Gamble v. United States ( 2019 )


Menu:
  •                                                        7/19/2019 9:34:03 AM
    Compare Results
    Old File:                                              New File:
    17-646.pdf                                           17-646_new2.pdf
    versus
    88 pages (422 KB)                                         88 pages (430 KB)
    6/17/2019 8:05:53 AM                                      7/19/2019 9:32:26 AM
    Total Changes              Content                                 Styling and
    Annotations
    4
    5
    Replacements
    0   Styling
    0    Insertions
    0   Annotations
    1    Deletion
    Go to First Change (page 27)
    file://NoURLProvided[7/19/2019 9:34:03 AM]
    (Slip Opinion)              OCTOBER TERM, 2018                                       1
    Syllabus
    NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is
    being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued.
    The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been
    prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader.
    See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 
    200 U.S. 321
    , 337.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    Syllabus
    GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR
    THE ELEVENTH CIRCUIT
    No. 17–646.      Argued December 6, 2018—Decided June 17, 2019
    Petitioner Gamble pleaded guilty to a charge of violating Alabama’s
    felon-in-possession-of-a-firearm statute. Federal prosecutors then
    indicted him for the same instance of possession under federal law.
    Gamble moved to dismiss, arguing that the federal indictment was
    for “the same offence” as the one at issue in his state conviction, thus
    exposing him to double jeopardy under the Fifth Amendment. The
    District Court denied this motion, invoking the dual-sovereignty doc-
    trine, according to which two offenses “are not the ‘same offence’ ” for
    double jeopardy purposes if “prosecuted by different sovereigns,”
    Heath v. Alabama, 
    474 U.S. 82
    , 92. Gamble pleaded guilty to the
    federal offense but appealed on double jeopardy grounds. The Elev-
    enth Circuit affirmed.
    Held: This Court declines to overturn the longstanding dual-
    sovereignty doctrine. Pp. 3–31.
    (a) The dual-sovereignty doctrine is not an exception to the double
    jeopardy right but follows from the Fifth Amendment’s text. The
    Double Jeopardy Clause protects individuals from being “twice put in
    jeopardy” “for the same offence.” As originally understood, an “of-
    fence” is defined by a law, and each law is defined by a sovereign.
    Thus, where there are two sovereigns, there are two laws and two “of-
    fences.” Gamble attempts to show from the Clause’s drafting history
    that Congress must have intended to bar successive prosecutions re-
    gardless of the sovereign bringing the charge. But even if conjectures
    about subjective goals were allowed to inform this Court’s reading of
    the text, the Government’s contrary arguments on that score would
    prevail. Pp. 3–5.
    (b) This Court’s cases reflect the sovereign-specific reading of the
    phrase “same offence.” Three antebellum cases—Fox v. Ohio, 
    5 How. 2
                         GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Syllabus
    410; United States v. Marigold, 
    9 How. 560
    ; and Moore v. Illinois, 
    14 How. 13
    —laid the foundation that a crime against two sovereigns
    constitutes two offenses because each sovereign has an interest to
    vindicate. Seventy years later, that foundation was cemented in
    United States v. Lanza, 
    260 U.S. 377
    , which upheld a federal prose-
    cution that followed one by a State. This Court applied that prece-
    dent for decades until 1959, when it refused two requests to reverse
    course, see Bartkus v. Illinois, 
    359 U.S. 121
    ; Abbate v. United States,
    
    359 U.S. 187
    , and it has reinforced that precedent over the following
    six decades, see, e.g., Puerto Rico v. Sanchez Valle, 
    579 U.S.
    ___.
    Pp. 5–10.
    (c) Gamble claims that this Court’s precedent contradicts the com-
    mon-law rights that the Double Jeopardy Clause was originally un-
    derstood to engraft onto the Constitution, pointing to English and
    American cases and treatises. A departure from precedent, however,
    “demands special justification,” Arizona v. Rumsey, 
    467 U.S. 203
    ,
    212, and Gamble’s historical evidence is too feeble to break the chain
    of precedent linking dozens of cases over 170 years. This Court has
    previously concluded that the probative value of early English deci-
    sions on which Gamble relies was “dubious” due to “confused and in-
    adequate reporting.” Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 128, n. 9. On closer in-
    spection, that assessment has proven accurate; the passing years
    have not made those early cases any clearer or more valuable. Nor
    do the treatises cited by Gamble come close to settling the historical
    question with enough force to meet his particular burden. His posi-
    tion is also not supported by state court cases, which are equivocal at
    best. Less useful still are the two federal cases cited by Gamble—
    Houston v. Moore, 
    5 Wheat. 1
    , which squares with the dual-
    sovereignty doctrine, and United States v. Furlong, 
    5 Wheat. 1
    84,
    which actually supports it. Pp. 11–28.
    (d) Gamble’s attempts to blunt the force of stare decisis here do not
    succeed. He contends that the recognition of the Double Jeopardy
    Clause’s incorporation against the States washed away any theoreti-
    cal foundation for the dual-sovereignty rule. But this rule rests on
    the fact that only same-sovereign prosecutions can involve the “same
    offence,” and that is just as true after incorporation as before. Gam-
    ble also argues that the proliferation of federal criminal laws has
    raised the risk of successive prosecutions under state and federal law
    for the same criminal conduct, thus compounding the harm inflicted
    by precedent. But this objection obviously assumes that precedent
    was erroneous from the start, so it is only as strong as the historical
    arguments found wanting. In any case, eliminating the dual-
    sovereignty rule would do little to trim the reach of federal criminal
    law or prevent many successive state and federal prosecutions for the
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                     3
    Syllabus
    same criminal conduct, see Blockburger v. United States, 
    284 U.S. 299
    . Pp. 28–31.
    694 Fed. Appx. 750, affirmed.
    ALITO, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which ROBERTS, C. J.,
    and THOMAS, BREYER, SOTOMAYOR, KAGAN, and KAVANAUGH, JJ., joined.
    THOMAS, J., filed a concurring opinion. GINSBURG, J., and GORSUCH, J.,
    filed dissenting opinions.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                              1
    Opinion of the Court
    NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the
    preliminary print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested to
    notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Wash-
    ington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order
    that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 17–646
    _________________
    TERANCE MARTEZ GAMBLE, PETITIONER v.
    UNITED STATES
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE ELEVENTH CIRCUIT
    [June 17, 2019]
    JUSTICE ALITO delivered the opinion of the Court.
    We consider in this case whether to overrule a
    longstanding interpretation of the Double Jeopardy Clause
    of the Fifth Amendment. That Clause provides that no
    person may be “twice put in jeopardy” “for the same of-
    fence.” Our double jeopardy case law is complex, but at its
    core, the Clause means that those acquitted or convicted of
    a particular “offence” cannot be tried a second time for the
    same “offence.” But what does the Clause mean by an
    “offence”?
    We have long held that a crime under one sovereign’s
    laws is not “the same offence” as a crime under the laws of
    another sovereign. Under this “dual-sovereignty” doc-
    trine, a State may prosecute a defendant under state law
    even if the Federal Government has prosecuted him for
    the same conduct under a federal statute.
    Or the reverse may happen, as it did here. Terance
    Gamble, convicted by Alabama for possessing a firearm as
    a felon, now faces prosecution by the United States under
    its own felon-in-possession law. Attacking this second
    prosecution on double jeopardy grounds, Gamble asks us
    2               GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    to overrule the dual-sovereignty doctrine. He contends
    that it departs from the founding-era understanding of the
    right enshrined by the Double Jeopardy Clause. But the
    historical evidence assembled by Gamble is feeble; point-
    ing the other way are the Clause’s text, other historical
    evidence, and 170 years of precedent. Today we affirm
    that precedent, and with it the decision below.
    I
    In November 2015, a local police officer in Mobile, Ala-
    bama, pulled Gamble over for a damaged headlight.
    Smelling marijuana, the officer searched Gamble’s car,
    where he found a loaded 9-mm handgun. Since Gamble
    had been convicted of second-degree robbery, his posses-
    sion of the handgun violated an Alabama law providing
    that no one convicted of “a crime of violence” “shall own a
    firearm or have one in his or her possession.” Ala. Code
    §13A–11–72(a) (2015); see §13A–11–70(2) (defining “crime
    of violence” to include robbery). After Gamble pleaded
    guilty to this state offense, federal prosecutors indicted
    him for the same instance of possession under a federal
    law—one forbidding those convicted of “a crime punishable
    by imprisonment for a term exceeding one year . . . to ship
    or transport in interstate or foreign commerce, or possess
    in or affecting commerce, any firearm or ammunition.” 
    18 U.S. C
    . §922(g)(1).
    Gamble moved to dismiss on one ground: The federal
    indictment was for “the same offence” as the one at issue
    in his state conviction and thus exposed him to double
    jeopardy. But because this Court has long held that two
    offenses “are not the ‘same offence’ ” for double jeopardy
    purposes if “prosecuted by different sovereigns,” Heath v.
    Alabama, 
    474 U.S. 82
    , 92 (1985), the District Court de-
    nied Gamble’s motion to dismiss. Gamble then pleaded
    guilty to the federal offense while preserving his right to
    challenge the denial of his motion to dismiss on double
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                   3
    Opinion of the Court
    jeopardy grounds. But on appeal the Eleventh Circuit
    affirmed, citing the dual-sovereignty doctrine. 694 Fed.
    Appx. 750 (2017). We granted certiorari to determine
    whether to overturn that doctrine.1 
    585 U.S.
    ___ (2018).
    II
    Gamble contends that the Double Jeopardy Clause must
    forbid successive prosecutions by different sovereigns
    because that is what the founding-era common law did.
    But before turning to that historical claim, see Part III
    infra, we review the Clause’s text and some of the cases
    Gamble asks us to overturn.
    A
    We start with the text of the Fifth Amendment. Al-
    though the dual-sovereignty rule is often dubbed an “excep-
    tion” to the double jeopardy right, it is not an exception at
    all. On the contrary, it follows from the text that defines
    that right in the first place. “[T]he language of the Clause
    . . . protects individuals from being twice put in jeopardy
    ‘for the same offence,’ not for the same conduct or actions,”
    Grady v. Corbin, 
    495 U.S. 508
    , 529 (1990), as Justice
    Scalia wrote in a soon-vindicated dissent, see United
    States v. Dixon, 
    509 U.S. 688
     (1993) (overruling Grady).
    And the term “ ‘[o]ffence’ was commonly understood in
    1791 to mean ‘transgression,’ that is, ‘the Violation or
    Breaking of a Law.’ ” Grady, 495 U. S., at 529 (Scalia, J.,
    dissenting) (quoting Dictionarium Britannicum (Bailey ed.
    1730)). See also 2 R. Burn & J. Burn, A New Law Diction-
    ary 167 (1792) (“OFFENCE, is an act committed against
    law, or omitted where the law requires it”). As originally
    ——————
    1 In addressing that question, we follow the parties’ lead and assume,
    without deciding, that the state and federal offenses at issue here
    satisfy the other criteria for being the “same offence” under our double
    jeopardy precedent. See Blockburger v. United States, 
    284 U.S. 299
    ,
    304 (1932).
    4                   GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    understood, then, an “offence” is defined by a law, and
    each law is defined by a sovereign. So where there are two
    sovereigns, there are two laws, and two “offences.” See
    Grady, 495 U. S., at 529 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (“If the
    same conduct violates two (or more) laws, then each of-
    fense may be separately prosecuted”); Moore v. Illinois, 
    14 How. 13
    , 17 (1852) (“The constitutional provision is not,
    that no person shall be subject, for the same act, to be
    twice put in jeopardy of life or limb; but for the same
    offence, the same violation of law, no person’s life or limb
    shall be twice put in jeopardy” (emphasis added)).
    Faced with this reading, Gamble falls back on an epi-
    sode from the Double Jeopardy Clause’s drafting history.2
    The first Congress, working on an earlier draft that would
    have banned “ ‘more than one trial or one punishment for
    the same offence,’ ” voted down a proposal to add “ ‘by any
    law of the United States.’ ” 1 Annals of Cong. 753 (1789).
    In rejecting this addition, Gamble surmises, Congress
    must have intended to bar successive prosecutions regard-
    less of the sovereign bringing the charge.
    Even if that inference were justified—something that
    the Government disputes—it would count for little. The
    private intent behind a drafter’s rejection of one version of
    a text is shoddy evidence of the public meaning of an
    altogether different text. Cf. United States v. Craft, 535
    ——————
    2 Gamble also cites founding-era uses of the word “offence” that are
    not tied to violations of a sovereign’s laws, but the examples are not
    very telling. Some, for instance, play on the unremarkable fact that at
    the founding, “offence” could take on a different sense in nonlegal
    settings, much as “offense” does today. In this vein, Gamble cites a
    19th-century dictionary defining “offense” broadly as “any transgres-
    sion of law, divine or human; a crime; sin; act of wickedness or omission
    of duty.” 2 N. Webster, An American Dictionary of the English Lan-
    guage (1828). But the question is what “offence” meant in legal con-
    texts. See Moore v. Illinois, 
    14 How. 13
    , 19 (1852) (“An offence, in its
    legal signification, means the transgression of a law. . .” (emphasis
    added)).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)            5
    Opinion of the Court
    U. S. 274, 287 (2002) (“[F]ailed legislative proposals are a
    particularly dangerous ground on which to rest an inter-
    pretation of a prior statute” (internal quotation marks
    omitted)).
    Besides, if we allowed conjectures about purpose to
    inform our reading of the text, the Government’s conjec-
    ture would prevail. The Government notes that the Decla-
    ration of Independence denounced King George III for
    “protecting [British troops] by a mock Trial, from punish-
    ment for any Murders which they should commit on the
    Inhabitants of these States.” ¶ 17. The Declaration was
    alluding to “the so-called Murderers’ Act, passed by Par-
    liament after the Boston Massacre,” Amar, Sixth Amend-
    ment First Principles, 84 Geo. L. J. 641, 687, n. 181 (1996),
    a law that allowed British officials indicted for murder in
    America to be “ ‘tried in England, beyond the control of
    local juries.’ ” Ibid. (quoting J. Blum et al., The National
    Experience 95 (3d ed. 1973)). “During the late colonial
    period, Americans strongly objected to . . . [t]his circum-
    vention of the judgment of the victimized community.”
    Amar, 84 Geo. L. Rev., at 687, n. 181. Yet on Gamble’s
    reading, the same Founders who quite literally revolted
    against the use of acquittals abroad to bar criminal prose-
    cutions here would soon give us an Amendment allow-
    ing foreign acquittals to spare domestic criminals. We
    doubt it.
    We see no reason to abandon the sovereign-specific
    reading of the phrase “same offence,” from which the dual-
    sovereignty rule immediately follows.
    B
    Our cases reflect the same reading. A close look at them
    reveals how fidelity to the Double Jeopardy Clause’s text
    does more than honor the formal difference between two
    distinct criminal codes. It honors the substantive differ-
    ences between the interests that two sovereigns can have
    6                GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    in punishing the same act.
    The question of successive federal and state prosecu-
    tions arose in three antebellum cases implying and then
    spelling out the dual-sovereignty doctrine. The first, Fox
    v. Ohio, 
    5 How. 410
     (1847), involved an Ohio prosecution
    for the passing of counterfeit coins. The defendant argued
    that since Congress can punish counterfeiting, the States
    must be barred from doing so, or else a person could face
    two trials for the same offense, contrary to the Fifth
    Amendment. We rejected the defendant’s premise that
    under the Double Jeopardy Clause “offences falling within
    the competency of different authorities to restrain or
    punish them would not properly be subjected to the conse-
    quences which those authorities might ordain and affix to
    their perpetration.” Id., at 435. Indeed, we observed, the
    nature of the crime or its effects on “public safety” might
    well “deman[d]” separate prosecutions. Ibid. Generalizing
    from this point, we declared in a second case that “the
    same act might, as to its character and tendencies, and the
    consequences it involved, constitute an offence against
    both the State and Federal governments, and might draw
    to its commission the penalties denounced by either, as
    appropriate to its character in reference to each.” United
    States v. Marigold, 
    9 How. 560
    , 569 (1850).
    A third antebellum case, Moore v. Illinois, 
    14 How. 13
    ,
    expanded on this concern for the different interests of
    separate sovereigns, after tracing it to the text in the
    manner set forth above. Recalling that the Fifth Amend-
    ment prohibits double jeopardy not “for the same ac[t]” but
    “for the same offence,” and that “[a]n offence, in its legal
    signification, means the transgression of a law,” id., at 19,
    we drew the now-familiar inference: A single act “may be
    an offence or transgression of the laws of ” two sovereigns,
    and hence punishable by both, id., at 20. Then we gave
    color to this abstract principle—and to the diverse inter-
    ests it might vindicate—with an example. An assault on a
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)            7
    Opinion of the Court
    United States marshal, we said, would offend against the
    Nation and a State: the first by “hindering” the “execution
    of legal process,” and the second by “breach[ing]” the
    “peace of the State.” Ibid. That duality of harm explains
    how “one act” could constitute “two offences, for each of
    which [the offender] is justly punishable.” Ibid.
    This principle comes into still sharper relief when we
    consider a prosecution in this country for crimes commit-
    ted abroad. If, as Gamble suggests, only one sovereign
    may prosecute for a single act, no American court—state
    or federal—could prosecute conduct already tried in a
    foreign court. Imagine, for example, that a U. S. national
    has been murdered in another country. That country
    could rightfully seek to punish the killer for committing an
    act of violence within its territory. The foreign country’s
    interest lies in protecting the peace in that territory rather
    than protecting the American specifically. But the United
    States looks at the same conduct and sees an act of vio-
    lence against one of its nationals, a person under the
    particular protection of its laws. The murder of a U. S.
    national is an offense to the United States as much as it is
    to the country where the murder occurred and to which
    the victim is a stranger. That is why the killing of an
    American abroad is a federal offense that can be prose-
    cuted in our courts, see 
    18 U.S. C
    . §2332(a)(1), and
    why customary international law allows this exercise of
    jurisdiction.
    There are other reasons not to offload all prosecutions
    for crimes involving Americans abroad. We may lack
    confidence in the competence or honesty of the other coun-
    try’s legal system. Less cynically, we may think that
    special protection for U. S. nationals serves key national
    interests related to security, trade, commerce, or scholar-
    ship. Such interests might also give us a stake in punish-
    ing crimes committed by U. S. nationals abroad—
    especially crimes that might do harm to our national
    8               GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    security or foreign relations. See, e.g., §2332a(b) (bomb-
    ings). These examples reinforce the foundation laid in our
    antebellum cases: that a crime against two sovereigns
    constitutes two offenses because each sovereign has an
    interest to vindicate.
    We cemented that foundation 70 years after the last of
    those antebellum cases, in a decision upholding a federal
    prosecution that followed one by a State. See United
    States v. Lanza, 
    260 U.S. 377
    , 382 (1922) (“[A]n act de-
    nounced as a crime by both national and state sovereign-
    ties is an offense against the peace and dignity of both and
    may be punished by each”). And for decades more, we
    applied our precedent without qualm or quibble. See, e.g.,
    Screws v. United States, 
    325 U.S. 91
     (1945); Jerome v.
    United States, 
    318 U.S. 101
     (1943); Puerto Rico v. Shell
    Co. (P. R.), Ltd., 
    302 U.S. 253
     (1937); Westfall v. United
    States, 
    274 U.S. 256
     (1927); Hebert v. Louisiana, 
    272 U.S. 312
     (1926). When petitioners in 1959 asked us twice to
    reverse course, we twice refused, finding “[n]o considera-
    tion or persuasive reason not presented to the Court in the
    prior cases” for disturbing our “firmly established” doc-
    trine. Abbate v. United States, 
    359 U.S. 187
    , 195; see also
    Bartkus v. Illinois, 
    359 U.S. 121
    . And then we went on
    enforcing it, adding another six decades of cases to the
    doctrine’s history. See, e.g., Puerto Rico v. Sánchez Valle,
    
    579 U.S.
    ___ (2016); Heath v. Alabama, 
    474 U.S. 82
    (1985); United States v. Wheeler, 
    435 U.S. 313
     (1978);
    Rinaldi v. United States, 
    434 U.S. 22
     (1977) (per curiam).
    C
    We briefly address two objections to this analysis.
    First, the dissents contend that our dual-sovereignty
    rule errs in treating the Federal and State Governments as
    two separate sovereigns when in fact sovereignty belongs
    to the people. See post, at 3 (opinion of GINSBURG, J.);
    post, at 7 (opinion of GORSUCH, J.). This argument is
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)              9
    Opinion of the Court
    based on a non sequitur. Yes, our Constitution rests on
    the principle that the people are sovereign, but that does
    not mean that they have conferred all the attributes of
    sovereignty on a single government. Instead, the people,
    by adopting the Constitution, “‘split the atom of sovereignty.’”
    Alden v. Maine, 
    527 U.S. 706
    , 751 (1999) (alteration
    omitted) (internal quotation marks and citation omitted).
    As we explained last Term:
    “When the original States declared their independ-
    ence, they claimed the powers inherent in sovereignty
    . . . . The Constitution limited but did not abolish the
    sovereign powers of the States, which retained ‘a re-
    siduary and inviolable sovereignty.’ The Federalist
    No. 39, p. 245 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961). Thus, both the
    Federal Government and the States wield sovereign
    powers, and that is why our system of government is
    said to be one of ‘dual sovereignty.’ Gregory v. Ash-
    croft, 
    501 U.S. 452
    , 457 (1991).” Murphy v. National
    Collegiate Athletic Assn., 
    584 U.S.
    ___, ___ (2018)
    (slip op., at 14).
    It is true that the Republic is “ ‘ONE WHOLE,’ ” post, at 3
    (opinion of GINSBURG, J.) (quoting The Federalist No. 82,
    p. 493 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961) (A. Hamilton)); accord, post,
    at 7 (opinion of GORSUCH, J.). But there is a difference
    between the whole and a single part, and that difference
    underlies decisions as foundational to our legal system as
    McCulloch v. Maryland, 
    4 Wheat. 316
     (1819). There, in
    terms so directly relevant as to seem presciently tailored
    to answer this very objection, Chief Justice Marshall
    distinguished precisely between “the people of a State”
    and “[t]he people of all the States,” id., at 428, 435; be-
    tween the “sovereignty which the people of a single state
    possess” and the sovereign powers “conferred by the peo-
    ple of the United States on the government of the Union,”
    id., at 429–430; and thus between “the action of a part”
    10              GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    and “the action of the whole,” id., at 435–436. In short,
    McCulloch’s famous holding that a State may not tax the
    national bank rested on a recognition that the States and
    the Nation have different “interests” and “right[s].” Id.,
    431, 436. One strains to imagine a clearer statement of
    the premises of our dual-sovereignty rule, or a more au-
    thoritative source. The United States is a federal republic;
    it is not, contrary to JUSTICE GORSUCH’s suggestion, post,
    at 10–11, a unitary state like the United Kingdom.
    Gamble and the dissents lodge a second objection to this
    line of reasoning. They suggest that because the division
    of federal and state power was meant to promote liberty, it
    cannot support a rule that exposes Gamble to a second
    sentence. See post, at 3–4 (opinion of GINSBURG, J.); post,
    at 8–9 (opinion of GORSUCH, J.). This argument funda-
    mentally misunderstands the governmental structure
    established by our Constitution. Our federal system
    advances individual liberty in many ways. Among other
    things, it limits the powers of the Federal Government
    and protects certain basic liberties from infringement.
    But because the powers of the Federal Government and
    the States often overlap, allowing both to regulate often
    results in two layers of regulation. Taxation is an example
    that comes immediately to mind. It is also not at all un-
    common for the Federal Government to permit activities
    that a State chooses to forbid or heavily restrict—for
    example, gambling and the sale of alcohol. And a State
    may choose to legalize an activity that federal law prohib-
    its, such as the sale of marijuana. So while our system of
    federalism is fundamental to the protection of liberty, it
    does not always maximize individual liberty at the ex-
    pense of other interests. And it is thus quite extraordi-
    nary to say that the venerable dual-sovereignty doctrine
    represents a “ ‘desecrat[ion]’ ” of federalism. Post, at 9
    (opinion of GORSUCH, J.).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)           11
    Opinion of the Court
    III
    Gamble claims that our precedent contradicts the common-
    law rights that the Double Jeopardy Clause was
    originally understood to engraft onto the Constitution—
    rights stemming from the “common-law pleas of auterfoits
    acquit [former acquittal] and auterfoits convict [former
    conviction].” Grady, 495 U. S., at 530 (Scalia, J., dissent-
    ing). These pleas were treated as “reason[s] why the
    prisoner ought not to answer [an indictment] at all, nor
    put himself upon his trial for the crime alleged.” 4 W.
    Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 335
    (1773) (Blackstone). Gamble argues that those who rati-
    fied the Fifth Amendment understood these common-law
    principles (which the Amendment constitutionalized) to
    bar a domestic prosecution following one by a foreign
    nation. For support, he appeals to early English and
    American cases and treatises. We have highlighted one
    hurdle to Gamble’s reading: the sovereign-specific original
    meaning of “offence.” But the doctrine of stare decisis is
    another obstacle.
    Stare decisis “promotes the evenhanded, predictable,
    and consistent development of legal principles, fosters
    reliance on judicial decisions, and contributes to the actual
    and perceived integrity of the judicial process.” Payne v.
    Tennessee, 
    501 U.S. 808
    , 827 (1991). Of course, it is also
    important to be right, especially on constitutional matters,
    where Congress cannot override our errors by ordinary
    legislation. But even in constitutional cases, a departure
    from precedent “demands special justification.” Arizona v.
    Rumsey, 
    467 U.S. 203
    , 212 (1984). This means that some-
    thing more than “ambiguous historical evidence” is re-
    quired before we will “flatly overrule a number of major
    decisions of this Court.” Welch v. Texas Dept. of Highways
    and Public Transp., 
    483 U.S. 468
    , 479 (1987). And the
    strength of the case for adhering to such decisions grows
    in proportion to their “antiquity.” Montejo v. Louisiana,
    12               GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    
    556 U.S. 778
    , 792 (2009). Here, as noted, Gamble’s his-
    torical arguments must overcome numerous “major deci-
    sions of this Court” spanning 170 years. In light of these
    factors, Gamble’s historical evidence must, at a minimum,
    be better than middling.
    And it is not. The English cases are a muddle. Trea-
    tises offer spotty support. And early state and federal cases
    are by turns equivocal and downright harmful to Gamble’s
    position. All told, this evidence does not establish that
    those who ratified the Fifth Amendment took it to bar
    successive prosecutions under different sovereigns’ laws—
    much less do so with enough force to break a chain of
    precedent linking dozens of cases over 170 years.
    A
    Gamble’s core claim is that early English cases reflect
    an established common-law rule barring domestic prosecu-
    tion following a prosecution for the same act under a
    different sovereign’s laws. But from the very dawn of the
    common law in medieval England until the adoption of the
    Fifth Amendment in 1791, there is not one reported deci-
    sion barring a prosecution based on a prior trial under
    foreign law. We repeat: Gamble has not cited and we have
    not found a single pre-Fifth Amendment case in which a
    foreign acquittal or conviction barred a second trial in a
    British or American court. Given this void, Gamble faces
    a considerable challenge in convincing us that the Fifth
    Amendment was originally understood to establish such a
    bar.
    Attempting to show that such a bar was available,
    Gamble points to five early English decisions for which we
    have case reports. We will examine these in some detail,
    but we note at the outset that they play only a secondary
    role for Gamble.
    The foundation of his argument is a decision for which
    we have no case report: the prosecution in England in
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                13
    Opinion of the Court
    1677 of a man named Hutchinson. (We have a report of a
    decision denying Hutchinson bail but no report of his
    trial.) As told by Gamble, Hutchinson, having been tried
    and acquitted in a foreign court for a murder committed
    abroad, was accused of the same homicide in an English
    tribunal, but the English court held that the foreign prose-
    cution barred retrial.
    Everything for Gamble stems from this one unreported
    decision. To the extent that the cases he cites provide any
    support for his argument—and for the most part, they do
    not—those cases purport to take their cue from the
    Hutchinson episode; the same is true of the treatises on
    which Gamble relies.
    So what evidence do we have about what actually hap-
    pened to Hutchinson? The most direct evidence is a report
    of his application for bail before the Court of King’s Bench.
    The report spans all of one sentence:
    “On Habeas Corpus it appeared the Defendant was
    committed to Newgate on suspicion of Murder in Por-
    tugal, which by Mr. Attorny being a Fact out of the
    Kings Dominions, is not triable by Commission, upon
    35 H. 8. Cap. 2. §. I. N. 2. but by a Constable and
    Marshal, and the Court refused to Bail him, & c.” Rex
    v. Hutchinson, 3 Keb. 785, 84 Eng. Rep. 1011 (1677).
    From this report, all that we can tell about the court’s
    thinking is that it found no convincing reason to grant
    bail, as was typical in murder cases.3 The rest of the
    report concerns claims by an attorney. We are told that he
    contested the jurisdiction of the commission before which
    Hutchinson was to be tried, apparently a special commis-
    sion that would have issued pursuant to a statute enacted
    under Henry VIII.4 The commission lacked jurisdiction,
    ——————
    3 See J. Beattie, Crime and the Courts in England: 1660–1800, pp.
    281–282 (1986).
    4 Although this Act reached conduct committed “out of the King Maj-
    14                 GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    the attorney seemed to suggest, because the crime had
    occurred in Portugal and thus “out of the Kings Domin-
    ions.” The attorney claimed that jurisdiction lay instead
    with “a Constable and Marshal”—an apparent reference to
    the High Court of Chivalry, which dealt with treason and
    murder committed abroad.5 But what, if anything, did the
    King’s Bench make of the attorney’s jurisdictional claims?
    And more to the point, what happened after bail was
    denied? The bail report does not say.
    If Hutchinson did ultimately appear before the Court of
    Chivalry—and if that court accepted a plea of prior acquit-
    tal in Portugal—this would be paltry evidence of any
    common-law principle, which is what Gamble cites
    Hutchinson to establish. After all, the High Court of
    Chivalry was a civil-law court prohibited from proceeding
    under the common law (unlike every other English court
    of the time save Admiralty). 8 Ric. 2 ch. 5; see also Squibb
    162; id., at xxv–xxvi (“The essential distinction between
    the Court of Chivalry and other courts is . . . that it admin-
    isters justice in relation to those military matters which
    are not governed by the common law”). Nor would it be
    any surprise that we have no report of the proceeding; in
    fact, “[t]here is no report of a case in which a judge of the
    Court [of Chivalry] has set out the reasons for his decision
    earlier than the [20th] century.” Id., at 162.
    In the end, we have only two early accounts from judges
    of what finally became of Hutchinson, and both are indi-
    rect and shaky. First, they appear in the reports of cases
    decided in the Court of Chancery more than a half century
    after Hutchinson. Second, both judges cite only one
    ——————
    esties Realme of Englande and other his Graces [Dominions],” Acte
    concerning the triall of Treasons 1543–1544, 35 Hen. 8 ch. 2 (1543–
    1544), it applied only to treasons and misprisions of treason—not to
    homicide, of which Hutchinson was accused.
    5 See G. Squibb, The High Court of Chivalry 54, 147–148 (1959)
    (Squibb); 4 Blackstone 267.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                  15
    Opinion of the Court
    source, and it is of lower authority than their own: namely,
    an account of Hutchinson given by an interested party
    (a defendant) in a previous, non-criminal case—an account
    on which the court in that case did not rely or even com-
    ment.6 Insofar as our two judges seem to add their own
    details to the Hutchinson saga, we are not told where they
    obtained this information or whether it reflects mere
    guesses as to how gaps in the story should be filled in,
    decades after the fact. Finally, the two judges’ accounts
    are not entirely consistent. Still, they are the only early
    judicial glosses on Hutchinson that we have, so we will
    work with them.
    The more extensive account appears in the case of Gage
    v. Bulkeley, Ridg. T. H. 263, 27 Eng. Rep. 824 (Ch. 1744),
    and what the court said there—far from supporting Gam-
    ble’s argument—cuts against it. Gage involved a bill in
    chancery for an account of money deposited with a banker
    in Paris. The defendants pleaded, as a bar to this lawsuit,
    “a sentence” “given upon” the same demand in a French
    court. Ibid. In addressing this plea, Lord Chancellor
    Hardwicke first determined that foreign judgments are
    not binding in an English court of law. Here his reasoning
    was very similar to that found in our dual-sovereignty
    decisions. Because each judgment rests on the authority
    of a particular sovereign, the Chancellor thought, it cannot
    bind foreign courts, which operate by the power of a differ-
    ent sovereign. Id., at 263–264, 27 Eng. Rep., at 824.
    ——————
    6 See Gage v. Bulkeley, Ridg. T. H. 263, 271, 27 Eng. Rep. 824, 826–
    827 (Ch. 1744) (citing Beake v. Tyrrell, 1 Show. K. B. 6); Burrows v.
    Jemino, 2 Str. 733, 25 Eng. Rep. 235 (K. B. 1726) (same). As noted, the
    report cited by both judges—which also appears at 89 Eng. Rep. 411 (K.
    B. 1688)—mentions Hutchinson only in summarizing a defendant’s
    argument. So does the only other source cited by either judge. See
    Gage, Ridg. T. H., at 271, 27 Eng. Rep., at 826–827 (citing Beak v.
    Thyrwhit, 3 Mod. 194, 87 Eng. Rep. 124 (K. B. 1688)). Below we discuss
    in detail the case that figures in these two reports. See infra, at 19,
    and n. 11.
    16                  GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    Turning next to courts of equity, the Lord Chancellor
    saw no reason that the rule should be any different; there
    too, he thought, a foreign judgment is not binding. Id., at
    273, 27 Eng. Rep., at 827. But he did allow that in equity
    a foreign judgment could serve as “evidence, which may
    affect the right of [a plaintiff] when the cause comes to be
    heard.” Ibid.
    Elaborating on why foreign judgments did not bind
    English courts, whether of law or equity, the Lord Chan-
    cellor explained why Hutchinson was “no proof ” to the
    contrary. In the Chancellor’s telling, Hutchinson was not
    indicted by the Court of King’s Bench, which could have
    tried a murder committed in England,7 because that court
    had no jurisdiction over a homicide committed in Portugal.
    Gage, Ridge. T. H., at 271, 27 Eng. Rep., at 826–827.
    Instead, Hutchinson was (as the bail decision indicates)
    before that court on a writ of habeas corpus, and his case
    “was referred to the judges to know whether a commission
    should issue” under a statute similar to the one mentioned
    in the bail decision. Ibid., 27 Eng. Rep., at 827; see 33
    Hen. 8 ch. 28 (1541–1542).8 “And,” he explained, “the
    judges very rightly and mercifully thought not, because he
    had undergone one trial already.” Gage, Ridg. T. H., at
    271–272, 27 Eng. Rep., at 827 (emphasis added). This
    suggests that Hutchinson was spared retrial as a matter
    of discretion (“merc[y]”)—which must be true if the Chan-
    ——————
    74  Blackstone 262.
    8 This statute authorized commissioners to try certain defendants for
    acts of treason or murder committed “in whatsoever other Shire or
    place, within the King’s dominions or without.” But “[d]espite the
    words ‘or without’, contemporary opinion seems not to have regarded
    the extra-territorial operation of this Act as clear.” Squibb 149. In-
    deed, the statute cited in the Hutchinson bail report, dated to just two
    years later, cited lingering “doubtes and questions” about whether
    English courts could try treason committed abroad (in the course of
    clarifying that treason and misprisions of treason abroad could indeed
    be tried in England). 35 Hen. 8 ch. 2, § I.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                  17
    Opinion of the Court
    cellor was right that foreign judgments were not binding.
    Indeed, at least one modern scholar agrees (on other
    grounds as well) that the result in Hutchinson may have
    been based on “expediency rather than law.” M. Fried-
    land, Double Jeopardy 362–363 (1969).
    In the end, then, Gage is doubly damaging to Gamble.
    First, it squarely rejects the proposition that a litigant in
    an English court—even a civil litigant in equity—had a
    right to the benefit of a foreign judgment, a right that the
    Fifth Amendment might have codified. And second, Gage
    undermines      Gamble’s      chief   historical    example,
    Hutchinson, by giving a contrary reading of that case—
    and doing so, no less, in one of the only two judicial ac-
    counts of Hutchinson that we have from before the Fifth
    Amendment.
    The other account appears in Burrows v. Jemino, 2 Str.
    733, 93 Eng. Rep. 815 (K. B. 1726).9 In Burrows, a party
    that was sued in England on a bill of exchange sought an
    injunction against this suit in the Court of Chancery,
    contending that the suit was barred by the judgment of a
    court in Italy. In explaining why he would grant the
    injunction, Lord Chancellor King cited Hutchinson, which
    he thought had involved an acquittal in Spanish court
    that was “allowed to be a good bar to any proceedings
    here.” 2 Str., at 733, 93 Eng. Rep., at 815. This remark,
    showing that at least one English judge before the found-
    ing saw Hutchinson as Gamble does, provides a modicum
    of support for Gamble’s argument. But that support soft-
    ens just a few lines down in the report, where the Chan-
    cellor discusses the status of foreign judgments in courts
    of law in particular (as distinct from courts of equity like
    ——————
    9 This case is also reported as Burrows v. Jemineau in Sel. Ca. t. 69,
    25 Eng. Rep. 228 (Ch. 1726); as Burroughs v. Jamineau in Mos. 1, 25
    Eng. Rep. 235; as Burrows v. Jemineau in 2 Eq. Ca. Abr. 476, 22 Eng.
    Rep. 405; and as Burrows v. Jemino in 2 Eq. Ca. Abr. 524, 22 Eng. Rep.
    443.
    18                  GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    his own)—i.e., the courts that actually applied the common-
    law rules later codified by the Fifth Amendment.
    Here the Chancellor explained that while he personally
    would have accepted an Italian judgment as barring any
    suit at law, “other Judges might be of a different opinion.”
    Ibid. As a whole, then, the Chancellor’s comments in
    Burrows can hardly be cited to prove that the common law
    had made up its mind on this matter; just the opposite.
    Gamble’s other cases have even less force. The “most
    instructive” case, he claims, see Brief for Petitioner 13, is
    the 1775 case of King v. Roche, 1 Leach 134,10 168 Eng.
    Rep. 169 (K.B.), but that is a curious choice since the
    Roche court does not so much as mention Hutchinson or
    even tacitly affirm its supposed holding. The defendant in
    Roche entered two pleas: prior acquittal abroad and not
    guilty of the charged crime. All that the Roche court held
    was that, as a procedural matter, it made no sense to
    charge the jury with both pleas at once, because a finding
    for Roche on the first (prior acquittal) would, if successful,
    bar consideration of the second (not guilty). Roche, 1
    Leach, at 135, 168 Eng. Rep., at 169. But on our key
    question—whether a plea based on a foreign acquittal
    could be successful—the Roche court said absolutely noth-
    ing; it had no occasion to do so. Before the prosecution
    could reply to Roche’s plea of prior acquittal, he withdrew
    it, opting for a full trial. The name Hutchinson does not
    appear even in the marginalia of the 1789 edition of
    Roche, which existed in 1791. See Captain Roche’s Case, 1
    Leach at 138–139.
    Hutchinson is mentioned in connection with Roche only
    after the Fifth Amendment’s ratification, and only in a
    compiler’s annotation to the 1800 edition of the Roche case
    report. See 168 Eng. Rep., at 169, n. (a). That annotation
    ——————
    10 This case is reported as Captain Roche’s Case in 1 Leach 138 (1789
    ed.) and in 2 Leach 125 (1792 ed.).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                    19
    Opinion of the Court
    in turn cites one case as support for its reading of
    Hutchinson: Beak v. Thyrwhit, 3 Mod. 194, 87 Eng. Rep.
    124 (K. B. 1688). But Beak did not involve a foreign pros-
    ecution; indeed, it did not involve a prosecution at all. It
    was an admiralty case for trover and conversion of a ship,
    and—more to the point—Hutchinson is discussed only in
    the defendant’s argument in that case, not the court’s
    response. A report relaying the actual decision in Beak
    shows that the court ultimately said nothing about the
    defendant’s Hutchinson argument one way or another.
    See Beake v. Tyrrell, 1 Show. K. B. 6, 89 Eng. Rep. 411
    (1688).11 This same defendant’s argument was the only
    source of information about Hutchinson on which the
    Chancellors in Gage and Burrows explicitly relied, as we
    noted above. All later accounts of Hutchinson seem to
    stem from this one shallow root.
    The last of Gamble’s five pre-Fifth Amendment cases,
    Rex v. Thomas, 1 Lev. 118, 83 Eng. Rep. 326 (K. B. 1664),
    did not even involve a foreign prosecution. The defendant
    was indicted for murder in England, and he pleaded a
    prior acquittal by a Welsh court. But Wales was then part
    of the “kingdom of England”; its laws were “the laws of
    England and no other.” 1 Blackstone 94–95; see Thomas,
    1 Lev., at 118, 83 Eng. Rep., at 326–327. So the prior trial
    in Thomas was not under another sovereign’s laws, mak-
    ing it totally irrelevant for present purposes.
    Summing up the import of the preratification cases on
    which Gamble’s argument rests, we have the following: (1)
    not a single reported case in which a foreign acquittal or
    conviction barred a later prosecution for the same act in
    either Britain or America; (2) not a single reported deci-
    sion in which a foreign judgment was held to be binding in
    a civil case in a court of law; (3) fragmentary and not
    ——————
    11 This decision is also reported as Beake v. Tirrell, Com. 120, 90 Eng.
    Rep. 379.
    20              GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    entirely consistent evidence about a 17th-century case in
    which a defendant named Hutchinson, having been tried
    and acquitted for murder someplace in the Iberian Penin-
    sula, is said to have been spared a second trial for this
    crime on some ground, perhaps out of “merc[y],” not as a
    matter of right; (4) two cases (one criminal, one in admi-
    ralty) in which a party invoked a prior foreign judgment,
    but the court did not endorse or rest anything on the
    party’s reliance on that judgment; and (5) two Court of
    Chancery cases actually holding that foreign judgments
    were not (or not generally) treated as barring trial at
    common law. This is the flimsy foundation in case law for
    Gamble’s argument that when the Fifth Amendment was
    ratified, it was well understood that a foreign criminal
    judgment would bar retrial for the same act.
    Surveying the pre-Fifth Amendment cases in 1959, we
    concluded that their probative value was “dubious” due to
    “confused and inadequate reporting.” Bartkus, 359 U. S.,
    at 128, n. 9. Our assessment was accurate then, and the
    passing years have not made those early cases any clearer
    or more valuable.
    B
    Not to worry, Gamble responds: Whatever the English
    courts actually did prior to adoption of the Fifth Amend-
    ment, by that time the early English cases were widely
    thought to support his view. This is a curious argument
    indeed. It would have us hold that the Fifth Amendment
    codified a common-law right that existed in legend, not
    case law. In any event, the evidence that this right was
    thought to be settled is very thin.
    Gamble’s argument is based on treatises, but they are
    not nearly as helpful as he claims. Alone they do not come
    close to settling the historical question with enough force
    to meet Gamble’s particular burden under stare decisis.
    Gamble begins with Blackstone, but he reads volumes
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)           21
    Opinion of the Court
    into a flyspeck. In the body of his Commentaries, all that
    Blackstone stated was that successive prosecutions could
    be barred by prior acquittals by “any court having compe-
    tent jurisdiction of the offence.” 4 Blackstone 335. This is
    simply a statement of the general double-jeopardy rule,
    without a word on separate sovereigns. So Gamble directs
    our attention to a footnote that appears after the phrase
    “any court having competent jurisdiction.” The footnote
    refers to the report of Beak v. Thyrwhit, which, as noted,
    merely rehearses the argument of the defendant in that
    case, who in turn mentioned Hutchinson—but not in a
    criminal prosecution, much less one preceded by a foreign
    trial. This thread tying Blackstone to Hutchinson—a
    thread woven through footnotes and reports of reports but
    not a single statement by a court (or even by a party to an
    actual prosecution)—is tenuous evidence that Blackstone
    endorsed Gamble’s reading of Hutchinson.
    When Gamble’s attorney was asked at argument which
    other treatises he found most likely to have informed
    those who ratified the Fifth Amendment, he offered four.
    See Tr. of Oral Arg. 30–31. But two of the four treatises
    did not exist when the Fifth Amendment was ratified. See
    1 J. Chitty, Criminal Law 458 (1816); 1 T. Starkie, Crimi-
    nal Pleading 300–301, n. h (1814). And a third discusses
    not a single case involving a prior prosecution under for-
    eign law. See 2 W. Hawkins, Pleas of the Crown 372
    (1739).
    That leaves one treatise cited by Gamble that spoke to
    this issue before ratification, F. Buller, An Introduction to
    the Law Relative to Trials at Nisi Prius (5th ed. 1788).
    That treatise concerned the trial of civil cases, id., at 2,
    and its discussion of prior judgments appeared under the
    heading “Of Evidence in general,” id., at 221. After con-
    sidering the evidentiary value of such documents as acts of
    Parliament, deeds, and depositions, Buller addressed what
    we would later call issue preclusion. Lifting language
    22                  GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    from an earlier publication, H. Bathurst, The Theory of
    Evidence 39 (1761), Buller wrote that a final judgment
    was “conclusive Evidence” “against all the World” of the
    factual determinations underlying the judgment. Buller,
    Nisi Prius, at 245. And it is on this basis that Buller
    (again lifting from Bathurst) said that even someone
    acquitted of a crime in Spain “might,” upon indictment in
    England, “plead the Acquittal in Spain in Bar.” Ibid.
    This endorsement of the preclusive effect of a foreign
    judgment in civil litigation (which even today is not uni-
    formly accepted in this country12) provides no direct sup-
    port for Gamble since his prior judgment was one of con-
    viction, not acquittal.     (There is, after all, a major
    difference between the preclusive effect of a prior acquittal
    and that of a prior conviction: Only the first would make a
    subsequent prosecution pointless, by requiring later courts
    to assume a defendant’s innocence from the start.) And in
    any case, the fleeting references in the Buller and Bat-
    ——————
    12 Compare   Restatement (Fourth) of Foreign Relations Law of the
    United States § 481 (2018) (With a few specified exceptions, “a final,
    conclusive, and enforceable judgment of a court of a foreign state
    granting or denying recovery of a sum of money, or determining a legal
    controversy, is entitled to recognition by courts in the United States”)
    and Restatement (Second) of Conflict of Laws § 98, Comment b. (1969)
    (“In most respects,” judgments rendered in a foreign nation satisfying
    specified criteria “will be accorded the same degree of recognition to
    which sister State judgments are entitled”), with, e.g., Derr v. Swarek,
    
    766 F.3d 430
    , 437 (CA5 2014) (recognition of foreign judgments is not
    required but is a matter of comity); Diorinou v. Mezitis, 
    237 F.3d 133
    ,
    142–143 (CA2 2001) (same); id., at 139–140 (“It is well-established that
    United States courts are not obliged to recognize judgments rendered
    by a foreign state, but may choose to give res judicata effect to foreign
    judgments on the basis of comity” (emphasis in original; internal
    quotation marks omitted)); MacArthur v. San Juan County, 
    497 F.3d 1057
    , 1067 (CA10 2007) (“Comity is not an inexorable command . . . and
    a request for recognition of a foreign judgment may be rebuffed on any
    number of grounds”); Guinness PLC v. Ward, 
    955 F.2d 875
    , 883 (CA4
    1992) (“The effect to be given foreign judgments has therefore histori-
    cally been determined by more flexible principles of comity”).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                 23
    Opinion of the Court
    hurst treatises are hardly sufficient to show that the Mem-
    bers of the First Congress and the state legislators who
    ratified the Fifth Amendment understood the Double
    Jeopardy Clause to bar a prosecution in this country after
    acquittal abroad for the same criminal conduct.
    Gamble attempts to augment his support by citing
    treatises published after the Fifth Amendment was adopted.13
    And he notes that the Court in District of Columbia
    v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 605–610 (2008), took treatises of a
    similar vintage to shed light on the public understanding
    in 1791 of the right codified by the Second Amendment.
    But the Heller Court turned to these later treatises only
    after surveying what it regarded as a wealth of authority
    for its reading—including the text of the Second Amend-
    ment and state constitutions. The 19th-century treatises
    were treated as mere confirmation of what the Court
    thought had already been established. Here Gamble’s
    evidence as to the understanding in 1791 of the double
    jeopardy right is not at all comparable.
    C
    When we turn from 19th-century treatises to 19th-
    century state cases, Gamble’s argument appears no
    stronger. The last time we looked, we found these state
    cases to be “inconclusive.” Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 131.
    They seemed to be evenly split and to “manifest conflict[s]
    in conscience” rather than confident conclusions about the
    common law. Ibid. Indeed, two of those cases manifested
    nothing more than a misreading of a then-recent decision
    of ours. Id., at 130. We see things no differently today.
    The distinction between believing successive prosecu-
    tions by separate sovereigns unjust and holding them
    ——————
    13 See, e.g., F. Wharton, A Treatise on the Law of Homicide in the
    United States 283 (1855); F. Wharton, A Treatise on the Criminal Law
    of the United States 137 (1846); L. MacNally, The Rules of Evidence on
    Pleas of the Crown 428 (1802).
    24               GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    unlawful appears right on the face of the first state case
    that Gamble discusses. In State v. Brown, 2 N. C. 100,
    101 (1794), the court opined that it would be “against
    natural justice” for a man who stole a horse in the Southwest
    Territory to be punished for theft in North Carolina just
    for having brought the horse to that State. To avoid this
    result, the Brown court simply construed North Carolina’s
    theft law not to reach the defendant’s conduct. But it did
    so precisely because the defendant otherwise could face
    two prosecutions for the same act of theft—despite the
    common-law rule against double jeopardy for the same
    “offence”—since “the offence against the laws of this State,
    and the offence against the laws of [the Territory] are
    distinct; and satisfaction made for the offence committed
    against this State, is no satisfaction for the offence com-
    mitted against the laws there.” Ibid. Far from undermin-
    ing the dual-sovereignty rule, Brown expressly affirms it,
    rejecting outright the idea that a judgment in one sover-
    eign’s court could “be pleadable in bar to an indictment” in
    another’s. Ibid.
    Other state courts were divided. Massachusetts and
    Michigan courts thought that at least some trials in either
    federal or state court could bar prosecution in the other,
    see Commonwealth v. Fuller, 
    49 Mass. 313
    , 318 (1844);
    Harlan v. People, 
    1 Doug. 207
    , 212 (Mich. 1843), but those
    antebellum cases are poor images of the founding-era
    common law, resting as they do on what we have ex-
    plained, see Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 130, was a misreading
    of our then-recent decision in Houston v. Moore, 
    5 Wheat. 1
     (1820), which we discuss below. A Vermont court did
    take the same view based on its own analysis of the ques-
    tion, State v. Randall, 
    2 Aik. 89
    , 100–101 (1827), but just a
    few years later a Virginia court declared the opposite,
    Hendrick v. Commonwealth, 
    32 Va. 707
    , 713 (1834) (pun-
    ishment for forgery under both federal and Virginia law is
    not double punishment for the “same offence” since “the
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                   25
    Opinion of the Court
    law of Virginia punishes the forgery, not because it is an
    offence against the U. States, but because it is an offence
    against this commonwealth”). And South Carolina—a
    perfect emblem of the time—produced cases cutting both
    ways. See State v. Antonio, 
    2 Tread. 776
    , 781 (1816); State
    v. Tutt, 
    2 Bail. 44
    , 47–48 (1831).
    This is not the quantum of support for Gamble’s claim
    about early American common law that might withstand
    his burden under stare decisis. And once we look beyond
    the Nation’s earliest years, the body of state-court deci-
    sions appears even less helpful to Gamble’s position. We
    aptly summarized those cases in Bartkus, 359 U. S., at
    134–136, and need not add to that discussion here.14
    D
    Less useful still, for Gamble’s purposes, are the two
    early Supreme Court cases on which he relies. In the first,
    a member of the Pennsylvania militia was tried by a state
    court-martial for the federal offense of deserting the mili-
    tia. See Houston v. Moore, 
    5 Wheat. 1
     (1820). The ac-
    ——————
    14 As  we put it in Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 134–136:
    “Of the twenty-eight States which have considered the validity of
    successive state and federal prosecutions as against a challenge of
    violation of either a state constitutional double-jeopardy provision or a
    common-law evidentiary rule of autrefois acquit and autrefois convict,
    twenty-seven have refused to rule that the second prosecution was or
    would be barred. These States were not bound to follow this Court and
    its interpretation of the Fifth Amendment. The rules, constitutional,
    statutory, or common law which bound them, drew upon the same
    experience as did the Fifth Amendment, but were and are of separate
    and independent authority.
    “Not all of the state cases manifest careful reasoning, for in some of
    them the language concerning double jeopardy is but offhand dictum.
    But in an array of state cases there may be found full consideration of
    the arguments supporting and denying a bar to a second prosecution.
    These courts interpreted their rules as not proscribing a second prose-
    cution where the first was by a different government and for violation
    of a different statute.” (Footnote omitted.)
    26               GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    cused objected that the state court-martial lacked jurisdic-
    tion to try this federal offense. Since the offense could be
    tried in federal court, the defendant argued, allowing the
    state court-martial to try him for this crime could expose
    him to successive federal and state prosecutions for the
    same offense. Justice Washington answered that a ruling
    in either federal or state court would bar a second trial in
    the other. See id., at 31. But as we later explained,
    “that language by Mr. Justice Washington reflected
    his belief that the state statute imposed state sanc-
    tions for violation of a federal criminal law. As he
    viewed the matter, the two trials would not be of simi-
    lar crimes arising out of the same conduct; they would
    be of the same crime. Mr. Justice Johnson agreed
    that if the state courts had become empowered to try
    the defendant for the federal offense, then such a
    state trial would bar a federal prosecution. Thus
    Houston v. Moore can be cited only for the presence of
    a bar in a case in which the second trial is for a viola-
    tion of the very statute whose violation by the same
    conduct has already been tried in the courts of an-
    other government empowered to try that question.”
    Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 130 (citations omitted).
    In other words, Justice Washington taught only that the
    law prohibits two sovereigns (in that case, Pennsylvania
    and the United States) from both trying an offense against
    one of them (the United States). That is consistent with
    our doctrine allowing successive prosecutions for offenses
    against separate sovereigns. In light of this reading of
    Houston, the case does not undercut our dual-sovereignty
    doctrine.
    It may seem strange to think of state courts as prosecut-
    ing crimes against the United States, but that is just what
    state courts and commentators writing within a decade of
    Houston thought it involved. See, e.g., Tutt, 2 Bail., at 47
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                  27
    Opinion of the Court
    (“In [Houston], the act punished by the law of the State,
    was certainly and exclusively an offence against the gen-
    eral Government . . . [whereas h]ere, certainly there is an
    offence against the State, and a very different one from
    that committed against the United States” (emphasis
    added)); 1 J. Kent, Commentaries on American Law 373–
    374 (1826) (“[M]any . . . acts of [C]ongress . . . permit
    jurisdiction, over the offences therein described, to be
    exercised by state magistrates and courts,” and what
    Houston bars are successive prosecutions for the same
    “crime against the United States”). Even the scholar
    Gamble cites for his cause finds Houston not “[o]n point”
    because it “was discussing the jurisdiction of the state
    court to try a crime against the nation and impose a fine
    payable to the latter government.” Grant, Successive
    Prosecutions by State and Nation: Common Law and
    British Empire Comparisons, 4 UCLA L. Rev. 1, 7, and n.
    27 (1956) (citing Warren, Federal Criminal Laws and the
    State Courts, 38 Harv. L. Rev. 545 (1925)).
    Perhaps feeling Houston wobble, Gamble says pre-
    emptively that if it is “inconclusive,” Brief for Petitioner
    26, other cases are clear. But the other federal case on
    which he leans is worse for his argument. In United
    States v. Furlong, 
    5 Wheat. 1
    84, 197 (1820), we said that
    an acquittal of piracy in the court of any “civilized State”
    would bar prosecution in any other nation because piracy,
    as an “offence within the criminal jurisdiction of all na-
    tions,” is “punished by all.”15 Ending his quotation from
    ——————
    15 Piracywas understood as a violation of the law of nations, which
    was seen as common to all. That is why any successive prosecution for
    piracy, being under the same law, would have been for the same of-
    fense. See United States v. Smith, 
    5 Wheat. 1
    53, 163, n. a (1820)
    (quoting definitions of piracy by several ancient and more recent
    authorities). See also 4 Blackstone 71 (“[T]he crime of piracy, or rob-
    bery and depredation upon the high seas, is an offence against the
    universal law of society; a pirate being, according to Sir Edward Coke,
    28                  GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    Furlong at this point, Gamble gives the impression that
    Furlong rejects any dual-sovereignty rule. But that im-
    pression is shattered by the next sentence: “Not so with
    the crime of murder.” Ibid. As to that crime, the Furlong
    Court was “inclined to think that an acquittal” in the
    United States “would not have been a good plea in a Court
    of Great Britain.” Ibid. (emphasis added). And that was
    precisely because murder is “punishable under the laws of
    each State” rather than falling under some “universal
    jurisdiction.” Ibid. (emphasis added). When it came to
    crimes that were understood to offend against more than
    one sovereign, Furlong treated them as separate offenses—
    just as we have a dozen times since, and just as we do
    today.
    Thus, of the two federal cases that Gamble cites against
    the dual-sovereignty rule, Houston squares with it and
    Furlong supports it. Together with the muddle in the
    early state cases, this undermines Gamble’s claim that the
    early American bench and bar took the Fifth Amendment
    to proscribe successive prosecutions by different sover-
    eigns. And without making a splash in the legal practice
    of the time, a few early treatises by themselves cannot
    unsettle almost two centuries of precedent.
    IV
    Besides appealing to the remote past, Gamble contends
    that recent changes—one doctrinal, one practical—blunt
    the force of stare decisis here. They do not.
    ——————
    hostis humani generis [enemies of mankind]. As therefore he has
    renounced all the benefits of society and government, and has reduced
    himself afresh to the savage state of nature, by declaring war against
    all mankind, all mankind must declare war against him: so that every
    community has a right, by the rule of self-defence, to inflict that pun-
    ishment upon him, which every individual would in a state of nature
    have been otherwise entitled to do, for any invasion of his person or
    personal property” (footnote omitted)).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                29
    Opinion of the Court
    A
    If historical claims form the chorus of Gamble’s argu-
    ment, his refrain is “incorporation.” In Gamble’s telling,
    the recognition of the Double Jeopardy Clause’s incorpora-
    tion against the States, see Benton v. Maryland, 
    395 U.S. 784
    , 794 (1969), washed away any theoretical foundation
    for the dual-sovereignty rule, see United States v. Gaudin,
    
    515 U.S. 506
    , 521 (1995) (abrogating precedent when
    “subsequent decisions of this Court” have “eroded” its
    foundations). But this incorporation-changes-everything
    argument trades on a false analogy.
    The analogy Gamble draws is to the evolution of our
    doctrine on the Fourth Amendment right against unrea-
    sonable searches and seizures.16 We have long enforced
    this right by barring courts from relying on evidence gath-
    ered in an illegal search. Thus, in Weeks v. United States,
    
    232 U.S. 383
    , 391–393 (1914), the Court held that federal
    prosecutors could not rely on the fruits of an unreasonable
    search undertaken by federal agents. But what if state or
    local police conducted a search that would have violated
    the Fourth Amendment if conducted by federal agents?
    Before incorporation, the state search would not have
    violated the Federal Constitution, so federal law would not
    have barred admission of the resulting evidence in a state
    prosecution. But by the very same token, under what was
    termed “the silver-platter doctrine,” state authorities could
    hand such evidence over to federal prosecutors for use in a
    federal case. See id., at 398.
    Once the Fourth Amendment was held to apply to the
    States as well as the Federal Government, however, the
    silver-platter doctrine was scuttled. See Elkins v. United
    States, 
    364 U.S. 206
     (1960); Wolf v. Colorado, 
    338 U.S. 25
    ——————
    16 He draws a similar analogy to the Fifth Amendment right against
    self-incrimination, but our response to his Fourth Amendment analogy
    would answer that argument as well.
    30               GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    Opinion of the Court
    (1949). Now the fruits of unreasonable state searches are
    inadmissible in federal and state courts alike.
    Gamble contends that the incorporation of the Double
    Jeopardy Clause should likewise end the dual-sovereignty
    rule, but his analogy fails. The silver-platter doctrine was
    based on the fact that the state searches to which it ap-
    plied did not at that time violate federal law. Once the
    Fourth Amendment was incorporated against the States,
    the status of those state searches changed. Now they did
    violate federal law, so the basis for the silver-platter doc-
    trine was gone. See Elkins, 364 U. S., at 213 (“The foun-
    dation upon which the admissibility of state-seized evi-
    dence in a federal trial originally rested—that
    unreasonable state searches did not violate the Federal
    Constitution—thus disappeared [with incorporation]”).
    By contrast, the premises of the dual-sovereignty doc-
    trine have survived incorporation intact. Incorporation
    meant that the States were now required to abide by this
    Court’s interpretation of the Double Jeopardy Clause. But
    that interpretation has long included the dual-sovereignty
    doctrine, and there is no logical reason why incorporation
    should change it. After all, the doctrine rests on the fact
    that only same-sovereign successive prosecutions are
    prosecutions for the “same offense,” see Part II, supra—
    and that is just as true after incorporation as before.
    B
    If incorporation is the doctrinal shift that Gamble in-
    vokes to justify a departure from precedent, the practical
    change he cites is the proliferation of federal criminal law.
    Gamble says that the resulting overlap of federal and
    criminal codes heightens the risk of successive prosecu-
    tions under state and federal law for the same criminal
    conduct. Thus, Gamble contends, our precedent should
    yield to “ ‘far-reaching systemic and structural changes’ ”
    that make our “earlier error all the more egregious and
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)           31
    Opinion of the Court
    harmful.” South Dakota v. Wayfair, Inc., 
    585 U.S.
    ___,
    ___ (2018) (slip op., at 18). But unlike Gamble’s appeal to
    incorporation, this argument obviously assumes that the
    dual-sovereignty doctrine was legal error from the start.
    So the argument is only as strong as Gamble’s argument
    about the original understanding of double jeopardy
    rights, an argument that we have found wanting.
    Insofar as the expansion of the reach of federal criminal
    law has been questioned on constitutional rather than
    policy grounds, the argument has focused on whether
    Congress has overstepped its legislative powers under the
    Constitution. See, e.g., Gonzales v. Raich, 
    545 U.S. 1
    , 57–
    74 (2005) (THOMAS, J., dissenting). Eliminating the dual-
    sovereignty rule would do little to trim the reach of federal
    criminal law, and it would not even prevent many succes-
    sive state and federal prosecutions for the same criminal
    conduct unless we also overruled the long-settled rule that
    an “offence” for double jeopardy purposes is defined by
    statutory elements, not by what might be described in a
    looser sense as a unit of criminal conduct. See Block-
    burger v. United States, 
    284 U.S. 299
     (1932). Perhaps
    believing that two revolutionary assaults in the same case
    would be too much, Gamble has not asked us to overrule
    Blockburger along with the dual-sovereignty rule.
    *    *     *
    The judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Eleventh
    Circuit is affirmed.
    It is so ordered.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                     1
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 17–646
    _________________
    TERANCE MARTEZ GAMBLE, PETITIONER v.
    UNITED STATES
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE ELEVENTH CIRCUIT
    [June 17, 2019]
    JUSTICE THOMAS, concurring.
    I agree that the historical record does not bear out my
    initial skepticism of the dual-sovereignty doctrine. See
    Puerto Rico v. Sánchez Valle, 
    579 U.S.
    ___ (2016)
    (GINSBURG, J., joined by THOMAS, J. concurring).
    The founding generation foresaw very limited potential for
    overlapping criminal prosecutions by the States and the
    Federal Government.1 The Founders therefore had no
    reason to address the double jeopardy question that the
    Court resolves today. Given their understanding of Con-
    gress’ limited criminal jurisdiction and the absence of an
    analogous dual-sovereign system in England, it is difficult
    to conclude that the People who ratified the Fifth Amend-
    ——————
    1 As the Court suggests, Congress is responsible for the proliferation
    of duplicative prosecutions for the same offenses by the States and the
    Federal Government. Ante, at 28. By legislating beyond its limited
    powers, Congress has taken from the People authority that they never
    gave. U. S. Const., Art. I, §8; The Federalist No. 22, p. 152 (C. Rossiter
    ed. 1961) (“all legitimate authority” derives from “the consent of the
    people” (capitalization omitted)). And the Court has been complicit by
    blessing this questionable expansion of the Commerce Clause. See, e.g.,
    Gonzales v. Raich, 
    545 U.S. 1
    , 57–74 (2005) (THOMAS, J., dissenting).
    Indeed, it seems possible that much of Title 18, among other parts of
    the U. S. Code, is premised on the Court’s incorrect interpretation of
    the Commerce Clause and is thus an incursion into the States’ general
    criminal jurisdiction and an imposition on the People’s liberty.
    2                GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    ment understood it to prohibit prosecution by a State and
    the Federal Government for the same offense. And, of
    course, we are not entitled to interpret the Constitution to
    align it with our personal sensibilities about “ ‘unjust’ ”
    prosecutions. Post, at 6 (GINSBURG, J., dissenting); see
    Currier v. Virginia, 
    585 U.S.
    ___, ___ (2018) (plurality
    opinion) (slip op., at 16) (“While the growing number of
    criminal offenses in our statute books may be cause for
    concern, no one should expect (or want) judges to revise
    the Constitution to address every social problem they
    happen to perceive” (citation omitted)).
    I write separately to address the proper role of the
    doctrine of stare decisis. In my view, the Court’s typical
    formulation of the stare decisis standard does not comport
    with our judicial duty under Article III because it elevates
    demonstrably erroneous decisions—meaning decisions
    outside the realm of permissible interpretation—over the
    text of the Constitution and other duly enacted federal
    law. It is always “tempting for judges to confuse our own
    preferences with the requirements of the law,” Obergefell
    v. Hodges, 
    576 U.S.
    ___, ___ (2015) (ROBERTS, C. J., dis-
    senting) (slip op., at 3), and the Court’s stare decisis doc-
    trine exacerbates that temptation by giving the veneer of
    respectability to our continued application of demonstra-
    bly incorrect precedents. By applying demonstrably erro-
    neous precedent instead of the relevant law’s text—as the
    Court is particularly prone to do when expanding federal
    power or crafting new individual rights—the Court exer-
    cises “force” and “will,” two attributes the People did not
    give it. The Federalist No. 78, p. 465 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961)
    (capitalization omitted).
    We should restore our stare decisis jurisprudence to
    ensure that we exercise “mer[e] judgment,” ibid., which
    can be achieved through adherence to the correct, original
    meaning of the laws we are charged with applying. In my
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                     3
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    view, anything less invites arbitrariness into judging.2
    I
    The Court currently views stare decisis as a “ ‘principle
    of policy’ ” that balances several factors to decide whether
    the scales tip in favor of overruling precedent. Citizens
    United v. Federal Election Comm’n, 
    558 U.S. 310
    , 363
    (2010) (quoting Helvering v. Hallock, 
    309 U.S. 106
    , 119
    (1940)). Among these factors are the “workability” of the
    standard, “the antiquity of the precedent, the reliance
    interests at stake, and of course whether the decision was
    well reasoned.” Montejo v. Louisiana, 
    556 U.S. 778
    , 792–
    793 (2009). The influence of this last factor tends to ebb
    and flow with the Court’s desire to achieve a particular
    end, and the Court may cite additional, ad hoc factors to
    reinforce the result it chooses. But the shared theme is
    the need for a “special reason over and above the belief
    that a prior case was wrongly decided” to overrule a prec-
    edent. Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey,
    
    505 U.S. 833
    , 864 (1992). The Court has advanced this
    view of stare decisis on the ground that “it promotes the
    evenhanded, predictable, and consistent development of
    legal principles” and “contributes to the actual and per-
    ceived integrity of the judicial process.” Payne v. Tennes-
    see, 
    501 U.S. 808
    , 827 (1991).
    This approach to stare decisis might have made sense in
    a common-law legal system in which courts systematically
    developed the law through judicial decisions apart from
    written law. But our federal system is different. The
    Constitution tasks the political branches—not the Judici-
    ary—with systematically developing the laws that govern
    our society. The Court’s role, by contrast, is to exercise the
    ——————
    2 My focus in this opinion is on this Court’s adherence to its own prec-
    edents. I make no claim about any obligation of “inferior” federal
    courts, U. S. Const., Art. III, §1, or state courts to follow Supreme Court
    precedent.
    4                GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    “judicial Power,” faithfully interpreting the Constitution
    and the laws enacted by those branches. Art. III, §1.
    A
    A proper understanding of stare decisis in our constitu-
    tional structure requires a proper understanding of the
    nature of the “judicial Power” vested in the federal courts.
    That “Power” is—as Chief Justice Marshall put it—the
    power “to say what the law is” in the context of a particu-
    lar “case” or “controversy” before the court. Marbury v.
    Madison, 1 Cranch 137, 177 (1803); Art. III, §2. Phrased
    differently, the “judicial Power” “is fundamentally the
    power to decide cases in accordance with law.” Lawson,
    The Constitutional Case Against Precedent, 17 Harv. J. L.
    & Pub. Pol’y 23, 26 (1994) (Lawson). It refers to the duty
    to exercise “judicial discretion” as distinct from “arbitrary
    discretion.” The Federalist No. 78, at 468, 471.
    That means two things, the first prohibitory and the
    second obligatory. First, the Judiciary lacks “force” (the
    power to execute the law) and “will” (the power to legis-
    late). Id., at 465 (capitalization omitted). Those powers
    are vested in the President and Congress, respectively.
    “Judicial power is never exercised for the purpose of giving
    effect to the will of the Judge; always for the purpose of
    giving effect to the will of the Legislature; or, in other
    words, to the will of the law.” Osborn v. Bank of United
    States, 
    9 Wheat. 738
    , 866 (1824) (Marshall, C. J.). The
    Judiciary thus may not “substitute [its] own pleasure to
    the constitutional intentions of the legislature.” The
    Federalist No. 78, at 468–469.
    Second, “judicial discretion” requires the “liquidat[ion]”
    or “ascertain[ment]” of the meaning of the law. Id., at
    467–468; see id., No. 37. At the time of the founding, “to
    liquidate” meant “to make clear or plain”; “to render un-
    ambiguous; to settle (differences, disputes).” Nelson, Stare
    Decisis and Demonstrably Erroneous Precedents, 87 Va.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)            5
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    L. Rev. 1, 13, and n. 35 (2001) (Nelson) (quoting 8 Oxford
    English Dictionary 1012 (2d ed. 1991); (internal quotation
    marks omitted)). Therefore, judicial discretion is not the
    power to “alter” the law; it is the duty to correctly “ex-
    pound” it. Letter from J. Madison to N. Trist (Dec. 1831),
    in 9 The Writings of James Madison 477 (G. Hunt ed.
    1910) (Writings of Madison).
    B
    This understanding of the judicial power had long been
    accepted at the time of the founding. But the federalist
    structure of the constitutional plan had significant impli-
    cations for the exercise of that power by the newly created
    Federal Judiciary. Whereas the common-law courts of
    England discerned and defined many legal principles in
    the first instance, the Constitution charged federal courts
    primarily with applying a limited body of written laws
    articulating those legal principles. This shift profoundly
    affects the application of stare decisis today.
    Stare decisis has its pedigree in the unwritten common
    law of England. As Blackstone explained, the common law
    included “[e]stablished customs” and “[e]stablished rules
    and maxims” that were discerned and articulated by
    judges. 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of
    England 68–69 (1765) (Blackstone). In the common-law
    system, stare decisis played an important role because
    “judicial decisions [were] the principal and most authorita-
    tive evidence, that [could] be given, of the existence of such
    a custom as shall form a part of the common law.” Id.,
    at 69. Accordingly, “precedents and rules must be fol-
    lowed, unless flatly absurd or unjust,” because a judge
    must issue judgments “according to the known laws and
    customs of the land” and not “according to his private
    sentiments” or “own private judgment.” Id., at 69–70. In
    other words, judges were expected to adhere to precedents
    because they embodied the very law the judges were
    6                   GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    bound to apply.
    “[C]ommon law doctrines, as articulated by judges, were
    seen as principles that had been discovered rather than
    new laws that were being made.” 3–4 G. White, The
    Marshall Court and Cultural Change, 1815–35, History of
    the Supreme Court of the United States 129 (1988).3 “It
    was the application of the dictates of natural justice, and
    of cultivated reason, to particular cases.” 1 J. Kent, Com-
    mentaries on American Law 439 (1826) (Kent); see id., at
    439–440 (the common law is “ ‘not the product of the wis-
    dom of some one man, or society of men, in any one age;
    but of the wisdom, counsel, experience, and observation, of
    many ages of wise and observing men’ ”). The common law
    therefore rested on “unarticulated social processes to
    mobilize and coordinate knowledge” gained primarily
    through “the social experience of the many,” rather than
    the “specifically articulated reason of the few.” T. Sowell,
    A Conflict of Visions: Ideological Origins of Political
    Struggles 49, 42 (1987). In other words, the common law
    was based in the collective, systematic development of the
    law through reason. See id., at 49–55.
    Importantly, however, the common law did not view
    precedent as unyielding when it was “most evidently
    contrary to reason” or “divine law.” Blackstone 69–70.
    The founding generation recognized that a “judge may
    mistake the law.” Id., at 71; see also 1 Kent 444 (“Even a
    series of decisions are not always conclusive evidence of
    what is law”). And according to Blackstone, judges should
    disregard precedent that articulates a rule incorrectly
    when necessary “to vindicate the old [rule] from misrepre-
    ——————
    3 Our founding documents similarly rest on the premise that certain
    fundamental principles are both knowable and objectively true. See,
    e.g., Declaration of Independence (“We hold these truths to be self-
    evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their
    Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life,
    Liberty, and the pursuit of Happiness”).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)            7
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    sentation.” Blackstone 70; see also 1 Kent 443 (“If . . . any
    solemnly adjudged case can be shown to be founded in
    error, it is no doubt the right and the duty of the judges
    who have a similar case before them, to correct the error”).
    He went further: When a “former decision is manifestly
    absurd or unjust” or fails to conform to reason, it is not
    simply “bad law,” but “not law” at all. Blackstone 70
    (emphasis).     This view—that demonstrably erroneous
    “blunders” of prior courts should be corrected—was ac-
    cepted by state courts throughout the 19th century. See,
    e.g., McDowell v. Oyer, 
    21 Pa. 417
    , 423 (1853); Guild v.
    Eager, 
    17 Mass. 615
    , 622 (1822).
    This view of precedent implies that even common-law
    judges did not act as legislators, inserting their own pref-
    erences into the law as it developed. Instead, consistent
    with the nature of the judicial power, common-law judges
    were tasked with identifying and applying objective prin-
    ciples of law—discerned from natural reason, custom, and
    other external sources—to particular cases. See Nelson
    23–27. Thus, the founding generation understood that an
    important function of the Judiciary in a common-law
    system was to ascertain what reason or custom required;
    that it was possible for courts to err in doing so; and that
    it was the Judiciary’s responsibility to “examin[e] without
    fear, and revis[e] without reluctance,” any “hasty and
    crude decisions” rather than leaving “the character of [the]
    law impaired, and the beauty and harmony of the system
    destroyed by the perpetuity of error.” 1 Kent 444.
    Federal courts today look to different sources of law
    when exercising the judicial power than did the common-
    law courts of England. The Court has long held that
    “[t]here is no federal general common law.” Erie R. Co. v.
    Tompkins, 
    304 U.S. 64
    , 78 (1938). Instead, the federal
    courts primarily interpret and apply three bodies of fed-
    eral positive law—the Constitution; federal statutes, rules,
    8                   GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    and regulations; and treaties.4 That removes most (if
    not all) of the force that stare decisis held in the English
    common-law system, where judicial precedents were among
    the only documents identifying the governing “customs” or
    “rules and maxims.” Blackstone 68. We operate in a
    system of written law in which courts need not—and
    generally cannot—articulate the law in the first instance.
    See U. S. Const., Art. I, §1 (vesting “[a]ll legislative Pow-
    ers” in Congress); Art. 1, §7 (describing the bicameralism
    and presentment process).        The Constitution, federal
    statutes, and treaties are the law, and the systematic
    development of the law is accomplished democratically.
    Our judicial task is modest: We interpret and apply writ-
    ten law to the facts of particular cases.
    Underlying this legal system is the key premise that
    words, including written laws, are capable of objective,
    ascertainable meaning. As I have previously explained,
    “[m]y vision of the process of judging is unabashedly based
    on the proposition that there are right and wrong answers
    to legal questions.” Thomas, Judging, 45 U. Kan. L. Rev.
    1, 5 (1996). Accordingly, judicial decisions may incorrectly
    interpret the law, and when they do, subsequent courts
    must confront the question when to depart from them.
    C
    Given that the primary role of federal courts today is to
    interpret legal texts with ascertainable meanings, prece-
    dent plays a different role in our exercise of the “judicial
    Power” than it did at common law. In my view, if the
    Court encounters a decision that is demonstrably errone-
    ous—i.e., one that is not a permissible interpretation of
    ——————
    4 There are certain exceptions to this general rule, including areas of
    law in which federal common law has historically been understood to
    govern (e.g., admiralty) and well-established judicial doctrines that are
    applied in the federal courts (e.g., issue preclusion). Additionally,
    federal courts apply state law where it governs.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)             9
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    the text—the Court should correct the error, regardless of
    whether other factors support overruling the precedent.
    Federal courts may (but need not) adhere to an incorrect
    decision as precedent, but only when traditional tools of
    legal interpretation show that the earlier decision adopted
    a textually permissible interpretation of the law. A de-
    monstrably incorrect judicial decision, by contrast, is
    tantamount to making law, and adhering to it both disre-
    gards the supremacy of the Constitution and perpetuates
    a usurpation of the legislative power.
    1
    When faced with a demonstrably erroneous precedent,
    my rule is simple: We should not follow it. This view of
    stare decisis follows directly from the Constitution’s su-
    premacy over other sources of law—including our own
    precedents. That the Constitution outranks other sources
    of law is inherent in its nature. See A. Amar, America’s
    Constitution 5 (2005) (explaining that the Constitution is
    a constitutive document); Kesavan, The Three Tiers of
    Federal Law, 100 NW.U. L. Rev. 1479, 1499, n. 99 (2006)
    (arguing that “[i]t is unnecessary for the Constitution to
    specify that it is superior to other law because it is higher
    law made by We the People—and the only such law”). The
    Constitution’s supremacy is also reflected in its require-
    ment that all judicial officers, executive officers, Con-
    gressmen, and state legislators take an oath to “support
    this Constitution.” Art. VI, cl. 3; see also Art. II, §1, cl. 8
    (requiring the President to “solemnly swear (or affirm)” to
    “preserve, protect and defend the Constitution of the
    United States”). Notably, the Constitution does not man-
    date that judicial officers swear to uphold judicial prece-
    dents. And the Court has long recognized the supremacy
    of the Constitution with respect to executive action and
    “legislative act[s] repugnant to” it. Marbury, 1 Cranch, at
    177; Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 
    343 U.S. 10
                      GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    579, 587–589 (1952); see also The Federalist No. 78, at 467
    (“No legislative act, therefore, contrary to the Constitu-
    tion, can be valid”).
    The same goes for judicial precedent. The “judicial
    Power” must be understood in light of “the Constitution’s
    status as the supreme legal document” over “lesser sources
    of law.” Lawson, 29–30. This status necessarily limits
    “the power of a court to give legal effect to prior judicial
    decisions” that articulate demonstrably erroneous inter-
    pretations of the Constitution because those prior deci-
    sions cannot take precedence over the Constitution itself.
    Ibid. Put differently, because the Constitution is supreme
    over other sources of law, it requires us to privilege its text
    over our own precedents when the two are in conflict. I
    am aware of no legitimate reason why a court may privi-
    lege a demonstrably erroneous interpretation of the Con-
    stitution over the Constitution itself.5
    The same principle applies when interpreting statutes
    and other sources of law: If a prior decision demonstrably
    erred in interpreting such a law, federal judges should
    exercise the judicial power—not perpetuate a usurpation
    of the legislative power—and correct the error. A contrary
    rule would permit judges to “substitute their own pleas-
    ure” for the law. The Federalist No. 78, at 468; see id., at
    ——————
    5 Congress and the Executive likewise must independently evaluate
    the constitutionality of their actions; they take an oath to uphold the
    Constitution, not to blindly follow judicial precedent. In the context of
    a judicial case or controversy, however, their determinations do not
    bind the Judiciary in performing its constitutionally assigned role. See,
    e.g., Zivotofsky v. Clinton, 
    566 U.S. 189
    , 197 (2012) (noting that there
    is “no exclusive commitment to the Executive of the power to determine
    the constitutionality of a statute”); INS v. Chadha, 
    462 U.S. 919
    , 944
    (1983) (Congress’ and President’s endorsement of “legislative veto”
    “sharpened rather than blunted” Court’s judicial review). Of course,
    consistent with the nature of the “judicial Power,” the federal courts’
    judgments bind all parties to the case, including Government officials
    and agencies.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                  11
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    466 (“ ‘[T]here is no liberty if the power of judging be not
    separated from the legislative and executive powers’ ”).
    In sum, my view of stare decisis requires adherence to
    decisions made by the People—that is, to the original
    understanding of the relevant legal text—which may not
    align with decisions made by the Court. Accord, Marshall
    v. Baltimore & Ohio R. Co., 
    16 How. 314
    , 343–344 (1854)
    (Daniel, J., dissenting) (“Wherever the Constitution com-
    mands, discretion terminates” because continued adher-
    ence to “palpable error” is a “violation of duty, an usurpa-
    tion”); Commonwealth v. Posey, 
    8 Va. 109
    , 116 (1787)
    (opinion of Tazewell, J.) (“[A]lthough I venerate prece-
    dents, I venerate the written law more”). Thus, no “ ‘spe-
    cial justification’ ” is needed for a federal court to depart
    from its own, demonstrably erroneous precedent. Halli-
    burton Co. v. Erica P. John Fund, Inc., 
    573 U.S. 258
    , 266
    (2014); see Nelson 62. Considerations beyond the correct
    legal meaning, including reliance, workability, and whether
    a precedent “has become well embedded in national
    culture,” S. Breyer, Making our Democracy Work: A
    Judge’s View 152 (2010), are inapposite. In our constitu-
    tional structure, our role of upholding the law’s original
    meaning is reason enough to correct course.6
    2
    Although precedent does not supersede the original
    meaning of a legal text, it may remain relevant when it is
    not demonstrably erroneous. As discussed, the “judicial
    ——————
    6I am not suggesting that the Court must independently assure itself
    that each precedent relied on in every opinion is correct as a matter of
    original understanding. We may, consistent with our constitutional
    duty and the Judiciary’s historical practice, proceed on the understand-
    ing that our predecessors properly discharged their constitutional role
    until we have reason to think otherwise—as, for example, when a party
    raises the issue or a previous opinion persuasively critiques the dis-
    puted precedent.
    12               GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    Power” requires the Court to clarify and settle—or, as
    Madison and Hamilton put it, to “liquidate”—the meaning
    of written laws. The Federalist No. 78, at 468 (“[I]t is the
    province of the courts to liquidate and fix [the] meaning
    and operation [of contradictory laws]”); The Federalist No.
    37, at 229 (explaining that the indeterminacy of laws
    requires courts to “liquidat[e] and ascertai[n]” their mean-
    ing “by a series of particular discussions and adjudica-
    tions”). This need to liquidate arises from the inability of
    human language to be fully unequivocal in every context.
    Written laws “have a range of indeterminacy,” and rea-
    sonable people may therefore arrive at different conclu-
    sions about the original meaning of a legal text after
    employing all relevant tools of interpretation. See Nelson
    11, 14. It is within that range of permissible interpreta-
    tions that precedent is relevant. If, for example, the
    meaning of a statute has been “liquidated” in a way that is
    not demonstrably erroneous (i.e., not an impermissible
    interpretation of the text), the judicial policy of stare deci-
    sis permits courts to constitutionally adhere to that inter-
    pretation, even if a later court might have ruled another
    way as a matter of first impression. Of course, a subse-
    quent court may nonetheless conclude that an incorrect
    precedent should be abandoned, even if the precedent
    might fall within the range of permissible interpretations.
    But nothing in the Constitution requires courts to take
    that step.
    Put another way, there is room for honest disagreement,
    even as we endeavor to find the correct answer. Compare
    McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm’n, 
    514 U.S. 334
    ,
    358–371 (1995) (THOMAS, J., concurring in judg-
    ment) (concluding that the “historical evidence from the
    framing” supports the view that the First Amend-
    ment permitted anonymous speech), with id., at 371–385
    (Scalia, J., dissenting) (concluding that the First Amendment
    does not protect anonymous speech based on a century of
    practice in the States). Reasonable jurists can apply
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                   13
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    traditional tools of construction and arrive at different
    interpretations of legal texts.
    “[L]iquidating” indeterminacies in written laws is far
    removed from expanding or altering them. See Writings of
    Madison 477 (explaining that judicial decisions cannot
    “alter” the Constitution, only “expound” it). The original
    meaning of legal texts “usually . . . is easy to discern and
    simple to apply.” A. Scalia, Common Law Courts in a
    Civil-Law System, in A Matter of Interpretation: Federal
    Courts and the Law 45 (A. Gutmann ed. 1997). And even
    in difficult cases, that the original meaning is not obvious
    at first blush does not excuse the Court from diligently
    pursuing that meaning. Stopping the interpretive inquiry
    short—or allowing personal views to color it—permits
    courts to substitute their own preferences over the text.
    Although the law may be, on rare occasion, truly ambigu-
    ous—meaning susceptible to multiple, equally correct
    legal meanings—the law never “runs out” in the sense
    that a Court may adopt an interpretation beyond the
    bounds of permissible construction.7 In that regard, a
    legal text is not capable of multiple permissible interpreta-
    tions merely because discerning its original meaning
    “requires a taxing inquiry.” Pauley v. BethEnergy Mines,
    Inc., 
    501 U.S. 680
    , 707 (1991) (Scalia, J., dissenting).
    This case is a good example. The historical record pre-
    sents knotty issues about the original meaning of the Fifth
    Amendment, and JUSTICE GORSUCH does an admirable job
    arguing against our longstanding interpretation of the
    Double Jeopardy Clause. Although JUSTICE GORSUCH
    identifies support for his view in several postratification
    treatises, see post, at 13–15 (dissenting opinion), I do not
    ——————
    7 Indeed, if a statute contained no objective meaning, it might consti-
    tute an improper delegation of legislative power to the Judicial Branch,
    among other problems. See Touby v. United States, 
    500 U.S. 160
    , 165
    (1991) (discussing the nondelegation doctrine).
    14               GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    find these treatises conclusive without a stronger showing
    that they reflected the understanding of the Fifth
    Amendment at the time of ratification. At that time, the
    common law certainly had not coalesced around this view,
    see ante, at 10–21, and petitioner has not pointed to con-
    temporaneous judicial opinions or other evidence estab-
    lishing that his view was widely shared. This lack of
    evidence, coupled with the unique two-sovereign federalist
    system created by our Constitution, leaves petitioner to
    rely on a general argument about “liberty.” Ultimately, I
    am not persuaded that our precedent is incorrect as an
    original matter, much less demonstrably erroneous.
    3
    Although this case involves a constitutional provision, I
    would apply the same stare decisis principles to matters of
    statutory interpretation. I am not aware of any legal (as
    opposed to practical) basis for applying a heightened
    version of stare decisis to statutory-interpretation deci-
    sions. Statutes are easier to amend than the Constitution,
    but our judicial duty is to apply the law to the facts of the
    case, regardless of how easy it is for the law to change. Cf.
    Clark v. Martinez, 
    543 U.S. 371
    , 402 (2005) (THOMAS, J.,
    dissenting) (explaining that “the realities of the legislative
    process” will “often preclude readopting the original mean-
    ing of a statute that we have upset”). Moreover, to the
    extent the Court has justified statutory stare decisis based
    on legislative inaction, this view is based on the “patently
    false premise that the correctness of statutory construc-
    tion is to be measured by what the current Congress de-
    sires, rather than by what the law as enacted meant.”
    Johnson v. Transportation Agency, Santa Clara Cty., 
    480 U.S. 616
    , 671 (1987) (Scalia, J., dissenting). Finally, even
    if congressional silence could be meaningfully understood
    as acquiescence, it still falls short of the bicameralism and
    presentment required by Article I and therefore is not a
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)           15
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    “valid way for our elected representatives to express their
    collective judgment.” Nelson 76.
    II
    For the reasons explained above, the Court’s multifactor
    approach to stare decisis invites conflict with its constitu-
    tional duty. Whatever benefits may be seen to inhere in
    that approach—e.g., “stability” in the law, preservation of
    reliance interests, or judicial “humility,” Tr. of Oral Arg.
    20, 41–42—they cannot overcome that fundamental flaw.
    In any event, these oft-cited benefits are frequently
    illusory. The Court’s multifactor balancing test for invok-
    ing stare decisis has resulted in policy-driven, “arbitrary
    discretion.” The Federalist No. 78, at 471. The inquiry
    attempts to quantify the unquantifiable and, by frequently
    sweeping in subjective factors, provides a ready means of
    justifying whatever result five Members of the Court seek
    to achieve. See Holder v. Hall, 
    512 U.S. 874
    , 943–944
    (1994) (THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment) (describing a
    “ ‘totality of circumstances’ ” test as “an empty incanta-
    tion—a mere conjurer’s trick”); Lawrence v. Texas, 
    539 U.S. 558
    , 577 (2003) (acknowledging that stare decisis is
    “ ‘a principle of policy and not a mechanical formula’ ”); see
    also Casey, 505 U. S., at 854–856 (invoking the “kind of
    reliance that would lend a special hardship to the conse-
    quences of overruling and add inequity to the cost of repu-
    diation”). These are not legal questions with right and
    wrong answers; they are policy choices. See, e.g., A. Gold-
    berg, Equal Justice: The Warren Era of the Supreme
    Court 96 (1971) (“[T]his concept of stare decisis both justi-
    fies the overruling involved in the expansion of human
    liberties during the Warren years and counsels against
    the future overruling of the Warren Court libertarian
    decisions”).
    Members of this Court have lamented the supposed
    “uncertainty” created when the Court overrules its prece-
    16               GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    dent. See Franchise Tax Bd. of Cal. v. Hyatt, ante, at ___–
    ___ (BREYER, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 12–13). But see
    Lawrence, supra, at 577 (asserting that not overruling
    precedent would “caus[e] uncertainty”). As I see it, we
    would eliminate a significant amount of uncertainty and
    provide the very stability sought if we replaced our malle-
    able balancing test with a clear, principled rule grounded
    in the meaning of the text.
    The true irony of our modern stare decisis doctrine lies
    in the fact that proponents of stare decisis tend to invoke it
    most fervently when the precedent at issue is least defen-
    sible. See, e.g., Holder, supra, at 944–945 (opinion of
    THOMAS, J.) (“Stare decisis should not bind the Court to an
    interpretation of the Voting Rights Act that was based on
    a flawed method of statutory construction from its incep-
    tion” and that has created “an irreconcilable conflict”
    between the Act and the Equal Protection Clause and
    requires “methodically carving the country into racially
    designated electoral districts”). It is no secret that stare
    decisis has had a “ratchet-like effect,” cementing certain
    grievous departures from the law into the Court’s juris-
    prudence. Goldberg, supra, at 96. Perhaps the most
    egregious example of this illegitimate use of stare decisis
    can be found in our “substantive due process” jurispru-
    dence. McDonald v. Chicago, 
    561 U.S. 742
    , 811 (2010)
    (THOMAS, J., concurring in part and concurring in judg-
    ment). The Court does not seriously defend the “legal
    fiction” of substantive due process as consistent with the
    original understanding of the Due Process Clause. Ibid.
    And as I have explained before, “this fiction is a particu-
    larly dangerous one” because it “lack[s] a guiding principle
    to distinguish ‘fundamental’ rights that warrant protec-
    tion from nonfundamental rights that do not.” Ibid.
    Unfortunately, the Court has doggedly adhered to these
    erroneous substantive-due-process precedents again and
    again, often to disastrous ends. See, e.g., Stenberg v.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)          17
    THOMAS, J., concurring
    Carhart, 
    530 U.S. 914
    , 982 (2000) (THOMAS, J., dissent-
    ing) (“The standard set forth in the Casey plurality has no
    historical or doctrinal pedigree” and “is the product of its
    authors’ own philosophical views about abortion” with “no
    origins in or relationship to the Constitution”). Likewise,
    the Court refuses to reexamine its jurisprudence about the
    Privileges or Immunities Clause, thereby relegating a
    “ ‘clause in the constitution’ ” “ ‘to be without effect.’ ”
    McDonald, supra, at 813 (quoting Marbury, 1 Cranch, at
    174); see Timbs v. Indiana, 
    586 U.S.
    ___, ___ (2019)
    (THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment) (criticizing the
    Court’s incorporation doctrine through a clause that ad-
    dresses procedures). No subjective balancing test can
    justify such a wholesale disregard of the People’s individ-
    ual rights protected by the Fourteenth Amendment.
    *     *    *
    Our judicial duty to interpret the law requires adher-
    ence to the original meaning of the text. For that reason,
    we should not invoke stare decisis to uphold precedents
    that are demonstrably erroneous. Because petitioner and
    the dissenting opinions have not shown that the Court’s
    dual-sovereignty doctrine is incorrect, much less demon-
    strably erroneous, I concur in the majority’s opinion.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)            1
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 17–646
    _________________
    TERANCE MARTEZ GAMBLE, PETITIONER v.
    UNITED STATES
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE ELEVENTH CIRCUIT
    [June, 17, 2019]
    JUSTICE GINSBURG, dissenting
    Terance Martez Gamble pleaded guilty in Alabama
    state court to both possession of a firearm by a person
    convicted of “a crime of violence” and drug possession, and
    was sentenced to ten years’ imprisonment, all but one year
    suspended. Apparently regarding Alabama’s sentence as
    too lenient, federal prosecutors pursued a parallel charge,
    possession of a firearm by a convicted felon, in violation of
    federal law. Gamble again pleaded guilty and received
    nearly three more years in prison.
    Had either the Federal Government or Alabama brought
    the successive prosecutions, the second would have violated
    Gamble’s right not to be “twice put in jeopardy . . . for the
    same offence.” U. S. Const., Amdt. 5, cl. 2. Yet the Federal
    Government was able to multiply Gamble’s time in prison
    because of the doctrine that, for double jeopardy purposes,
    identical criminal laws enacted by “separate sovereigns”
    are different “offence[s].”
    I dissent from the Court’s adherence to that misguided
    doctrine. Instead of “fritter[ing] away [Gamble’s] libert[y]
    upon a metaphysical subtlety, two sovereignties,” Grant,
    The Lanza Rule of Successive Prosecutions, 32 Colum.
    L. Rev. 1309, 1331 (1932), I would hold that the Double
    Jeopardy Clause bars “successive prosecutions [for the
    same offense] by parts of the whole USA.” Puerto Rico v.
    2                GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    Sánchez Valle, 
    579 U.S.
    ___, ___ (2016) (GINSBURG, J.,
    concurring) (slip op., at 2).
    I
    A
    Gamble urges that the Double Jeopardy Clause incorpo-
    rates English common law. That law, he maintains, rec-
    ognized a foreign acquittal or conviction as a bar to retrial
    in England for the same offense. See Brief for Petitioner
    11–15. The Court, in turn, strives mightily to refute
    Gamble’s account of the common law. See ante, at 8–21.
    This case, however, does not call for an inquiry into
    whether and when an 18th-century English court would
    have credited a foreign court’s judgment in a criminal
    case. Gamble was convicted in both Alabama and the
    United States, jurisdictions that are not foreign to each
    other. English court decisions regarding the respect due
    to a foreign nation’s judgment are therefore inapposite.
    B
    In United States v. Lanza, 
    260 U.S. 377
     (1922), this
    Court held that “an act denounced as a crime by both
    national and state sovereignties is an offense against the
    peace and dignity of both and may be punished by each.”
    Id., at 382. Decades later, a sharply divided Court reaf-
    firmed this separate-sovereigns doctrine. Abbate v. United
    States, 
    359 U.S. 187
     (1959); Bartkus v. Illinois, 
    359 U.S. 121
     (1959). I would not cling to those ill-advised decisions.
    1
    Justification for the separate-sovereigns doctrine cen-
    ters on the word “offence”: An “offence,” the argument
    runs, is the violation of a sovereign’s law, the United
    States and each State are separate sovereigns, ergo suc-
    cessive state and federal prosecutions do not place a de-
    fendant in “jeopardy . . . for the same offence.” Ante, at 1,
    3–4 (internal quotation marks omitted).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)            3
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    This “compact syllogism” is fatally flawed. See Braun,
    Praying to False Sovereigns: The Rule Permitting Succes-
    sive Prosecutions in the Age of Cooperative Federalism, 20
    Am. J. Crim. L. 1, 25 (1992). The United States and its
    constituent States, unlike foreign nations, are “kindred
    systems,” “parts of ONE WHOLE.” The Federalist No. 82,
    p. 493 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961) (A. Hamilton). They compose
    one people, bound by an overriding Federal Constitution.
    Within that “WHOLE,” the Federal and State Govern-
    ments should be disabled from accomplishing together
    “what neither government [could] do alone—prosecute an
    ordinary citizen twice for the same offence.” Amar &
    Marcus, Double Jeopardy Law After Rodney King, 95
    Colum. L. Rev. 1, 2 (1995).
    The notion that the Federal Government and the States
    are separate sovereigns overlooks a basic tenet of our
    federal system. The doctrine treats governments as sover-
    eign, with state power to prosecute carried over from years
    predating the Constitution. See Heath v. Alabama, 
    474 U.S. 82
    , 89 (1985) (citing Lanza, 260 U. S., at 382). In the
    system established by the Federal Constitution, however,
    “ultimate sovereignty” resides in the governed. Arizona
    State Legislature v. Arizona Independent Redistricting
    Comm’n, 
    576 U.S.
    ___, ___ (2015) (slip op., at 31); Martin
    v. Hunter’s Lessee, 
    1 Wheat. 304
    , 324–325 (1816); Braun,
    supra, at 26–30. Insofar as a crime offends the “peace and
    dignity” of a sovereign, Lanza, 260 U. S., at 382, that
    “sovereign” is the people, the “original fountain of all
    legitimate authority,” The Federalist No. 22, at 152 (A.
    Hamilton); see Note, Double Prosecution by State and
    Federal Governments: Another Exercise in Federalism, 80
    Harv. L. Rev. 1538, 1542 (1967). States may be separate,
    but their populations are part of the people composing the
    United States.
    In our “compound republic,” the division of authority
    between the United States and the States was meant to
    4                   GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    operate as “a double security [for] the rights of the people.”
    The Federalist No. 51, at 323 (J. Madison); see Bond v.
    United States, 
    564 U.S. 211
    , 221 (2011). The separate-
    sovereigns doctrine, however, scarcely shores up people’s
    rights. Instead, it invokes federalism to withhold liberty.
    See Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 155–156 (Black, J., dissenting).1
    It is the doctrine’s premise that each government has—
    and must be allowed to vindicate—a distinct interest in
    enforcing its own criminal laws. That is a peculiar way to
    look at the Double Jeopardy Clause, which by its terms
    safeguards the “person” and restrains the government.
    See, e.g., id., at 155; United States v. All Assets of G.P.S.
    Automotive Corp., 
    66 F.3d 483
    , 498 (CA2 1995) (Calabresi,
    J., concurring). The Double Jeopardy Clause embodies a
    principle, “deeply ingrained” in our system of justice,
    “that the State with all its resources and power should
    not be allowed to make repeated attempts to convict
    an individual for an alleged offense, thereby subject-
    ing him to embarrassment, expense and ordeal and
    compelling him to live in a continuing state of anxiety
    and insecurity, as well as enhancing the possibility
    that even though innocent he may be found guilty.”
    Green v. United States, 
    355 U.S. 184
    , 187–188 (1957).
    “Looked at from the standpoint of the individual who is
    being prosecuted,” the liberty-denying potential of succes-
    sive prosecutions, when Federal and State Governments
    prosecute in tandem, is the same as it is when either
    prosecutes twice. Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 155 (Black, J.,
    ——————
    1 The Court writes that federalism “advances individual liberty in
    many ways,” but does not always do so. Ante, at 10 (citing, for example,
    state prohibition of activities authorized by federal law). The analogy
    of the separate-sovereigns doctrine to dual regulation is inapt. The
    former erodes a constitutional safeguard against successive prosecu-
    tions, while the Constitution contains no guarantee against dual
    regulation.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                    5
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    dissenting).
    2
    I turn, next, to further justifications the Court has
    supplied for the separate-sovereigns doctrine.     None
    should survive close inspection.
    a
    One rationale emphasizes that the Double Jeopardy
    Clause originally restrained only the Federal Government
    and did not bar successive state prosecutions. Id., at 124;
    Lanza, 260 U. S., at 382; Fox v. Ohio, 
    5 How. 410
    , 434–435
    (1847). Incorporation of the Clause as a restraint on
    action by the States, effected in Benton v. Maryland, 
    395 U.S. 784
     (1969), has rendered this rationale obsolete.
    b
    Another justification is precedent. In adopting and
    reaffirming the separate-sovereigns doctrine, the Court
    relied on dicta from 19th-century opinions. See Abbate,
    359 U. S., at 190–193; Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 129–132;
    Lanza, 260 U. S., at 382–384. The persuasive force of
    those opinions is diminished by their dubious reasoning.
    See supra, at 2–4. While drawing upon dicta from prior
    opinions, the Court gave short shrift to contrary authority.
    See Braun, supra, at 20–23.
    First, the Framers of the Bill of Rights voted down an
    amendment that would have permitted the Federal Gov-
    ernment to reprosecute a defendant initially tried by a
    State. 1 Annals of Cong. 753 (1789); J. Sigler, Double
    Jeopardy: The Development of a Legal and Social Policy
    30–31 (1969). But cf. ante, at 4–5. Nevermind that this
    amendment failed; the Court has attributed to the Clause
    the very meaning the First Congress refrained from
    adopting.2
    ——————
    2 The   Court sees this history as poor evidence of congressional intent.
    6                   GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    Second, early American courts regarded with disfavor
    the prospect of successive prosecutions by the Federal and
    State Governments. In Houston v. Moore, 
    5 Wheat. 1
    (1820), Justice Washington expressed concern that such
    prosecutions would be “very much like oppression, if not
    worse”; he noted that an acquittal or conviction by one
    sovereign “might be pleaded in bar of the prosecution
    before the other.” Id., at 23, 31. The Court today follows
    Bartkus in distinguishing Justice Washington’s opinion as
    addressing only the “strange” situation in which a State
    has prosecuted an offense “against the United States.”
    Ante, at 24; see Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 130. The distinction
    is thin, given the encompassing language in Justice Wash-
    ington’s opinion. Justice Story’s dissent, moreover, de-
    clared successive prosecutions for the same offense contrary
    to “the principles of the common law, and the genius of our
    free government.” Houston, 5 Wheat., at 72.
    Most of the early state decisions cited by the parties
    regarded successive federal-state prosecutions as unac-
    ceptable. See Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 158–159 (Black, J.,
    dissenting). Only one court roundly endorsed a separate-
    sovereigns theory. Hendrick v. Commonwealth, 
    32 Va. 707
    , 713 (1834). The Court reads the state-court opinions
    as “distin[guishing] between believing successive prosecu-
    tions by separate sovereigns unjust and holding them
    unlawful.” Ante, at 21. I would not read the Double Jeop-
    ardy Clause to tolerate “unjust” prosecutions and believe
    early American courts would have questioned the Court’s
    distinction. See State v. Brown, 2 N. C. 100, 101 (1794)
    ——————
    See ante, at 4. On another day, the Court looked to the First Congress’
    rejection of proposed amendments as instructive. See Cook v. Gralike,
    
    531 U.S. 510
    , 521 (2001). Moreover, a “compelling” principle of statu-
    tory interpretation is “the proposition that Congress does not intend
    sub silentio to enact statutory language that it has earlier discarded in
    favor of other language.” INS v. Cardoza-Fonseca, 
    480 U.S. 421
    , 442–
    443 (1987) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)            7
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    (allowing successive prosecutions would be “against natu-
    ral justice, and therefore I cannot believe it to be law”).
    c
    Finally, the Court has reasoned that the separate-
    sovereigns doctrine is necessary to prevent either the
    Federal Government or a State from encroaching on the
    other’s law enforcement prerogatives. Without this doc-
    trine, the Court has observed, the Federal Government, by
    prosecuting first, could bar a State from pursuing more
    serious charges for the same offense, Bartkus, 359 U. S., at
    137; and conversely, a State, by prosecuting first, could
    effectively nullify federal law, Abbate, 359 U. S., at 195.
    This concern envisions federal and state prosecutors work-
    ing at cross purposes, but cooperation between authorities
    is the norm. See Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 123. And when
    federal-state tension exists, successive prosecutions for the
    federal and state offenses may escape double-jeopardy
    blockage under the test prescribed in Blockburger v. United
    States, 
    284 U.S. 299
     (1932). Offenses are distinct, Block-
    burger held, if “each . . . requires proof of a fact which the
    other does not.” Id., at 304; see Amar, 95 Colum. L. Rev.,
    at 45–46 (violation of federal civil rights law and state
    assault law are different offenses).
    II
    The separate-sovereigns doctrine, I acknowledge, has
    been embraced repeatedly by the Court. But “[s]tare
    decisis is not an inexorable command.” Payne v. Tennes-
    see, 
    501 U.S. 808
    , 828 (1991). Our adherence to precedent
    is weakest in cases “concerning procedural rules that
    implicate fundamental constitutional protections.” Alleyne
    v. United States, 
    570 U.S. 99
    , 116, n. 5 (2013). Gamble’s
    case fits that bill. I would lay the “separate-sovereigns”
    rationale to rest for the aforesaid reasons and those stated
    below.
    8                GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    A
    First, Benton v. Maryland, 
    395 U.S. 784
    , which ren-
    dered the double jeopardy safeguard applicable to the
    States, left the separate-sovereigns doctrine the sort of
    “legal last-man-standing for which we sometimes depart
    from stare decisis.” Kimble v. Marvel Entertainment, LLC,
    
    576 U.S.
    ___, ___ (2015) (slip op., at 11). In adopting and
    cleaving to the doctrine, the Court stressed that originally,
    the Clause restrained only federal, not state, action. E.g.,
    Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 127; Lanza, 260 U. S., at 382; cf.
    Abbate, 359 U. S., at 190.
    Before incorporation, the separate-sovereigns doctrine
    had a certain logic: Without a carve-out for successive
    prosecutions by separate sovereigns, the Double Jeopardy
    Clause would have barred the Federal Government from
    prosecuting a defendant previously tried by a State, but
    would not have prevented a State from prosecuting a
    defendant previously tried by the Federal Government.
    Incorporation changed this. Operative against the States
    since 1969, when the Court decided Benton v. Maryland,
    
    395 U.S. 784
    , the double jeopardy proscription now ap-
    plies to the Federal Government and the States alike. The
    remaining office of the separate-sovereigns doctrine, then,
    is to enable federal and state prosecutors, proceeding one
    after the other, to expose defendants to double jeopardy.
    The separate-sovereigns doctrine’s persistence contrasts
    with the fate of analogous dual-sovereignty doctrines
    following application of the rights at issue to the States.
    Prior to incorporation of the Fourth Amendment as a
    restraint on state action, federal prosecutors were free to
    use evidence obtained illegally by state or local officers,
    then served up to federal officers on a “silver platter.” See
    Elkins v. United States, 
    364 U.S. 206
    , 208–214 (1960);
    Weeks v. United States, 
    232 U.S. 383
    , 398 (1914). Once
    the Fourth Amendment applied to the States, abandon-
    ment of this “silver platter doctrine” was impelled by
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)            9
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    “principles of logic” and the reality that, from the perspec-
    tive of the victim of an unreasonable search and seizure, it
    mattered not at all “whether his constitutional right ha[d]
    been invaded by a federal agent or by a state officer.”
    Elkins, 364 U. S., at 208, 215. As observed by Justice
    Harlan, Elkins’ abandonment of a separate-sovereigns
    exception to the exclusionary rule was at odds with reten-
    tion of the separate-sovereigns doctrine for double jeop-
    ardy purposes in Abbate and Bartkus. See 364 U. S., at
    252.
    Similarly, before incorporation of the Fifth Amendment
    privilege against self-incrimination, the Court held that
    the privilege did not prevent state authorities from com-
    pelling a defendant to provide testimony that could in-
    criminate him or her in another jurisdiction. Knapp v.
    Schweitzer, 
    357 U.S. 371
    , 375–381 (1958). After applica-
    tion of the self-incrimination privilege to the States, the
    Court concluded that its prior position was incompatible
    with the “policies and purposes” of the privilege. Murphy
    v. Waterfront Comm’n of N. Y. Harbor, 
    378 U.S. 52
    , 55, 77
    (1964). No longer, the Court held, could a witness “ be
    whipsawed into incriminating himself under both state
    and federal law even though the constitutional privilege
    against self-incrimination is applicable to each.” Id., at 55
    (internal quotation marks omitted; emphasis added).
    The Court regards incorporation as immaterial because
    application of the Double Jeopardy Clause to the States
    did not affect comprehension of the word “offence” to mean
    the violation of one sovereign’s law. Ante, at 28. But the
    Court attributed a separate-sovereigns meaning to “of-
    fence” at least in part because the Double Jeopardy Clause
    did not apply to the States. See supra, at 5. Incorporation
    of the Clause should prompt the Court to consider the
    protection against double jeopardy from the defendant’s
    perspective and to ask why each of two governments
    within the United States should be permitted to try a
    10                  GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    defendant once for the same offense when neither could
    try him or her twice.
    B
    The expansion of federal criminal law has exacerbated
    the problems created by the separate-sovereigns doctrine.
    Ill effects of the doctrine might once have been tempered
    by the limited overlap between federal and state criminal
    law. All Assets of G.P.S. Automotive, 
    66 F. 3d
    , at 498
    (Calabresi, J., concurring). In the last half century, how-
    ever, federal criminal law has been extended pervasively
    into areas once left to the States. Guerra, The Myth of
    Dual Sovereignty: Multijurisdictional Drug Law Enforce-
    ment and Double Jeopardy, 73 N. C. L. Rev. 1159, 1165–
    1192 (1995); Brief for Sen. Orrin Hatch as Amicus Curiae
    8–14. This new “age of ‘cooperative federalism,’ [in which]
    the Federal and State Governments are waging a united
    front against many types of criminal activity,” Murphy,
    378 U. S., at 55–56, provides new opportunities for federal
    and state prosecutors to “join together to take a second
    bite at the apple,” All Assets of G.P.S. Automotive, 
    66 F. 3d
    , at 498 (Calabresi, J., concurring).3 This situation
    might be less troublesome if successive prosecutions oc-
    curred only in “instances of peculiar enormity, or where
    the public safety demanded extraordinary rigor.” Fox, 5
    How., at 435. The run-of-the-mill felon-in-possession
    charges Gamble encountered indicate that, in practice,
    successive prosecutions are not limited to exceptional
    circumstances.
    ——————
    3 Bartkus v. Illinois, 
    359 U.S. 121
     (1959), left open the prospect that
    the double jeopardy ban might block a successive state prosecution that
    was merely “a sham and a cover for a federal prosecution.” Id., at 123–
    124. The Courts of Appeals have read this potential exception narrowly.
    See, e.g., United States v. Figueroa-Soto, 
    938 F.2d 1015
    , 1019 (CA9
    1991).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                   11
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    C
    Against all this, there is little to be said for keeping the
    separate-sovereigns doctrine. Gamble’s case “do[es] not
    implicate the reliance interests of private parties.” Al-
    leyne, 570 U. S., at 119 (SOTOMAYOR, J., concurring). The
    closest thing to a reliance interest would be the interest
    Federal and State Governments have in avoiding avulsive
    changes that could complicate ongoing prosecutions. As
    the Court correctly explains, however, overruling the
    separate-sovereigns doctrine would not affect large num-
    bers of cases. See ante, at 28–29. In prosecutions based
    on the same conduct, federal and state prosecutors will
    often charge offenses having different elements, charges
    that, under Blockburger, will not trigger double jeopardy
    protection. See Poulin, Double Jeopardy Protection From
    Successive Prosecution: A Proposed Approach, 92 Geo.
    L. J. 1183, 1244–1245 (2004); Brief for Criminal Defense
    Experts as Amici Curiae 5–11.4
    Notably, the Federal Government has endeavored to
    reduce the incidence of “same offense” prosecutions. Un-
    der the Petite policy adopted by the Department of Jus-
    tice,5 the Department will pursue a federal prosecution
    ——————
    4 The  Government implies there is tension between Gamble’s position
    and Blockburger v. United States, 
    284 U.S. 299
     (1932). Brief for
    United States 18–20. But if courts can ascertain how laws enacted by
    different Congresses fare under Blockburger, they can do the same for
    laws enacted by Congress and a State, or by two States. But cf. Amar
    & Marcus, Double Jeopardy Law After Rodney King, 95 Colum. L. Rev.
    1, 39 (1995) (“Because different legislatures often do not work from the
    same linguistic building blocks, they will not use uniform language to
    describe an offence, even when each is indeed outlawing the same crime
    with the same elements.”).
    5 Formally the “Dual and Successive Prosecution Policy,” the policy is
    popularly known by the name of the case in which this Court first took
    note of it, Petite v. United States, 
    361 U.S. 529
     (1960) (per curiam).
    The policy was adopted “in direct response to” Bartkus and Abbate v.
    United States, 
    359 U.S. 187
     (1959). Rinaldi v. United States, 
    434 U.S. 12
                      GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GINSBURG, J., dissenting
    “based on substantially the same act(s) or transaction(s)”
    previously prosecuted in state court only if the first prose-
    cution left a “substantial federal interest . . . demonstrably
    unvindicated” and a Department senior official authorizes
    the prosecution. Dept. of Justice, Justice Manual §9–
    2.031(A) (rev. July 2009).
    At oral argument, the Government estimated that it
    authorizes only “about a hundred” Petite prosecutions per
    year. Tr. of Oral Arg. 54. But see id., at 65–66 (referring
    to the “few hundred successive prosecutions that [the
    Government] bring[s] each year”). Some of these prosecu-
    tions will not implicate double jeopardy, as the Petite
    policy uses a same-conduct test that is broader than the
    Blockburger same-elements test. And more than half the
    States forbid successive prosecutions for all or some of-
    fenses previously resolved on the merits by a federal or
    state court. Brief for Criminal Defense Experts as Amici
    Curiae 4–5, and n. 2 (collecting statutes); Brief for State of
    Texas et al. as Amici Curiae 28–30, and nn. 6–15 (same).
    In short, it is safe to predict that eliminating the separate-
    sovereigns doctrine would spark no large disruption in
    practice.
    *  *    *
    The separate-sovereigns doctrine, especially since
    Bartkus and Abbate, has been subject to relentless criti-
    cism by members of the bench, bar, and academy. Never-
    theless, the Court reaffirms the doctrine, thereby dimin-
    ishing the individual rights shielded by the Double
    Jeopardy Clause. Different parts of the “WHOLE” United
    States should not be positioned to prosecute a defendant a
    second time for the same offense. I would reverse Gam-
    ble’s federal conviction.
    ——————
    22, 28 (1977) (per curiam).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                          1
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    No. 17–646
    _________________
    TERANCE MARTEZ GAMBLE, PETITIONER v.
    UNITED STATES
    ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE ELEVENTH CIRCUIT
    [June 17, 2019]
    JUSTICE GORSUCH, dissenting.
    A free society does not allow its government to try the
    same individual for the same crime until it’s happy with
    the result. Unfortunately, the Court today endorses a
    colossal exception to this ancient rule against double
    jeopardy. My colleagues say that the federal government
    and each State are “separate sovereigns” entitled to try
    the same person for the same crime. So if all the might of
    one “sovereign” cannot succeed against the presumptively
    free individual, another may insist on the chance to try
    again. And if both manage to succeed, so much the better;
    they can add one punishment on top of the other. But this
    “separate sovereigns exception” to the bar against double
    jeopardy finds no meaningful support in the text of the
    Constitution, its original public meaning, structure, or
    history. Instead, the Constitution promises all Americans
    that they will never suffer double jeopardy. I would en-
    force that guarantee.
    I
    “Fear and abhorrence of governmental power to try
    people twice for the same conduct is one of the oldest ideas
    found in western civilization.”1 Throughout history, peo-
    ple have worried about the vast disparity of power be-
    ——————
    1 Bartkus   v. Illinois, 
    359 U.S. 121
    , 151 (1959) (Black, J., dissenting).
    2                    GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    tween governments and individuals, the capacity of the
    state to bring charges repeatedly until it wins the result it
    wants, and what little would be left of human liberty if
    that power remained unchecked. To address the problem,
    the law in ancient Athens held that “[a] man could not be
    tried twice for the same offense.”2 The Roman Republic
    and Empire incorporated a form of double jeopardy protec-
    tion in their laws.3 The Old Testament and later church
    teachings endorsed the bar against double jeopardy too.4
    And from the earliest days of the common law, courts
    recognized that to “punish a man twice over for one of-
    fence” would be deeply unjust.5
    The rule against double jeopardy was firmly entrenched
    in both the American colonies and England at the time of
    our Revolution.6 And the Fifth Amendment, which prohib-
    its placing a defendant “twice . . . in jeopardy of life or
    limb” for “the same offence” sought to carry the traditional
    common law rule into our Constitution.7 As Joseph Story
    put it, the Constitution’s prohibition against double jeop-
    ardy grew from a “great privilege secured by the common
    law” and meant “that a party shall not be tried a second
    time for the same offence, after he has once been convicted,
    ——————
    2 R.
    Bonner, Lawyers and Litigants in Ancient Athens 195 (1927).
    3 J.
    Sigler, Double Jeopardy: The Development of a Legal and Social
    Policy 2–3 (1969); Digest of Justinian: Digest 48.2.7.2, translated in 11
    S. Scott, The Civil Law 17 (1932).
    4 See Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 152, n. 4 (Black, J., dissenting); Z. Brooke,
    The English Church and the Papacy 204–205, n. 1 (1931).
    5 1 F. Pollock & F. Maitland, The History of English Law 448 (2d ed.
    1898).
    6 See, e.g., The Massachusetts Body of Liberties of 1641, cl. 42, in The
    Colonial Laws of Massachusetts 42–43 (W. Whitmore ed. 1889); 4 W.
    Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 335–336 (5th ed.
    1773) (Blackstone, Commentaries); 2 W. Hawkins, Pleas of the Crown
    368 (1762) (Hawkins).
    7 Ex parte Lange, 
    18 Wall. 163
    , 170 (1874). See also Benton v. Mary-
    land, 
    395 U.S. 784
    , 795–796 (1969); F. Wharton, Criminal Law of the
    United States 147 (1846).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                  3
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    or acquitted of the offence charged, by the verdict of a jury,
    and judgment has passed thereon for or against him.”8
    Given all this, it might seem that Mr. Gamble should
    win this case handily. Alabama prosecuted him for violat-
    ing a state law that “prohibits a convicted felon from
    possessing a pistol” and sentenced him to a year in prison.9
    But then the federal government, apparently displeased
    with the sentence, charged Mr. Gamble under 
    18 U.S. C
    .
    §922(g)(1) with being a felon in possession of a firearm
    based on the same facts that gave rise to the state prose-
    cution. Ultimately, a federal court sentenced him to 46
    months in prison and three years of supervised release.
    Most any ordinary speaker of English would say that Mr.
    Gamble was tried twice for “the same offence,” precisely
    what the Fifth Amendment prohibits. Tellingly, no one
    before us doubts that if either the federal government or
    Alabama had prosecuted Mr. Gamble twice on these facts
    and in this manner, it surely would have violated the
    Constitution.
    So how does the government manage to evade the Fifth
    Amendment’s seemingly plain command? On the govern-
    ment’s account, the fact that federal and state authorities
    split up the prosecutions makes all the difference. Though
    the Double Jeopardy Clause doesn’t say anything about
    allowing “separate sovereigns” to do sequentially what
    neither may do separately, the government assures us the
    Fifth Amendment’s phrase “same offence” does this work.
    Adopting the government’s argument, the Court supplies
    the following syllogism: “[A]n ‘offence’ is defined by a law,
    and each law is defined by a sovereign. So where there
    are two sovereigns, there are two laws, and two ‘offences.’ ”
    ——————
    83 J. Story, Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States
    §1781, p. 659 (1833).
    9 Ex parte Taylor, 
    636 So. 2d 1246
     (Ala. 1993); see Ala. Code §§13A–
    11–70(2), 13A–11–72(a) (2015).
    4                     GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    Ante, at 3–4.
    But the major premise of this argument—that “where
    there are two laws there are ‘two offenses’ ”—is mistaken.
    We know that the Constitution is not so easily evaded and
    that two statutes can punish the same offense.10 The
    framers understood the term “offence” to mean a “trans-
    gression.”11 And they understood that the same trans-
    gression might be punished by two pieces of positive law:
    After all, constitutional protections were not meant to be
    flimsy things but to embody “principles that are perma-
    nent, uniform, and universal.”12 As this Court explained
    long ago in Blockburger v. United States, “where the same
    act or transaction constitutes a violation of two distinct
    statutory provisions, the test to be applied to determine
    whether there are two offenses or only one, is whether
    each provision requires proof of a fact which the other does
    not.”13 So if two laws demand proof of the same facts to
    secure a conviction, they constitute a single offense under
    our Constitution and a second trial is forbidden. And by
    everyone’s admission, that is exactly what we have here:
    The statute under which the federal government pro-
    ceeded required it to prove no facts beyond those Alabama
    needed to prove under state law to win its conviction; the
    two prosecutions were for the same offense.
    That leaves the government and the Court to rest on the
    fact that distinct governmental entities, federal and state,
    enacted these identical laws. This, we are told, is enough
    to transform what everyone agrees would otherwise be the
    same offense into two different offenses. But where is that
    distinction to be found in the Constitution’s text or origi-
    ——————
    10 Whalenv. United States, 
    445 U.S. 684
    , 691–692 (1980).
    11 Dictionarium Britannicum (N. Bailey ed. 1730); see also N. Web-
    ster, An American Dictionary of the English Language (1828) (defining
    an “offense” as including “[a]ny transgression of law, divine or human”).
    12 4 Blackstone, Commentaries 3.
    13 
    284 U.S. 299
    , 304 (1932).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                     5
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    nal public understanding? We know that the framers
    didn’t conceive of the term “same offence” in some tech-
    nical way as referring only to the same statute. And if
    double jeopardy prevents one government from prosecut-
    ing a defendant multiple times for the same offense under
    the banner of separate statutory labels, on what account
    can it make a difference when many governments collec-
    tively seek to do the same thing?
    The government identifies no evidence suggesting that
    the framers understood the term “same offence” to bear
    such a lawyerly sovereign-specific meaning. Meanwhile,
    Blackstone’s Commentaries explained how “Roman law,”
    “Athens,” “the Jewish republic,” and “English Law” ad-
    dressed the singular “offence of homicide,” and how the
    Roman, Gothic, and ancient Saxon law approached the
    singular “offence of arson.”14 Other treatises of the period
    contain similar taxonomies of “offences” that are not
    sovereign-specific.15 Members of the Continental Con-
    gress, too, used the word “offence” in this same way. In
    1786, a congressional committee endorsed federal control
    over import duties because otherwise “thirteen separate
    authorities” might “ordain various penalties for the same
    offence.”16 In 1778, the Continental Congress passed a
    resolution declaring that a person should not be tried in
    state court “for the same offense, for which he had previ-
    ous thereto been tried by a Court Martial.”17 And in 1785,
    the Continental Congress considered an ordinance declar-
    ing that a defendant could “plead a formal Acquital on a
    Trial” in a maritime court “for the same supposed Offences,
    ——————
    14 4 Blackstone, Commentaries 176–187, 222.
    15 See, e.g., 2 J. Bishop, Commentaries on the Criminal Law §§90–120
    (5th ed. 1872) (discussing the singular offense of “burglary” by reference
    to the “common law,” English law, and the laws of multiple States).
    16 30 Journals of the Continental Congress 440 (J. Fitzpatrick ed.
    1934).
    17 10 id., at 72 (W. Ford ed. 1908).
    6                      GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    in a similar Court in one of the other United States.”18 In
    all of these examples, early legislators—including many of
    the same people who would vote to add the Fifth Amend-
    ment to the Bill of Rights just a few years later—
    recognized that transgressions of state and federal law
    could constitute the “same offence.”
    The history of the Double Jeopardy Clause itself sup-
    plies more evidence yet. The original draft prohibited
    “more than one trial or one punishment for the same
    offence.”19 One representative then proposed adding the
    words “by any law of the United States” after “same of-
    fence.”20 That proposal clearly would have codified the
    government’s sovereign-specific view of the Clause’s oper-
    ation. Yet, Congress proceeded to reject it.
    Viewed from the perspective of an ordinary reader of the
    Fifth Amendment, whether at the time of its adoption or
    in our own time, none of this can come as a surprise.
    Imagine trying to explain the Court’s separate sovereigns
    rule to a criminal defendant, then or now. Yes, you were
    sentenced to state prison for being a felon in possession of
    a firearm. And don’t worry—the State can’t prosecute you
    again. But a federal prosecutor can send you to prison
    again for exactly the same thing. What’s more, that federal
    prosecutor may work hand-in-hand with the same state
    prosecutor who already went after you. They can share
    evidence and discuss what worked and what didn’t the
    first time around. And the federal prosecutor can pursue
    you even if you were acquitted in the state case. None of
    that offends the Constitution’s plain words protecting a
    person from being placed “twice . . . in jeopardy of life or
    limb” for “the same offence.” Really?
    ——————
    18 29 id., at 803 (J. Fitzpatrick ed. 1933).
    19 1 Annals of Cong. 753 (1789).
    20 Ibid.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)           7
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    II
    Without meaningful support in the text of the Double
    Jeopardy Clause, the government insists that the separate
    sovereigns exception is at least compelled by the structure
    of our Constitution. On its view, adopted by the Court
    today, allowing the federal and state governments to
    punish the same defendant for the same conduct “honors
    the substantive differences between the interests that two
    sovereigns can have” in our federal system. Ante, at 5.
    But this argument errs from the outset. The Court
    seems to assume that sovereignty in this country belongs
    to the state and federal governments, much as it once
    belonged to the King of England. But as Chief Justice
    Marshall explained, “[t]he government of the Union . . . is
    emphatically, and truly, a government of the people,” and
    all sovereignty “emanates from them.”21 Alexander Ham-
    ilton put the point this way: “[T]he national and State
    systems are to be regarded” not as different sovereigns
    foreign to one another but “as ONE WHOLE.”22 Under
    our Constitution, the federal and state governments are
    but two expressions of a single and sovereign people.
    This principle resonates throughout our history and law.
    State courts that refused to entertain federal causes of
    action found little sympathy when attempting the very
    separate sovereigns theory underlying today’s decision.23
    In time, too, it became clear that federal courts may decide
    state-law issues, and state courts may decide federal
    questions.24 Even in the criminal context, this Court has
    upheld removal of some state criminal actions to federal
    court.25 And any remaining doubt about whether the
    ——————
    21 McCulloch   v. Maryland, 
    4 Wheat. 316
    , 404–405 (1819).
    22 The Federalist No. 82, p. 494 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961).
    23 See Testa v. Katt, 
    330 U.S. 386
     (1947).
    24 Claflin v. Houseman, 
    93 U.S. 130
     (1876).
    25 See Tennessee v. Davis, 
    100 U.S. 257
     (1880).
    8                    GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    States and the federal government are truly separate
    sovereigns was ultimately “resolved by war.”26
    From its mistaken premise, the Court continues to the
    flawed conclusion that the federal and state governments
    can successively prosecute the same person for the same
    offense. This turns the point of our federal experiment on
    its head. When the “ONE WHOLE” people of the United
    States assigned different aspects of their sovereign power
    to the federal and state governments, they sought not to
    multiply governmental power but to limit it. As this Court
    has explained, “[b]y denying any one government complete
    jurisdiction over all the concerns of public life, federalism
    protects the liberty of the individual from arbitrary power.”27
    Yet today’s Court invokes federalism not to protect indi-
    vidual liberty but to threaten it, allowing two governments
    to achieve together an objective denied to each. The Court
    brushes this concern aside because “the powers of the
    Federal Government and the States often overlap,” which
    “often results in two layers of regulation.” Ante, at 10.
    But the Court’s examples—taxation, alcohol, and mari-
    ——————
    26 Testa,330 U. S., at 390. The Court tries to make the most of
    McCulloch, pointing out that Chief Justice Marshall distinguished
    between “ ‘the people of a State’ ” and “ ‘the people of all the States.’ ”
    Ante, at 9. But of course our federal republic is composed of separate
    governments. My point is that the federal and state governments
    ultimately derive their sovereignty from one and the same source; they
    are not truly “separate” in the manner of, say, the governments of
    England and Portugal. The American people “ ‘split the atom of sover-
    eignty,’ ” ante, at 9, to set two levels of government against each other,
    not to set both against the people. McCulloch is consistent with that
    understanding. In holding that the States could not tax the national
    bank, McCulloch sought to ensure that the national and state govern-
    ments remained each in its proper sphere; it did not hold that the two
    governments could work in concert to abridge the people’s liberty in a
    way that neither could on its own.
    27 Bond v. United States, 
    564 U.S. 211
    , 222 (2011); see also New York
    v. United States, 
    505 U.S. 144
    , 181 (1992); Alden v. Maine, 
    527 U.S. 706
    , 758 (1999); The Federalist No. 51.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)               9
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    juana—involve areas that the federal and state governments
    each may regulate separately under the Constitution as
    interpreted by this Court. That is miles away from the
    separate sovereigns exception, which allows the federal
    and state governments to accomplish together what nei-
    ther may do separately consistent with the Constitution’s
    commands. As Justice Black understood, the Court’s view
    today “misuse[s] and desecrat[es] . . . the concept” of fed-
    eralism.28 For “it is just as much an affront to . . . human
    freedom for a man to be punished twice for the same
    offense” by two parts of the people’s government “as it
    would be for one . . . to throw him in prison twice for the
    offense.”29
    III
    A
    If the Constitution’s text and structure do not supply
    persuasive support for the government’s position, what
    about a more thorough exploration of the common law
    from which the Fifth Amendment was drawn?
    By 1791 when the Fifth Amendment was adopted, an
    array of common law authorities suggested that a prosecu-
    tion in any court, so long as the court had jurisdiction over
    the offense, was enough to bar future reprosecution in
    another court. Blackstone, for example, reported that an
    acquittal “before any court having competent jurisdiction
    of the offence” could be pleaded “in bar of any subsequent
    accusation for the same crime.”30 For support, Blackstone
    pointed to Beak v. Tyrhwhit,31 a 1688 case in which the
    reporter described an acquittal in a foreign country fol-
    lowed by an attempted second prosecution in England that
    the court held impermissible. Another treatise by William
    ——————
    28 Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 155 (dissenting opinion).
    29 Abbate v. United States, 
    359 U.S. 187
    , 203 (1959) (same).
    30 4 Blackstone, Commentaries 335, and n. j.
    31 3 Mod. 194, 87 Eng. Rep. 124 (K. B.).
    10                  GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    Hawkins likewise considered it “settled” as early as 1716
    “[t]hat an Acquittal in any Court whatsoever, which has a
    Jurisdiction of the Cause, is as good a Bar of any subse-
    quent Prosecution for the same Crime.”32
    What these authorities suggest many more confirm.
    Henry Bathurst’s 1761 treatise on evidence taught that “a
    final Determination in a Court having competent Jurisdic-
    tion is conclusive in all Courts of concurrent Jurisdic-
    tion.”33 Nor was this merely a rule about the competency
    of evidence, as the next sentence reveals: “If A. having
    killed a Person in Spain was there prosecuted, tried, and
    acquitted, and afterwards was indicted here [in England],
    he might plead the Acquittal in Spain in Bar.”34 Francis
    Buller’s 1772 treatise repeated the same rule, articulating
    it the same way.35 And to illustrate their point, both
    treatises cited the 1678 English case of King v.
    Hutchinson. Although no surviving written report of
    Hutchinson remains, several early common law cases—
    including Beak v. Thyrwhit,36 Burrows v. Jemino,37 and
    King v. Roche38—described its holding in exactly the same
    way the treatise writers did: All agreed that it barred the
    retrial in England of a defendant previously tried for
    murder in Spain or Portugal.
    When they envisioned the relationship between the
    national government and the States under the new Con-
    stitution, the framers sometimes referenced by way of
    comparison the relationship between Wales, Scotland, and
    ——————
    32 2 Hawkins §10, at 372 (emphasis added).
    33 H. Bathurst, Theory of Evidence 39.
    34 Ibid.
    35 F. Buller, An Introduction to the Law Relative to Trials at Nisi
    Prius 241.
    36 3 Mod. 194, 87 Eng. Rep. 124, sub nom. Beake v. Tyrrell, 1 Show. K.
    B. 6, 89 Eng. Rep. 411, sub nom. Beake v. Tirrell, Comb. 120, 90 Eng.
    Rep. 379.
    37 2 Str. 733, 93 Eng. Rep. 815 (K. B. 1726)
    38 1 Leach 134, 168 Eng. Rep. 169 (K. B. 1775).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                  11
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    England.39 And prosecutions in one of these places pretty
    plainly barred subsequent prosecutions for the same
    offense in the others. So, for example, treatises explained
    that “an Acquittal of Murder at a Grand Sessions in
    Wales, may be pleaded to an Indictment for the same
    Murder in England. For the Rule is, That a Man’s Life
    shall not be brought into Danger for the same Offence
    more than once.”40 Indeed, when an English county in-
    dicted a defendant “for a murder committed . . . in Wales,”
    it was barred from proceeding when the court learned that
    the defendant had already been tried and acquitted “of the
    same offence” in Wales.41
    Against this uniform body of common law weighs Gage
    v. Bulkeley—a civil, not criminal, case from 1744 that
    suggested Hutchinson had held only that the English
    courts lacked jurisdiction to try a defendant for an offense
    committed in Portugal. Because “the murder was commit-
    ted in Portugal,” Gage argued, “the Court of King’s Bench
    could not indict him, and there was no method of trying
    him but upon a special commission.”42 But no one else—
    not the treatise writers or the other English cases that
    favorably cited Hutchinson—adopted Gage’s restrictive
    reading of that precedent.
    In the end, then, it’s hard to see how anyone consulting
    the common law in 1791 could have avoided this conclu-
    sion: While the issue may not have arisen often, the great
    weight of authority indicated that successive prosecutions
    by different sovereigns—even sovereigns as foreign to each
    ——————
    39 See, e.g., A. Amar, America’s Constitution: A Biography 45 (2005);
    The Federalist No. 5, pp. 50–51; The Federalist No. 17; Jay, An Address
    to the People of the State of New York, in Pamphlets on the Constitu-
    tion of the United States 84 (P. Ford ed. 1788).
    40 2 Hawkins §10, at 372.
    41 King v. Thomas, 1 Lev. 118, 83 Eng. Rep. 326 (K. B. 1664).
    42 Gage v. Bulkeley, Ridg. t. H. 263, 270–271, 27 Eng. Rep. 824, 827.
    (1794).
    12                  GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    other as England and Portugal—were out of bounds. And
    anyone familiar with the American federal system likely
    would have thought the rule applied with even greater
    force to successive prosecutions by the United States and a
    constituent State, given that both governments derive
    their sovereignty from the American people.
    Unable to summon any useful preratification common
    law sources of its own, the government is left to nitpick
    those that undermine its position. For example, the Court
    dismisses Beak because “Hutchinson is discussed only in
    the defendant’s argument in that case, not the court’s
    response.” Ante, at 16. But the Beak court did not reject
    the Hutchinson argument, and counsel’s use of the case
    sheds light on how 17th- and 18th-century lawyers under-
    stood the double jeopardy bar. The Court likewise derides
    King v. Thomas as “totally irrelevant” because in the 17th
    century, Wales and England shared the same laws. But
    our federal and state governments share the same funda-
    mental law and source of authority, and the Wales exam-
    ple is at least somewhat analogous to our federal system.43
    Finally, the Court complains that Roche’s footnote citing
    Hutchinson was added only in 1800, after the Fifth
    Amendment’s ratification. Ante, at 16. But that is hardly
    a point for the government, because even so it provides an
    example of a later reporter attempting to describe the pre-
    existing state of the law; nor, as it turns out, was the
    footnote even essential to the Roche court’s original analy-
    sis and conclusion reached in 1775, well before the Fifth
    Amendment’s ratification.44 And among all these com-
    ——————
    43 Indeed, though England ruled Wales at the time, a contemporane-
    ous lawyer might have thought that Wales’ authority to prosecute a
    defendant derived at least in part from its earlier status as “an absolute
    and undependent Kingdom” rather than purely from authority delegated
    by England. 1 Keb. 663, 83 Eng. Rep. 1172 (K. B. 1663); see United
    States v. Lara, 
    541 U.S. 193
    , 210 (2004).
    44 Indeed, everything that matters was contained in the 1775 version
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                    13
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    plaints, we should not lose the forest for the trees. The
    Court’s attempts to explain away so many uncomfortable
    authorities are lengthy, detailed, even herculean. But in
    the end, neither it nor the government has mustered a
    single preratification common law authority approving a
    case of successive prosecutions by separate sovereigns for
    the same offense.
    B
    What we know about the common law before the Fifth
    Amendment’s ratification in 1791 finds further confirma-
    tion in how later legal thinkers in both England and
    America described the rule they had inherited.
    Start with England. As it turns out, “it would have been
    difficult to have made more than the most cursory exami-
    nation of nineteenth century or later English treatises or
    digests without encountering” the Hutchinson rule.45 In
    1802, a British treatise explained that “an acquittal on a
    criminal charge in a foreign country may be pleaded in bar
    of an indictment for the same offence in England.”46 Three
    ——————
    of the Roche case report. Roche was indicted in England for a murder
    committed in South Africa. “To this indictment Captain Roche pleaded
    Autrefois acquit.” Roche, 1 Leach 134, 168 Eng. Rep. 169. In response,
    the prosecution asked the court to charge the jury both with “this issue
    [the plea of autrefois acquit], and that of Not guilty.” Ibid. The court
    rejected that proposal, reasoning that “if the first finding was for the
    prisoner, they could not go to the second, because that finding would be
    a bar.” Ibid. Far from saying “absolutely nothing” about double jeop-
    ardy, ante, at 16, Roche is a serious problem for the government be-
    cause it explicitly recognizes that a successful plea of autrefois acquit,
    even one based on a foreign conviction, would bar a prosecution in
    England. But the Court ignores this, focusing instead on the missing
    explanatory citation to Hutchinson that was, in any event, added
    shortly thereafter.
    45 Grant, Successive Prosecutions by State and Nation: Common Law
    and British Empire Comparisons, 4 UCLA L. Rev. 1, 9–11 (1956)
    (footnotes omitted).
    46 2 L. MacNally, Rules of Evidence on Pleas of the Crown 428 (1802);
    14                   GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    decades later, another treatise observed (citing
    Hutchinson) that “[a]n acquittal by a competent jurisdic-
    tion abroad is a bar to an indictment for the same offence
    before any other tribunal.”47 In 1846, the Scottish High
    Court of Justiciary declared that “[i]f a man has been tried
    for theft in England, we would not try him again here.”48
    Twentieth century treatises recited the same rule.49 In
    1931, the American Law Institute stated that “[i]f a person
    has been acquitted in a court of competent jurisdiction for
    an offense in another country he may not be tried for the
    same offense again in an English Court.”50 And in 1971,
    an English judge explained that the bar on “double jeop-
    ardy . . . has always applied whether the previous convic-
    tion or acquittal based on the same facts was by an Eng-
    lish court or by a foreign court.”51 The Court today asks us
    to assume that all these legal authorities misunderstood
    the common law’s ancient rule. I would not.
    ——————
    see also 1 T. Starkie, Criminal Pleading 300–301, n. h (1814); 1 J.
    Chitty, Criminal Law 458 (2d ed. 1816).
    47 J. Archbold, Pleading and Evidence in Criminal Cases 89 (5th ed.
    1834). Many more authorities are to the same effect. See, e.g., 1 Encyc.
    of the Laws of England, Autrefois aquit, 424–425 (A. Renton ed. 1897);
    2 J. Gabbett, Criminal Law 334 (1843); 2 E. Deacon, Digest of the
    Criminal Law of England 931 (1831); R. Matthews, Digest of Criminal
    Law 26 (1833); H. Nelson, Private International Law 368, n. y (1889); 1
    W. Russell, Crimes and Indictable Misdemeanors 471–472 (2d ed.
    1826); H. Woolrych, Criminal Law 129 (1862); 2 M. Hale, Pleas of the
    Crown 255 (1st Am. ed., S. Emlyn ed. 1847); H. Smith, Roscoe on the
    Law of Evidence 199 (8th ed. 1874).
    48 Her Majesty’s Advocate v. MacGregor, (1846) Ark. 49, 60.
    49 A. Gibb, International Law of Jurisdiction in England and Scotland
    285–286 (1926); A. Gibson & A. Weldon, Criminal and Magisterial Law
    225 (7th ed. 1919); S. Harris, Criminal Law 377 (9th ed. 1901); C.
    Kenny, Outlines of Criminal Law 469 (10th ed. 1920); H. Cohen, Roscoe
    on the Law of Evidence 172 (13th ed. 1908).
    50 ALI, Administration of Criminal Law §16, p. 129 (Proposed Final
    Draft, Mar. 18, 1935).
    51 Regina v. Treacy, [1971] A. C. 537, 562, 2 W. L. R. 112, 125 (opinion
    of Diplock, L. J.) (citing Roche, 1 Leach 134, 168 Eng. Rep. 169).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                  15
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    Even more pertinently, consider how 18th-century
    Americans understood the double jeopardy provision they
    had adopted. The legal treatises an American lawyer
    practicing between the founding and the Civil War might
    have consulted uniformly recited the Hutchinson rule as
    black letter law. Chancellor Kent wrote that “the plea of
    autrefois acquit, resting on a prosecution [in] any civilized
    state, would be a good plea in any other civilized state.”52
    Thomas Sergeant explained that “[w]here the jurisdiction
    of the United States court and of a state Court is concur-
    rent, the sentence of either court, whether of conviction or
    acquittal, may be pleaded in bar to a prosecution in the
    other.”53 William Rawle echoed that conclusion in virtually
    identical words.54 Indeed, one early commentator wrote
    that a “principal reason” for the Double Jeopardy Clause
    was to prevent successive state and federal prosecutions,
    which he considered to be against “[n]atural justice.”55
    Nor did these treatises purport to invent a new rule; they
    claimed only to recite the traditional one.
    This Court’s early decisions reflected the same principle.
    In Houston v. Moore, a Pennsylvania court-martial tried a
    member of the state militia for desertion under an “act of
    the legislature of Pennsylvania.”56 The defendant objected
    that the state court-martial lacked jurisdiction because
    federal law criminalized the same conduct and prosecuting
    him in the state court could thus expose him to double
    jeopardy. In an opinion by Justice Washington, the Court
    disagreed and allowed the prosecution, but reassured the
    defendant that “if the jurisdiction of the two Courts be
    concurrent, the sentence of either Court, either of convic-
    ——————
    52 1 Commentaries on American Law 176 (1826).
    53 Constitutional Law 278 (1830).
    54 View of the Constitution 191 (1825).
    55 J. Bayard, Brief Exposition of the Constitution of the United States
    150–151 (1845).
    56 
    5 Wheat. 1
    , 12 (1820).
    16                  GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    tion or acquittal, might be [later] pleaded in bar of the
    prosecution before the other.”57 In dissent, Justice Story
    thought the state court lacked jurisdiction because other-
    wise the defendant would be “liable to be twice tried and
    punished for the same offence, against the manifest intent
    of the act of Congress, the principles of the common law,
    and the genius of our free government.”58 But notice the
    point of agreement between majority and dissent: Both
    acknowledged that a second prosecution for the same
    underlying offense would be prohibited even if brought by
    a separate government.59
    Another case decided the same year also reflected the
    Hutchinson rule. In United States v. Furlong, one British
    subject killed another on the high seas, and the killer was
    indicted in an American federal court for robbery and
    murder. This Court unanimously held that “[r]obbery on
    the seas is considered as an offence within the criminal
    jurisdiction of all nations” that can therefore be “punished
    by all,” and there can be “no doubt that the plea of autre
    fois acquit [double jeopardy] would be good in any civilized
    State, though resting on a prosecution instituted in the
    Courts of any other civilized State.”60
    ——————
    57 Id.,at 31.
    58 Id.,at 72.
    59 The Court insists that Houston involved an unusual state statute
    that “imposed state sanctions for violation of a federal criminal law.”
    Ante, at 23. But so what? Everyone involved in Houston agreed that
    the defendant had been tried by a Pennsylvania court, under a Penn-
    sylvania statute, passed by the Pennsylvania Legislature. And though
    there were separate sovereigns with separate laws, everyone agreed
    there was only one offense.
    60 
    5 Wheat. 1
    84, 197 (1820). To be sure, Furlong proceeded to indi-
    cate that an acquittal for murder in an American court would not have
    prohibited a later prosecution in a British court in this case. But that
    was only because the British courts would not have recognized the
    jurisdiction of an American court to try a murder committed by a
    British subject on the high seas. Furlong’s discussion is therefore
    perfectly consistent with the Hutchinson principle—a rule that applied
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                    17
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    A number of early state cases followed the same rule.
    Indeed, the Court today acknowledges that Massachu-
    setts, Michigan, and Vermont all followed Hutchinson.
    Ante, at 22.61 The Court agrees that South Carolina did
    too,62 but it believes that a later South Carolina case
    might have deviated from the Hutchinson rule. That
    decision, however, contains at best only “an inconclusive
    discussion coming from a State whose highest court had
    previously stated unequivocally that a bar against double
    prosecutions would exist.”63
    In the face of so much contrary authority, the Court
    winds up leaning heavily on a single 1794 North Carolina
    Superior Court decision, State v. Brown. But the Court’s
    choice here is revealing. True, Brown said that a verdict
    in North Carolina would not be “pleadable in bar to an
    indictment preferred against [the defendant] in the Terri-
    tory South of the Ohio.”64 But the Court leaves out what
    happened next. Brown went on to reject concurrent juris-
    diction because trying the defendant “according to the
    several laws of each State” could result in him being
    “cropped in one, branded and whipped in another, impris-
    oned in a third, and hanged in a fourth; and all for one and
    the same offence.”65 The North Carolina court viewed that
    result as “against natural justice” and “therefore [could]
    not believe it to be law.”66 So it is that the principal sup-
    port the Court cites for its position is a state case that both
    ——————
    only when both courts had “competent jurisdiction of the offence” and
    could actually place the defendant in jeopardy. See 4 Blackstone,
    Commentaries 365.
    61 Citing Commonwealth v. Fuller, 
    49 Mass. 313
    , 318 (1844); Harlan
    v. People, 
    1 Doug. 207
    , 212 (Mich. 1843); State v. Randall, 
    2 Aik. 89
     (Vt.
    1827).
    62 State v. Antonio, 7 S. C. L. 776 (1816).
    63 Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 158–159 (Black, J., dissenting).
    64 2 N. C. 100, 101.
    65 Ibid. (emphasis added).
    66 Ibid.
    18                  GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    (1) regarded transgressions of the laws of a State and a
    U. S. territory as the “same offence,” and (2) expressed
    aversion at the thought of both jurisdictions punishing the
    defendant for that singular offense.67
    IV
    With the text, principles of federalism, and history now
    arrayed against it, the government is left to suggest that
    we should retain the separate sovereigns exception under
    the doctrine of stare decisis. But if that’s the real basis for
    today’s result, let’s at least acknowledge this: By all ap-
    pearances, the Constitution as originally adopted and
    understood did not allow successive state and federal
    prosecutions for the same offense, yet the government
    wants this Court to tolerate the practice anyway.
    Stare decisis has many virtues, but when it comes to
    enforcing the Constitution this Court must take (and
    always has taken) special care in the doctrine’s applica-
    tion. After all, judges swear to protect and defend the
    Constitution, not to protect what it prohibits. And while
    we rightly pay heed to the considered views of those who
    have come before us, especially in close cases, stare decisis
    isn’t supposed to be “the art of being methodically ignorant
    of what everyone knows.”68 Indeed, blind obedience to
    stare decisis would leave this Court still abiding grotesque
    errors like Dred Scott v. Sandford,69 Plessy v. Ferguson,70
    ——————
    67 Perhaps  the only early state-law discussion that truly supports the
    Court’s position is dicta in an 1834 Virginia decision. Hendrick v.
    Commonwealth, 
    32 Va. 707
    . Yet even that support proves threadbare
    in the end, given that “the highest court of the same State later ex-
    pressed the view that such double trials would virtually never occur in
    our country.” Bartkus, 359 U. S., at 159 (Black, J., dissenting) (citing
    Jett v. Commonwealth, 
    59 Va. 933
    , 947, 959 (1867)).
    68 R. Cross & J. Harris, Precedent in English Law, intro. comment
    (4th ed. 1991) (attributing the aphorism to Jeremy Bentham).
    69 
    19 How. 393
     (1857).
    70 
    163 U.S. 537
     (1896).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                  19
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    and Korematsu v. United States.71 As Justice Brandeis
    explained, “in cases involving the Federal Constitution,
    where correction through legislative action is practically
    impossible, this Court has often overruled its earlier deci-
    sions. The Court bows to the lessons of experience and the
    force of better reasoning, recognizing that the process of
    trial and error, so fruitful in the physical sciences, is ap-
    propriate also in the judicial function.”72
    For all these reasons, while stare decisis warrants re-
    spect, it has never been “ ‘an inexorable command,’ ”73 and
    it is “at its weakest when we interpret the Constitution.”74
    In deciding whether one of our cases should be retained or
    overruled, this Court has traditionally considered “the
    quality of the decision’s reasoning; its consistency with
    related decisions; legal developments since the decision;
    and reliance on the decision.”75 Each of these factors, I
    believe, suggests we should reject the separate sovereigns
    exception.
    Take the “quality of [the] reasoning.”76 The first cases to
    suggest that successive prosecutions by state and federal
    authorities might be permissible did not seek to address
    the original meaning of the word “offence,” the troubling
    federalism implications of the exception, or the relevant
    historical sources. Between 1847 and 1850, the Court
    decided a pair of cases, United States v. Marigold77 and
    Fox v. Ohio.78 While addressing other matters in those
    decisions, the Court offered passing approval to the possi-
    ——————
    71 
    323 U.S. 214
     (1944).
    72 Burnet v. Coronado Oil & Gas Co., 
    285 U.S. 393
    , 406–408 (1932)
    (dissenting opinion) (footnotes omitted).
    73 Pearson v. Callahan, 
    555 U.S. 223
    , 233 (2009).
    74 Agostini v. Felton, 
    521 U.S. 203
    , 235 (1997).
    75 Franchise Tax Bd. of Cal. v. Hyatt, ante, at ___ (slip op., at 17).
    76 Janus v. State, County, and Municipal Employees, 
    585 U.S.
    ___,
    ___ (2018) (slip op., at 35).
    77 
    9 How. 560
     (1850).
    78 
    5 How. 410
     (1847).
    20                 GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    bility of successive state and federal prosecutions, but did
    so without analysis and without actually upholding a
    successive conviction. Indeed, in place of a careful consti-
    tutional analysis, the Fox Court merely offered its judg-
    ment that “the benignant spirit” of prosecutors could be
    relied on to protect individuals from too many repetitive
    prosecutions.79 We do not normally give precedential
    effect to such stray commentary.
    Perhaps the first real roots of the separate sovereigns
    exception can be traced to this Court’s 1852 decision in
    Moore v. Illinois.80 As it did five years later and more
    notoriously in Dred Scott,81 the Court in Moore did vio-
    lence to the Constitution in the name of protecting slavery
    and slaveowners. In Dred Scott the Court held that the
    Due Process Clause prevented Congress from prohibiting
    slavery in the territories, though of course the Clause did
    nothing of the sort.82 And in Moore the Court upheld a
    state fugitive slave law that it judged important because
    the States supposedly needed “to protect themselves
    against the influx either of liberated or fugitive slaves, and
    to repel from their soil a population likely to become bur-
    densome and injurious, either as paupers or criminals.”83
    The defendant, who had harbored a fugitive slave, objected
    that upholding the state law could potentially expose him
    to double prosecutions by the state and federal govern-
    ments. The Court rejected that argument, reasoning
    simply that such double punishment could be consistent
    with the Constitution if the defendant had violated both
    state and federal law.84 Yet notably, even here, the Court
    did not actually approve a successive prosecution.
    ——————
    79 Id., at 435.
    80 
    14 How. 13
    .
    81 
    19 How. 393
    .
    82 Id., at 450.
    83 Moore, 14 How., at 18.
    84 Id., at 16.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)               21
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    Nor did the trajectory of the separate sovereigns excep-
    tion improve much from there. The first time the Court
    actually approved an “instance of double prosecution [and]
    failed to find some remedy . . . to avoid it” didn’t arrive
    until 1922.85 In that case, United States v. Lanza,86 the
    federal government prosecuted the defendants for manu-
    facturing, transporting, and possessing alcohol in violation
    of the National Prohibition Act. The defendants argued
    that they had already been prosecuted by the State of
    Washington for the same offense. But, notably, the de-
    fendants did not directly question the permissibility of
    successive prosecutions for the same offense under state
    and federal law. Instead, the defendants argued that both
    of the laws under which they were punished really derived
    from the “same sovereign:” the national government, by
    way of the Eighteenth Amendment that authorized Prohi-
    bition. After rejecting that argument as an “erroneous
    view of the matter,” the Court proceeded on, perhaps
    unnecessarily, to offer its view that “an act denounced as a
    crime by both national and state sovereignties is an of-
    fense against the peace and dignity of both and may be
    punished by each.”87 Given that the Court was not asked
    directly to consider the propriety of successive prosecu-
    tions under separate state and federal laws for the same
    offense, it is perhaps unsurprising the Court did not con-
    sult the original meaning of the Double Jeopardy Clause
    or consult virtually any of the relevant historical sources
    before offering its dictum.
    It matters, too, that these cases “were decided by the
    narrowest of margins, over spirited dissents challenging
    the basic underpinnings of those decisions.”88 In Moore,
    ——————
    85 Grant, The Lanza Rule of Successive Prosecutions, 32 Colum. L.
    Rev. 1309, 1311 (1932).
    86 
    260 U.S. 377
     (1922).
    87 Id., at 381, 382.
    88 Payne v. Tennessee, 
    501 U.S. 808
    , 828–829 (1991).
    22                     GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    Justice McLean wrote that although “the Federal and
    State Governments emanate from different sovereignties,”
    they “operate upon the same people, and should have the
    same end in view.”89 He “deeply regret[ted] that our gov-
    ernment should be an exception to a great principle of
    action, sanctioned by humanity and justice.”90 Bartkus
    and Abbate, cases decided in the 1950s that more clearly
    approved the separate sovereigns exception, were decided
    only by 5-to-4 and 6-to-3 margins, and Justice Black’s
    eloquent dissents in those cases have triggered an ava-
    lanche of persuasive academic support.91
    What is more, the “underpinnings” of the separate
    sovereigns exception have been “erode[d] by subsequent
    decisions of this Court.”92 When this Court decided Moore,
    Lanza, Bartkus, and Abbate, the Double Jeopardy Clause
    applied only to the federal government under this Court’s
    decision in Palko v. Connecticut.93 In those days, one
    might have thought, the separate sovereigns exception at
    least served to level the playing field between the federal
    government and the States: If a State could retry a de-
    fendant after a federal trial, then the federal government
    ought to be able to retry a defendant after a state trial.
    But in time the Court overruled Palko and held that the
    Double Jeopardy Clause does apply to the States—and,
    ——————
    89 14   How., at 22 (dissenting opinion).
    90 Ibid.
    91 See,e.g., Cassell, The Rodney King Trials and the Double Jeopardy
    Clause: Some Observations on Original Meaning and the ACLU’s
    Schizophrenic Views of the Dual Sovereign Doctrine, 41 UCLA L. Rev.
    693, 708–720 (1994); Braun, Praying to False Sovereigns: The Rule
    Permitting Successive Prosecutions in the Age of Cooperative Federal-
    ism, 20 Am. J. Crim. L. 1 (1992); Amar & Marcus, Double Jeopardy
    Law After Rodney King, 95 Colum. L. Rev. 1, 6–15 (1995); King, The
    Problem of Double Jeopardy in Successive Federal-State Prosecutions:
    A Fifth Amendment Solution, 31 Stan. L. Rev. 477 (1979).
    92 United States v. Gaudin, 
    515 U.S. 506
    , 521 (1995).
    93 
    302 U.S. 319
    , 328–329 (1937).
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)                     23
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    with that, a premise once thought important to the excep-
    tion fell away.94
    Nor has only the law changed; the world has too. And
    when “far-reaching systemic and structural changes”
    make an “earlier error all the more egregious and harm-
    ful,” stare decisis can lose its force.95 In the era when the
    separate sovereigns exception first emerged, the federal
    criminal code was new, thin, modest, and restrained.
    Today, it can make none of those of boasts. Some suggest
    that “the federal government has [now] duplicated vir-
    tually every major state crime.”96 Others estimate that the
    U. S. Code contains more than 4,500 criminal statutes, not
    even counting the hundreds of thousands of federal regu-
    lations that can trigger criminal penalties.97 Still others
    suggest that “ ‘[t]here is no one in the United States over
    the age of 18 who cannot be indicted for some federal
    crime.’ ”98 If long ago the Court could have thought “the
    benignant spirit” of prosecutors rather than unwavering
    enforcement of the Constitution sufficient protection
    against the threat of double prosecutions, it’s unclear how
    we still might.
    That leaves reliance. But the only people who have
    relied on the separate sovereigns exception are prosecu-
    tors who have sought to double-prosecute and double-
    ——————
    94 Benton,  395 U. S., at 794.
    95 South  Dakota v. Wayfair, Inc., 
    585 U.S.
    ___, ___ (2018) (slip op., at
    18) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    96 E. Meese, Big Brother on the Beat: The Expanding Federalization
    of Crime, 1 Texas L. Rev. L. & Pol’y 1, 22 (1997).
    97 See Wilson, That Justice Shall Be Done, 36 No. Ill. L. Rev. 111, 121
    (2015).
    98 Clark & Joukov, Criminalization of America, 
    76 Ala. L
    . 225 (2015).
    See also Larkin, Public Choice Theory and Overcriminalization, 36
    Harv. J. L. Pub. Pol’y 715, 726 (2013) (“There are so many federal
    criminal laws that no one, including the Justice Department, the
    principal federal law enforcement agency, knows the actual number of
    crimes”).
    24                     GAMBLE v. UNITED STATES
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    punish. And this Court has long rejected the idea that
    “law enforcement reliance interests outweig[h] the interest
    in protecting individual constitutional rights so as to
    warrant fidelity to an unjustifiable rule.”99 Instead, “[i]f it
    is clear that a practice is unlawful, individuals’ interest in
    its discontinuance clearly outweighs any law enforcement
    ‘entitlement’ to its persistence.”100 That is the case here.
    The Court today disregards these lessons. It worries
    that overturning the separate sovereigns rule could un-
    dermine the reliance interests of prosecutors in transna-
    tional cases who might be prohibited from trying individu-
    als already acquitted by a foreign court. Ante, at 7. Yet
    even on its own terms, this argument is unpersuasive.
    The government has not even attempted to quantify the
    scope of the alleged “problem,” and perhaps for good rea-
    son. Domestic prosecutors regularly coordinate with their
    foreign counterparts when pursuing transnational crimi-
    nals, so they can often choose the most favorable forum for
    their mutual efforts. And because Blockburger requires an
    identity of elements before the double jeopardy bar can
    take hold, domestic prosecutors, armed with their own
    abundant criminal codes, will often be able to find new
    offenses to charge if they are unsatisfied with outcomes
    elsewhere.
    *    *     *
    Enforcing the Constitution always bears its costs. But
    when the people adopted the Constitution and its Bill of
    Rights, they thought the liberties promised there worth
    the costs. It is not for this Court to reassess this judgment
    to make the prosecutor’s job easier. Nor is there any
    doubt that the benefits the framers saw in prohibiting
    double prosecutions remain real, and maybe more vital
    ——————
    99 Arizona     v. Gant, 
    556 U.S. 332
    , 350 (2009).
    100 Id.,   at 349.
    Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019)        25
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    than ever, today. When governments may unleash all
    their might in multiple prosecutions against an individual,
    exhausting themselves only when those who hold the reins
    of power are content with the result, it is “the poor and the
    weak,”101 and the unpopular and controversial, who suffer
    first—and there is nothing to stop them from being the
    last. The separate sovereigns exception was wrong when
    it was invented, and it remains wrong today.
    I respectfully dissent.
    ——————
    101 Bartkus,   359 U. S., at 163 (Black, J., dissenting).