in March 2007, the
    University’s Provost appeared before the Board of Regents
    to present strategies to increase diversity in light of the
    passage of Proposal 2. Proceedings 2006–2007, pp. 264–
    265 (Mar. 2007), online at http://name.umdl.umich.edu/
    ACW7513.2006.001.
    Second, the boards may enact bylaws with respect to
    specific admissions policies and may alter any admissions
    policies set by university officials. The Board of Regents
    may amend any bylaw “at any regular meeting of the
    board, or at any special meeting, provided notice is given
    to each regent one week in advance.” Bylaws §14.03. And
    Michigan State University’s Board of Trustees may,
    “[u]pon the recommendation of the President[,] . . . deter-
    mine and establish the qualifications of students for ad-
    missions at any level.” Bylaws, Art. 8. The boards may
    also permanently remove certain admissions decisions
    from university officials.10 This authority is not merely
    theoretical. Between 2008 and 2012, the University of
    Michigan’s Board of Regents “revised more than two dozen
    of its bylaws, two of which fall within Chapter VIII, the
    section regulating admissions practices.” App. to Pet. for
    Cert. 30a.
    Finally, the boards may appoint university officials who
    share their admissions goals, and they may remove those
    officials if the officials’ goals diverge from those of the
    boards. The University of Michigan’s Board of Regents
    “directly appoints [the University’s] Associate Vice Provost
    and Executive Director of Undergraduate Admissions,”
    ——————
    10 Under the bylaws of the University of Michigan’s Board of Regents,
    “[a]ny and all delegations of authority made at any time and from time
    to time by the board to any member of the university staff, or to any
    unit of the university may be revoked by the board at any time, and
    notice of such revocation shall be given in writing.” Bylaws §14.04,
    online at http://www.regents.umich.edu/bylaws.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)             29
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    and Michigan State University’s Board of Trustees elects
    that institution’s President. Brief for Respondents Re-
    gents of the University of Michigan, the Board of Trustees
    of Michigan State University et al. 14.
    The salient point is this: Although the elected and polit-
    ically accountable boards may well entrust university
    officials with certain day-to-day admissions responsibili-
    ties, they often weigh in on admissions policies themselves
    and, at all times, they retain complete supervisory author-
    ity over university officials and over all admissions
    decisions.
    There is no question, then, that the elected boards in
    Michigan had the power to eliminate or adopt race-
    sensitive admissions policies prior to §26. There is also no
    question that §26 worked an impermissible reordering of
    the political process; it removed that power from the elected
    boards and placed it instead at a higher level of the
    political process in Michigan. 
    See supra, at 17
    –22. This
    case is no different from Hunter and Seattle in that re-
    spect. Just as in Hunter and Seattle, minorities in Michi-
    gan “participated in the political process and won.” Ante,
    at 5 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment). And just as in
    Hunter and Seattle, “the majority’s subsequent reordering
    of the political process repealed the minority’s successes
    and made it more difficult for the minority to succeed in
    the future,” thereby “diminish[ing] the minority’s ability to
    participate meaningfully in the electoral process.” 
    Ibid. There is therefore
    no need to consider “extend[ing] the
    holding of Hunter and Seattle to reach situations in which
    decisionmaking authority is moved from an administrative
    body to a political one,” 
    ibid. Such a scenario
    is not be-
    fore us.
    III
    The political-process doctrine not only resolves this case
    as a matter of stare decisis; it is correct as a matter of first
    30                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    principles.
    A
    Under our Constitution, majority rule is not without
    limit. Our system of government is predicated on an
    equilibrium between the notion that a majority of citizens
    may determine governmental policy through legislation
    enacted by their elected representatives, and the overrid-
    ing principle that there are nonetheless some things the
    Constitution forbids even a majority of citizens to do. The
    political-process doctrine, grounded in the Fourteenth
    Amendment, is a central check on majority rule.
    The Fourteenth Amendment instructs that all who act
    for the government may not “deny to any person . . . the
    equal protection of the laws.” We often think of equal
    protection as a guarantee that the government will apply
    the law in an equal fashion—that it will not intentionally
    discriminate against minority groups. But equal protec-
    tion of the laws means more than that; it also secures the
    right of all citizens to participate meaningfully and equally
    in the process through which laws are created.
    Few rights are as fundamental as the right to partici-
    pate meaningfully and equally in the process of govern-
    ment. See Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 
    118 U.S. 356
    , 370 (1886)
    (political rights are “fundamental” because they are “pre-
    servative of all rights”). That right is the bedrock of our
    democracy, recognized from its very inception. See J. Ely,
    Democracy and Distrust 87 (1980) (the Constitution “is
    overwhelmingly concerned, on the one hand, with proce-
    dural fairness in the resolution of individual disputes,”
    and on the other, “with ensuring broad participation in the
    processes and distributions of government”).
    This should come as no surprise. The political process is
    the channel of change. 
    Id., at 10
    3 (describing the im-
    portance of the judiciary in policing the “channels of politi-
    cal change”). It is the means by which citizens may both
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)           31
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    obtain desirable legislation and repeal undesirable legisla-
    tion. Of course, we do not expect minority members of our
    society to obtain every single result they seek through the
    political process—not, at least, when their views conflict
    with those of the majority. The minority plainly does not
    have a right to prevail over majority groups in any given
    political contest. But the minority does have a right to
    play by the same rules as the majority. It is this right
    that Hunter and Seattle so boldly vindicated.
    This right was hardly novel at the time of Hunter and
    Seattle. For example, this Court focused on the vital
    importance of safeguarding minority groups’ access to the
    political process in United States v. Carolene Products Co.,
    
    304 U.S. 144
    (1938), a case that predated Hunter by 30
    years. In a now-famous footnote, the Court explained that
    while ordinary social and economic legislation carries a
    presumption of constitutionality, the same may not be
    true of legislation that offends fundamental rights or
    targets minority groups.        Citing cases involving re-
    strictions on the right to vote, restraints on the dissemina-
    tion of information, interferences with political organiza-
    tions, and prohibition of peaceable assembly, the Court
    recognized that “legislation which restricts those political
    processes which can ordinarily be expected to bring about
    repeal of undesirable legislation” could be worthy of “more
    exacting judicial scrutiny under the general prohibitions of
    the Fourteenth Amendment than are most other types of
    legislation.” 
    Id., at 152,
    n. 4; see also 
    Ely, supra, at 76
    (explaining that “[p]aragraph two [of Carolene Products
    footnote 4] suggests that it is an appropriate function of
    the Court to keep the machinery of democratic govern-
    ment running as it should, to make sure the channels of
    political participation and communication are kept open”).
    The Court also noted that “prejudice against discrete and
    insular minorities may be a special condition, which tends
    seriously to curtail the operation of those political pro-
    32                      SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    cesses ordinarily to be relied upon to protect minorities,
    and which may call for a correspondingly more search-
    ing judicial inquiry.” Carolene 
    Products, 304 U.S., at 153
    ,
    n. 4, see also 
    Ely, supra, at 76
    (explaining that
    “[p]aragraph three [of Carolene Products footnote 4] sug-
    gests that the Court should also concern itself with what
    majorities do to minorities, particularly mentioning laws
    ‘directed at’ religious, national and racial minorities and
    those infected by prejudice against them”).
    The values identified in Carolene Products lie at the
    heart of the political-process doctrine. Indeed, Seattle
    explicitly relied on Carolene Products. 
    See 458 U.S., at 486
    (“[W]hen the State’s allocation of power places unusual
    burdens on the ability of racial groups to enact legisla-
    tion specifically designed to overcome the ‘special condi-
    tion’ of prejudice, the governmental action seriously
    ‘curtail[s] the operation of those political processes ordi-
    narily to be relied upon to protect minorities’ ” (quoting
    Carolene 
    Products, 304 U.S., at 153
    , n. 4)). These values
    are central tenets of our equal protection jurisprudence.
    Our cases recognize at least three features of the right
    to meaningful participation in the political process. Two
    of them, thankfully, are uncontroversial. First, every
    eligible citizen has a right to vote. See Shaw v. Reno, 
    509 U.S. 630
    , 639 (1993). This, woefully, has not always been
    the case. But it is a right no one would take issue with
    today. Second, the majority may not make it more diffi-
    cult for the minority to exercise the right to vote. This,
    too, is widely accepted. After all, the Court has invalidat-
    ed grandfather clauses, good character requirements, poll
    taxes, and gerrymandering provisions.11 The third fea-
    ——————
    11 Attempts by the majority to make it more difficult for the minority
    to exercise its right to vote are, sadly, not a thing of the past. See
    Shelby County v. Holder, 570 U. S. ___, ___ (2013) (slip op., at 15–17)
    (GINSBURG, J., dissenting) (describing recent examples of discriminatory
    changes to state voting laws, including a 1995 dual voter registration
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)                   33
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    ture, the one the plurality dismantles today, is that a
    majority may not reconfigure the existing political process
    in a manner that creates a two-tiered system of political
    change, subjecting laws designed to protect or benefit
    discrete and insular minorities to a more burdensome
    political process than all other laws. This is the political-
    process doctrine of Hunter and Seattle.
    My colleagues would stop at the second. The plurality
    embraces the freedom of “self-government” without limits.
    See ante, at 13. And JUSTICE SCALIA values a “near-
    limitless” notion of state sovereignty. See ante, at 13
    (opinion concurring in judgment). The wrong sought to be
    corrected by the political-process doctrine, they say, is not
    one that should concern us and is in any event beyond the
    reach of the Fourteenth Amendment. As they see it, the
    Court’s role in protecting the political process ends once
    we have removed certain barriers to the minority’s partic-
    ipation in that process. Then, they say, we must sit back
    and let the majority rule without the key constitutional
    limit recognized in Hunter and Seattle.
    That view drains the Fourteenth Amendment of one of
    its core teachings. Contrary to today’s decision, protecting
    the right to meaningful participation in the political pro-
    cess must mean more than simply removing barriers to
    participation. It must mean vigilantly policing the politi-
    cal process to ensure that the majority does not use other
    methods to prevent minority groups from partaking in
    that process on equal footing. Why? For the same reason
    we guard the right of every citizen to vote. If “[e]fforts to
    reduce the impact of minority votes, in contrast to direct
    ——————
    system in Mississippi to disfranchise black voters, a 2000 redistricting
    plan in Georgia to decrease black voting strength, and a 2003 proposal
    to change the voting mechanism for school board elections in South
    Carolina). Until this Court’s decision last Term in Shelby County, the
    preclearance requirement of §5 of the Voting Rights Act of 1965 blocked
    those and many other discriminatory changes to voting procedures.
    34                        SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    attempts to block access to the ballot,” were “ ‘second-
    generation barriers’ ” to minority voting, Shelby County v.
    Holder, 570 U. S. ___, ___ (2013) (GINSBURG, J., dissent-
    ing) (slip op., at 5), efforts to reconfigure the political
    process in ways that uniquely disadvantage minority
    groups who have already long been disadvantaged are
    third-generation barriers. For as the Court recognized in
    Seattle, “minorities are no less powerless with the vote
    than without it when a racial criterion is used to assign
    governmental power in such a way as to exclude particular
    racial groups ‘from effective participation in the political
    proces[s].’ 
    ”12 458 U.S., at 486
    .
    To accept the first two features of the right to meaning-
    ful participation in the political process, while renouncing
    the third, paves the way for the majority to do what it has
    done time and again throughout our Nation’s history:
    afford the minority the opportunity to participate, yet
    manipulate the ground rules so as to ensure the minority’s
    defeat. This is entirely at odds with our idea of equality
    under the law.
    To reiterate, none of this is to say that the political-
    process doctrine prohibits the exercise of democratic self-
    government. Nothing prevents a majority of citizens from
    pursuing or obtaining its preferred outcome in a political
    contest. Here, for instance, I agree with the plurality that
    ——————
    12 Preserving the right to participate meaningfully and equally in the
    process of government is especially important with respect to education
    policy. I do not mean to suggest that “the constitutionality of laws
    forbidding racial preferences depends on the policy interest at stake.”
    Ante, at 14–15 (plurality opinion). I note only that we have long recog-
    nized that “ ‘education . . . is the very foundation of good citizenship.’ ”
    
    Grutter, 539 U.S., at 331
    (quoting Brown v. Board of Education, 
    347 U.S. 483
    , 493 (1954)). Our Nation’s colleges and universities “repre-
    sent the training ground for a large number of our Nation’s leaders,”
    and so there is special reason to safeguard the guarantee “ ‘that public
    institutions are open and available to all segments of American society,
    including people of all races and ethnicities.’ 
    539 U.S., at 331
    –332.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)            35
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    Michiganders who were unhappy with Grutter were free to
    pursue an end to race-sensitive admissions policies in
    their State. See ante, at 16–17. They were free to elect
    governing boards that opposed race-sensitive admissions
    policies or, through public discourse and dialogue, to lobby
    the existing boards toward that end. They were also free
    to remove from the boards the authority to make any
    decisions with respect to admissions policies, as opposed to
    only decisions concerning race-sensitive admissions poli-
    cies. But what the majority could not do, consistent with
    the Constitution, is change the ground rules of the politi-
    cal process in a manner that makes it more difficult for
    racial minorities alone to achieve their goals. In doing so,
    the majority effectively rigs the contest to guarantee a
    particular outcome. That is the very wrong the political-
    process doctrine seeks to remedy. The doctrine “hews to
    the unremarkable notion that when two competitors are
    running a race, one may not require the other to run twice
    as far or to scale obstacles not present in the first runner’s
    course.” BAMN v. Regents of Univ. of Michigan, 
    701 F.3d 466
    , 474 (CA6 2012).
    B
    The political-process doctrine also follows from the rest
    of our equal protection jurisprudence—in particular, our
    reapportionment and vote dilution cases. In those cases,
    the Court described the right to vote as “ ‘the essence of a
    democratic society.’ ” 
    Shaw, 509 U.S., at 639
    . It rejected
    States’ use of ostensibly race-neutral measures to prevent
    minorities from exercising their political rights. See 
    id., at 639–640.
    And it invalidated practices such as at-large
    electoral systems that reduce or nullify a minority group’s
    ability to vote as a cohesive unit, when those practices
    were adopted with a discriminatory purpose. 
    Id., at 641.
    These cases, like the political-process doctrine, all sought
    to preserve the political rights of the minority.
    36                      SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    Two more recent cases involving discriminatory restruc-
    turings of the political process are also worthy of mention:
    Romer v. Evans, 
    517 U.S. 620
    (1996), and League of United
    Latin American Citizens v. Perry, 
    548 U.S. 399
    (2006)
    (LULAC).
    Romer involved a Colorado constitutional amendment
    that removed from the local political process an issue
    primarily affecting gay and lesbian citizens. The amend-
    ment, enacted in response to a number of local ordinances
    prohibiting discrimination against gay citizens, repealed
    these ordinances and effectively prohibited the adoption of
    similar ordinances in the future without another amend-
    ment to the State 
    Constitution. 517 U.S., at 623
    –624.
    Although the Court did not apply the political-process
    doctrine in Romer,13 the case resonates with the principles
    undergirding the political-process doctrine. The Court
    rejected an attempt by the majority to transfer decision-
    making authority from localities (where the targeted
    minority group could influence the process) to state gov-
    ernment (where it had less ability to participate effec-
    tively). See 
    id., at 632
    (describing this type of political
    restructuring as a “disability” on the minority group).
    Rather than being able to appeal to municipalities for
    policy changes, the Court commented, the minority was
    forced to “enlis[t] the citizenry of Colorado to amend the
    State Constitution,” 
    id., at 631—just
    as in this case.
    LULAC, a Voting Rights Act case, involved an enact-
    ment by the Texas Legislature that redrew district lines
    for a number of Texas seats in the House of Representa-
    
    tives. 548 U.S., at 409
    (plurality opinion). In striking
    ——————
    13 The Court invalidated Amendment 2 on the basis that it lacked any
    rational relationship to a legitimate end. It concluded that the
    amendment “impose[d] a broad and undifferentiated disability on a
    single named group,” and was “so discontinuous with the reasons
    offered for it that [it] seem[ed] inexplicable by anything but animus
    toward the class it affect[ed].” 
    Romer, 517 U.S., at 632
    .
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)             37
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    down the enactment, the Court acknowledged the “ ‘long,
    well-documented history of discrimination’ ” in Texas that
    “ ‘touched upon the rights of . . . Hispanics to register, to
    vote, or to participate otherwise in the electoral process,’ ”
    
    id., at 439,
    and it observed that that the “ ‘political, social,
    and economic legacy of past discrimination’ . . . may well
    [have] ‘hinder[ed] their ability to participate effectively in
    the political process,’ ” 
    id., at 440.
    Against this backdrop,
    the Court found that just as “Latino voters were poised to
    elect their candidate of choice,” 
    id., at 438,
    the State’s
    enactment “took away [their] opportunity because [they]
    were about to exercise it,” 
    id., at 440.
    The Court refused
    to sustain “the resulting vote dilution of a group that was
    beginning to achieve [the] goal of overcoming prior elec-
    toral discrimination.” 
    Id., at 442.
        As in Romer, the LULAC Court—while using a different
    analytic framework—applied the core teaching of Hunter
    and Seattle: The political process cannot be restructured in
    a manner that makes it more difficult for a traditionally
    excluded group to work through the existing process to
    seek beneficial policies. And the events giving rise to
    LULAC are strikingly similar to those here. Just as redis-
    tricting prevented Latinos in Texas from attaining a bene-
    fit they had fought for and were poised to enjoy, §26
    prevents racial minorities in Michigan from enjoying a
    last-resort benefit that they, too, had fought for through
    the existing political processes.
    IV
    My colleagues claim that the political-process doctrine is
    unadministrable and contrary to our more recent equal
    protection precedents. See ante, at 11–15 (plurality opin-
    ion); ante, at 7–17 (SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment). It
    is only by not acknowledging certain strands of our juris-
    prudence that they can reach such a conclusion.
    38                  SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    A
    Start with the claim that Hunter and Seattle are no
    longer viable because of the cases that have come after
    them. I note that in the view of many, it is those prece-
    dents that have departed from the mandate of the Equal
    Protection Clause in the first place, by applying strict
    scrutiny to actions designed to benefit rather than burden
    the minority. See 
    Gratz, 539 U.S., at 301
    (GINSBURG, J.,
    dissenting) (“[A]s I see it, government decisionmakers may
    properly distinguish between policies of exclusion and
    inclusion. Actions designed to burden groups long denied
    full citizenship stature are not sensibly ranked with
    measures taken to hasten the day when entrenched dis-
    crimination and its aftereffects have been extirpated”
    (citation omitted)); 
    id., at 282
    (BREYER, J., concurring in
    judgment) (“I agree . . . that, in implementing the Consti-
    tution’s equality instruction, government decisionmakers
    may properly distinguish between policies of inclusion and
    exclusion, for the former are more likely to prove con-
    sistent with the basic constitutional obligation that the
    law respect each individual equally” (citation omitted));
    Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña, 
    515 U.S. 200
    , 243
    (1995) (Stevens, J., dissenting) (“There is no moral or
    constitutional equivalence between a policy that is de-
    signed to perpetuate a caste system and one that seeks to
    eradicate racial subordination. Invidious discrimination is
    an engine of oppression, subjugating a disfavored group to
    enhance or maintain the power of the majority. Remedial
    race-based preferences reflect the opposite impulse: a
    desire to foster equality in society”); Wygant v. Jackson
    Bd. of Ed., 
    476 U.S. 267
    , 301–302 (1986) (Marshall, J.,
    dissenting) (when dealing with an action to eliminate
    “pernicious vestiges of past discrimination,” a “less exact-
    ing standard of review is appropriate”); Fullilove v. Klutz­
    nick, 
    448 U.S. 448
    , 518–519 (1980) (Marshall, J., concur-
    ring in judgment) (race-based governmental action
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)             39
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    designed to “remed[y] the continuing effects of past racial
    discrimination . . . should not be subjected to conventional
    ‘strict scrutiny’ ”); 
    Bakke, 438 U.S., at 359
    (Brennan,
    White, Marshall, and Blackmun, JJ., concurring in judg-
    ment in part and dissenting in part) (“racial classifications
    designed to further remedial purposes” should be subjected
    only to intermediate scrutiny).
    But even assuming that strict scrutiny should apply to
    policies designed to benefit racial minorities, that view is
    not inconsistent with Hunter and Seattle. For nothing the
    Court has said in the last 32 years undermines the princi-
    ples announced in those cases.
    1
    JUSTICE SCALIA first argues that the political-process
    doctrine “misreads the Equal Protection Clause to protect
    ‘particular group[s],’ ” running counter to a line of cases
    that treat “ ‘equal protection as a personal right.’ ” Ante, at
    9 (opinion concurring in judgment) (quoting 
    Adarand, 515 U.S., at 230
    ). Equal protection, he says, protects “ ‘per­
    sons, not groups.’ ” Ante, at 10 (quoting 
    Adarand, 515 U.S., at 227
    ). This criticism ignores the obvious: Discrim-
    ination against an individual occurs because of that indi-
    vidual’s membership in a particular group. Yes, equal
    protection is a personal right, but there can be no equal
    protection violation unless the injured individual is a
    member of a protected group or a class of individuals. It is
    membership in the group—here the racial minority—that
    gives rise to an equal protection violation.
    Relatedly, JUSTICE SCALIA argues that the political-
    process doctrine is inconsistent with our precedents be-
    cause it protects only the minority from political restruc-
    turings. This aspect of the doctrine, he says, cannot be
    tolerated because our precedents have rejected “ ‘a reading
    of the guarantee of equal protection under which the level
    of scrutiny varies according to the ability of different
    40                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    groups to defend their interests in the representative
    process.’ ” Ante, at 10 (quoting Richmond v. J. A. Croson
    Co., 488 U. S., 469, 495 (1989) (plurality opinion)). Equal
    protection, he continues, “ ‘cannot mean one thing when
    applied to one individual and something else when applied
    to a person of another color.’ ” Ante, at 10 (quoting 
    Bakke, 438 U.S., at 289
    –290) (opinion of Powell, J.).
    JUSTICE SCALIA is troubled that the political-process
    doctrine has not been applied to trigger strict scrutiny for
    political restructurings that burden the majority. But the
    doctrine is inapplicable to the majority. The minority
    cannot achieve such restructurings against the majority,
    for the majority is, well, the majority. As the Seattle Court
    explained, “ ‘[t]he majority needs no protection against
    discriminat[ory restructurings], and if it did, a referen-
    dum, [for instance], might be bothersome but no more
    than that.’ 
    458 U.S., at 468
    . Stated differently, the
    doctrine protects only the minority because it implicates a
    problem that affects only the minority. Nothing in my
    opinion suggests, as JUSTICE SCALIA says, that under the
    political-process doctrine, “the Constitution prohibits
    discrimination against minority groups, but not against
    majority groups.” Ante, at 10, n. 7. If the minority some-
    how managed to effectuate a political restructuring that
    burdened only the majority, we could decide then whether
    to apply the political-process doctrine to safeguard the
    political right of the majority. But such a restructuring is
    not before us, and I cannot fathom how it could be
    achieved.
    2
    JUSTICE SCALIA next invokes state sovereignty, arguing
    that “we have emphasized the near-limitless sovereignty
    of each State to design its governing structure as it sees
    fit.” Ante, at 13 (opinion concurring in judgment). But
    state sovereignty is not absolute; it is subject to constitu-
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)            41
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    tional limits. The Court surely did not offend state sover-
    eignty by barring States from changing their voting proce-
    dures to exclude racial minorities. So why does the
    political-process doctrine offend state sovereignty? The
    doctrine takes nothing away from state sovereignty that
    the Equal Protection Clause does not require. All it says
    is that a State may not reconfigure its existing political
    processes in a manner that establishes a distinct and more
    burdensome process for minority members of our society
    alone to obtain legislation in their interests.
    More broadly, JUSTICE SCALIA is troubled that the
    political-process doctrine would create supposed “affirma-
    tive-action safe havens” in places where the ordinary
    political process has thus far produced race-sensitive
    admissions policies. Ante, at 13–14. It would not. As
    explained previously, the voters in Michigan who opposed
    race-sensitive admissions policies had any number of
    options available to them to challenge those policies. 
    See supra, at 34
    –35. And in States where decisions regarding
    race-sensitive admissions policies are not subject to the
    political process in the first place, voters are entirely free
    to eliminate such policies via a constitutional amendment
    because that action would not reallocate power in the
    manner condemned in Hunter and Seattle (and, of course,
    present here). The Seattle Court recognized this careful
    balance between state sovereignty and constitutional
    protections:
    “[W]e do not undervalue the magnitude of the State’s
    interest in its system of education. Washington could
    have reserved to state officials the right to make all
    decisions in the areas of education and student as-
    signment. It has chosen, however, to use a more elab-
    orate system; having done so, the State is obligated to
    operate that system within the confines of the Four-
    teenth 
    Amendment.” 458 U.S., at 487
    .
    42                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    The same is true of Michigan.
    3
    Finally, JUSTICE SCALIA disagrees with “the proposition
    that a facially neutral law may deny equal protection
    solely because it has a disparate racial impact.” Ante,
    at 15 (opinion concurring in judgment).            He would
    acknowledge, however, that an act that draws racial dis-
    tinctions or makes racial classifications triggers strict
    scrutiny regardless of whether discriminatory intent is
    shown. See 
    Adarand, 515 U.S., at 213
    . That should
    settle the matter: Section 26 draws a racial distinction. As
    the Seattle Court explained, “when the political process or
    the decisionmaking mechanism used to address racially
    conscious legislation—and only such legislation—is sin-
    gled out for peculiar and disadvantageous treatment, the
    governmental action plainly rests on ‘distinctions based on
    race.’ 
    458 U.S., at 485
    (some internal quotation marks
    omitted); see also 
    id., at 470
    (noting that although a State
    may “ ‘allocate governmental power on the basis of any
    general principle,’ ” it may not use racial considerations “to
    define the governmental decisionmaking structure”).
    But in JUSTICE SCALIA’s view, cases like Washington v.
    Davis, 
    426 U.S. 229
    (1976), and Arlington Heights v.
    Metropolitan Housing Development Corp., 
    429 U.S. 252
    (1977), call Seattle into question. It is odd to suggest that
    prior precedents call into question a later one. Seattle
    (decided in 1982) postdated both Washington v. Davis
    (1976) and Arlington Heights (1977). JUSTICE SCALIA’s
    suggestion that Seattle runs afoul of the principles estab-
    lished in Washington v. Davis and Arlington Heights
    would come as a surprise to Justice Blackmun, who joined
    the majority opinions in all three cases. Indeed, the Seat­
    tle Court explicitly rejected the argument that Hunter had
    been effectively overruled by Washington v. Davis and
    Arlington Heights:
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)                     43
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    “There is one immediate and crucial difference be-
    tween Hunter and [those cases]. While decisions such
    as Washington v. Davis and Arlington Heights consid-
    ered classifications facially unrelated to race, the
    charter amendment at issue in Hunter dealt in explic-
    itly racial terms with legislation designed to benefit
    minorities ‘as minorities,’ not legislation intended to
    benefit some larger group of underprivileged citizens
    among whom minorities were disproportionately rep-
    resented.
    458 U.S., at 485
    .
    And it concluded that both the Hunter amendment and
    the Seattle initiative rested on distinctions based on 
    race. 458 U.S., at 485
    . So does §26.14
    B
    My colleagues also attack the first prong of the doctrine
    as “rais[ing] serious constitutional concerns,” ante, at 11
    (plurality opinion), and being “unadministrable,” ante, at 7
    (SCALIA, J., concurring in judgment). JUSTICE SCALIA
    wonders whether judges are equipped to weigh in on what
    constitutes a “racial issue.” See ante, at 8. The plurality,
    too, thinks courts would be “with no clear legal standards
    or accepted sources to guide judicial decision.” Ante, at 12.
    ——————
    14 The plurality raises another concern with respect to precedent. It
    points to decisions by the California Supreme Court and the United
    States Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit upholding as constitu-
    tional Proposition 209, a California constitutional amendment identical
    in substance to §26. Ante, at 14. The plurality notes that if we were to
    affirm the lower court’s decision in this case, “those holdings would be
    invalidated . . . .” 
    Ibid. I fail to
    see the significance. We routinely
    resolve conflicts between lower courts; the necessary result, of course, is
    that decisions of courts on one side of the debate are invalidated or
    called into question. I am unaware of a single instance where that
    (inevitable) fact influenced the Court’s decision one way or the other.
    Had the lower courts proceeded in opposite fashion—had the California
    Supreme Court and Ninth Circuit invalidated Proposition 209 and the
    Sixth Circuit upheld §26—would the plurality come out the other way?
    44                    SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    Yet as JUSTICE SCALIA recognizes, Hunter and Seattle
    provide a standard: Does the public policy at issue “inur[e]
    primarily to the benefit of the minority, and [was it] de-
    signed for that purpose”? 
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 472
    ; see
    ante, at 8. Surely this is the kind of factual inquiry that
    judges are capable of making. JUSTICE SCALIA, for in-
    stance, accepts the standard announced in Washington v.
    Davis, which requires judges to determine whether dis-
    crimination is intentional or whether it merely has a
    discriminatory effect. Such an inquiry is at least as diffi-
    cult for judges as the one called for by Hunter and Seattle.
    In any event, it is clear that the constitutional amendment
    in this case has a racial focus; it is facially race-based and,
    by operation of law, disadvantages only minorities. 
    See supra, at 15
    –16.
    “No good can come” from these inquiries, JUSTICE
    SCALIA responds, because they divide the Nation along
    racial lines and perpetuate racial stereotypes. Ante, at 9.
    The plurality shares that view; it tells us that we must not
    assume all individuals of the same race think alike. See
    ante, at 11–12. The same could have been said about
    desegregation: Not all members of a racial minority in
    Seattle necessarily regarded the integration of public
    schools as good policy. Yet the Seattle Court had little
    difficulty saying that school integration as a general mat-
    ter “inure[d] . . . to the benefit of ” the 
    minority. 458 U.S., at 472
    .
    My colleagues are of the view that we should leave race
    out of the picture entirely and let the voters sort it out.
    See ante, at 13 (plurality opinion) (“Racial division would
    be validated, not discouraged, were the Seattle formula-
    tion . . . to remain in force”); ante, at 9 (SCALIA, J., concur-
    ring in judgment) (“ ‘[R]acial stereotyping [is] at odds with
    equal protection mandates’ ”). We have seen this reason-
    ing before. See Parents 
    Involved, 551 U.S., at 748
    (“The
    way to stop discrimination on the basis of race is to stop
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)           45
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    discriminating on the basis of race”). It is a sentiment out
    of touch with reality, one not required by our Constitution,
    and one that has properly been rejected as “not sufficient”
    to resolve cases of this nature. 
    Id., at 788
    (KENNEDY, J.,
    concurring in part and concurring in judgment). While
    “[t]he enduring hope is that race should not matter[,] the
    reality is that too often it does.” 
    Id., at 787.
    “[R]acial
    discrimination . . . [is] not ancient history.” Bartlett v.
    Strickland, 
    556 U.S. 1
    , 25 (2009) (plurality opinion).
    Race matters. Race matters in part because of the long
    history of racial minorities’ being denied access to the
    political process. See Part 
    I, supra
    ; see also South Carolina
    v. Katzenbach, 
    383 U.S. 301
    , 309 (1966) (describing
    racial discrimination in voting as “an insidious and perva-
    sive evil which had been perpetuated in certain parts of
    our country through unremitting and ingenious defiance of
    the Constitution”). And although we have made great
    strides, “voting discrimination still exists; no one doubts
    that.” Shelby County, 570 U. S., at __ (slip op., at 2).
    Race also matters because of persistent racial inequality
    in society—inequality that cannot be ignored and that has
    produced stark socioeconomic disparities. See 
    Gratz, 539 U.S., at 298
    –300 (GINSBURG, J., dissenting) (cataloging
    the many ways in which “the effects of centuries of law-
    sanctioned inequality remain painfully evident in our
    communities and schools,” in areas like employment,
    poverty, access to health care, housing, consumer transac-
    tions, and education); 
    Adarand, 515 U.S., at 273
    (GINSBURG, J., dissenting) (recognizing that the “lingering
    effects” of discrimination, “reflective of a system of racial
    caste only recently ended, are evident in our workplaces,
    markets, and neighborhoods”).
    And race matters for reasons that really are only skin
    deep, that cannot be discussed any other way, and that
    cannot be wished away. Race matters to a young man’s
    view of society when he spends his teenage years watching
    46                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    others tense up as he passes, no matter the neighborhood
    where he grew up. Race matters to a young woman’s
    sense of self when she states her hometown, and then is
    pressed, “No, where are you really from?”, regardless of
    how many generations her family has been in the country.
    Race matters to a young person addressed by a stranger in
    a foreign language, which he does not understand because
    only English was spoken at home. Race matters because
    of the slights, the snickers, the silent judgments that
    reinforce that most crippling of thoughts: “I do not belong
    here.”
    In my colleagues’ view, examining the racial impact of
    legislation only perpetuates racial discrimination. This
    refusal to accept the stark reality that race matters is
    regrettable. The way to stop discrimination on the basis of
    race is to speak openly and candidly on the subject of race,
    and to apply the Constitution with eyes open to the unfor-
    tunate effects of centuries of racial discrimination. As
    members of the judiciary tasked with intervening to carry
    out the guarantee of equal protection, we ought not sit
    back and wish away, rather than confront, the racial
    inequality that exists in our society. It is this view that
    works harm, by perpetuating the facile notion that what
    makes race matter is acknowledging the simple truth that
    race does matter.
    V
    Although the only constitutional rights at stake in this
    case are process-based rights, the substantive policy at
    issue is undeniably of some relevance to my colleagues.
    See ante, at 18 (plurality opinion) (suggesting that race-
    sensitive admissions policies have the “potential to be-
    come . . . the source of the very resentments and hostilities
    based on race that this Nation seeks to put behind it”). I
    will therefore speak in response.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)           47
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    A
    For over a century, racial minorities in Michigan fought
    to bring diversity to their State’s public colleges and uni-
    versities. Before the advent of race-sensitive admissions
    policies, those institutions, like others around the country,
    were essentially segregated. In 1868, two black students
    were admitted to the University of Michigan, the first of
    their race. See Expert Report of James D. Anderson 4, in
    Gratz v. Bollinger, No. 97–75231 (ED Mich.). In 1935,
    over six decades later, there were still only 35 black stu-
    dents at the University. 
    Ibid. By 1954, this
    number had
    risen to slightly below 200. 
    Ibid. And by 1966,
    to around
    400, among a total student population of roughly 32,500—
    barely over 1 percent. 
    Ibid. The numbers at
    the University
    of Michigan Law School are even more telling. During
    the 1960’s, the Law School produced 9 black graduates
    among a total of 3,041—less than three-tenths of 1 per-
    cent. See App. in Grutter v. Bollinger, O. T. 2002, No. 02–
    241, p. 204.
    The housing and extracurricular policies at these insti-
    tutions also perpetuated open segregation. For instance,
    incoming students were permitted to opt out of rooming
    with black students. 
    Anderson, supra, at 7
    –8. And some
    fraternities and sororities excluded black students from
    membership. 
    Id., at 6–7.
       In 1966, the Defense Department conducted an investi-
    gation into the University’s compliance with Title VI of the
    Civil Rights Act, and made 25 recommendations for in-
    creasing opportunities for minority students. 
    Id., at 9.
    In
    1970, a student group launched a number of protests,
    including a strike, demanding that the University increase
    its minority enrollment. 
    Id., at 16–23.
    The University’s
    Board of Regents responded, adopting a goal of 10 percent
    black admissions by the fall of 1973. 
    Id., at 23.
    48                       SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    During the 1970’s, the University continued to improve
    its admissions policies,15 encouraged by this Court’s 1978
    decision in Bakke. In that case, the Court told our Na-
    tion’s colleges and universities that they could consider
    race in admissions as part of a broader goal to create a
    diverse student body, in which students of different back-
    grounds would learn together, and thereby learn to live
    together. A little more than a decade ago, in Grutter, the
    Court reaffirmed this understanding. In upholding the
    admissions policy of the Law School, the Court laid to rest
    any doubt whether student body diversity is a compelling
    interest that may justify the use of race.
    Race-sensitive admissions policies are now a thing of the
    past in Michigan after §26, even though—as experts agree
    and as research shows—those policies were making a
    difference in achieving educational diversity. In Grutter,
    Michigan’s Law School spoke candidly about the strides
    the institution had taken successfully because of race-
    sensitive admissions. One expert retained by the Law
    School opined that a race-blind admissions system would
    have a “very dramatic, negative effect on underrepresented
    minority admissions.” 
    Grutter, 539 U.S., at 320
    (inter-
    nal quotation marks omitted). He testified that the school
    had admitted 35 percent of underrepresented minority
    students who had applied in 2000, as opposed to only 10
    percent who would have been admitted had race not been
    considered. 
    Ibid. Underrepresented minority students
    would thus have constituted 4 percent, as opposed to the
    actual 14.5 percent, of the class that entered in 2000.
    
    Ibid. —————— 15 In
    1973, the Law School graduated 41 black students (out of a class
    of 446) and the first Latino student in its history. App. in Grutter v.
    Bollinger, O. T. 2002, No. 02–241, p. 204. In 1976, it graduated its first
    Native American student. 
    Ibid. On the whole,
    during the 1970’s, the
    Law School graduated 262 black students, compared to 9 in the previ-
    ous decade, along with 41 Latino students. 
    Ibid. Cite as: 572
    U. S. ___ (2014)           49
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    Michigan’s public colleges and universities tell us the
    same today. The Board of Regents of the University of
    Michigan and the Board of Trustees of Michigan State
    University inform us that those institutions cannot
    achieve the benefits of a diverse student body without
    race-sensitive admissions plans. See Brief for Respond-
    ents Regents of the University of Michigan, the Board of
    Trustees of Michigan State University et al. 18–25. Dur-
    ing proceedings before the lower courts, several university
    officials testified that §26 would depress minority enroll-
    ment at Michigan’s public universities. The Director of
    Undergraduate Admissions at the University of Michigan
    “expressed doubts over the ability to maintain minority
    enrollment through the use of a proxy, like socioeconomic
    status.” Supp. App. to Pet. for Cert. 285a. He explained
    that university officials in States with laws similar to §26
    had not “ ‘achieve[d] the same sort of racial and ethnic
    diversity that they had prior to such measures . . . without
    considering race.’ ” 
    Ibid. Similarly, the Law
    School’s Dean
    of Admissions testified that she expected “a decline in
    minority admissions because, in her view, it is impossible
    ‘to get a critical mass of underrepresented minori-
    ties . . . without considering race.’ ” 
    Ibid. And the Dean
    of
    Wayne State University Law School stated that “although
    some creative approaches might mitigate the effects of
    [§26], he ‘did not think that any one of these proposals or
    any combination of these proposals was reasonably likely
    to result in the admission of a class that had the same or
    similar or higher numbers of African Americans, Latinos
    and Native Americans as the prior policy.’ ” 
    Ibid. Michigan tells a
    different story. It asserts that although
    the statistics are difficult to track, “the number of un-
    derrepresented minorities . . . [in] the entering freshman
    class at Michigan as a percentage changed very little”
    after §26. Tr. of Oral Arg. 15. It also claims that “the
    statistics in California across the 17 campuses in the
    50                      SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    University of California system show that today the un-
    derrepresented minority percentage is better on 16 out of
    those 17 campuses”—all except Berkeley—than before
    California’s equivalent initiative took effect. 
    Id., at 16.
    As
    it turns out, these statistics weren’t “ ‘even good enough to
    be wrong.’ ” Reference Manual on Scientific Evidence 4 (2d
    ed. 2000) (Introduction by Stephen G. Breyer (quoting
    Wolfgang Pauli)).
    Section 26 has already led to decreased minority en-
    rollment at Michigan’s public colleges and universities. In
    2006 (before §26 took effect), underrepresented minorities
    made up 12.15 percent of the University of Michigan’s
    freshman class, compared to 9.54 percent in 2012—a
    roughly 25 percent decline. See University of Michigan—
    New Freshman Enrollment Overview, Office of the Registrar,
    online at http://www.ro.umich.edu/report/10enrolloverview.pdf
    and http://www.ro.umich.edu/report/12enrollmentsummary.pdf.16
    Moreover, the total number of college-aged underrepre-
    sented minorities in Michigan has increased even as the
    number of underrepresented minorities admitted to the
    University has decreased. For example, between 2006 and
    2011, the proportion of black freshmen among those en-
    rolled at the University of Michigan declined from 7 per-
    cent to 5 percent, even though the proportion of black
    college-aged persons in Michigan increased from 16 to 19
    percent. See Fessenden and Keller, How Minorities Have
    Fared in States with Affirmative Action Bans, N. Y.
    Times, June 24, 2013, online at http://www.nytimes.com/
    interactive/2013/06/24/us/affirmative-action-bans.html.
    ——————
    16 These percentages include enrollment statistics for black students,
    Hispanic students, Native American students, and students who
    identify as members of two or more underrepresented minority groups.
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)
    51
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN
    Black Students17
    A recent study also confirms that §26 has decreased
    minority degree attainment in Michigan. The University
    of Michigan’s graduating class of 2012, the first admitted
    after §26 took effect, is quite different from previous clas-
    ses. The proportion of black students among those attain-
    ing bachelor’s degrees was 4.4 percent, the lowest since
    1991; the proportion of black students among those attain-
    ing master’s degrees was 5.1 percent, the lowest since
    1989; the proportion of black students among those attain-
    ing doctoral degrees was 3.9 percent, the lowest since
    1993; and the proportion of black students among those
    attaining professional school degrees was 3.5 percent, the
    lowest since the mid-1970’s. See Kidder, Restructuring
    Higher Education Opportunity?: African American Degree
    Attainment After Michigan’s Ban on Affirmative Action,
    p. 1 (Aug. 2013), online at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/
    abstract=2318523.
    ——————
    17 Thischart is reproduced from Fessenden and Keller, How Minori-
    ties Have Fared in States with Affirmative Action Bans, N. Y. Times,
    June 24, 2013, online at http://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2013/
    06/24/us/affirmative-action-bans.html.
    52                  SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    The President and Chancellors of the University of
    California (which has 10 campuses, not 17) inform us that
    “[t]he abandonment of race-conscious admissions policies
    resulted in an immediate and precipitous decline in the
    rates at which underrepresented-minority students ap-
    plied to, were admitted to, and enrolled at” the university.
    Brief for President and Chancellors of the University of
    California as Amici Curiae 10 (hereinafter President and
    Chancellors Brief). At the University of California, Los
    Angeles (UCLA), for example, admission rates for un-
    derrepresented minorities plummeted from 52.4 percent in
    1995 (before California’s ban took effect) to 24 percent
    in 1998. 
    Id., at 12.
    As a result, the percentage of un-
    derrepresented minorities fell by more than half: from
    30.1 percent of the entering class in 1995 to 14.3 percent
    in 1998. 
    Ibid. The admissions rate
    for underrepresented
    minorities at UCLA reached a new low of 13.6 percent in
    2012. See Brief for California Social Science Researchers
    and Admissions Experts as Amici Curiae 28.
    The elimination of race-sensitive admissions policies in
    California has been especially harmful to black students.
    In 2006, for example, there were fewer than 100 black
    students in UCLA’s incoming class of roughly 5,000, the
    lowest number since at least 1973. See 
    id., at 24.
       The University of California also saw declines in minor-
    ity representation at its graduate programs and profes-
    sional schools. In 2005, underrepresented minorities
    made up 17 percent of the university’s new medical stu-
    dents, which is actually a lower rate than the 17.4 percent
    reported in 1975, three years before Bakke. President and
    Chancellors Brief 13. The numbers at the law schools are
    even more alarming. In 2005, underrepresented minori-
    ties made up 12 percent of entering law students, well
    below the 20.1 percent in 1975. 
    Id., at 14.
       As in Michigan, the declines in minority representation
    at the University of California have come even as the
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)          53
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    minority population in California has increased.       At
    UCLA, for example, the proportion of Hispanic freshmen
    among those enrolled declined from 23 percent in 1995 to
    17 percent in 2011, even though the proportion of Hispanic
    college-aged persons in California increased from 41 per-
    cent to 49 percent during that same period. See Fessenden
    and Keller.
    UCLA
    Hispanic Students18
    And the proportion of black freshmen among those
    enrolled at UCLA declined from 8 percent in 1995 to 3
    percent in 2011, even though the proportion of black
    college-aged persons in California increased from 8 per-
    cent to 9 percent during that same period. See 
    ibid. —————— 18 Ibid.
    54                 SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    UCLA
    Black Students19
    While the minority admissions rates at UCLA and
    Berkeley have decreased, the number of minorities en-
    rolled at colleges across the country has increased. See
    Phillips, Colleges Straining to Restore Diversity: Bans on
    Race-Conscious Admissions Upend Racial Makeup at
    California Schools, Wall Street Journal, Mar. 7, 2014,
    p. A3.
    ——————
    19 
    Ibid. Cite as: 572
    U. S. ___ (2014)                  55
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    BERKELEY AND UCLA20
    The President and Chancellors assure us that they have
    tried. They tell us that notwithstanding the university’s
    efforts for the past 15 years “to increase diversity on [the
    University of California’s] campuses through the use of
    race-neutral initiatives,” enrollment rates have “not re-
    bounded . . . [or] kept pace with the demographic changes
    among California’s graduating high-school population.”
    President and Chancellors Brief 14. Since Proposition 209
    took effect, the university has spent over a half-billion
    dollars on programs and policies designed to increase
    diversity. 
    Phillips, supra
    , at A3. Still, it has been unable
    to meet its diversity goals. 
    Ibid. Proposition 209, it
    says,
    has “ ‘completely changed the character’ of the university.”
    
    Ibid. (quoting the Associate
    President and Chief Policy
    ——————
    20 This chart is reproduced from Phillips, Colleges Straining to Re-
    store Diversity: Bans on Race-Conscious Admissions Upend Racial
    Makeup at California Schools, Wall Street Journal, Mar. 7, 2014, p. A3.
    56                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    Advisor of the University of California).
    B
    These statistics may not influence the views of some of
    my colleagues, as they question the wisdom of adopting
    race-sensitive admissions policies and would prefer if our
    Nation’s colleges and universities were to discard those
    policies altogether. See ante, at 2 (ROBERTS, C. J., concur-
    ring) (suggesting that race-sensitive admissions policies
    might “do more harm than good”); ante, at 9, n. 6 (SCALIA,
    J., concurring in judgment); 
    Grutter, 539 U.S., at 371
    –373
    (THOMAS, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part);
    
    id., at 347–348
    (SCALIA, J., concurring in part and dissent-
    ing in part). That view is at odds with our recognition in
    Grutter, and more recently in Fisher v. University of Texas
    at Austin, 570 U. S. ___ (2013), that race-sensitive admis-
    sions policies are necessary to achieve a diverse student
    body when race-neutral alternatives have failed. More
    fundamentally, it ignores the importance of diversity in
    institutions of higher education and reveals how little my
    colleagues understand about the reality of race in America.
    This Court has recognized that diversity in education is
    paramount. With good reason. Diversity ensures that the
    next generation moves beyond the stereotypes, the as-
    sumptions, and the superficial perceptions that students
    coming from less-heterogeneous communities may harbor,
    consciously or not, about people who do not look like them.
    Recognizing the need for diversity acknowledges that,
    “[j]ust as growing up in a particular region or having
    particular professional experiences is likely to affect an
    individual’s views, so too is one’s own, unique experience
    of being a racial minority in a society, like our own, in
    which race unfortunately still matters.” 
    Grutter, 539 U.S., at 333
    . And it acknowledges that “to cultivate a set
    of leaders with legitimacy in the eyes of the citizenry, it is
    necessary that the path to leadership be visibly open to
    Cite as: 572 U. S. ___ (2014)          57
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    talented and qualified individuals of every race and eth-
    nicity.” 
    Id., at 332.
      Colleges and universities must be free to prioritize the
    goal of diversity. They must be free to immerse their
    students in a multiracial environment that fosters fre-
    quent and meaningful interactions with students of other
    races, and thereby pushes such students to transcend any
    assumptions they may hold on the basis of skin color.
    Without race-sensitive admissions policies, this might well
    be impossible. The statistics I have described make that
    fact glaringly obvious. We should not turn a blind eye to
    something we cannot help but see.
    To be clear, I do not mean to suggest that the virtues of
    adopting race-sensitive admissions policies should inform
    the legal question before the Court today regarding the
    constitutionality of §26. But I cannot ignore the unfortu-
    nate outcome of today’s decision: Short of amending the
    State Constitution, a Herculean task, racial minorities in
    Michigan are deprived of even an opportunity to convince
    Michigan’s public colleges and universities to consider race
    in their admissions plans when other attempts to achieve
    racial diversity have proved unworkable, and those insti-
    tutions are unnecessarily hobbled in their pursuit of a
    diverse student body.
    *     *    *
    The Constitution does not protect racial minorities from
    political defeat. But neither does it give the majority free
    rein to erect selective barriers against racial minorities.
    The political-process doctrine polices the channels of
    change to ensure that the majority, when it wins, does so
    without rigging the rules of the game to ensure its success.
    Today, the Court discards that doctrine without good
    reason.
    In doing so, it permits the decision of a majority of the
    voters in Michigan to strip Michigan’s elected university
    58                   SCHUETTE v. BAMN
    SOTOMAYOR, J., dissenting
    boards of their authority to make decisions with respect to
    constitutionally permissible race-sensitive admissions
    policies, while preserving the boards’ plenary authority to
    make all other educational decisions. “In a most direct
    sense, this implicates the judiciary’s special role in safe-
    guarding the interests of those groups that are relegated
    to such a position of political powerlessness as to com-
    mand extraordinary protection from the majoritarian
    political process.” 
    Seattle, 458 U.S., at 486
    (internal
    quotation marks omitted). The Court abdicates that role,
    permitting the majority to use its numerical advantage to
    change the rules mid-contest and forever stack the deck
    against racial minorities in Michigan. The result is that
    Michigan’s public colleges and universities are less
    equipped to do their part in ensuring that students of all
    races are “better prepare[d] . . . for an increasingly diverse
    workforce and society . . .” 
    Grutter, 539 U.S., at 330
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    Today’s decision eviscerates an important strand of our
    equal protection jurisprudence. For members of historically
    marginalized groups, which rely on the federal courts to
    protect their constitutional rights, the decision can hardly
    bolster hope for a vision of democracy that preserves for
    all the right to participate meaningfully and equally in
    self-government.
    I respectfully dissent.
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 12–682.

Citation Numbers: 188 L. Ed. 2d 613, 134 S. Ct. 1623, 2014 U.S. LEXIS 2932, 82 U.S.L.W. 4251, 572 U.S. 291, 24 Fla. L. Weekly Fed. S 667, 2014 WL 1577512

Judges: Kagan, Roberts

Filed Date: 4/22/2014

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 10/19/2024

Authorities (42)

League of United Latin American Citizens v. Perry , 126 S. Ct. 2594 ( 2006 )

the-coalition-for-economic-equity-california-naacp-northern-california , 122 F.3d 692 ( 1997 )

Hunter v. City of Pittsburgh , 28 S. Ct. 40 ( 1907 )

Brown v. Board of Education , 74 S. Ct. 686 ( 1954 )

Sailors v. Board of Ed. of Kent Cty. , 87 S. Ct. 1549 ( 1967 )

Regents of the University of California v. Bakke , 98 S. Ct. 2733 ( 1978 )

Washington v. Seattle School District No. 1 , 102 S. Ct. 3187 ( 1982 )

City of Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co. , 109 S. Ct. 706 ( 1989 )

Gregory v. Ashcroft , 111 S. Ct. 2395 ( 1991 )

Shaw v. Reno , 113 S. Ct. 2816 ( 1993 )

United States v. Lopez , 115 S. Ct. 1624 ( 1995 )

Village of Arlington Heights v. Metropolitan Housing ... , 97 S. Ct. 555 ( 1977 )

Yick Wo v. Hopkins , 6 S. Ct. 1064 ( 1886 )

Freeman v. Pitts , 112 S. Ct. 1430 ( 1992 )

Terry v. Adams , 73 S. Ct. 809 ( 1953 )

brian-ho-by-his-parent-and-next-friend-carl-ho-patrick-wong-by-his , 147 F.3d 854 ( 1998 )

Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School ... , 127 S. Ct. 2738 ( 2007 )

United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co. , 26 S. Ct. 282 ( 1906 )

Coalition to Def. Aff. Act. v. REGENTS OF U OF MI. , 539 F. Supp. 2d 924 ( 2008 )

Grutter v. Bollinger , 123 S. Ct. 2325 ( 2003 )

View All Authorities »