Obergefell v. Hodges ( 2015 )


Menu:
  • (Slip Opinion)              OCTOBER TERM, 2014                                       1
    Syllabus
    NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is
    being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued.
    The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been
    prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader.
    See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 
    200 U.S. 321
    , 337.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    Syllabus
    OBERGEFELL ET AL. v. HODGES, DIRECTOR, OHIO
    DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH, ET AL.
    CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR
    THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    No. 14–556.      Argued April 28, 2015—Decided June 26, 2015*
    Michigan, Kentucky, Ohio, and Tennessee define marriage as a union
    between one man and one woman. The petitioners, 14 same-sex cou-
    ples and two men whose same-sex partners are deceased, filed suits
    in Federal District Courts in their home States, claiming that re-
    spondent state officials violate the Fourteenth Amendment by deny-
    ing them the right to marry or to have marriages lawfully performed
    in another State given full recognition. Each District Court ruled in
    petitioners’ favor, but the Sixth Circuit consolidated the cases and
    reversed.
    Held: The Fourteenth Amendment requires a State to license a mar-
    riage between two people of the same sex and to recognize a marriage
    between two people of the same sex when their marriage was lawful-
    ly licensed and performed out-of-State. Pp. 3–28.
    (a) Before turning to the governing principles and precedents, it is
    appropriate to note the history of the subject now before the Court.
    Pp. 3–10.
    (1) The history of marriage as a union between two persons of
    the opposite sex marks the beginning of these cases. To the respond-
    ents, it would demean a timeless institution if marriage were extend-
    ed to same-sex couples. But the petitioners, far from seeking to de-
    value marriage, seek it for themselves because of their respect—and
    need—for its privileges and responsibilities, as illustrated by the pe-
    ——————
    * Together with No. 14–562, Tanco et al. v. Haslam, Governor of Ten-
    nessee, et al., No. 14–571, DeBoer et al. v. Snyder, Governor of Michigan,
    et al., and No. 14–574, Bourke et al. v. Beshear, Governor of Kentucky,
    also on certiorari to the same court.
    2                       OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Syllabus
    titioners’ own experiences. Pp. 3–6.
    (2) The history of marriage is one of both continuity and change.
    Changes, such as the decline of arranged marriages and the aban-
    donment of the law of coverture, have worked deep transformations
    in the structure of marriage, affecting aspects of marriage once
    viewed as essential. These new insights have strengthened, not
    weakened, the institution. Changed understandings of marriage are
    characteristic of a Nation where new dimensions of freedom become
    apparent to new generations.
    This dynamic can be seen in the Nation’s experience with gay and
    lesbian rights. Well into the 20th century, many States condemned
    same-sex intimacy as immoral, and homosexuality was treated as an
    illness. Later in the century, cultural and political developments al-
    lowed same-sex couples to lead more open and public lives. Extensive
    public and private dialogue followed, along with shifts in public atti-
    tudes. Questions about the legal treatment of gays and lesbians soon
    reached the courts, where they could be discussed in the formal dis-
    course of the law. In 2003, this Court overruled its 1986 decision in
    Bowers v. Hardwick, 
    478 U.S. 186
    , which upheld a Georgia law that
    criminalized certain homosexual acts, concluding laws making same-
    sex intimacy a crime “demea[n] the lives of homosexual persons.”
    Lawrence v. Texas, 
    539 U.S. 558
    , 575. In 2012, the federal Defense
    of Marriage Act was also struck down. United States v. Windsor, 570
    U. S. ___. Numerous same-sex marriage cases reaching the federal
    courts and state supreme courts have added to the dialogue. Pp. 6–
    10.
    (b) The Fourteenth Amendment requires a State to license a mar-
    riage between two people of the same sex. Pp. 10–27.
    (1) The fundamental liberties protected by the Fourteenth
    Amendment’s Due Process Clause extend to certain personal choices
    central to individual dignity and autonomy, including intimate choic-
    es defining personal identity and beliefs. See, e.g., Eisenstadt v.
    Baird, 
    405 U.S. 438
    , 453; Griswold v. Connecticut, 
    381 U.S. 479
    ,
    484–486. Courts must exercise reasoned judgment in identifying in-
    terests of the person so fundamental that the State must accord them
    its respect. History and tradition guide and discipline the inquiry
    but do not set its outer boundaries. When new insight reveals dis-
    cord between the Constitution’s central protections and a received le-
    gal stricture, a claim to liberty must be addressed.
    Applying these tenets, the Court has long held the right to marry is
    protected by the Constitution. For example, Loving v. Virginia, 
    388 U.S. 1
    , 12, invalidated bans on interracial unions, and Turner v.
    Safley, 
    482 U.S. 78
    , 95, held that prisoners could not be denied the
    right to marry. To be sure, these cases presumed a relationship in-
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)                      3
    Syllabus
    volving opposite-sex partners, as did Baker v. Nelson, 
    409 U.S. 810
    , a
    one-line summary decision issued in 1972, holding that the exclusion
    of same-sex couples from marriage did not present a substantial fed-
    eral question. But other, more instructive precedents have expressed
    broader principles. See, e.g., 
    Lawrence, supra, at 574
    . In assessing
    whether the force and rationale of its cases apply to same-sex cou-
    ples, the Court must respect the basic reasons why the right to marry
    has been long protected. See, e.g., 
    Eisenstadt, supra, at 453
    –454.
    This analysis compels the conclusion that same-sex couples may ex-
    ercise the right to marry. Pp. 10–12.
    (2) Four principles and traditions demonstrate that the rea-
    sons marriage is fundamental under the Constitution apply with
    equal force to same-sex couples. The first premise of this Court’s rel-
    evant precedents is that the right to personal choice regarding mar-
    riage is inherent in the concept of individual autonomy. This abiding
    connection between marriage and liberty is why Loving invalidated
    interracial marriage bans under the Due Process Clause. 
    See 388 U.S., at 12
    . Decisions about marriage are among the most intimate
    that an individual can make. See 
    Lawrence, supra, at 574
    . This is
    true for all persons, whatever their sexual orientation.
    A second principle in this Court’s jurisprudence is that the right to
    marry is fundamental because it supports a two-person union unlike
    any other in its importance to the committed individuals. The inti-
    mate association protected by this right was central to Griswold v.
    Connecticut, which held the Constitution protects the right of mar-
    ried couples to use 
    contraception, 381 U.S., at 485
    , and was acknowl-
    edged in 
    Turner, supra, at 95
    . Same-sex couples have the same right
    as opposite-sex couples to enjoy intimate association, a right extend-
    ing beyond mere freedom from laws making same-sex intimacy a
    criminal offense. See 
    Lawrence, supra, at 567
    .
    A third basis for protecting the right to marry is that it safeguards
    children and families and thus draws meaning from related rights of
    childrearing, procreation, and education. See, e.g., Pierce v. Society of
    Sisters, 
    268 U.S. 510
    . Without the recognition, stability, and pre-
    dictability marriage offers, children suffer the stigma of knowing
    their families are somehow lesser. They also suffer the significant
    material costs of being raised by unmarried parents, relegated to a
    more difficult and uncertain family life. The marriage laws at issue
    thus harm and humiliate the children of same-sex couples. See
    
    Windsor, supra
    , at ___. This does not mean that the right to marry is
    less meaningful for those who do not or cannot have children. Prece-
    dent protects the right of a married couple not to procreate, so the
    right to marry cannot be conditioned on the capacity or commitment
    to procreate.
    4                       OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Syllabus
    Finally, this Court’s cases and the Nation’s traditions make clear
    that marriage is a keystone of the Nation’s social order. See
    Maynard v. Hill, 
    125 U.S. 190
    , 211. States have contributed to the
    fundamental character of marriage by placing it at the center of
    many facets of the legal and social order. There is no difference be-
    tween same- and opposite-sex couples with respect to this principle,
    yet same-sex couples are denied the constellation of benefits that the
    States have linked to marriage and are consigned to an instability
    many opposite-sex couples would find intolerable. It is demeaning to
    lock same-sex couples out of a central institution of the Nation’s soci-
    ety, for they too may aspire to the transcendent purposes of marriage.
    The limitation of marriage to opposite-sex couples may long have
    seemed natural and just, but its inconsistency with the central mean-
    ing of the fundamental right to marry is now manifest. Pp. 12–18.
    (3) The right of same-sex couples to marry is also derived from
    the Fourteenth Amendment’s guarantee of equal protection. The Due
    Process Clause and the Equal Protection Clause are connected in a
    profound way. Rights implicit in liberty and rights secured by equal
    protection may rest on different precepts and are not always co-
    extensive, yet each may be instructive as to the meaning and reach of
    the other. This dynamic is reflected in Loving, where the Court in-
    voked both the Equal Protection Clause and the Due Process Clause;
    and in Zablocki v. Redhail, 
    434 U.S. 374
    , where the Court invalidat-
    ed a law barring fathers delinquent on child-support payments from
    marrying. Indeed, recognizing that new insights and societal under-
    standings can reveal unjustified inequality within fundamental insti-
    tutions that once passed unnoticed and unchallenged, this Court has
    invoked equal protection principles to invalidate laws imposing sex-
    based inequality on marriage, see, e.g., Kirchberg v. Feenstra, 
    450 U.S. 455
    , 460–461, and confirmed the relation between liberty and
    equality, see, e.g., M. L. B. v. S. L. J., 
    519 U.S. 102
    , 120–121.
    The Court has acknowledged the interlocking nature of these con-
    stitutional safeguards in the context of the legal treatment of gays
    and lesbians. See 
    Lawrence, 539 U.S., at 575
    . This dynamic also
    applies to same-sex marriage. The challenged laws burden the liber-
    ty of same-sex couples, and they abridge central precepts of equality.
    The marriage laws at issue are in essence unequal: Same-sex couples
    are denied benefits afforded opposite-sex couples and are barred from
    exercising a fundamental right. Especially against a long history of
    disapproval of their relationships, this denial works a grave and con-
    tinuing harm, serving to disrespect and subordinate gays and lesbi-
    ans. Pp. 18–22.
    (4) The right to marry is a fundamental right inherent in the
    liberty of the person, and under the Due Process and Equal Protec-
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)                     5
    Syllabus
    tion Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment couples of the same-sex
    may not be deprived of that right and that liberty. Same-sex couples
    may exercise the fundamental right to marry. Baker v. Nelson is
    overruled. The State laws challenged by the petitioners in these cas-
    es are held invalid to the extent they exclude same-sex couples from
    civil marriage on the same terms and conditions as opposite-sex cou-
    ples. Pp. 22–23.
    (5) There may be an initial inclination to await further legisla-
    tion, litigation, and debate, but referenda, legislative debates, and
    grassroots campaigns; studies and other writings; and extensive liti-
    gation in state and federal courts have led to an enhanced under-
    standing of the issue. While the Constitution contemplates that de-
    mocracy is the appropriate process for change, individuals who are
    harmed need not await legislative action before asserting a funda-
    mental right. Bowers, in effect, upheld state action that denied gays
    and lesbians a fundamental right. Though it was eventually repudi-
    ated, men and women suffered pain and humiliation in the interim,
    and the effects of these injuries no doubt lingered long after Bowers
    was overruled. A ruling against same-sex couples would have the
    same effect and would be unjustified under the Fourteenth Amend-
    ment. The petitioners’ stories show the urgency of the issue they
    present to the Court, which has a duty to address these claims and
    answer these questions. Respondents’ argument that allowing same-
    sex couples to wed will harm marriage as an institution rests on a
    counterintuitive view of opposite-sex couples’ decisions about mar-
    riage and parenthood. Finally, the First Amendment ensures that
    religions, those who adhere to religious doctrines, and others have
    protection as they seek to teach the principles that are so fulfilling
    and so central to their lives and faiths. Pp. 23–27.
    (c) The Fourteenth Amendment requires States to recognize same-
    sex marriages validly performed out of State. Since same-sex couples
    may now exercise the fundamental right to marry in all States, there
    is no lawful basis for a State to refuse to recognize a lawful same-sex
    marriage performed in another State on the ground of its same-sex
    character. Pp. 27–28.
    
    772 F.3d 388
    , reversed.
    KENNEDY, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which GINSBURG,
    BREYER, SOTOMAYOR, and KAGAN, JJ., joined. ROBERTS, C. J., filed a
    dissenting opinion, in which SCALIA and THOMAS, JJ., joined. SCALIA,
    J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which THOMAS, J., joined. THOMAS, J.,
    filed a dissenting opinion, in which SCALIA, J., joined. ALITO, J., filed a
    dissenting opinion, in which SCALIA and THOMAS, JJ., joined.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)                              1
    Opinion of the Court
    NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the
    preliminary print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested to
    notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Wash-
    ington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order
    that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press.
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    Nos. 14–556, 14-562, 14-571 and 14–574
    _________________
    JAMES OBERGEFELL, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–556               v.
    RICHARD HODGES, DIRECTOR, OHIO
    DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH, ET AL.;
    VALERIA TANCO, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–562                  v.
    BILL HASLAM, GOVERNOR OF
    TENNESSEE, ET AL.;
    APRIL DEBOER, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–571                 v.
    RICK SNYDER, GOVERNOR OF MICHIGAN,
    ET AL.; AND
    GREGORY BOURKE, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–574              v.
    STEVE BESHEAR, GOVERNOR OF
    KENTUCKY
    ON WRITS OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    [June 26, 2015]
    JUSTICE KENNEDY delivered the opinion of the Court.
    The Constitution promises liberty to all within its reach,
    a liberty that includes certain specific rights that allow
    2                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    persons, within a lawful realm, to define and express their
    identity. The petitioners in these cases seek to find that
    liberty by marrying someone of the same sex and having
    their marriages deemed lawful on the same terms and
    conditions as marriages between persons of the opposite
    sex.
    I
    These cases come from Michigan, Kentucky, Ohio, and
    Tennessee, States that define marriage as a union be-
    tween one man and one woman. See, e.g., Mich. Const.,
    Art. I, §25; Ky. Const. §233A; Ohio Rev. Code Ann.
    §3101.01 (Lexis 2008); Tenn. Const., Art. XI, §18. The
    petitioners are 14 same-sex couples and two men whose
    same-sex partners are deceased. The respondents are
    state officials responsible for enforcing the laws in ques-
    tion. The petitioners claim the respondents violate the
    Fourteenth Amendment by denying them the right to
    marry or to have their marriages, lawfully performed in
    another State, given full recognition.
    Petitioners filed these suits in United States District
    Courts in their home States. Each District Court ruled in
    their favor. Citations to those cases are in Appendix A,
    infra. The respondents appealed the decisions against
    them to the United States Court of Appeals for the Sixth
    Circuit. It consolidated the cases and reversed the judg-
    ments of the District Courts. DeBoer v. Snyder, 
    772 F.3d 388
    (2014). The Court of Appeals held that a State has no
    constitutional obligation to license same-sex marriages or
    to recognize same-sex marriages performed out of State.
    The petitioners sought certiorari. This Court granted
    review, limited to two questions. 574 U. S. ___ (2015).
    The first, presented by the cases from Michigan and Ken-
    tucky, is whether the Fourteenth Amendment requires a
    State to license a marriage between two people of the
    same sex. The second, presented by the cases from Ohio,
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)            3
    Opinion of the Court
    Tennessee, and, again, Kentucky, is whether the Four-
    teenth Amendment requires a State to recognize a same-
    sex marriage licensed and performed in a State which does
    grant that right.
    II
    Before addressing the principles and precedents that
    govern these cases, it is appropriate to note the history of
    the subject now before the Court.
    A
    From their beginning to their most recent page, the
    annals of human history reveal the transcendent im-
    portance of marriage. The lifelong union of a man and a
    woman always has promised nobility and dignity to all
    persons, without regard to their station in life. Marriage
    is sacred to those who live by their religions and offers
    unique fulfillment to those who find meaning in the secu-
    lar realm. Its dynamic allows two people to find a life that
    could not be found alone, for a marriage becomes greater
    than just the two persons. Rising from the most basic
    human needs, marriage is essential to our most profound
    hopes and aspirations.
    The centrality of marriage to the human condition
    makes it unsurprising that the institution has existed for
    millennia and across civilizations. Since the dawn of
    history, marriage has transformed strangers into rela-
    tives, binding families and societies together. Confucius
    taught that marriage lies at the foundation of government.
    2 Li Chi: Book of Rites 266 (C. Chai & W. Chai eds., J.
    Legge transl. 1967). This wisdom was echoed centuries
    later and half a world away by Cicero, who wrote, “The
    first bond of society is marriage; next, children; and then
    the family.” See De Officiis 57 (W. Miller transl. 1913).
    There are untold references to the beauty of marriage in
    religious and philosophical texts spanning time, cultures,
    4                 OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    and faiths, as well as in art and literature in all their
    forms. It is fair and necessary to say these references
    were based on the understanding that marriage is a union
    between two persons of the opposite sex.
    That history is the beginning of these cases. The re-
    spondents say it should be the end as well. To them, it
    would demean a timeless institution if the concept and
    lawful status of marriage were extended to two persons of
    the same sex. Marriage, in their view, is by its nature a
    gender-differentiated union of man and woman. This view
    long has been held—and continues to be held—in good
    faith by reasonable and sincere people here and through-
    out the world.
    The petitioners acknowledge this history but contend
    that these cases cannot end there. Were their intent to
    demean the revered idea and reality of marriage, the
    petitioners’ claims would be of a different order. But that
    is neither their purpose nor their submission. To the
    contrary, it is the enduring importance of marriage that
    underlies the petitioners’ contentions. This, they say, is
    their whole point. Far from seeking to devalue marriage,
    the petitioners seek it for themselves because of their
    respect—and need—for its privileges and responsibilities.
    And their immutable nature dictates that same-sex mar-
    riage is their only real path to this profound commitment.
    Recounting the circumstances of three of these cases
    illustrates the urgency of the petitioners’ cause from their
    perspective. Petitioner James Obergefell, a plaintiff in the
    Ohio case, met John Arthur over two decades ago. They
    fell in love and started a life together, establishing a last-
    ing, committed relation. In 2011, however, Arthur was
    diagnosed with amyotrophic lateral sclerosis, or ALS.
    This debilitating disease is progressive, with no known
    cure. Two years ago, Obergefell and Arthur decided to
    commit to one another, resolving to marry before Arthur
    died. To fulfill their mutual promise, they traveled from
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)            5
    Opinion of the Court
    Ohio to Maryland, where same-sex marriage was legal. It
    was difficult for Arthur to move, and so the couple were
    wed inside a medical transport plane as it remained on the
    tarmac in Baltimore. Three months later, Arthur died.
    Ohio law does not permit Obergefell to be listed as the
    surviving spouse on Arthur’s death certificate. By statute,
    they must remain strangers even in death, a state-
    imposed separation Obergefell deems “hurtful for the rest
    of time.” App. in No. 14–556 etc., p. 38. He brought suit
    to be shown as the surviving spouse on Arthur’s death
    certificate.
    April DeBoer and Jayne Rowse are co-plaintiffs in the
    case from Michigan. They celebrated a commitment cere-
    mony to honor their permanent relation in 2007. They
    both work as nurses, DeBoer in a neonatal unit and Rowse
    in an emergency unit. In 2009, DeBoer and Rowse fos-
    tered and then adopted a baby boy. Later that same year,
    they welcomed another son into their family. The new
    baby, born prematurely and abandoned by his biological
    mother, required around-the-clock care. The next year, a
    baby girl with special needs joined their family. Michigan,
    however, permits only opposite-sex married couples or
    single individuals to adopt, so each child can have only one
    woman as his or her legal parent. If an emergency were to
    arise, schools and hospitals may treat the three children
    as if they had only one parent. And, were tragedy to befall
    either DeBoer or Rowse, the other would have no legal
    rights over the children she had not been permitted to
    adopt. This couple seeks relief from the continuing uncer-
    tainty their unmarried status creates in their lives.
    Army Reserve Sergeant First Class Ijpe DeKoe and his
    partner Thomas Kostura, co-plaintiffs in the Tennessee
    case, fell in love. In 2011, DeKoe received orders to deploy
    to Afghanistan. Before leaving, he and Kostura married
    in New York. A week later, DeKoe began his deployment,
    which lasted for almost a year. When he returned, the two
    6                 OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    settled in Tennessee, where DeKoe works full-time for the
    Army Reserve. Their lawful marriage is stripped from
    them whenever they reside in Tennessee, returning and
    disappearing as they travel across state lines. DeKoe, who
    served this Nation to preserve the freedom the Constitu-
    tion protects, must endure a substantial burden.
    The cases now before the Court involve other petitioners
    as well, each with their own experiences. Their stories
    reveal that they seek not to denigrate marriage but rather
    to live their lives, or honor their spouses’ memory, joined
    by its bond.
    B
    The ancient origins of marriage confirm its centrality,
    but it has not stood in isolation from developments in law
    and society. The history of marriage is one of both conti-
    nuity and change. That institution—even as confined to
    opposite-sex relations—has evolved over time.
    For example, marriage was once viewed as an arrange-
    ment by the couple’s parents based on political, religious,
    and financial concerns; but by the time of the Nation’s
    founding it was understood to be a voluntary contract
    between a man and a woman. See N. Cott, Public Vows: A
    History of Marriage and the Nation 9–17 (2000); S.
    Coontz, Marriage, A History 15–16 (2005). As the role and
    status of women changed, the institution further evolved.
    Under the centuries-old doctrine of coverture, a married
    man and woman were treated by the State as a single,
    male-dominated legal entity. See 1 W. Blackstone, Com-
    mentaries on the Laws of England 430 (1765). As women
    gained legal, political, and property rights, and as society
    began to understand that women have their own equal
    dignity, the law of coverture was abandoned. See Brief for
    Historians of Marriage et al. as Amici Curiae 16–19. These
    and other developments in the institution of marriage over
    the past centuries were not mere superficial changes.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           7
    Opinion of the Court
    Rather, they worked deep transformations in its structure,
    affecting aspects of marriage long viewed by many as essen-
    tial. See generally N. Cott, Public Vows; S. Coontz, Mar-
    riage; H. Hartog, Man & Wife in America: A History (2000).
    These new insights have strengthened, not weakened,
    the institution of marriage. Indeed, changed understand-
    ings of marriage are characteristic of a Nation where new
    dimensions of freedom become apparent to new genera-
    tions, often through perspectives that begin in pleas or
    protests and then are considered in the political sphere
    and the judicial process.
    This dynamic can be seen in the Nation’s experiences
    with the rights of gays and lesbians. Until the mid-20th
    century, same-sex intimacy long had been condemned as
    immoral by the state itself in most Western nations, a
    belief often embodied in the criminal law. For this reason,
    among others, many persons did not deem homosexuals to
    have dignity in their own distinct identity. A truthful
    declaration by same-sex couples of what was in their
    hearts had to remain unspoken. Even when a greater
    awareness of the humanity and integrity of homosexual
    persons came in the period after World War II, the argu-
    ment that gays and lesbians had a just claim to dignity
    was in conflict with both law and widespread social con-
    ventions. Same-sex intimacy remained a crime in many
    States. Gays and lesbians were prohibited from most
    government employment, barred from military service,
    excluded under immigration laws, targeted by police, and
    burdened in their rights to associate. See Brief for Organ-
    ization of American Historians as Amicus Curiae 5–28.
    For much of the 20th century, moreover, homosexuality
    was treated as an illness. When the American Psychiatric
    Association published the first Diagnostic and Statistical
    Manual of Mental Disorders in 1952, homosexuality was
    classified as a mental disorder, a position adhered to until
    1973. See Position Statement on Homosexuality and Civil
    8                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    Rights, 1973, in 131 Am. J. Psychiatry 497 (1974). Only in
    more recent years have psychiatrists and others recog-
    nized that sexual orientation is both a normal expression
    of human sexuality and immutable. See Brief for Ameri-
    can Psychological Association et al. as Amici Curiae 7–17.
    In the late 20th century, following substantial cultural
    and political developments, same-sex couples began to
    lead more open and public lives and to establish families.
    This development was followed by a quite extensive dis-
    cussion of the issue in both governmental and private
    sectors and by a shift in public attitudes toward greater
    tolerance. As a result, questions about the rights of gays
    and lesbians soon reached the courts, where the issue
    could be discussed in the formal discourse of the law.
    This Court first gave detailed consideration to the legal
    status of homosexuals in Bowers v. Hardwick, 
    478 U.S. 186
    (1986). There it upheld the constitutionality of a
    Georgia law deemed to criminalize certain homosexual
    acts. Ten years later, in Romer v. Evans, 
    517 U.S. 620
    (1996), the Court invalidated an amendment to Colorado’s
    Constitution that sought to foreclose any branch or politi-
    cal subdivision of the State from protecting persons
    against discrimination based on sexual orientation. Then,
    in 2003, the Court overruled Bowers, holding that laws
    making same-sex intimacy a crime “demea[n] the lives of
    homosexual persons.” Lawrence v. Texas, 
    539 U.S. 558
    ,
    575.
    Against this background, the legal question of same-sex
    marriage arose. In 1993, the Hawaii Supreme Court held
    Hawaii’s law restricting marriage to opposite-sex couples
    constituted a classification on the basis of sex and was
    therefore subject to strict scrutiny under the Hawaii Con-
    stitution. Baehr v. Lewin, 
    74 Haw. 530
    , 
    852 P.2d 44
    .
    Although this decision did not mandate that same-sex
    marriage be allowed, some States were concerned by its
    implications and reaffirmed in their laws that marriage is
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)            9
    Opinion of the Court
    defined as a union between opposite-sex partners. So too
    in 1996, Congress passed the Defense of Marriage Act
    (DOMA), 110 Stat. 2419, defining marriage for all federal-
    law purposes as “only a legal union between one man and
    one woman as husband and wife.” 
    1 U.S. C
    . §7.
    The new and widespread discussion of the subject led
    other States to a different conclusion. In 2003, the Su-
    preme Judicial Court of Massachusetts held the State’s
    Constitution guaranteed same-sex couples the right to
    marry. See Goodridge v. Department of Public Health, 
    440 Mass. 309
    , 
    798 N.E.2d 941
    (2003). After that ruling,
    some additional States granted marriage rights to same-
    sex couples, either through judicial or legislative proc-
    esses. These decisions and statutes are cited in Appendix B,
    infra. Two Terms ago, in United States v. Windsor, 570
    U. S. ___ (2013), this Court invalidated DOMA to the
    extent it barred the Federal Government from treating
    same-sex marriages as valid even when they were lawful
    in the State where they were licensed. DOMA, the Court
    held, impermissibly disparaged those same-sex couples
    “who wanted to affirm their commitment to one another
    before their children, their family, their friends, and their
    community.” Id., at ___ (slip op., at 14).
    Numerous cases about same-sex marriage have reached
    the United States Courts of Appeals in recent years. In
    accordance with the judicial duty to base their decisions on
    principled reasons and neutral discussions, without scorn-
    ful or disparaging commentary, courts have written a
    substantial body of law considering all sides of these is-
    sues. That case law helps to explain and formulate the
    underlying principles this Court now must consider. With
    the exception of the opinion here under review and one
    other, see Citizens for Equal Protection v. Bruning, 
    455 F.3d 859
    , 864–868 (CA8 2006), the Courts of Appeals
    have held that excluding same-sex couples from marriage
    violates the Constitution. There also have been many
    10                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    thoughtful District Court decisions addressing same-sex
    marriage—and most of them, too, have concluded same-
    sex couples must be allowed to marry. In addition the
    highest courts of many States have contributed to this
    ongoing dialogue in decisions interpreting their own State
    Constitutions. These state and federal judicial opinions
    are cited in Appendix A, infra.
    After years of litigation, legislation, referenda, and the
    discussions that attended these public acts, the States are
    now divided on the issue of same-sex marriage. See Office
    of the Atty. Gen. of Maryland, The State of Marriage
    Equality in America, State-by-State Supp. (2015).
    III
    Under the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth
    Amendment, no State shall “deprive any person of life,
    liberty, or property, without due process of law.” The
    fundamental liberties protected by this Clause include
    most of the rights enumerated in the Bill of Rights. See
    Duncan v. Louisiana, 
    391 U.S. 145
    , 147–149 (1968). In
    addition these liberties extend to certain personal choices
    central to individual dignity and autonomy, including
    intimate choices that define personal identity and beliefs.
    See, e.g., Eisenstadt v. Baird, 
    405 U.S. 438
    , 453 (1972);
    Griswold v. Connecticut, 
    381 U.S. 479
    , 484–486 (1965).
    The identification and protection of fundamental rights
    is an enduring part of the judicial duty to interpret the
    Constitution. That responsibility, however, “has not been
    reduced to any formula.” Poe v. Ullman, 
    367 U.S. 497
    ,
    542 (1961) (Harlan, J., dissenting). Rather, it requires
    courts to exercise reasoned judgment in identifying inter-
    ests of the person so fundamental that the State must
    accord them its respect. See 
    ibid. That process is
    guided
    by many of the same considerations relevant to analysis of
    other constitutional provisions that set forth broad princi-
    ples rather than specific requirements. History and tradi-
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           11
    Opinion of the Court
    tion guide and discipline this inquiry but do not set its
    outer boundaries. See 
    Lawrence, supra, at 572
    . That
    method respects our history and learns from it without
    allowing the past alone to rule the present.
    The nature of injustice is that we may not always see it
    in our own times. The generations that wrote and ratified
    the Bill of Rights and the Fourteenth Amendment did not
    presume to know the extent of freedom in all of its dimen-
    sions, and so they entrusted to future generations a char-
    ter protecting the right of all persons to enjoy liberty as we
    learn its meaning. When new insight reveals discord
    between the Constitution’s central protections and a re-
    ceived legal stricture, a claim to liberty must be addressed.
    Applying these established tenets, the Court has long
    held the right to marry is protected by the Constitution.
    In Loving v. Virginia, 
    388 U.S. 1
    , 12 (1967), which invali-
    dated bans on interracial unions, a unanimous Court held
    marriage is “one of the vital personal rights essential to
    the orderly pursuit of happiness by free men.” The Court
    reaffirmed that holding in Zablocki v. Redhail, 
    434 U.S. 374
    , 384 (1978), which held the right to marry was bur-
    dened by a law prohibiting fathers who were behind on
    child support from marrying. The Court again applied
    this principle in Turner v. Safley, 
    482 U.S. 78
    , 95 (1987),
    which held the right to marry was abridged by regulations
    limiting the privilege of prison inmates to marry. Over
    time and in other contexts, the Court has reiterated that
    the right to marry is fundamental under the Due Process
    Clause. See, e.g., M. L. B. v. S. L. J., 
    519 U.S. 102
    , 116
    (1996); Cleveland Bd. of Ed. v. LaFleur, 
    414 U.S. 632
    ,
    639–640 (1974); 
    Griswold, supra, at 486
    ; Skinner v. Okla-
    homa ex rel. Williamson, 
    316 U.S. 535
    , 541 (1942); Meyer
    v. Nebraska, 
    262 U.S. 390
    , 399 (1923).
    It cannot be denied that this Court’s cases describing
    the right to marry presumed a relationship involving
    opposite-sex partners. The Court, like many institutions,
    12                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    has made assumptions defined by the world and time of
    which it is a part. This was evident in Baker v. Nelson,
    
    409 U.S. 810
    , a one-line summary decision issued in 1972,
    holding the exclusion of same-sex couples from marriage
    did not present a substantial federal question.
    Still, there are other, more instructive precedents. This
    Court’s cases have expressed constitutional principles of
    broader reach. In defining the right to marry these cases
    have identified essential attributes of that right based in
    history, tradition, and other constitutional liberties inher-
    ent in this intimate bond. See, e.g., 
    Lawrence, 539 U.S., at 574
    ; 
    Turner, supra, at 95
    ; 
    Zablocki, supra, at 384
    ;
    
    Loving, supra, at 12
    ; 
    Griswold, supra, at 486
    . And in
    assessing whether the force and rationale of its cases
    apply to same-sex couples, the Court must respect the
    basic reasons why the right to marry has been long pro-
    tected. See, e.g., 
    Eisenstadt, supra, at 453
    –454; Poe, su-
    pra, at 542–553 (Harlan, J., dissenting).
    This analysis compels the conclusion that same-sex
    couples may exercise the right to marry. The four princi-
    ples and traditions to be discussed demonstrate that the
    reasons marriage is fundamental under the Constitution
    apply with equal force to same-sex couples.
    A first premise of the Court’s relevant precedents is that
    the right to personal choice regarding marriage is inherent
    in the concept of individual autonomy. This abiding con-
    nection between marriage and liberty is why Loving inval-
    idated interracial marriage bans under the Due Process
    Clause. 
    See 388 U.S., at 12
    ; see also 
    Zablocki, supra, at 384
    (observing Loving held “the right to marry is of fun-
    damental importance for all individuals”). Like choices
    concerning contraception, family relationships, procrea-
    tion, and childrearing, all of which are protected by the
    Constitution, decisions concerning marriage are among
    the most intimate that an individual can make. See Law-
    
    rence, supra, at 574
    . Indeed, the Court has noted it would
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           13
    Opinion of the Court
    be contradictory “to recognize a right of privacy with re-
    spect to other matters of family life and not with respect to
    the decision to enter the relationship that is the founda-
    tion of the family in our society.” 
    Zablocki, supra, at 386
    .
    Choices about marriage shape an individual’s destiny.
    As the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts has
    explained, because “it fulfils yearnings for security, safe
    haven, and connection that express our common human-
    ity, civil marriage is an esteemed institution, and the
    decision whether and whom to marry is among life’s mo-
    mentous acts of self-definition.” 
    Goodridge, 440 Mass., at 322
    , 
    798 N.E. 2d
    , at 955.
    The nature of marriage is that, through its enduring
    bond, two persons together can find other freedoms, such
    as expression, intimacy, and spirituality. This is true for
    all persons, whatever their sexual orientation. See Wind-
    sor, 570 U. S., at ___– ___ (slip op., at 22–23). There is
    dignity in the bond between two men or two women who
    seek to marry and in their autonomy to make such pro-
    found choices. Cf. 
    Loving, supra, at 12
    (“[T]he freedom to
    marry, or not marry, a person of another race resides with
    the individual and cannot be infringed by the State”).
    A second principle in this Court’s jurisprudence is that
    the right to marry is fundamental because it supports a
    two-person union unlike any other in its importance to the
    committed individuals. This point was central to Griswold
    v. Connecticut, which held the Constitution protects the
    right of married couples to use 
    contraception. 381 U.S., at 485
    . Suggesting that marriage is a right “older than the
    Bill of Rights,” Griswold described marriage this way:
    “Marriage is a coming together for better or for worse,
    hopefully enduring, and intimate to the degree of be-
    ing sacred. It is an association that promotes a way of
    life, not causes; a harmony in living, not political
    faiths; a bilateral loyalty, not commercial or social
    14                 OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    projects. Yet it is an association for as noble a purpose
    as any involved in our prior decisions. ” 
    Id., at 486.
    And in Turner, the Court again acknowledged the inti-
    mate association protected by this right, holding prisoners
    could not be denied the right to marry because their com-
    mitted relationships satisfied the basic reasons why mar-
    riage is a fundamental right. 
    See 482 U.S., at 95
    –96. The
    right to marry thus dignifies couples who “wish to define
    themselves by their commitment to each other.” 
    Windsor, supra
    , at ___ (slip op., at 14). Marriage responds to the
    universal fear that a lonely person might call out only to
    find no one there. It offers the hope of companionship and
    understanding and assurance that while both still live
    there will be someone to care for the other.
    As this Court held in Lawrence, same-sex couples have
    the same right as opposite-sex couples to enjoy intimate
    association. Lawrence invalidated laws that made same-
    sex intimacy a criminal act. And it acknowledged that
    “[w]hen sexuality finds overt expression in intimate con-
    duct with another person, the conduct can be but one
    element in a personal bond that is more 
    enduring.” 539 U.S., at 567
    . But while Lawrence confirmed a dimension
    of freedom that allows individuals to engage in intimate
    association without criminal liability, it does not follow
    that freedom stops there. Outlaw to outcast may be a step
    forward, but it does not achieve the full promise of liberty.
    A third basis for protecting the right to marry is that it
    safeguards children and families and thus draws meaning
    from related rights of childrearing, procreation, and edu-
    cation. See Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 
    268 U.S. 510
    (1925); 
    Meyer, 262 U.S., at 399
    . The Court has recognized
    these connections by describing the varied rights as a
    unified whole: “[T]he right to ‘marry, establish a home and
    bring up children’ is a central part of the liberty protected
    by the Due Process Clause.” 
    Zablocki, 434 U.S., at 384
                     Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)          15
    Opinion of the Court
    (quoting 
    Meyer, supra, at 399
    ). Under the laws of the
    several States, some of marriage’s protections for children
    and families are material. But marriage also confers more
    profound benefits. By giving recognition and legal struc-
    ture to their parents’ relationship, marriage allows chil-
    dren “to understand the integrity and closeness of their
    own family and its concord with other families in their
    community and in their daily lives.” 
    Windsor, supra
    , at
    ___ (slip op., at 23). Marriage also affords the permanency
    and stability important to children’s best interests. See
    Brief for Scholars of the Constitutional Rights of Children
    as Amici Curiae 22–27.
    As all parties agree, many same-sex couples provide
    loving and nurturing homes to their children, whether
    biological or adopted. And hundreds of thousands of chil-
    dren are presently being raised by such couples. See Brief
    for Gary J. Gates as Amicus Curiae 4. Most States have
    allowed gays and lesbians to adopt, either as individuals
    or as couples, and many adopted and foster children have
    same-sex parents, see 
    id., at 5.
    This provides powerful
    confirmation from the law itself that gays and lesbians can
    create loving, supportive families.
    Excluding same-sex couples from marriage thus con-
    flicts with a central premise of the right to marry. With-
    out the recognition, stability, and predictability marriage
    offers, their children suffer the stigma of knowing their
    families are somehow lesser. They also suffer the signifi-
    cant material costs of being raised by unmarried parents,
    relegated through no fault of their own to a more difficult
    and uncertain family life. The marriage laws at issue here
    thus harm and humiliate the children of same-sex couples.
    See 
    Windsor, supra
    , at ___ (slip op., at 23).
    That is not to say the right to marry is less meaningful
    for those who do not or cannot have children. An ability,
    desire, or promise to procreate is not and has not been a
    prerequisite for a valid marriage in any State. In light of
    16                 OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    precedent protecting the right of a married couple not to
    procreate, it cannot be said the Court or the States have
    conditioned the right to marry on the capacity or commit-
    ment to procreate. The constitutional marriage right has
    many aspects, of which childbearing is only one.
    Fourth and finally, this Court’s cases and the Nation’s
    traditions make clear that marriage is a keystone of our
    social order. Alexis de Tocqueville recognized this truth
    on his travels through the United States almost two cen-
    turies ago:
    “There is certainly no country in the world where the
    tie of marriage is so much respected as in America . . .
    [W]hen the American retires from the turmoil of pub-
    lic life to the bosom of his family, he finds in it the im-
    age of order and of peace . . . . [H]e afterwards carries
    [that image] with him into public affairs.” 1 Democ-
    racy in America 309 (H. Reeve transl., rev. ed. 1990).
    In Maynard v. Hill, 
    125 U.S. 190
    , 211 (1888), the Court
    echoed de Tocqueville, explaining that marriage is “the
    foundation of the family and of society, without which
    there would be neither civilization nor progress.” Mar-
    riage, the Maynard Court said, has long been “ ‘a great
    public institution, giving character to our whole civil
    polity.’ ” 
    Id., at 213.
    This idea has been reiterated even as
    the institution has evolved in substantial ways over time,
    superseding rules related to parental consent, gender, and
    race once thought by many to be essential. See generally
    N. Cott, Public Vows. Marriage remains a building block
    of our national community.
    For that reason, just as a couple vows to support each
    other, so does society pledge to support the couple, offering
    symbolic recognition and material benefits to protect and
    nourish the union. Indeed, while the States are in general
    free to vary the benefits they confer on all married cou-
    ples, they have throughout our history made marriage the
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)          17
    Opinion of the Court
    basis for an expanding list of governmental rights, bene-
    fits, and responsibilities. These aspects of marital status
    include: taxation; inheritance and property rights; rules of
    intestate succession; spousal privilege in the law of evi-
    dence; hospital access; medical decisionmaking authority;
    adoption rights; the rights and benefits of survivors; birth
    and death certificates; professional ethics rules; campaign
    finance restrictions; workers’ compensation benefits;
    health insurance; and child custody, support, and visita-
    tion rules. See Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae
    6–9; Brief for American Bar Association as Amicus Curiae
    8–29. Valid marriage under state law is also a significant
    status for over a thousand provisions of federal law. See
    Windsor, 570 U. S., at ___ – ___ (slip op., at 15–16). The
    States have contributed to the fundamental character of
    the marriage right by placing that institution at the center
    of so many facets of the legal and social order.
    There is no difference between same- and opposite-sex
    couples with respect to this principle. Yet by virtue of
    their exclusion from that institution, same-sex couples are
    denied the constellation of benefits that the States have
    linked to marriage. This harm results in more than just
    material burdens. Same-sex couples are consigned to an
    instability many opposite-sex couples would deem intoler-
    able in their own lives. As the State itself makes marriage
    all the more precious by the significance it attaches to it,
    exclusion from that status has the effect of teaching that
    gays and lesbians are unequal in important respects. It
    demeans gays and lesbians for the State to lock them out
    of a central institution of the Nation’s society. Same-sex
    couples, too, may aspire to the transcendent purposes of
    marriage and seek fulfillment in its highest meaning.
    The limitation of marriage to opposite-sex couples may
    long have seemed natural and just, but its inconsistency
    with the central meaning of the fundamental right to
    marry is now manifest. With that knowledge must come
    18                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    the recognition that laws excluding same-sex couples from
    the marriage right impose stigma and injury of the kind
    prohibited by our basic charter.
    Objecting that this does not reflect an appropriate fram-
    ing of the issue, the respondents refer to Washington v.
    Glucksberg, 
    521 U.S. 702
    , 721 (1997), which called for a
    “ ‘careful description’ ” of fundamental rights. They assert
    the petitioners do not seek to exercise the right to marry
    but rather a new and nonexistent “right to same-sex mar-
    riage.” Brief for Respondent in No. 14–556, p. 8. Glucks-
    berg did insist that liberty under the Due Process Clause
    must be defined in a most circumscribed manner, with
    central reference to specific historical practices. Yet while
    that approach may have been appropriate for the asserted
    right there involved (physician-assisted suicide), it is
    inconsistent with the approach this Court has used in
    discussing other fundamental rights, including marriage
    and intimacy. Loving did not ask about a “right to inter-
    racial marriage”; Turner did not ask about a “right of
    inmates to marry”; and Zablocki did not ask about a “right
    of fathers with unpaid child support duties to marry.”
    Rather, each case inquired about the right to marry in its
    comprehensive sense, asking if there was a sufficient
    justification for excluding the relevant class from the
    right. See also 
    Glucksberg, 521 U.S., at 752
    –773 (Souter,
    J., concurring in judgment); 
    id., at 789–792
    (BREYER, J.,
    concurring in judgments).
    That principle applies here. If rights were defined by
    who exercised them in the past, then received practices
    could serve as their own continued justification and new
    groups could not invoke rights once denied. This Court
    has rejected that approach, both with respect to the right
    to marry and the rights of gays and lesbians. See 
    Loving 388 U.S., at 12
    ; 
    Lawrence, 539 U.S., at 566
    –567.
    The right to marry is fundamental as a matter of history
    and tradition, but rights come not from ancient sources
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           19
    Opinion of the Court
    alone. They rise, too, from a better informed understand-
    ing of how constitutional imperatives define a liberty that
    remains urgent in our own era. Many who deem same-sex
    marriage to be wrong reach that conclusion based on
    decent and honorable religious or philosophical premises,
    and neither they nor their beliefs are disparaged here.
    But when that sincere, personal opposition becomes en-
    acted law and public policy, the necessary consequence is to
    put the imprimatur of the State itself on an exclusion that
    soon demeans or stigmatizes those whose own liberty is
    then denied. Under the Constitution, same-sex couples
    seek in marriage the same legal treatment as opposite-sex
    couples, and it would disparage their choices and diminish
    their personhood to deny them this right.
    The right of same-sex couples to marry that is part of
    the liberty promised by the Fourteenth Amendment is
    derived, too, from that Amendment’s guarantee of the
    equal protection of the laws. The Due Process Clause and
    the Equal Protection Clause are connected in a profound
    way, though they set forth independent principles. Rights
    implicit in liberty and rights secured by equal protection
    may rest on different precepts and are not always co-
    extensive, yet in some instances each may be instructive
    as to the meaning and reach of the other. In any particu-
    lar case one Clause may be thought to capture the essence
    of the right in a more accurate and comprehensive way,
    even as the two Clauses may converge in the identification
    and definition of the right. See M. L. 
    B., 519 U.S., at 120
    –
    121; 
    id., at 128–129
    (KENNEDY, J., concurring in judg-
    ment); Bearden v. Georgia, 
    461 U.S. 660
    , 665 (1983). This
    interrelation of the two principles furthers our under-
    standing of what freedom is and must become.
    The Court’s cases touching upon the right to marry
    reflect this dynamic. In Loving the Court invalidated a
    prohibition on interracial marriage under both the Equal
    Protection Clause and the Due Process Clause. The Court
    20                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    first declared the prohibition invalid because of its un-
    equal treatment of interracial couples. It stated: “There
    can be no doubt that restricting the freedom to marry
    solely because of racial classifications violates the central
    meaning of the Equal Protection 
    Clause.” 388 U.S., at 12
    .
    With this link to equal protection the Court proceeded to
    hold the prohibition offended central precepts of liberty:
    “To deny this fundamental freedom on so unsupportable a
    basis as the racial classifications embodied in these stat-
    utes, classifications so directly subversive of the principle
    of equality at the heart of the Fourteenth Amendment, is
    surely to deprive all the State’s citizens of liberty without
    due process of law.” 
    Ibid. The reasons why
    marriage is a
    fundamental right became more clear and compelling from
    a full awareness and understanding of the hurt that re-
    sulted from laws barring interracial unions.
    The synergy between the two protections is illustrated
    further in Zablocki. There the Court invoked the Equal
    Protection Clause as its basis for invalidating the chal-
    lenged law, which, as already noted, barred fathers who
    were behind on child-support payments from marrying
    without judicial approval. The equal protection analysis
    depended in central part on the Court’s holding that the
    law burdened a right “of fundamental 
    importance.” 434 U.S., at 383
    . It was the essential nature of the marriage
    right, discussed at length in Zablocki, see 
    id., at 383–387,
    that made apparent the law’s incompatibility with re-
    quirements of equality. Each concept—liberty and equal
    protection—leads to a stronger understanding of the other.
    Indeed, in interpreting the Equal Protection Clause, the
    Court has recognized that new insights and societal un-
    derstandings can reveal unjustified inequality within our
    most fundamental institutions that once passed unnoticed
    and unchallenged. To take but one period, this occurred
    with respect to marriage in the 1970’s and 1980’s. Not-
    withstanding the gradual erosion of the doctrine of cover-
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           21
    Opinion of the Court
    ture, 
    see supra, at 6
    , invidious sex-based classifications in
    marriage remained common through the mid-20th cen-
    tury. See App. to Brief for Appellant in Reed v. Reed, O. T.
    1971, No. 70–4, pp. 69–88 (an extensive reference to laws
    extant as of 1971 treating women as unequal to men in
    marriage). These classifications denied the equal dignity
    of men and women. One State’s law, for example, pro-
    vided in 1971 that “the husband is the head of the family
    and the wife is subject to him; her legal civil existence is
    merged in the husband, except so far as the law recognizes
    her separately, either for her own protection, or for her
    benefit.” Ga. Code Ann. §53–501 (1935). Responding to a
    new awareness, the Court invoked equal protection prin-
    ciples to invalidate laws imposing sex-based inequality on
    marriage. See, e.g., Kirchberg v. Feenstra, 
    450 U.S. 455
    (1981); Wengler v. Druggists Mut. Ins. Co., 
    446 U.S. 142
    (1980); Califano v. Westcott, 
    443 U.S. 76
    (1979); Orr v.
    Orr, 
    440 U.S. 268
    (1979); Califano v. Goldfarb, 
    430 U.S. 199
    (1977) (plurality opinion); Weinberger v. Wiesenfeld,
    
    420 U.S. 636
    (1975); Frontiero v. Richardson, 
    411 U.S. 677
    (1973). Like Loving and Zablocki, these precedents
    show the Equal Protection Clause can help to identify
    and correct inequalities in the institution of marriage,
    vindicating precepts of liberty and equality under the
    Constitution.
    Other cases confirm this relation between liberty and
    equality. In M. L. B. v. S. L. J., the Court invalidated
    under due process and equal protection principles a stat-
    ute requiring indigent mothers to pay a fee in order to
    appeal the termination of their parental rights. 
    See 519 U.S., at 119
    –124. In Eisenstadt v. Baird, the Court in-
    voked both principles to invalidate a prohibition on the
    distribution of contraceptives to unmarried persons but
    not married persons. 
    See 405 U.S., at 446
    –454. And in
    Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson, the Court invali-
    dated under both principles a law that allowed steriliza-
    22                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    tion of habitual criminals. 
    See 316 U.S., at 538
    –543.
    In Lawrence the Court acknowledged the interlocking
    nature of these constitutional safeguards in the context of
    the legal treatment of gays and lesbians. 
    See 539 U.S., at 575
    . Although Lawrence elaborated its holding under the
    Due Process Clause, it acknowledged, and sought to rem-
    edy, the continuing inequality that resulted from laws
    making intimacy in the lives of gays and lesbians a crime
    against the State. See 
    ibid. Lawrence therefore drew
    upon principles of liberty and equality to define and pro-
    tect the rights of gays and lesbians, holding the State
    “cannot demean their existence or control their destiny by
    making their private sexual conduct a crime.” 
    Id., at 578.
       This dynamic also applies to same-sex marriage. It is
    now clear that the challenged laws burden the liberty of
    same-sex couples, and it must be further acknowledged
    that they abridge central precepts of equality. Here the
    marriage laws enforced by the respondents are in essence
    unequal: same-sex couples are denied all the benefits
    afforded to opposite-sex couples and are barred from exer-
    cising a fundamental right. Especially against a long
    history of disapproval of their relationships, this denial to
    same-sex couples of the right to marry works a grave and
    continuing harm. The imposition of this disability on gays
    and lesbians serves to disrespect and subordinate them.
    And the Equal Protection Clause, like the Due Process
    Clause, prohibits this unjustified infringement of the
    fundamental right to marry. See, e.g., 
    Zablocki, supra, at 383
    –388; 
    Skinner, 316 U.S., at 541
    .
    These considerations lead to the conclusion that the
    right to marry is a fundamental right inherent in the
    liberty of the person, and under the Due Process and
    Equal Protection Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment
    couples of the same-sex may not be deprived of that right
    and that liberty. The Court now holds that same-sex
    couples may exercise the fundamental right to marry. No
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)          23
    Opinion of the Court
    longer may this liberty be denied to them. Baker v. Nelson
    must be and now is overruled, and the State laws chal-
    lenged by Petitioners in these cases are now held invalid
    to the extent they exclude same-sex couples from civil
    marriage on the same terms and conditions as opposite-
    sex couples.
    IV
    There may be an initial inclination in these cases to
    proceed with caution—to await further legislation, litiga-
    tion, and debate. The respondents warn there has been
    insufficient democratic discourse before deciding an issue
    so basic as the definition of marriage. In its ruling on the
    cases now before this Court, the majority opinion for the
    Court of Appeals made a cogent argument that it would be
    appropriate for the respondents’ States to await further
    public discussion and political measures before licensing
    same-sex marriages. See 
    DeBoer, 772 F.3d, at 409
    .
    Yet there has been far more deliberation than this
    argument acknowledges. There have been referenda,
    legislative debates, and grassroots campaigns, as well as
    countless studies, papers, books, and other popular and
    scholarly writings. There has been extensive litigation in
    state and federal courts. See Appendix A, infra. Judicial
    opinions addressing the issue have been informed by the
    contentions of parties and counsel, which, in turn, reflect
    the more general, societal discussion of same-sex marriage
    and its meaning that has occurred over the past decades.
    As more than 100 amici make clear in their filings, many
    of the central institutions in American life—state and local
    governments, the military, large and small businesses,
    labor unions, religious organizations, law enforcement,
    civic groups, professional organizations, and universities—
    have devoted substantial attention to the question. This
    has led to an enhanced understanding of the issue—an
    understanding reflected in the arguments now presented
    24                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    for resolution as a matter of constitutional law.
    Of course, the Constitution contemplates that democ-
    racy is the appropriate process for change, so long as that
    process does not abridge fundamental rights. Last Term,
    a plurality of this Court reaffirmed the importance of the
    democratic principle in Schuette v. BAMN, 572 U. S. ___
    (2014), noting the “right of citizens to debate so they can
    learn and decide and then, through the political process,
    act in concert to try to shape the course of their own
    times.” Id., at ___ – ___ (slip op., at 15–16). Indeed, it is
    most often through democracy that liberty is preserved
    and protected in our lives. But as Schuette also said,
    “[t]he freedom secured by the Constitution consists, in one
    of its essential dimensions, of the right of the individual
    not to be injured by the unlawful exercise of governmental
    power.” Id., at ___ (slip op., at 15). Thus, when the rights
    of persons are violated, “the Constitution requires redress
    by the courts,” notwithstanding the more general value of
    democratic decisionmaking. Id., at ___ (slip op., at 17).
    This holds true even when protecting individual rights
    affects issues of the utmost importance and sensitivity.
    The dynamic of our constitutional system is that indi-
    viduals need not await legislative action before asserting a
    fundamental right. The Nation’s courts are open to in-
    jured individuals who come to them to vindicate their own
    direct, personal stake in our basic charter. An individual
    can invoke a right to constitutional protection when he or
    she is harmed, even if the broader public disagrees and
    even if the legislature refuses to act. The idea of the
    Constitution “was to withdraw certain subjects from the
    vicissitudes of political controversy, to place them beyond
    the reach of majorities and officials and to establish them
    as legal principles to be applied by the courts.” West Vir-
    ginia Bd. of Ed. v. Barnette, 
    319 U.S. 624
    , 638 (1943).
    This is why “fundamental rights may not be submitted to
    a vote; they depend on the outcome of no elections.” 
    Ibid. Cite as: 576
    U. S. ____ (2015)           25
    Opinion of the Court
    It is of no moment whether advocates of same-sex mar-
    riage now enjoy or lack momentum in the democratic
    process. The issue before the Court here is the legal ques-
    tion whether the Constitution protects the right of same-
    sex couples to marry.
    This is not the first time the Court has been asked to
    adopt a cautious approach to recognizing and protecting
    fundamental rights. In Bowers, a bare majority upheld a
    law criminalizing same-sex intimacy. 
    See 478 U.S., at 186
    , 190–195. That approach might have been viewed as
    a cautious endorsement of the democratic process, which
    had only just begun to consider the rights of gays and
    lesbians. Yet, in effect, Bowers upheld state action that
    denied gays and lesbians a fundamental right and caused
    them pain and humiliation. As evidenced by the dissents
    in that case, the facts and principles necessary to a correct
    holding were known to the Bowers Court. See 
    id., at 199
    (Blackmun, J., joined by Brennan, Marshall, and Stevens,
    JJ., dissenting); 
    id., at 214
    (Stevens, J., joined by Brennan
    and Marshall, JJ., dissenting). That is why Lawrence held
    Bowers was “not correct when it was 
    decided.” 539 U.S., at 578
    . Although Bowers was eventually repudiated in
    Lawrence, men and women were harmed in the interim,
    and the substantial effects of these injuries no doubt
    lingered long after Bowers was overruled. Dignitary
    wounds cannot always be healed with the stroke of a pen.
    A ruling against same-sex couples would have the same
    effect—and, like Bowers, would be unjustified under the
    Fourteenth Amendment. The petitioners’ stories make
    clear the urgency of the issue they present to the Court.
    James Obergefell now asks whether Ohio can erase his
    marriage to John Arthur for all time. April DeBoer and
    Jayne Rowse now ask whether Michigan may continue to
    deny them the certainty and stability all mothers desire to
    protect their children, and for them and their children the
    childhood years will pass all too soon. Ijpe DeKoe and
    26                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    Thomas Kostura now ask whether Tennessee can deny to
    one who has served this Nation the basic dignity of recog-
    nizing his New York marriage. Properly presented with
    the petitioners’ cases, the Court has a duty to address
    these claims and answer these questions.
    Indeed, faced with a disagreement among the Courts of
    Appeals—a disagreement that caused impermissible
    geographic variation in the meaning of federal law—the
    Court granted review to determine whether same-sex
    couples may exercise the right to marry. Were the Court
    to uphold the challenged laws as constitutional, it would
    teach the Nation that these laws are in accord with our
    society’s most basic compact. Were the Court to stay its
    hand to allow slower, case-by-case determination of the
    required availability of specific public benefits to same-sex
    couples, it still would deny gays and lesbians many rights
    and responsibilities intertwined with marriage.
    The respondents also argue allowing same-sex couples
    to wed will harm marriage as an institution by leading to
    fewer opposite-sex marriages. This may occur, the re-
    spondents contend, because licensing same-sex marriage
    severs the connection between natural procreation and
    marriage. That argument, however, rests on a counterin-
    tuitive view of opposite-sex couple’s decisionmaking pro-
    cesses regarding marriage and parenthood. Decisions
    about whether to marry and raise children are based on
    many personal, romantic, and practical considerations;
    and it is unrealistic to conclude that an opposite-sex cou-
    ple would choose not to marry simply because same-sex
    couples may do so. See Kitchen v. Herbert, 
    755 F.3d 1193
    ,
    1223 (CA10 2014) (“[I]t is wholly illogical to believe that
    state recognition of the love and commitment between
    same-sex couples will alter the most intimate and personal
    decisions of opposite-sex couples”). The respondents have
    not shown a foundation for the conclusion that allowing
    same-sex marriage will cause the harmful outcomes they
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           27
    Opinion of the Court
    describe. Indeed, with respect to this asserted basis for
    excluding same-sex couples from the right to marry, it is
    appropriate to observe these cases involve only the rights
    of two consenting adults whose marriages would pose no
    risk of harm to themselves or third parties.
    Finally, it must be emphasized that religions, and those
    who adhere to religious doctrines, may continue to advo-
    cate with utmost, sincere conviction that, by divine pre-
    cepts, same-sex marriage should not be condoned. The
    First Amendment ensures that religious organizations and
    persons are given proper protection as they seek to teach
    the principles that are so fulfilling and so central to their
    lives and faiths, and to their own deep aspirations to
    continue the family structure they have long revered. The
    same is true of those who oppose same-sex marriage for
    other reasons. In turn, those who believe allowing same-
    sex marriage is proper or indeed essential, whether as a
    matter of religious conviction or secular belief, may engage
    those who disagree with their view in an open and search-
    ing debate. The Constitution, however, does not permit
    the State to bar same-sex couples from marriage on the
    same terms as accorded to couples of the opposite sex.
    V
    These cases also present the question whether the Con-
    stitution requires States to recognize same-sex marriages
    validly performed out of State. As made clear by the case
    of Obergefell and Arthur, and by that of DeKoe and Kos-
    tura, the recognition bans inflict substantial and continuing
    harm on same-sex couples.
    Being married in one State but having that valid mar-
    riage denied in another is one of “the most perplexing and
    distressing complication[s]” in the law of domestic rela-
    tions. Williams v. North Carolina, 
    317 U.S. 287
    , 299
    (1942) (internal quotation marks omitted). Leaving the
    current state of affairs in place would maintain and pro-
    28                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion of the Court
    mote instability and uncertainty. For some couples, even
    an ordinary drive into a neighboring State to visit family
    or friends risks causing severe hardship in the event of a
    spouse’s hospitalization while across state lines. In light
    of the fact that many States already allow same-sex mar-
    riage—and hundreds of thousands of these marriages
    already have occurred—the disruption caused by the
    recognition bans is significant and ever-growing.
    As counsel for the respondents acknowledged at argu-
    ment, if States are required by the Constitution to issue
    marriage licenses to same-sex couples, the justifications
    for refusing to recognize those marriages performed else-
    where are undermined. See Tr. of Oral Arg. on Question
    2, p. 44. The Court, in this decision, holds same-sex cou-
    ples may exercise the fundamental right to marry in all
    States. It follows that the Court also must hold—and it
    now does hold—that there is no lawful basis for a State to
    refuse to recognize a lawful same-sex marriage performed
    in another State on the ground of its same-sex character.
    *    *    *
    No union is more profound than marriage, for it embod-
    ies the highest ideals of love, fidelity, devotion, sacrifice,
    and family. In forming a marital union, two people be-
    come something greater than once they were. As some of
    the petitioners in these cases demonstrate, marriage
    embodies a love that may endure even past death. It
    would misunderstand these men and women to say they
    disrespect the idea of marriage. Their plea is that they do
    respect it, respect it so deeply that they seek to find its
    fulfillment for themselves. Their hope is not to be con-
    demned to live in loneliness, excluded from one of civiliza-
    tion’s oldest institutions. They ask for equal dignity in the
    eyes of the law. The Constitution grants them that right.
    The judgment of the Court of Appeals for the Sixth
    Circuit is reversed.
    It is so ordered.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)         29
    Opinion
    Appendix       of the Court
    A to opinion  of the Court
    APPENDICES
    A
    State and Federal Judicial Decisions
    Addressing Same-Sex Marriage
    United States Courts of Appeals Decisions
    Adams v. Howerton, 
    673 F.2d 1036
    (CA9 1982)
    Smelt v. County of Orange, 
    447 F.3d 673
    (CA9 2006)
    Citizens for Equal Protection v. Bruning, 
    455 F.3d 859
    (CA8 2006)
    Windsor v. United States, 
    699 F.3d 169
    (CA2 2012)
    Massachusetts v. Department of Health and Human
    Services, 
    682 F.3d 1
    (CA1 2012)
    Perry v. Brown, 
    671 F.3d 1052
    (CA9 2012)
    Latta v. Otter, 
    771 F.3d 456
    (CA9 2014)
    Baskin v. Bogan, 
    766 F.3d 648
    (CA7 2014)
    Bishop v. Smith, 
    760 F.3d 1070
    (CA10 2014)
    Bostic v. Schaefer, 
    760 F.3d 352
    (CA4 2014)
    Kitchen v. Herbert, 
    755 F.3d 1193
    (CA10 2014)
    DeBoer v. Snyder, 
    772 F.3d 388
    (CA6 2014)
    Latta v. Otter, 
    779 F.3d 902
    (CA9 2015) (O’Scannlain,
    J., dissenting from the denial of rehearing en banc)
    United States District Court Decisions
    Adams v. Howerton, 
    486 F. Supp. 1119
    (CD Cal. 1980)
    Citizens for Equal Protection, Inc. v. Bruning, 
    290 F. Supp. 2d 1004
    (Neb. 2003)
    Citizens for Equal Protection v. Bruning, 
    368 F. Supp. 2d
    980 (Neb. 2005)
    Wilson v. Ake, 
    354 F. Supp. 2d 1298
    (MD Fla. 2005)
    Smelt v. County of Orange, 
    374 F. Supp. 2d 861
    (CD Cal.
    2005)
    Bishop v. Oklahoma ex rel. Edmondson, 
    447 F. Supp. 2d 1239
    (ND Okla. 2006)
    30               OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion
    Appendix       of the Court
    A to opinion  of the Court
    Massachusetts v. Department of Health and Human
    Services, 
    698 F. Supp. 2d 234
    (Mass. 2010)
    Gill v. Office of Personnel Management, 
    699 F. Supp. 2d 374
    (Mass. 2010)
    Perry v. Schwarzenegger, 
    704 F. Supp. 2d 921
    (ND Cal.
    2010)
    Dragovich v. Department of Treasury, 
    764 F. Supp. 2d 1178
    (ND Cal. 2011)
    Golinski v. Office of Personnel Management, 
    824 F. Supp. 2d 968
    (ND Cal. 2012)
    Dragovich v. Department of Treasury, 
    872 F. Supp. 2d 944
    (ND Cal. 2012)
    Windsor v. United States, 
    833 F. Supp. 2d 394
    (SDNY
    2012)
    Pedersen v. Office of Personnel Management, 
    881 F. Supp. 2d 294
    (Conn. 2012)
    Jackson v. Abercrombie, 
    884 F. Supp. 2d 1065
    (Haw.
    2012)
    Sevcik v. Sandoval, 
    911 F. Supp. 2d 996
    (Nev. 2012)
    Merritt v. Attorney General, 
    2013 WL 6044329
    (MD La.,
    Nov. 14, 2013)
    Gray v. Orr, 
    4 F. Supp. 3d 984
    (ND Ill. 2013)
    Lee v. Orr, 
    2013 WL 6490577
    (ND Ill., Dec. 10, 2013)
    Kitchen v. Herbert, 
    961 F. Supp. 2d 1181
    (Utah 2013)
    Obergefell v. Wymyslo, 
    962 F. Supp. 2d 968
    (SD Ohio
    2013)
    Bishop v. United States ex rel. Holder, 
    962 F. Supp. 2d 1252
    (ND Okla. 2014)
    Bourke v. Beshear, 
    996 F. Supp. 2d 542
    (WD Ky. 2014)
    Lee v. Orr, 
    2014 WL 683680
    (ND Ill., Feb. 21, 2014)
    Bostic v. Rainey, 
    970 F. Supp. 2d 456
    (ED Va. 2014)
    De Leon v. Perry, 
    975 F. Supp. 2d 632
    (WD Tex. 2014)
    Tanco v. Haslam, 
    7 F. Supp. 3d 759
    (MD Tenn. 2014)
    DeBoer v. Snyder, 
    973 F. Supp. 2d 757
    (ED Mich. 2014)
    Henry v. Himes, 
    14 F. Supp. 3d 1036
    (SD Ohio 2014)
    Latta v. Otter, 
    19 F. Supp. 3d 1054
    (Idaho 2014)
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)         31
    Opinion
    Appendix       of the Court
    A to opinion  of the Court
    Geiger v. Kitzhaber, 
    994 F. Supp. 2d 1128
    (Ore. 2014)
    Evans v. Utah, 
    21 F. Supp. 3d 1192
    (Utah 2014)
    Whitewood v. Wolf, 
    992 F. Supp. 2d 410
    (MD Pa. 2014)
    Wolf v. Walker, 
    986 F. Supp. 2d 982
    (WD Wis. 2014)
    Baskin v. Bogan, 
    12 F. Supp. 3d 1144
    (SD Ind. 2014)
    Love v. Beshear, 
    989 F. Supp. 2d 536
    (WD Ky. 2014)
    Burns v. Hickenlooper, 
    2014 WL 3634834
    (Colo., July
    23, 2014)
    Bowling v. Pence, 
    39 F. Supp. 3d 1025
    (SD Ind. 2014)
    Brenner v. Scott, 
    999 F. Supp. 2d 1278
    (ND Fla. 2014)
    Robicheaux v. Caldwell, 
    2 F. Supp. 3d 910
    (ED La. 2014)
    General Synod of the United Church of Christ v. Resing-
    er, 
    12 F. Supp. 3d 790
    (WDNC 2014)
    Hamby v. Parnell, 
    56 F. Supp. 3d 1056
    (Alaska 2014)
    Fisher-Borne v. Smith, 
    14 F. Supp. 3d 695
    (MDNC 2014)
    Majors v. Horne, 
    14 F. Supp. 3d 1313
    (Ariz. 2014)
    Connolly v. Jeanes, ___ F. Supp. 3d ___, 
    2014 WL 5320642
    (Ariz., Oct. 17, 2014)
    Guzzo v. Mead, 
    2014 WL 5317797
    (Wyo., Oct. 17, 2014)
    Conde-Vidal v. Garcia-Padilla, 
    54 F. Supp. 3d 157
    (PR
    2014)
    Marie v. Moser, ___ F. Supp. 3d ___, 
    2014 WL 5598128
    (Kan., Nov. 4, 2014)
    Lawson v. Kelly, 
    58 F. Supp. 3d 923
    (WD Mo. 2014)
    McGee v. Cole, ___ F. Supp. 3d ___, 
    2014 WL 5802665
    (SD W. Va., Nov. 7, 2014)
    Condon v. Haley, 
    21 F. Supp. 3d 572
    (S. C. 2014)
    Bradacs v. Haley, 
    58 F. Supp. 3d 514
    (S. C. 2014)
    Rolando v. Fox, 
    23 F. Supp. 3d 1227
    (Mont. 2014)
    Jernigan v. Crane, ___ F. Supp. 3d ___, 
    2014 WL 6685391
    (ED Ark., Nov. 25, 2014)
    Campaign for Southern Equality v. Bryant, ___ F. Supp.
    3d ___, 
    2014 WL 6680570
    (SD Miss., Nov. 25, 2014)
    Inniss v. Aderhold, ___ F. Supp. 3d ___, 
    2015 WL 300593
    (ND Ga., Jan. 8, 2015)
    32               OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion
    Appendix       of the Court
    A to opinion  of the Court
    Rosenbrahn v. Daugaard, 
    61 F. Supp. 3d 862
    (S. D.,
    2015)
    Caspar v. Snyder, ___ F. Supp. 3d ___, 
    2015 WL 224741
    (ED Mich., Jan. 15, 2015)
    Searcey v. Strange, 2015 U. S. Dist. LEXIS 7776 (SD
    Ala., Jan. 23, 2015)
    Strawser v. Strange, 
    44 F. Supp. 3d 1206
    (SD Ala. 2015)
    Waters v. Ricketts, 
    48 F. Supp. 3d 1271
    (Neb. 2015)
    State Highest Court Decisions
    Baker v. Nelson, 
    291 Minn. 310
    , 
    191 N.W.2d 185
    (1971)
    Jones v. Hallahan, 
    501 S.W.2d 588
    (Ky. 1973)
    Baehr v. Lewin, 
    74 Haw. 530
    , 
    852 P.2d 44
    (1993)
    Dean v. District of Columbia, 
    653 A.2d 307
    (D. C. 1995)
    Baker v. State, 
    170 Vt. 194
    , 
    744 A.2d 864
    (1999)
    Brause v. State, 
    21 P.3d 357
    (Alaska 2001) (ripeness)
    Goodridge v. Department of Public Health, 
    440 Mass. 309
    , 
    798 N.E.2d 941
    (2003)
    In re Opinions of the Justices to the Senate, 
    440 Mass. 1201
    , 
    802 N.E.2d 565
    (2004)
    Li v. State, 
    338 Or. 376
    , 
    110 P.3d 91
    (2005)
    Cote-Whitacre v. Department of Public Health,446 Mass.
    350, 
    844 N.E.2d 623
    (2006)
    Lewis v. Harris, 188 N. J. 415, 
    908 A.2d 196
    (2006)
    Andersen v. King County, 
    158 Wash. 2d 1
    , 
    138 P.3d 963
    (2006)
    Hernandez v. Robles, 
    7 N.Y. 3d
    338, 
    855 N.E.2d 1
    (2006)
    Conaway v. Deane, 
    401 Md. 219
    , 
    932 A.2d 571
    (2007)
    In re Marriage Cases, 
    43 Cal. 4th 757
    , 
    183 P.3d 384
    (2008)
    Kerrigan v. Commissioner of Public Health, 
    289 Conn. 135
    , 
    957 A.2d 407
    (2008)
    Strauss v. Horton, 
    46 Cal. 4th 364
    , 
    207 P.3d 48
    (2009)
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)        33
    Opinion
    Appendix       of the Court
    A to opinion  of the Court
    Varnum v. Brien, 
    763 N.W.2d 862
    (Iowa 2009)
    Griego v. Oliver, 2014–NMSC–003, ___ N. M. ___, 
    316 P.3d 865
    (2013)
    Garden State Equality v. Dow, 216 N. J. 314, 
    79 A.3d 1036
    (2013)
    Ex parte State ex rel. Alabama Policy Institute, ___ So.
    3d ___, 
    2015 WL 892752
    (Ala., Mar. 3, 2015)
    34               OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    Opinion
    Appendix       of the Court
    B to opinion  of the Court
    B
    State Legislation and Judicial Decisions
    Legalizing Same-Sex Marriage
    Legislation
    Del. Code Ann., Tit. 13, §129 (Cum. Supp. 2014)
    D. C. Act No. 18–248, 
    57 Dall. C
    . Reg. 27 (2010)
    Haw. Rev. Stat. §572 –1 (2006) and 2013 Cum. Supp.)
    Ill. Pub. Act No. 98–597
    Me. Rev. Stat. Ann., Tit. 19, §650–A (Cum. Supp. 2014)
    2012 Md. Laws p. 9
    2013 Minn Laws p. 404
    2009 N. H. Laws p. 60
    2011 N. Y Laws p. 749
    
    2013 Rawle I
    . Laws p. 7
    2009 Vt. Acts & Resolves p. 33
    2012 Wash. Sess. Laws p. 199
    Judicial Decisions
    Goodridge v. Department of Public Health, 
    440 Mass. 309
    , 
    798 N.E.2d 941
    (2003)
    Kerrigan v. Commissioner of Public Health, 
    289 Conn. 135
    , 
    957 A.2d 407
    (2008)
    Varnum v. Brien, 
    763 N.W.2d 862
    (Iowa 2009)
    Griego v. Oliver, 2014–NMSC–003, ___ N. M. ___, 
    316 P.3d 865
    (2013)
    Garden State Equality v. Dow, 216 N. J. 314, 
    79 A.3d 1036
    (2013)
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)        1
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    Nos. 14–556, 14-562, 14-571 and 14–574
    _________________
    JAMES OBERGEFELL, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–556               v.
    RICHARD HODGES, DIRECTOR, OHIO
    DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH, ET AL.;
    VALERIA TANCO, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–562                  v.
    BILL HASLAM, GOVERNOR OF
    TENNESSEE, ET AL.;
    APRIL DEBOER, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–571                 v.
    RICK SNYDER, GOVERNOR OF MICHIGAN,
    ET AL.; AND
    GREGORY BOURKE, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–574              v.
    STEVE BESHEAR, GOVERNOR OF
    KENTUCKY
    ON WRITS OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    [June 26, 2015]
    CHIEF JUSTICE ROBERTS, with whom JUSTICE SCALIA
    and JUSTICE THOMAS join, dissenting.
    Petitioners make strong arguments rooted in social
    policy and considerations of fairness. They contend that
    same-sex couples should be allowed to affirm their love
    and commitment through marriage, just like opposite-sex
    couples. That position has undeniable appeal; over the
    2                 OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    past six years, voters and legislators in eleven States and
    the District of Columbia have revised their laws to allow
    marriage between two people of the same sex.
    But this Court is not a legislature. Whether same-sex
    marriage is a good idea should be of no concern to us.
    Under the Constitution, judges have power to say what
    the law is, not what it should be. The people who ratified
    the Constitution authorized courts to exercise “neither
    force nor will but merely judgment.” The Federalist No.
    78, p. 465 (C. Rossiter ed. 1961) (A. Hamilton) (capitaliza-
    tion altered).
    Although the policy arguments for extending marriage
    to same-sex couples may be compelling, the legal argu-
    ments for requiring such an extension are not. The fun-
    damental right to marry does not include a right to make
    a State change its definition of marriage. And a State’s
    decision to maintain the meaning of marriage that has
    persisted in every culture throughout human history can
    hardly be called irrational. In short, our Constitution does
    not enact any one theory of marriage. The people of a
    State are free to expand marriage to include same-sex
    couples, or to retain the historic definition.
    Today, however, the Court takes the extraordinary step
    of ordering every State to license and recognize same-sex
    marriage. Many people will rejoice at this decision, and I
    begrudge none their celebration. But for those who believe
    in a government of laws, not of men, the majority’s ap-
    proach is deeply disheartening. Supporters of same-sex
    marriage have achieved considerable success persuading
    their fellow citizens—through the democratic process—to
    adopt their view. That ends today. Five lawyers have
    closed the debate and enacted their own vision of marriage
    as a matter of constitutional law. Stealing this issue from
    the people will for many cast a cloud over same-sex mar-
    riage, making a dramatic social change that much more
    difficult to accept.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)            3
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    The majority’s decision is an act of will, not legal judg-
    ment. The right it announces has no basis in the Consti-
    tution or this Court’s precedent. The majority expressly
    disclaims judicial “caution” and omits even a pretense of
    humility, openly relying on its desire to remake society
    according to its own “new insight” into the “nature of
    injustice.” Ante, at 11, 23. As a result, the Court invali-
    dates the marriage laws of more than half the States and
    orders the transformation of a social institution that has
    formed the basis of human society for millennia, for the
    Kalahari Bushmen and the Han Chinese, the Carthagin-
    ians and the Aztecs. Just who do we think we are?
    It can be tempting for judges to confuse our own prefer-
    ences with the requirements of the law. But as this Court
    has been reminded throughout our history, the Constitu-
    tion “is made for people of fundamentally differing views.”
    Lochner v. New York, 
    198 U.S. 45
    , 76 (1905) (Holmes, J.,
    dissenting). Accordingly, “courts are not concerned with
    the wisdom or policy of legislation.” 
    Id., at 69
    (Harlan, J.,
    dissenting). The majority today neglects that restrained
    conception of the judicial role. It seizes for itself a ques-
    tion the Constitution leaves to the people, at a time when
    the people are engaged in a vibrant debate on that ques-
    tion. And it answers that question based not on neutral
    principles of constitutional law, but on its own “under-
    standing of what freedom is and must become.” Ante, at
    19. I have no choice but to dissent.
    Understand well what this dissent is about: It is not
    about whether, in my judgment, the institution of mar-
    riage should be changed to include same-sex couples. It is
    instead about whether, in our democratic republic, that
    decision should rest with the people acting through their
    elected representatives, or with five lawyers who happen
    to hold commissions authorizing them to resolve legal
    disputes according to law. The Constitution leaves no
    doubt about the answer.
    4                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    I
    Petitioners and their amici base their arguments on the
    “right to marry” and the imperative of “marriage equality.”
    There is no serious dispute that, under our precedents, the
    Constitution protects a right to marry and requires States
    to apply their marriage laws equally. The real question in
    these cases is what constitutes “marriage,” or—more
    precisely—who decides what constitutes “marriage”?
    The majority largely ignores these questions, relegating
    ages of human experience with marriage to a paragraph or
    two. Even if history and precedent are not “the end” of
    these cases, ante, at 4, I would not “sweep away what has
    so long been settled” without showing greater respect for
    all that preceded us. Town of Greece v. Galloway, 572
    U. S. ___, ___ (2014) (slip op., at 8).
    A
    As the majority acknowledges, marriage “has existed for
    millennia and across civilizations.” Ante, at 3. For all
    those millennia, across all those civilizations, “marriage”
    referred to only one relationship: the union of a man and a
    woman. See ante, at 4; Tr. of Oral Arg. on Question 1,
    p. 12 (petitioners conceding that they are not aware of any
    society that permitted same-sex marriage before 2001). As
    the Court explained two Terms ago, “until recent years,
    . . . marriage between a man and a woman no doubt had
    been thought of by most people as essential to the very
    definition of that term and to its role and function
    throughout the history of civilization.” United States v.
    Windsor, 570 U. S. ___, ___ (2013) (slip op., at 13).
    This universal definition of marriage as the union of a
    man and a woman is no historical coincidence. Marriage
    did not come about as a result of a political movement,
    discovery, disease, war, religious doctrine, or any other
    moving force of world history—and certainly not as a
    result of a prehistoric decision to exclude gays and lesbi-
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           5
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    ans. It arose in the nature of things to meet a vital need:
    ensuring that children are conceived by a mother and
    father committed to raising them in the stable conditions
    of a lifelong relationship. See G. Quale, A History of
    Marriage Systems 2 (1988); cf. M. Cicero, De Officiis 57
    (W. Miller transl. 1913) (“For since the reproductive in-
    stinct is by nature’s gift the common possession of all
    living creatures, the first bond of union is that between
    husband and wife; the next, that between parents and
    children; then we find one home, with everything in
    common.”).
    The premises supporting this concept of marriage are so
    fundamental that they rarely require articulation. The
    human race must procreate to survive. Procreation occurs
    through sexual relations between a man and a woman.
    When sexual relations result in the conception of a child,
    that child’s prospects are generally better if the mother
    and father stay together rather than going their separate
    ways. Therefore, for the good of children and society,
    sexual relations that can lead to procreation should occur
    only between a man and a woman committed to a lasting
    bond.
    Society has recognized that bond as marriage. And by
    bestowing a respected status and material benefits on
    married couples, society encourages men and women to
    conduct sexual relations within marriage rather than
    without. As one prominent scholar put it, “Marriage is a
    socially arranged solution for the problem of getting people
    to stay together and care for children that the mere desire
    for children, and the sex that makes children possible,
    does not solve.” J. Q. Wilson, The Marriage Problem 41
    (2002).
    This singular understanding of marriage has prevailed
    in the United States throughout our history. The majority
    accepts that at “the time of the Nation’s founding [mar-
    riage] was understood to be a voluntary contract between
    6                  OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    a man and a woman.” Ante, at 6. Early Americans drew
    heavily on legal scholars like William Blackstone, who
    regarded marriage between “husband and wife” as one of
    the “great relations in private life,” and philosophers like
    John Locke, who described marriage as “a voluntary com-
    pact between man and woman” centered on “its chief end,
    procreation” and the “nourishment and support” of chil-
    dren. 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries *410; J. Locke,
    Second Treatise of Civil Government §§78–79, p. 39 (J.
    Gough ed. 1947). To those who drafted and ratified the
    Constitution, this conception of marriage and family “was
    a given: its structure, its stability, roles, and values ac-
    cepted by all.” Forte, The Framers’ Idea of Marriage and
    Family, in The Meaning of Marriage 100, 102 (R. George
    & J. Elshtain eds. 2006).
    The Constitution itself says nothing about marriage,
    and the Framers thereby entrusted the States with “[t]he
    whole subject of the domestic relations of husband and
    wife.” Windsor, 570 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 17) (quoting
    In re Burrus, 
    136 U.S. 586
    , 593–594 (1890)). There is no
    dispute that every State at the founding—and every State
    throughout our history until a dozen years ago—defined
    marriage in the traditional, biologically rooted way. The
    four States in these cases are typical. Their laws, before
    and after statehood, have treated marriage as the union of
    a man and a woman. See DeBoer v. Snyder, 
    772 F.3d 388
    ,
    396–399 (CA6 2014). Even when state laws did not spec-
    ify this definition expressly, no one doubted what they
    meant. See Jones v. Hallahan, 
    501 S.W.2d 588
    , 589 (Ky.
    App. 1973). The meaning of “marriage” went without
    saying.
    Of course, many did say it. In his first American dic-
    tionary, Noah Webster defined marriage as “the legal
    union of a man and woman for life,” which served the
    purposes of “preventing the promiscuous intercourse of the
    sexes, . . . promoting domestic felicity, and . . . securing the
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           7
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    maintenance and education of children.” 1 An American
    Dictionary of the English Language (1828). An influential
    19th-century treatise defined marriage as “a civil status,
    existing in one man and one woman legally united for life
    for those civil and social purposes which are based in the
    distinction of sex.” J. Bishop, Commentaries on the Law of
    Marriage and Divorce 25 (1852). The first edition of
    Black’s Law Dictionary defined marriage as “the civil
    status of one man and one woman united in law for life.”
    Black’s Law Dictionary 756 (1891) (emphasis deleted).
    The dictionary maintained essentially that same definition
    for the next century.
    This Court’s precedents have repeatedly described
    marriage in ways that are consistent only with its tradi-
    tional meaning. Early cases on the subject referred to
    marriage as “the union for life of one man and one wom-
    an,” Murphy v. Ramsey, 
    114 U.S. 15
    , 45 (1885), which
    forms “the foundation of the family and of society, without
    which there would be neither civilization nor progress,”
    Maynard v. Hill, 
    125 U.S. 190
    , 211 (1888). We later
    described marriage as “fundamental to our very existence
    and survival,” an understanding that necessarily implies a
    procreative component. Loving v. Virginia, 
    388 U.S. 1
    , 12
    (1967); see Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson, 
    316 U.S. 535
    , 541 (1942). More recent cases have directly
    connected the right to marry with the “right to procreate.”
    Zablocki v. Redhail, 
    434 U.S. 374
    , 386 (1978).
    As the majority notes, some aspects of marriage have
    changed over time. Arranged marriages have largely
    given way to pairings based on romantic love. States have
    replaced coverture, the doctrine by which a married man
    and woman became a single legal entity, with laws that
    respect each participant’s separate status. Racial re-
    strictions on marriage, which “arose as an incident to
    slavery” to promote “White Supremacy,” were repealed by
    many States and ultimately struck down by this Court.
    8                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    
    Loving, 388 U.S., at 6
    –7.
    The majority observes that these developments “were
    not mere superficial changes” in marriage, but rather
    “worked deep transformations in its structure.” Ante, at
    6–7. They did not, however, work any transformation in
    the core structure of marriage as the union between a man
    and a woman. If you had asked a person on the street how
    marriage was defined, no one would ever have said, “Mar-
    riage is the union of a man and a woman, where the woman
    is subject to coverture.” The majority may be right that
    the “history of marriage is one of both continuity and
    change,” but the core meaning of marriage has endured.
    Ante, at 6.
    B
    Shortly after this Court struck down racial restrictions
    on marriage in Loving, a gay couple in Minnesota sought a
    marriage license. They argued that the Constitution
    required States to allow marriage between people of the
    same sex for the same reasons that it requires States to
    allow marriage between people of different races. The
    Minnesota Supreme Court rejected their analogy to Lov-
    ing, and this Court summarily dismissed an appeal.
    Baker v. Nelson, 
    409 U.S. 810
    (1972).
    In the decades after Baker, greater numbers of gays and
    lesbians began living openly, and many expressed a desire
    to have their relationships recognized as marriages. Over
    time, more people came to see marriage in a way that
    could be extended to such couples. Until recently, this
    new view of marriage remained a minority position. After
    the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court in 2003 inter-
    preted its State Constitution to require recognition of
    same-sex marriage, many States—including the four at
    issue here—enacted constitutional amendments formally
    adopting the longstanding definition of marriage.
    Over the last few years, public opinion on marriage has
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           9
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    shifted rapidly. In 2009, the legislatures of Vermont, New
    Hampshire, and the District of Columbia became the first
    in the Nation to enact laws that revised the definition of
    marriage to include same-sex couples, while also providing
    accommodations for religious believers. In 2011, the New
    York Legislature enacted a similar law. In 2012, voters in
    Maine did the same, reversing the result of a referendum
    just three years earlier in which they had upheld the
    traditional definition of marriage.
    In all, voters and legislators in eleven States and the
    District of Columbia have changed their definitions of
    marriage to include same-sex couples. The highest courts
    of five States have decreed that same result under their
    own Constitutions. The remainder of the States retain the
    traditional definition of marriage.
    Petitioners brought lawsuits contending that the Due
    Process and Equal Protection Clauses of the Fourteenth
    Amendment compel their States to license and recognize
    marriages between same-sex couples. In a carefully rea-
    soned decision, the Court of Appeals acknowledged the
    democratic “momentum” in favor of “expand[ing] the
    definition of marriage to include gay couples,” but con-
    cluded that petitioners had not made “the case for consti-
    tutionalizing the definition of marriage and for removing
    the issue from the place it has been since the founding: in
    the hands of state 
    voters.” 772 F.3d, at 396
    , 403. That
    decision interpreted the Constitution correctly, and I
    would affirm.
    II
    Petitioners first contend that the marriage laws of their
    States violate the Due Process Clause. The Solicitor Gen-
    eral of the United States, appearing in support of petition-
    ers, expressly disowned that position before this Court.
    See Tr. of Oral Arg. on Question 1, at 38–39. The majority
    nevertheless resolves these cases for petitioners based
    10                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    almost entirely on the Due Process Clause.
    The majority purports to identify four “principles and
    traditions” in this Court’s due process precedents that
    support a fundamental right for same-sex couples to
    marry. Ante, at 12. In reality, however, the majority’s ap-
    proach has no basis in principle or tradition, except for the
    unprincipled tradition of judicial policymaking that char-
    acterized discredited decisions such as Lochner v. New
    York, 
    198 U.S. 45
    . Stripped of its shiny rhetorical gloss,
    the majority’s argument is that the Due Process Clause
    gives same-sex couples a fundamental right to marry
    because it will be good for them and for society. If I were a
    legislator, I would certainly consider that view as a matter
    of social policy. But as a judge, I find the majority’s posi-
    tion indefensible as a matter of constitutional law.
    A
    Petitioners’ “fundamental right” claim falls into the
    most sensitive category of constitutional adjudication.
    Petitioners do not contend that their States’ marriage laws
    violate an enumerated constitutional right, such as the
    freedom of speech protected by the First Amendment.
    There is, after all, no “Companionship and Understand-
    ing” or “Nobility and Dignity” Clause in the Constitution.
    See ante, at 3, 14. They argue instead that the laws vio-
    late a right implied by the Fourteenth Amendment’s
    requirement that “liberty” may not be deprived without
    “due process of law.”
    This Court has interpreted the Due Process Clause to
    include a “substantive” component that protects certain
    liberty interests against state deprivation “no matter what
    process is provided.” Reno v. Flores, 
    507 U.S. 292
    , 302
    (1993). The theory is that some liberties are “so rooted in
    the traditions and conscience of our people as to be ranked
    as fundamental,” and therefore cannot be deprived with-
    out compelling justification. Snyder v. Massachusetts, 291
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           11
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    U. S. 97, 105 (1934).
    Allowing unelected federal judges to select which un-
    enumerated rights rank as “fundamental”—and to strike
    down state laws on the basis of that determination—raises
    obvious concerns about the judicial role. Our precedents
    have accordingly insisted that judges “exercise the utmost
    care” in identifying implied fundamental rights, “lest the
    liberty protected by the Due Process Clause be subtly
    transformed into the policy preferences of the Members of
    this Court.” Washington v. Glucksberg, 
    521 U.S. 702
    , 720
    (1997) (internal quotation marks omitted); see Kennedy,
    Unenumerated Rights and the Dictates of Judicial Re-
    straint 13 (1986) (Address at Stanford) (“One can conclude
    that certain essential, or fundamental, rights should exist
    in any just society. It does not follow that each of those
    essential rights is one that we as judges can enforce under
    the written Constitution. The Due Process Clause is not a
    guarantee of every right that should inhere in an ideal
    system.”).
    The need for restraint in administering the strong medi-
    cine of substantive due process is a lesson this Court has
    learned the hard way. The Court first applied substantive
    due process to strike down a statute in Dred Scott v. Sand-
    ford, 
    19 How. 393
    (1857). There the Court invalidated the
    Missouri Compromise on the ground that legislation re-
    stricting the institution of slavery violated the implied
    rights of slaveholders. The Court relied on its own concep-
    tion of liberty and property in doing so. It asserted that
    “an act of Congress which deprives a citizen of the United
    States of his liberty or property, merely because he came
    himself or brought his property into a particular Territory
    of the United States . . . could hardly be dignified with the
    name of due process of law.” 
    Id., at 450.
    In a dissent that
    has outlasted the majority opinion, Justice Curtis ex-
    plained that when the “fixed rules which govern the inter-
    pretation of laws [are] abandoned, and the theoretical
    12                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    opinions of individuals are allowed to control” the Consti-
    tution’s meaning, “we have no longer a Constitution; we
    are under the government of individual men, who for the
    time being have power to declare what the Constitution is,
    according to their own views of what it ought to mean.”
    
    Id., at 621.
       Dred Scott’s holding was overruled on the battlefields of
    the Civil War and by constitutional amendment after
    Appomattox, but its approach to the Due Process Clause
    reappeared. In a series of early 20th-century cases, most
    prominently Lochner v. New York, this Court invalidated
    state statutes that presented “meddlesome interferences
    with the rights of the individual,” and “undue interference
    with liberty of person and freedom of 
    contract.” 198 U.S., at 60
    , 61. In Lochner itself, the Court struck down a New
    York law setting maximum hours for bakery employees,
    because there was “in our judgment, no reasonable foun-
    dation for holding this to be necessary or appropriate as a
    health law.” 
    Id., at 58.
       The dissenting Justices in Lochner explained that the
    New York law could be viewed as a reasonable response to
    legislative concern about the health of bakery employees,
    an issue on which there was at least “room for debate and
    for an honest difference of opinion.” 
    Id., at 72
    (opinion of
    Harlan, J.). The majority’s contrary conclusion required
    adopting as constitutional law “an economic theory which
    a large part of the country does not entertain.” 
    Id., at 75
    (opinion of Holmes, J.). As Justice Holmes memorably put
    it, “The Fourteenth Amendment does not enact Mr. Her-
    bert Spencer’s Social Statics,” a leading work on the phi-
    losophy of Social Darwinism. 
    Ibid. The Constitution “is
    not intended to embody a particular economic theory . . . .
    It is made for people of fundamentally differing views, and
    the accident of our finding certain opinions natural and
    familiar or novel and even shocking ought not to conclude
    our judgment upon the question whether statutes embody-
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           13
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    ing them conflict with the Constitution.” 
    Id., at 75
    –76.
    In the decades after Lochner, the Court struck down
    nearly 200 laws as violations of individual liberty, often
    over strong dissents contending that “[t]he criterion of
    constitutionality is not whether we believe the law to be
    for the public good.” Adkins v. Children’s Hospital of
    D. C., 
    261 U.S. 525
    , 570 (1923) (opinion of Holmes, J.). By
    empowering judges to elevate their own policy judgments
    to the status of constitutionally protected “liberty,” the
    Lochner line of cases left “no alternative to regarding the
    court as a . . . legislative chamber.” L. Hand, The Bill of
    Rights 42 (1958).
    Eventually, the Court recognized its error and vowed
    not to repeat it. “The doctrine that . . . due process author-
    izes courts to hold laws unconstitutional when they believe
    the legislature has acted unwisely,” we later explained,
    “has long since been discarded. We have returned to the
    original constitutional proposition that courts do not
    substitute their social and economic beliefs for the judg-
    ment of legislative bodies, who are elected to pass laws.”
    Ferguson v. Skrupa, 
    372 U.S. 726
    , 730 (1963); see Day-
    Brite Lighting, Inc. v. Missouri, 
    342 U.S. 421
    , 423 (1952)
    (“we do not sit as a super-legislature to weigh the wisdom
    of legislation”). Thus, it has become an accepted rule that
    the Court will not hold laws unconstitutional simply be-
    cause we find them “unwise, improvident, or out of har-
    mony with a particular school of thought.” Williamson v.
    Lee Optical of Okla., Inc., 
    348 U.S. 483
    , 488 (1955).
    Rejecting Lochner does not require disavowing the
    doctrine of implied fundamental rights, and this Court has
    not done so. But to avoid repeating Lochner’s error of
    converting personal preferences into constitutional man-
    dates, our modern substantive due process cases have
    stressed the need for “judicial self-restraint.” Collins v.
    Harker Heights, 
    503 U.S. 115
    , 125 (1992). Our precedents
    have required that implied fundamental rights be “objec-
    14                 OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    tively, deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradi-
    tion,” and “implicit in the concept of ordered liberty, such
    that neither liberty nor justice would exist if they were
    sacrificed.” 
    Glucksberg, 521 U.S., at 720
    –721 (internal
    quotation marks omitted).
    Although the Court articulated the importance of his-
    tory and tradition to the fundamental rights inquiry most
    precisely in Glucksberg, many other cases both before and
    after have adopted the same approach. See, e.g., District
    Attorney’s Office for Third Judicial Dist. v. Osborne, 
    557 U.S. 52
    , 72 (2009); 
    Flores, 507 U.S., at 303
    ; United States
    v. Salerno, 
    481 U.S. 739
    , 751 (1987); Moore v. East Cleve-
    land, 
    431 U.S. 494
    , 503 (1977) (plurality opinion); see also
    
    id., at 544
    (White, J., dissenting) (“The Judiciary, includ-
    ing this Court, is the most vulnerable and comes nearest
    to illegitimacy when it deals with judge-made constitu-
    tional law having little or no cognizable roots in the lan-
    guage or even the design of the Constitution.”); Troxel v.
    Granville, 
    530 U.S. 57
    , 96–101 (2000) (KENNEDY, J.,
    dissenting) (consulting “ ‘[o]ur Nation’s history, legal tradi-
    tions, and practices’ ” and concluding that “[w]e owe it to
    the Nation’s domestic relations legal structure . . . to
    proceed with caution” (quoting 
    Glucksberg, 521 U.S., at 721
    )).
    Proper reliance on history and tradition of course re-
    quires looking beyond the individual law being challenged,
    so that every restriction on liberty does not supply its own
    constitutional justification. The Court is right about that.
    Ante, at 18. But given the few “guideposts for responsible
    decisionmaking in this unchartered area,” 
    Collins, 503 U.S., at 125
    , “an approach grounded in history imposes
    limits on the judiciary that are more meaningful than any
    based on [an] abstract formula,” 
    Moore, 431 U.S., at 504
    ,
    n. 12 (plurality opinion). Expanding a right suddenly and
    dramatically is likely to require tearing it up from its
    roots. Even a sincere profession of “discipline” in identify-
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)            15
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    ing fundamental rights, ante, at 10–11, does not provide a
    meaningful constraint on a judge, for “what he is really
    likely to be ‘discovering,’ whether or not he is fully aware
    of it, are his own values,” J. Ely, Democracy and Distrust
    44 (1980). The only way to ensure restraint in this deli-
    cate enterprise is “continual insistence upon respect for
    the teachings of history, solid recognition of the basic
    values that underlie our society, and wise appreciation of
    the great roles [of] the doctrines of federalism and separa-
    tion of powers.” Griswold v. Connecticut, 
    381 U.S. 479
    ,
    501 (1965) (Harlan, J., concurring in judgment).
    B
    The majority acknowledges none of this doctrinal back-
    ground, and it is easy to see why: Its aggressive applica-
    tion of substantive due process breaks sharply with dec-
    ades of precedent and returns the Court to the
    unprincipled approach of Lochner.
    1
    The majority’s driving themes are that marriage is
    desirable and petitioners desire it. The opinion describes
    the “transcendent importance” of marriage and repeatedly
    insists that petitioners do not seek to “demean,” “devalue,”
    “denigrate,” or “disrespect” the institution. Ante, at 3, 4, 6,
    28. Nobody disputes those points. Indeed, the compelling
    personal accounts of petitioners and others like them are
    likely a primary reason why many Americans have
    changed their minds about whether same-sex couples
    should be allowed to marry. As a matter of constitutional
    law, however, the sincerity of petitioners’ wishes is not
    relevant.
    When the majority turns to the law, it relies primarily
    on precedents discussing the fundamental “right to marry.”
    Turner v. Safley, 
    482 U.S. 78
    , 95 (1987); 
    Zablocki, 434 U.S., at 383
    ; see 
    Loving, 388 U.S., at 12
    . These cases
    16                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    do not hold, of course, that anyone who wants to get mar-
    ried has a constitutional right to do so. They instead
    require a State to justify barriers to marriage as that
    institution has always been understood. In Loving, the
    Court held that racial restrictions on the right to marry
    lacked a compelling justification. In Zablocki, restrictions
    based on child support debts did not suffice. In Turner,
    restrictions based on status as a prisoner were deemed
    impermissible.
    None of the laws at issue in those cases purported to
    change the core definition of marriage as the union of a
    man and a woman. The laws challenged in Zablocki and
    Turner did not define marriage as “the union of a man and
    a woman, where neither party owes child support or is in
    prison.” Nor did the interracial marriage ban at issue in
    Loving define marriage as “the union of a man and a
    woman of the same race.” See Tragen, Comment, Statu-
    tory Prohibitions Against Interracial Marriage, 
    32 Cal. L
    . Rev. 269 (1944) (“at common law there was no ban on
    interracial marriage”); post, at 11–12, n. 5 (THOMAS, J.,
    dissenting). Removing racial barriers to marriage there-
    fore did not change what a marriage was any more than
    integrating schools changed what a school was. As the
    majority admits, the institution of “marriage” discussed in
    every one of these cases “presumed a relationship involv-
    ing opposite-sex partners.” Ante, at 11.
    In short, the “right to marry” cases stand for the im-
    portant but limited proposition that particular restrictions
    on access to marriage as traditionally defined violate due
    process. These precedents say nothing at all about a right
    to make a State change its definition of marriage, which is
    the right petitioners actually seek here. See Windsor, 570
    U. S., at ___ (ALITO, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 8) (“What
    Windsor and the United States seek . . . is not the protec-
    tion of a deeply rooted right but the recognition of a very
    new right.”). Neither petitioners nor the majority cites a
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           17
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    single case or other legal source providing any basis for
    such a constitutional right. None exists, and that is
    enough to foreclose their claim.
    2
    The majority suggests that “there are other, more in-
    structive precedents” informing the right to marry. Ante,
    at 12. Although not entirely clear, this reference seems to
    correspond to a line of cases discussing an implied funda-
    mental “right of privacy.” 
    Griswold, 381 U.S., at 486
    . In
    the first of those cases, the Court invalidated a criminal
    law that banned the use of contraceptives. 
    Id., at 485–
    486. The Court stressed the invasive nature of the ban,
    which threatened the intrusion of “the police to search the
    sacred precincts of marital bedrooms.” 
    Id., at 485.
    In the
    Court’s view, such laws infringed the right to privacy in its
    most basic sense: the “right to be let alone.” Eisenstadt v.
    Baird, 
    405 U.S. 438
    , 453–454, n. 10 (1972) (internal quo-
    tation marks omitted); see Olmstead v. United States, 
    277 U.S. 438
    , 478 (1928) (Brandeis, J., dissenting).
    The Court also invoked the right to privacy in Lawrence
    v. Texas, 
    539 U.S. 558
    (2003), which struck down a Texas
    statute criminalizing homosexual sodomy.           Lawrence
    relied on the position that criminal sodomy laws, like bans
    on contraceptives, invaded privacy by inviting “unwar-
    ranted government intrusions” that “touc[h] upon the
    most private human conduct, sexual behavior . . . in the
    most private of places, the home.” 
    Id., at 562,
    567.
    Neither Lawrence nor any other precedent in the pri-
    vacy line of cases supports the right that petitioners assert
    here. Unlike criminal laws banning contraceptives and
    sodomy, the marriage laws at issue here involve no gov-
    ernment intrusion. They create no crime and impose no
    punishment. Same-sex couples remain free to live together,
    to engage in intimate conduct, and to raise their fami-
    lies as they see fit. No one is “condemned to live in loneli-
    18                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    ness” by the laws challenged in these cases—no one. Ante,
    at 28. At the same time, the laws in no way interfere with
    the “right to be let alone.”
    The majority also relies on Justice Harlan’s influential
    dissenting opinion in Poe v. Ullman, 
    367 U.S. 497
    (1961).
    As the majority recounts, that opinion states that “[d]ue
    process has not been reduced to any formula.” 
    Id., at 542.
    But far from conferring the broad interpretive discretion
    that the majority discerns, Justice Harlan’s opinion makes
    clear that courts implying fundamental rights are not
    “free to roam where unguided speculation might take
    them.” 
    Ibid. They must instead
    have “regard to what
    history teaches” and exercise not only “judgment” but
    “restraint.” 
    Ibid. Of particular relevance,
    Justice Harlan
    explained that “laws regarding marriage which provide
    both when the sexual powers may be used and the legal
    and societal context in which children are born and
    brought up . . . form a pattern so deeply pressed into the
    substance of our social life that any Constitutional doc-
    trine in this area must build upon that basis.” 
    Id., at 546.
       In sum, the privacy cases provide no support for the
    majority’s position, because petitioners do not seek pri-
    vacy. Quite the opposite, they seek public recognition of
    their relationships, along with corresponding government
    benefits. Our cases have consistently refused to allow
    litigants to convert the shield provided by constitutional
    liberties into a sword to demand positive entitlements
    from the State. See DeShaney v. Winnebago County Dept.
    of Social Servs., 
    489 U.S. 189
    , 196 (1989); San Antonio
    Independent School Dist. v. Rodriguez, 
    411 U.S. 1
    , 35–37
    (1973); post, at 9–13 (THOMAS, J., dissenting). Thus,
    although the right to privacy recognized by our precedents
    certainly plays a role in protecting the intimate conduct of
    same-sex couples, it provides no affirmative right to rede-
    fine marriage and no basis for striking down the laws at
    issue here.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           19
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    3
    Perhaps recognizing how little support it can derive
    from precedent, the majority goes out of its way to jettison
    the “careful” approach to implied fundamental rights
    taken by this Court in Glucksberg. Ante, at 18 
    (quoting 521 U.S., at 721
    ). It is revealing that the majority’s posi-
    tion requires it to effectively overrule Glucksberg, the
    leading modern case setting the bounds of substantive due
    process. At least this part of the majority opinion has the
    virtue of candor. Nobody could rightly accuse the majority
    of taking a careful approach.
    Ultimately, only one precedent offers any support for
    the majority’s methodology: Lochner v. New York, 
    198 U.S. 45
    . The majority opens its opinion by announcing
    petitioners’ right to “define and express their identity.”
    Ante, at 1–2. The majority later explains that “the right to
    personal choice regarding marriage is inherent in the
    concept of individual autonomy.” Ante, at 12. This free-
    wheeling notion of individual autonomy echoes nothing so
    much as “the general right of an individual to be free in his
    person and in his power to contract in relation to his own
    labor.” 
    Lochner, 198 U.S., at 58
    (emphasis added).
    To be fair, the majority does not suggest that its indi-
    vidual autonomy right is entirely unconstrained. The
    constraints it sets are precisely those that accord with its
    own “reasoned judgment,” informed by its “new insight”
    into the “nature of injustice,” which was invisible to all
    who came before but has become clear “as we learn [the]
    meaning” of liberty. Ante, at 10, 11. The truth is that
    today’s decision rests on nothing more than the majority’s
    own conviction that same-sex couples should be allowed to
    marry because they want to, and that “it would disparage
    their choices and diminish their personhood to deny them
    this right.” Ante, at 19. Whatever force that belief may
    have as a matter of moral philosophy, it has no more basis
    in the Constitution than did the naked policy preferences
    20                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    adopted in Lochner. 
    See 198 U.S., at 61
    (“We do not
    believe in the soundness of the views which uphold this
    law,” which “is an illegal interference with the rights of
    individuals . . . to make contracts regarding labor upon
    such terms as they may think best”).
    The majority recognizes that today’s cases do not mark
    “the first time the Court has been asked to adopt a cau-
    tious approach to recognizing and protecting fundamental
    rights.” Ante, at 25. On that much, we agree. The Court
    was “asked”—and it agreed—to “adopt a cautious ap-
    proach” to implying fundamental rights after the debacle
    of the Lochner era. Today, the majority casts caution
    aside and revives the grave errors of that period.
    One immediate question invited by the majority’s posi-
    tion is whether States may retain the definition of mar-
    riage as a union of two people. Cf. Brown v. Buhman, 
    947 F. Supp. 2d 1170
    (Utah 2013), appeal pending, No. 14-
    4117 (CA10). Although the majority randomly inserts the
    adjective “two” in various places, it offers no reason at all
    why the two-person element of the core definition of mar-
    riage may be preserved while the man-woman element
    may not. Indeed, from the standpoint of history and tradi-
    tion, a leap from opposite-sex marriage to same-sex mar-
    riage is much greater than one from a two-person union to
    plural unions, which have deep roots in some cultures
    around the world. If the majority is willing to take the big
    leap, it is hard to see how it can say no to the shorter one.
    It is striking how much of the majority’s reasoning
    would apply with equal force to the claim of a fundamental
    right to plural marriage. If “[t]here is dignity in the bond
    between two men or two women who seek to marry and in
    their autonomy to make such profound choices,” ante, at
    13, why would there be any less dignity in the bond be-
    tween three people who, in exercising their autonomy,
    seek to make the profound choice to marry? If a same-sex
    couple has the constitutional right to marry because their
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           21
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    children would otherwise “suffer the stigma of knowing
    their families are somehow lesser,” ante, at 15, why
    wouldn’t the same reasoning apply to a family of three or
    more persons raising children? If not having the oppor-
    tunity to marry “serves to disrespect and subordinate” gay
    and lesbian couples, why wouldn’t the same “imposition of
    this disability,” ante, at 22, serve to disrespect and subor-
    dinate people who find fulfillment in polyamorous rela-
    tionships? See Bennett, Polyamory: The Next Sexual
    Revolution? Newsweek, July 28, 2009 (estimating 500,000
    polyamorous families in the United States); Li, Married
    Lesbian “Throuple” Expecting First Child, N. Y. Post, Apr.
    23, 2014; Otter, Three May Not Be a Crowd: The Case for
    a Constitutional Right to Plural Marriage, 64 Emory L. J.
    1977 (2015).
    I do not mean to equate marriage between same-sex
    couples with plural marriages in all respects. There may
    well be relevant differences that compel different legal
    analysis. But if there are, petitioners have not pointed to
    any. When asked about a plural marital union at oral
    argument, petitioners asserted that a State “doesn’t have
    such an institution.” Tr. of Oral Arg. on Question 2, p. 6.
    But that is exactly the point: the States at issue here do
    not have an institution of same-sex marriage, either.
    4
    Near the end of its opinion, the majority offers perhaps
    the clearest insight into its decision. Expanding marriage
    to include same-sex couples, the majority insists, would
    “pose no risk of harm to themselves or third parties.”
    Ante, at 27. This argument again echoes Lochner, which
    relied on its assessment that “we think that a law like the
    one before us involves neither the safety, the morals nor
    the welfare of the public, and that the interest of the
    public is not in the slightest degree affected by such an
    
    act.” 198 U.S., at 57
    .
    22                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    Then and now, this assertion of the “harm principle”
    sounds more in philosophy than law. The elevation of the
    fullest individual self-realization over the constraints that
    society has expressed in law may or may not be attractive
    moral philosophy. But a Justice’s commission does not
    confer any special moral, philosophical, or social insight
    sufficient to justify imposing those perceptions on fellow
    citizens under the pretense of “due process.” There is
    indeed a process due the people on issues of this sort—the
    democratic process. Respecting that understanding re-
    quires the Court to be guided by law, not any particular
    school of social thought. As Judge Henry Friendly once
    put it, echoing Justice Holmes’s dissent in Lochner, the
    Fourteenth Amendment does not enact John Stuart Mill’s
    On Liberty any more than it enacts Herbert Spencer’s
    Social Statics. See Randolph, Before Roe v. Wade: Judge
    Friendly’s Draft Abortion Opinion, 29 Harv. J. L. & Pub.
    Pol’y 1035, 1036–1037, 1058 (2006). And it certainly does
    not enact any one concept of marriage.
    The majority’s understanding of due process lays out a
    tantalizing vision of the future for Members of this Court:
    If an unvarying social institution enduring over all of
    recorded history cannot inhibit judicial policymaking,
    what can? But this approach is dangerous for the rule of
    law. The purpose of insisting that implied fundamental
    rights have roots in the history and tradition of our people
    is to ensure that when unelected judges strike down dem-
    ocratically enacted laws, they do so based on something
    more than their own beliefs. The Court today not only
    overlooks our country’s entire history and tradition but
    actively repudiates it, preferring to live only in the heady
    days of the here and now. I agree with the majority that
    the “nature of injustice is that we may not always see it in
    our own times.” Ante, at 11. As petitioners put it, “times
    can blind.” Tr. of Oral Arg. on Question 1, at 9, 10. But to
    blind yourself to history is both prideful and unwise. “The
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)             23
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    past is never dead. It’s not even past.”           W. Faulkner,
    Requiem for a Nun 92 (1951).
    III
    In addition to their due process argument, petitioners
    contend that the Equal Protection Clause requires their
    States to license and recognize same-sex marriages. The
    majority does not seriously engage with this claim. Its
    discussion is, quite frankly, difficult to follow. The central
    point seems to be that there is a “synergy between” the
    Equal Protection Clause and the Due Process Clause, and
    that some precedents relying on one Clause have also
    relied on the other. Ante, at 20. Absent from this portion
    of the opinion, however, is anything resembling our usual
    framework for deciding equal protection cases. It is case-
    book doctrine that the “modern Supreme Court’s treat-
    ment of equal protection claims has used a means-ends
    methodology in which judges ask whether the classifica-
    tion the government is using is sufficiently related to the
    goals it is pursuing.” G. Stone, L. Seidman, C. Sunstein,
    M. Tushnet, & P. Karlan, Constitutional Law 453 (7th ed.
    2013). The majority’s approach today is different:
    “Rights implicit in liberty and rights secured by equal
    protection may rest on different precepts and are not
    always co-extensive, yet in some instances each may
    be instructive as to the meaning and reach of the
    other. In any particular case one Clause may be
    thought to capture the essence of the right in a more
    accurate and comprehensive way, even as the two
    Clauses may converge in the identification and defini-
    tion of the right.” Ante, at 19.
    The majority goes on to assert in conclusory fashion that
    the Equal Protection Clause provides an alternative basis
    for its holding. Ante, at 22. Yet the majority fails to pro-
    vide even a single sentence explaining how the Equal
    24                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    Protection Clause supplies independent weight for its
    position, nor does it attempt to justify its gratuitous viola-
    tion of the canon against unnecessarily resolving constitu-
    tional questions. See Northwest Austin Municipal Util.
    Dist. No. One v. Holder, 
    557 U.S. 193
    , 197 (2009). In any
    event, the marriage laws at issue here do not violate the
    Equal Protection Clause, because distinguishing between
    opposite-sex and same-sex couples is rationally related to
    the States’ “legitimate state interest” in “preserving the
    traditional institution of marriage.” 
    Lawrence, 539 U.S., at 585
    (O’Connor, J., concurring in judgment).
    It is important to note with precision which laws peti-
    tioners have challenged. Although they discuss some of
    the ancillary legal benefits that accompany marriage, such
    as hospital visitation rights and recognition of spousal
    status on official documents, petitioners’ lawsuits target
    the laws defining marriage generally rather than those
    allocating benefits specifically.     The equal protection
    analysis might be different, in my view, if we were con-
    fronted with a more focused challenge to the denial of
    certain tangible benefits. Of course, those more selective
    claims will not arise now that the Court has taken the
    drastic step of requiring every State to license and recog-
    nize marriages between same-sex couples.
    IV
    The legitimacy of this Court ultimately rests “upon the
    respect accorded to its judgments.” Republican Party of
    Minn. v. White, 
    536 U.S. 765
    , 793 (2002) (KENNEDY, J.,
    concurring). That respect flows from the perception—and
    reality—that we exercise humility and restraint in decid-
    ing cases according to the Constitution and law. The role
    of the Court envisioned by the majority today, however, is
    anything but humble or restrained. Over and over, the
    majority exalts the role of the judiciary in delivering social
    change. In the majority’s telling, it is the courts, not the
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)          25
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    people, who are responsible for making “new dimensions of
    freedom . . . apparent to new generations,” for providing
    “formal discourse” on social issues, and for ensuring “neu-
    tral discussions, without scornful or disparaging commen-
    tary.” Ante, at 7–9.
    Nowhere is the majority’s extravagant conception of
    judicial supremacy more evident than in its description—
    and dismissal—of the public debate regarding same-sex
    marriage. Yes, the majority concedes, on one side are
    thousands of years of human history in every society
    known to have populated the planet. But on the other
    side, there has been “extensive litigation,” “many thought-
    ful District Court decisions,” “countless studies, papers,
    books, and other popular and scholarly writings,” and
    “more than 100” amicus briefs in these cases alone. Ante,
    at 9, 10, 23. What would be the point of allowing the
    democratic process to go on? It is high time for the Court
    to decide the meaning of marriage, based on five lawyers’
    “better informed understanding” of “a liberty that remains
    urgent in our own era.” Ante, at 19. The answer is surely
    there in one of those amicus briefs or studies.
    Those who founded our country would not recognize the
    majority’s conception of the judicial role. They after all
    risked their lives and fortunes for the precious right to
    govern themselves. They would never have imagined
    yielding that right on a question of social policy to unac-
    countable and unelected judges. And they certainly would
    not have been satisfied by a system empowering judges to
    override policy judgments so long as they do so after “a
    quite extensive discussion.” Ante, at 8. In our democracy,
    debate about the content of the law is not an exhaustion
    requirement to be checked off before courts can impose
    their will. “Surely the Constitution does not put either the
    legislative branch or the executive branch in the position
    of a television quiz show contestant so that when a given
    period of time has elapsed and a problem remains unre-
    26                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    solved by them, the federal judiciary may press a buzzer
    and take its turn at fashioning a solution.” Rehnquist,
    The Notion of a Living Constitution, 54 Texas L. Rev. 693,
    700 (1976). As a plurality of this Court explained just last
    year, “It is demeaning to the democratic process to pre-
    sume that voters are not capable of deciding an issue of
    this sensitivity on decent and rational grounds.” Schuette
    v. BAMN, 572 U. S. ___, ___ –___ (2014) (slip op., at 16–
    17).
    The Court’s accumulation of power does not occur in a
    vacuum. It comes at the expense of the people. And they
    know it. Here and abroad, people are in the midst of a
    serious and thoughtful public debate on the issue of same-
    sex marriage. They see voters carefully considering same-
    sex marriage, casting ballots in favor or opposed, and
    sometimes changing their minds. They see political lead-
    ers similarly reexamining their positions, and either re-
    versing course or explaining adherence to old convictions
    confirmed anew. They see governments and businesses
    modifying policies and practices with respect to same-sex
    couples, and participating actively in the civic discourse.
    They see countries overseas democratically accepting
    profound social change, or declining to do so. This delib-
    erative process is making people take seriously questions
    that they may not have even regarded as questions before.
    When decisions are reached through democratic means,
    some people will inevitably be disappointed with the re-
    sults. But those whose views do not prevail at least know
    that they have had their say, and accordingly are—in the
    tradition of our political culture—reconciled to the result
    of a fair and honest debate. In addition, they can gear up
    to raise the issue later, hoping to persuade enough on the
    winning side to think again. “That is exactly how our
    system of government is supposed to work.” Post, at 2–3
    (SCALIA, J., dissenting).
    But today the Court puts a stop to all that. By deciding
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           27
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    this question under the Constitution, the Court removes it
    from the realm of democratic decision. There will be
    consequences to shutting down the political process on an
    issue of such profound public significance. Closing debate
    tends to close minds. People denied a voice are less likely
    to accept the ruling of a court on an issue that does not
    seem to be the sort of thing courts usually decide. As a
    thoughtful commentator observed about another issue,
    “The political process was moving . . . , not swiftly enough
    for advocates of quick, complete change, but majoritarian
    institutions were listening and acting. Heavy-handed
    judicial intervention was difficult to justify and appears to
    have provoked, not resolved, conflict.” Ginsburg, Some
    Thoughts on Autonomy and Equality in Relation to Roe v.
    Wade, 63 N. C. L. Rev. 375, 385–386 (1985) (footnote
    omitted). Indeed, however heartened the proponents of
    same-sex marriage might be on this day, it is worth ac-
    knowledging what they have lost, and lost forever: the
    opportunity to win the true acceptance that comes from
    persuading their fellow citizens of the justice of their
    cause. And they lose this just when the winds of change
    were freshening at their backs.
    Federal courts are blunt instruments when it comes to
    creating rights. They have constitutional power only to
    resolve concrete cases or controversies; they do not have
    the flexibility of legislatures to address concerns of parties
    not before the court or to anticipate problems that may
    arise from the exercise of a new right. Today’s decision,
    for example, creates serious questions about religious
    liberty. Many good and decent people oppose same-sex
    marriage as a tenet of faith, and their freedom to exercise
    religion is—unlike the right imagined by the majority—
    actually spelled out in the Constitution. Amdt. 1.
    Respect for sincere religious conviction has led voters
    and legislators in every State that has adopted same-sex
    marriage democratically to include accommodations for
    28                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    religious practice. The majority’s decision imposing same-
    sex marriage cannot, of course, create any such accommo-
    dations. The majority graciously suggests that religious
    believers may continue to “advocate” and “teach” their
    views of marriage. Ante, at 27. The First Amendment
    guarantees, however, the freedom to “exercise” religion.
    Ominously, that is not a word the majority uses.
    Hard questions arise when people of faith exercise
    religion in ways that may be seen to conflict with the new
    right to same-sex marriage—when, for example, a reli-
    gious college provides married student housing only to
    opposite-sex married couples, or a religious adoption
    agency declines to place children with same-sex married
    couples. Indeed, the Solicitor General candidly acknowl-
    edged that the tax exemptions of some religious institu-
    tions would be in question if they opposed same-sex mar-
    riage. See Tr. of Oral Arg. on Question 1, at 36–38. There
    is little doubt that these and similar questions will soon be
    before this Court. Unfortunately, people of faith can take
    no comfort in the treatment they receive from the majority
    today.
    Perhaps the most discouraging aspect of today’s decision
    is the extent to which the majority feels compelled to sully
    those on the other side of the debate. The majority offers a
    cursory assurance that it does not intend to disparage
    people who, as a matter of conscience, cannot accept same-
    sex marriage. Ante, at 19. That disclaimer is hard to
    square with the very next sentence, in which the majority
    explains that “the necessary consequence” of laws codify-
    ing the traditional definition of marriage is to “demea[n]
    or stigmatiz[e]” same-sex couples. Ante, at 19. The major-
    ity reiterates such characterizations over and over. By the
    majority’s account, Americans who did nothing more than
    follow the understanding of marriage that has existed for
    our entire history—in particular, the tens of millions of
    people who voted to reaffirm their States’ enduring defini-
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           29
    ROBERTS, C. J., dissenting
    tion of marriage—have acted to “lock . . . out,” “disparage,”
    “disrespect and subordinate,” and inflict “[d]ignitary
    wounds” upon their gay and lesbian neighbors. Ante, at
    17, 19, 22, 25. These apparent assaults on the character of
    fairminded people will have an effect, in society and in
    court. See post, at 6–7 (ALITO, J., dissenting). Moreover,
    they are entirely gratuitous. It is one thing for the major-
    ity to conclude that the Constitution protects a right to
    same-sex marriage; it is something else to portray every-
    one who does not share the majority’s “better informed
    understanding” as bigoted. Ante, at 19.
    In the face of all this, a much different view of the
    Court’s role is possible. That view is more modest and
    restrained. It is more skeptical that the legal abilities of
    judges also reflect insight into moral and philosophical
    issues. It is more sensitive to the fact that judges are
    unelected and unaccountable, and that the legitimacy of
    their power depends on confining it to the exercise of legal
    judgment. It is more attuned to the lessons of history, and
    what it has meant for the country and Court when Jus-
    tices have exceeded their proper bounds. And it is less
    pretentious than to suppose that while people around the
    world have viewed an institution in a particular way for
    thousands of years, the present generation and the pre-
    sent Court are the ones chosen to burst the bonds of that
    history and tradition.
    *   *    *
    If you are among the many Americans—of whatever
    sexual orientation—who favor expanding same-sex mar-
    riage, by all means celebrate today’s decision. Celebrate
    the achievement of a desired goal. Celebrate the oppor-
    tunity for a new expression of commitment to a partner.
    Celebrate the availability of new benefits. But do not
    celebrate the Constitution. It had nothing to do with it.
    I respectfully dissent.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           1
    SCALIA, J., dissenting
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    Nos. 14–556, 14-562, 14-571 and 14–574
    _________________
    JAMES OBERGEFELL, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–556               v.
    RICHARD HODGES, DIRECTOR, OHIO
    DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH, ET AL.;
    VALERIA TANCO, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–562                  v.
    BILL HASLAM, GOVERNOR OF
    TENNESSEE, ET AL.;
    APRIL DEBOER, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–571                 v.
    RICK SNYDER, GOVERNOR OF MICHIGAN,
    ET AL.; AND
    GREGORY BOURKE, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–574              v.
    STEVE BESHEAR, GOVERNOR OF
    KENTUCKY
    ON WRITS OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    [June 26, 2015]
    JUSTICE SCALIA, with whom JUSTICE THOMAS joins,
    dissenting.
    I join THE CHIEF JUSTICE’s opinion in full. I write sepa-
    rately to call attention to this Court’s threat to American
    democracy.
    The substance of today’s decree is not of immense per-
    sonal importance to me. The law can recognize as mar-
    riage whatever sexual attachments and living arrange-
    ments it wishes, and can accord them favorable civil
    consequences, from tax treatment to rights of inheritance.
    2                         OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    SCALIA, J., dissenting
    Those civil consequences—and the public approval that
    conferring the name of marriage evidences—can perhaps
    have adverse social effects, but no more adverse than the
    effects of many other controversial laws. So it is not of
    special importance to me what the law says about mar-
    riage. It is of overwhelming importance, however, who it
    is that rules me. Today’s decree says that my Ruler, and
    the Ruler of 320 million Americans coast-to-coast, is a
    majority of the nine lawyers on the Supreme Court. The
    opinion in these cases is the furthest extension in fact—
    and the furthest extension one can even imagine—of the
    Court’s claimed power to create “liberties” that the Consti-
    tution and its Amendments neglect to mention. This
    practice of constitutional revision by an unelected commit-
    tee of nine, always accompanied (as it is today) by extrav-
    agant praise of liberty, robs the People of the most im-
    portant liberty they asserted in the Declaration of
    Independence and won in the Revolution of 1776: the
    freedom to govern themselves.
    I
    Until the courts put a stop to it, public debate over
    same-sex marriage displayed American democracy at its
    best. Individuals on both sides of the issue passionately,
    but respectfully, attempted to persuade their fellow citi-
    zens to accept their views. Americans considered the
    arguments and put the question to a vote. The electorates
    of 11 States, either directly or through their representa-
    tives, chose to expand the traditional definition of mar-
    riage. Many more decided not to.1 Win or lose, advocates
    for both sides continued pressing their cases, secure in the
    knowledge that an electoral loss can be negated by a later
    electoral win. That is exactly how our system of govern-
    ——————
    1 Brief   for Respondents in No. 14–571, p. 14.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)                     3
    SCALIA, J., dissenting
    ment is supposed to work.2
    The Constitution places some constraints on self-rule—
    constraints adopted by the People themselves when they
    ratified the Constitution and its Amendments. Forbidden
    are laws “impairing the Obligation of Contracts,”3 denying
    “Full Faith and Credit” to the “public Acts” of other
    States,4 prohibiting the free exercise of religion,5 abridging
    the freedom of speech,6 infringing the right to keep and
    bear arms,7 authorizing unreasonable searches and sei-
    zures,8 and so forth. Aside from these limitations, those
    powers “reserved to the States respectively, or to the
    people”9 can be exercised as the States or the People de-
    sire. These cases ask us to decide whether the Fourteenth
    Amendment contains a limitation that requires the States
    to license and recognize marriages between two people of
    the same sex. Does it remove that issue from the political
    process?
    Of course not. It would be surprising to find a prescrip-
    tion regarding marriage in the Federal Constitution since,
    as the author of today’s opinion reminded us only two
    years ago (in an opinion joined by the same Justices who
    join him today):
    “[R]egulation of domestic relations is an area that has
    long been regarded as a virtually exclusive province of
    the States.”10
    ——————
    2 Accord,   Schuette v. BAMN, 572 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2014) (plurality
    opinion) (slip op., at 15–17).
    3 U. S. Const., Art. I, §10.
    4 Art. IV, §1.
    5 Amdt. 1.
    6 
    Ibid. 7 Amdt. 2.
       8 Amdt. 4.
    9 Amdt. 10.
    10 United States v. Windsor, 570 U. S. ___, ___ (2013) (slip op., at 16)
    (internal quotation marks and citation omitted).
    4                    OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    SCALIA, J., dissenting
    “[T]he Federal Government, through our history, has
    deferred to state-law policy decisions with respect to
    domestic relations.”11
    But we need not speculate.          When the Fourteenth
    Amendment was ratified in 1868, every State limited
    marriage to one man and one woman, and no one doubted
    the constitutionality of doing so. That resolves these
    cases. When it comes to determining the meaning of a
    vague constitutional provision—such as “due process of
    law” or “equal protection of the laws”—it is unquestionable
    that the People who ratified that provision did not under-
    stand it to prohibit a practice that remained both univer-
    sal and uncontroversial in the years after ratification.12
    We have no basis for striking down a practice that is not
    expressly prohibited by the Fourteenth Amendment’s text,
    and that bears the endorsement of a long tradition of open,
    widespread, and unchallenged use dating back to the
    Amendment’s ratification. Since there is no doubt what-
    ever that the People never decided to prohibit the limita-
    tion of marriage to opposite-sex couples, the public debate
    over same-sex marriage must be allowed to continue.
    But the Court ends this debate, in an opinion lacking
    even a thin veneer of law. Buried beneath the mummeries
    and straining-to-be-memorable passages of the opinion is a
    candid and startling assertion: No matter what it was the
    People ratified, the Fourteenth Amendment protects those
    rights that the Judiciary, in its “reasoned judgment,”
    thinks the Fourteenth Amendment ought to protect.13
    That is so because “[t]he generations that wrote and rati-
    fied the Bill of Rights and the Fourteenth Amendment did
    not presume to know the extent of freedom in all of its
    ——————
    11 Id.,
    at ___ (slip op., at 17).
    12 See
    Town of Greece v. Galloway, 572 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2014) (slip
    op., at 7–8).
    13 Ante, at 10.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)      5
    SCALIA, J., dissenting
    dimensions . . . . ”14 One would think that sentence would
    continue: “. . . and therefore they provided for a means by
    which the People could amend the Constitution,” or per-
    haps “. . . and therefore they left the creation of additional
    liberties, such as the freedom to marry someone of the
    same sex, to the People, through the never-ending process
    of legislation.” But no. What logically follows, in the
    majority’s judge-empowering estimation, is: “and so they
    entrusted to future generations a charter protecting the
    right of all persons to enjoy liberty as we learn its mean-
    ing.”15 The “we,” needless to say, is the nine of us. “History
    and tradition guide and discipline [our] inquiry but do
    not set its outer boundaries.”16 Thus, rather than focusing
    on the People’s understanding of “liberty”—at the time of
    ratification or even today—the majority focuses on four
    “principles and traditions” that, in the majority’s view,
    prohibit States from defining marriage as an institution
    consisting of one man and one woman.17
    This is a naked judicial claim to legislative—indeed,
    super-legislative—power; a claim fundamentally at odds
    with our system of government. Except as limited by a
    constitutional prohibition agreed to by the People, the
    States are free to adopt whatever laws they like, even
    those that offend the esteemed Justices’ “reasoned judg-
    ment.” A system of government that makes the People
    subordinate to a committee of nine unelected lawyers does
    not deserve to be called a democracy.
    Judges are selected precisely for their skill as lawyers;
    whether they reflect the policy views of a particular con-
    stituency is not (or should not be) relevant. Not surpris-
    ingly then, the Federal Judiciary is hardly a cross-section
    ——————
    14 Ante,   at 11.
    15 
    Ibid. 16 Ante, at
    10–11.
    17 Ante,   at 12–18.
    6                    OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    SCALIA, J., dissenting
    of America. Take, for example, this Court, which consists
    of only nine men and women, all of them successful law-
    yers18 who studied at Harvard or Yale Law School. Four
    of the nine are natives of New York City. Eight of them
    grew up in east- and west-coast States. Only one hails
    from the vast expanse in-between. Not a single South-
    westerner or even, to tell the truth, a genuine Westerner
    (California does not count). Not a single evangelical
    Christian (a group that comprises about one quarter of
    Americans19), or even a Protestant of any denomination.
    The strikingly unrepresentative character of the body
    voting on today’s social upheaval would be irrelevant if
    they were functioning as judges, answering the legal
    question whether the American people had ever ratified a
    constitutional provision that was understood to proscribe
    the traditional definition of marriage. But of course the
    Justices in today’s majority are not voting on that basis;
    they say they are not. And to allow the policy question of
    same-sex marriage to be considered and resolved by a
    select, patrician, highly unrepresentative panel of nine is
    to violate a principle even more fundamental than no
    taxation without representation: no social transformation
    without representation.
    II
    But what really astounds is the hubris reflected in
    today’s judicial Putsch. The five Justices who compose
    today’s majority are entirely comfortable concluding that
    ——————
    18 The
    predominant attitude of tall-building lawyers with respect to
    the questions presented in these cases is suggested by the fact that the
    American Bar Association deemed it in accord with the wishes of its
    members to file a brief in support of the petitioners. See Brief for
    American Bar Association as Amicus Curiae in Nos. 14–571 and 14–
    574, pp. 1–5.
    19 See Pew Research Center, America’s Changing Religious Land-
    scape 4 (May 12, 2015).
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)                        7
    SCALIA, J., dissenting
    every State violated the Constitution for all of the 135
    years between the Fourteenth Amendment’s ratification
    and Massachusetts’ permitting of same-sex marriages in
    2003.20 They have discovered in the Fourteenth Amend-
    ment a “fundamental right” overlooked by every person
    alive at the time of ratification, and almost everyone else
    in the time since. They see what lesser legal minds—
    minds like Thomas Cooley, John Marshall Harlan, Oliver
    Wendell Holmes, Jr., Learned Hand, Louis Brandeis,
    William Howard Taft, Benjamin Cardozo, Hugo Black,
    Felix Frankfurter, Robert Jackson, and Henry Friendly—
    could not. They are certain that the People ratified the
    Fourteenth Amendment to bestow on them the power to
    remove questions from the democratic process when that
    is called for by their “reasoned judgment.” These Justices
    know that limiting marriage to one man and one woman is
    contrary to reason; they know that an institution as old as
    government itself, and accepted by every nation in history
    until 15 years ago,21 cannot possibly be supported by
    anything other than ignorance or bigotry. And they are
    willing to say that any citizen who does not agree with
    that, who adheres to what was, until 15 years ago, the
    unanimous judgment of all generations and all societies,
    stands against the Constitution.
    The opinion is couched in a style that is as pretentious
    as its content is egotistic. It is one thing for separate con-
    curring or dissenting opinions to contain extravagances,
    even silly extravagances, of thought and expression; it is
    something else for the official opinion of the Court to do
    so.22 Of course the opinion’s showy profundities are often
    ——————
    20 Goodridge v. Department of Public Health, 
    440 Mass. 309
    , 
    798 N.E. 2d
    941 (2003).
    21 Windsor, 570 U. S., at ___ (ALITO, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 7).
    22 If, even as the price to be paid for a fifth vote, I ever joined an opin-
    ion for the Court that began: “The Constitution promises liberty to all
    within its reach, a liberty that includes certain specific rights that
    8                   OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    SCALIA, J., dissenting
    profoundly incoherent. “The nature of marriage is that,
    through its enduring bond, two persons together can find
    other freedoms, such as expression, intimacy, and spiritu-
    ality.”23 (Really? Who ever thought that intimacy and
    spirituality [whatever that means] were freedoms? And if
    intimacy is, one would think Freedom of Intimacy is
    abridged rather than expanded by marriage. Ask the
    nearest hippie. Expression, sure enough, is a freedom, but
    anyone in a long-lasting marriage will attest that that
    happy state constricts, rather than expands, what one can
    prudently say.) Rights, we are told, can “rise . . . from a
    better informed understanding of how constitutional
    imperatives define a liberty that remains urgent in our
    own era.”24 (Huh? How can a better informed under-
    standing of how constitutional imperatives [whatever that
    means] define [whatever that means] an urgent liberty
    [never mind], give birth to a right?) And we are told that,
    “[i]n any particular case,” either the Equal Protection or
    Due Process Clause “may be thought to capture the es-
    sence of [a] right in a more accurate and comprehensive
    way,” than the other, “even as the two Clauses may con-
    verge in the identification and definition of the right.”25
    (What say? What possible “essence” does substantive due
    process “capture” in an “accurate and comprehensive
    way”? It stands for nothing whatever, except those free-
    doms and entitlements that this Court really likes. And
    the Equal Protection Clause, as employed today, identifies
    nothing except a difference in treatment that this Court
    ——————
    allow persons, within a lawful realm, to define and express their
    identity,” I would hide my head in a bag. The Supreme Court of the
    United States has descended from the disciplined legal reasoning of
    John Marshall and Joseph Story to the mystical aphorisms of the
    fortune cookie.
    23 Ante, at 13.
    24 Ante, at 19.
    25 
    Ibid. Cite as: 576
    U. S. ____ (2015)                   9
    SCALIA, J., dissenting
    really dislikes. Hardly a distillation of essence. If the
    opinion is correct that the two clauses “converge in the
    identification and definition of [a] right,” that is only
    because the majority’s likes and dislikes are predictably
    compatible.) I could go on. The world does not expect
    logic and precision in poetry or inspirational pop-
    philosophy; it demands them in the law. The stuff con-
    tained in today’s opinion has to diminish this Court’s
    reputation for clear thinking and sober analysis.
    *      *    *
    Hubris is sometimes defined as o’erweening pride; and
    pride, we know, goeth before a fall. The Judiciary is the
    “least dangerous” of the federal branches because it has
    “neither Force nor Will, but merely judgment; and must
    ultimately depend upon the aid of the executive arm” and
    the States, “even for the efficacy of its judgments.”26 With
    each decision of ours that takes from the People a question
    properly left to them—with each decision that is unabash-
    edly based not on law, but on the “reasoned judgment” of a
    bare majority of this Court—we move one step closer to
    being reminded of our impotence.
    ——————
    26 The Federalist No. 78, pp. 522, 523 (J. Cooke ed. 1961) (A. Hamil-
    ton).
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)          1
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    Nos. 14–556, 14-562, 14-571 and 14–574
    _________________
    JAMES OBERGEFELL, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–556               v.
    RICHARD HODGES, DIRECTOR, OHIO
    DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH, ET AL.;
    VALERIA TANCO, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–562                  v.
    BILL HASLAM, GOVERNOR OF
    TENNESSEE, ET AL.;
    APRIL DEBOER, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–571                 v.
    RICK SNYDER, GOVERNOR OF MICHIGAN,
    ET AL.; AND
    GREGORY BOURKE, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–574              v.
    STEVE BESHEAR, GOVERNOR OF
    KENTUCKY
    ON WRITS OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    [June 26, 2015]
    JUSTICE THOMAS, with whom JUSTICE SCALIA joins,
    dissenting.
    The Court’s decision today is at odds not only with the
    Constitution, but with the principles upon which our
    Nation was built. Since well before 1787, liberty has been
    understood as freedom from government action, not enti-
    tlement to government benefits. The Framers created our
    2                 OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    Constitution to preserve that understanding of liberty.
    Yet the majority invokes our Constitution in the name of a
    “liberty” that the Framers would not have recognized, to
    the detriment of the liberty they sought to protect. Along
    the way, it rejects the idea—captured in our Declaration of
    Independence—that human dignity is innate and suggests
    instead that it comes from the Government. This distor-
    tion of our Constitution not only ignores the text, it inverts
    the relationship between the individual and the state in
    our Republic. I cannot agree with it.
    I
    The majority’s decision today will require States to issue
    marriage licenses to same-sex couples and to recognize
    same-sex marriages entered in other States largely based
    on a constitutional provision guaranteeing “due process”
    before a person is deprived of his “life, liberty, or prop-
    erty.” I have elsewhere explained the dangerous fiction of
    treating the Due Process Clause as a font of substantive
    rights. McDonald v. Chicago, 
    561 U.S. 742
    , 811–812
    (2010) (THOMAS, J., concurring in part and concurring in
    judgment). It distorts the constitutional text, which guar-
    antees only whatever “process” is “due” before a person is
    deprived of life, liberty, and property. U. S. Const., Amdt.
    14, §1. Worse, it invites judges to do exactly what the
    majority has done here—“ ‘roa[m] at large in the constitu-
    tional field’ guided only by their personal views” as to the
    “ ‘fundamental rights’ ” protected by that document.
    Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 
    505 U.S. 833
    , 953, 965 (1992) (Rehnquist, C. J., concurring in
    judgment in part and dissenting in part) (quoting Gris-
    wold v. Connecticut, 
    381 U.S. 479
    , 502 (1965) (Harlan, J.,
    concurring in judgment)).
    By straying from the text of the Constitution, substan-
    tive due process exalts judges at the expense of the People
    from whom they derive their authority. Petitioners argue
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)                     3
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    that by enshrining the traditional definition of marriage in
    their State Constitutions through voter-approved amend-
    ments, the States have put the issue “beyond the reach of
    the normal democratic process.” Brief for Petitioners in
    No. 14–562, p. 54. But the result petitioners seek is far
    less democratic. They ask nine judges on this Court to
    enshrine their definition of marriage in the Federal Con-
    stitution and thus put it beyond the reach of the normal
    democratic process for the entire Nation. That a “bare
    majority” of this Court, ante, at 25, is able to grant this
    wish, wiping out with a stroke of the keyboard the results
    of the political process in over 30 States, based on a provi-
    sion that guarantees only “due process” is but further
    evidence of the danger of substantive due process.1
    II
    Even if the doctrine of substantive due process were
    somehow defensible—it is not—petitioners still would not
    have a claim. To invoke the protection of the Due Process
    Clause at all—whether under a theory of “substantive” or
    “procedural” due process—a party must first identify a
    deprivation of “life, liberty, or property.” The majority
    claims these state laws deprive petitioners of “liberty,” but
    the concept of “liberty” it conjures up bears no resem-
    blance to any plausible meaning of that word as it is used
    in the Due Process Clauses.
    ——————
    1 The majority states that the right it believes is “part of the liberty
    promised by the Fourteenth Amendment is derived, too, from that
    Amendment’s guarantee of the equal protection of the laws.” Ante, at
    19. Despite the “synergy” it finds “between th[ese] two protections,”
    ante, at 20, the majority clearly uses equal protection only to shore up
    its substantive due process analysis, an analysis both based on an
    imaginary constitutional protection and revisionist view of our history
    and tradition.
    4                 OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    A
    1
    As used in the Due Process Clauses, “liberty” most likely
    refers to “the power of loco-motion, of changing situation,
    or removing one’s person to whatsoever place one’s own
    inclination may direct; without imprisonment or restraint,
    unless by due course of law.” 1 W. Blackstone, Commen-
    taries on the Laws of England 130 (1769) (Blackstone).
    That definition is drawn from the historical roots of the
    Clauses and is consistent with our Constitution’s text and
    structure.
    Both of the Constitution’s Due Process Clauses reach
    back to Magna Carta. See Davidson v. New Orleans, 
    96 U.S. 97
    , 101–102 (1878). Chapter 39 of the original
    Magna Carta provided, “No free man shall be taken, im-
    prisoned, disseised, outlawed, banished, or in any way
    destroyed, nor will We proceed against or prosecute him,
    except by the lawful judgment of his peers and by the law
    of the land.” Magna Carta, ch. 39, in A. Howard, Magna
    Carta: Text and Commentary 43 (1964). Although the
    1215 version of Magna Carta was in effect for only a few
    weeks, this provision was later reissued in 1225 with
    modest changes to its wording as follows: “No freeman
    shall be taken, or imprisoned, or be disseised of his free-
    hold, or liberties, or free customs, or be outlawed, or ex-
    iled, or any otherwise destroyed; nor will we not pass upon
    him, nor condemn him, but by lawful judgment of his
    peers or by the law of the land.” 1 E. Coke, The Second
    Part of the Institutes of the Laws of England 45 (1797). In
    his influential commentary on the provision many years
    later, Sir Edward Coke interpreted the words “by the law
    of the land” to mean the same thing as “by due proces of
    the common law.” 
    Id., at 50.
       After Magna Carta became subject to renewed interest
    in the 17th century, see, e.g., ibid., William Blackstone
    referred to this provision as protecting the “absolute rights
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)                       5
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    of every Englishman.” 1 Blackstone 123. And he formu-
    lated those absolute rights as “the right of personal secu-
    rity,” which included the right to life; “the right of personal
    liberty”; and “the right of private property.” 
    Id., at 125.
    He defined “the right of personal liberty” as “the power of
    loco-motion, of changing situation, or removing one’s
    person to whatsoever place one’s own inclination may
    direct; without imprisonment or restraint, unless by due
    course of law.” 
    Id., at 125,
    130.2
    The Framers drew heavily upon Blackstone’s formula-
    tion, adopting provisions in early State Constitutions that
    replicated Magna Carta’s language, but were modified to
    refer specifically to “life, liberty, or property.”3 State
    ——————
    2 The seeds of this articulation can also be found in Henry Care’s
    influential treatise, English Liberties. First published in America in
    1721, it described the “three things, which the Law of England . . .
    principally regards and taketh Care of,” as “Life, Liberty and Estate,”
    and described habeas corpus as the means by which one could procure
    one’s “Liberty” from imprisonment. The Habeas Corpus Act, comment.,
    in English Liberties, or the Free-born Subject’s Inheritance 185 (H.
    Care comp. 5th ed. 1721). Though he used the word “Liberties” by itself
    more broadly, see, e.g., 
    id., at 7,
    34, 56, 58, 60, he used “Liberty” in a
    narrow sense when placed alongside the words “Life” or “Estate,” see,
    e.g., 
    id., at 185,
    200.
    3 Maryland, North Carolina, and South Carolina adopted the phrase
    “life, liberty, or property” in provisions otherwise tracking Magna
    Carta: “That no freeman ought to be taken, or imprisoned, or disseized
    of his freehold, liberties, or privileges, or outlawed, or exiled, or in any
    manner destroyed, or deprived of his life, liberty, or property, but by
    the judgment of his peers, or by the law of the land.” Md. Const.,
    Declaration of Rights, Art. XXI (1776), in 3 Federal and State Constitu-
    tions, Colonial Charters, and Other Organic Laws 1688 (F. Thorpe ed.
    1909); see also S. C. Const., Art. XLI (1778), in 6 
    id., at 3257;
    N. C.
    Const., Declaration of Rights, Art. XII (1776), in 5 
    id., at 2788.
    Massa-
    chusetts and New Hampshire did the same, albeit with some altera-
    tions to Magna Carta’s framework: “[N]o subject shall be arrested,
    imprisoned, despoiled, or deprived of his property, immunities, or
    privileges, put out of the protection of the law, exiled, or deprived of his
    life, liberty, or estate, but by the judgment of his peers, or the law of the
    land.” Mass. Const., pt. I, Art. XII (1780), in 3 
    id., at 1891;
    see also
    6                      OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    decisions interpreting these provisions between the found-
    ing and the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment
    almost uniformly construed the word “liberty” to refer only
    to freedom from physical restraint. See Warren, The New
    “Liberty” Under the Fourteenth Amendment, 39 Harv.
    L. Rev. 431, 441–445 (1926). Even one case that has been
    identified as a possible exception to that view merely used
    broad language about liberty in the context of a habeas
    corpus proceeding—a proceeding classically associated
    with obtaining freedom from physical restraint. Cf. 
    id., at 444–445.
       In enacting the Fifth Amendment’s Due Process Clause,
    the Framers similarly chose to employ the “life, liberty, or
    property” formulation, though they otherwise deviated
    substantially from the States’ use of Magna Carta’s lan-
    guage in the Clause. See Shattuck, The True Meaning of
    the Term “Liberty” in Those Clauses in the Federal and
    State Constitutions Which Protect “Life, Liberty, and
    Property,” 4 Harv. L. Rev. 365, 382 (1890). When read in
    light of the history of that formulation, it is hard to see
    how the “liberty” protected by the Clause could be inter-
    preted to include anything broader than freedom from
    physical restraint. That was the consistent usage of the
    time when “liberty” was paired with “life” and “property.”
    See 
    id., at 375.
    And that usage avoids rendering superflu-
    ous those protections for “life” and “property.”
    If the Fifth Amendment uses “liberty” in this narrow
    sense, then the Fourteenth Amendment likely does as
    well. See Hurtado v. California, 
    110 U.S. 516
    , 534–535
    (1884). Indeed, this Court has previously commented,
    “The conclusion is . . . irresistible, that when the same
    phrase was employed in the Fourteenth Amendment [as
    was used in the Fifth Amendment], it was used in the
    same sense and with no greater extent.” 
    Ibid. And this ——————
    N. H. Const., pt. I, Art. XV (1784), in 4 
    id., at 2455.
                      Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)            7
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    Court’s earliest Fourteenth Amendment decisions appear
    to interpret the Clause as using “liberty” to mean freedom
    from physical restraint. In Munn v. Illinois, 
    94 U.S. 113
    (1877), for example, the Court recognized the relationship
    between the two Due Process Clauses and Magna Carta,
    see 
    id., at 123–124,
    and implicitly rejected the dissent’s
    argument that “ ‘liberty’ ” encompassed “something more
    . . . than mere freedom from physical restraint or the
    bounds of a prison,” 
    id., at 142
    (Field, J., dissenting). That
    the Court appears to have lost its way in more recent
    years does not justify deviating from the original meaning
    of the Clauses.
    2
    Even assuming that the “liberty” in those Clauses en-
    compasses something more than freedom from physical
    restraint, it would not include the types of rights claimed
    by the majority. In the American legal tradition, liberty
    has long been understood as individual freedom from
    governmental action, not as a right to a particular gov-
    ernmental entitlement.
    The founding-era understanding of liberty was heavily
    influenced by John Locke, whose writings “on natural
    rights and on the social and governmental contract” were
    cited “[i]n pamphlet after pamphlet” by American writers.
    B. Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolu-
    tion 27 (1967). Locke described men as existing in a state
    of nature, possessed of the “perfect freedom to order their
    actions and dispose of their possessions and persons as
    they think fit, within the bounds of the law of nature,
    without asking leave, or depending upon the will of any
    other man.” J. Locke, Second Treatise of Civil Govern-
    ment, §4, p. 4 (J. Gough ed. 1947) (Locke). Because that
    state of nature left men insecure in their persons and
    property, they entered civil society, trading a portion of
    their natural liberty for an increase in their security. See
    8                     OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    
    id., §97, at
    49. Upon consenting to that order, men ob-
    tained civil liberty, or the freedom “to be under no other
    legislative power but that established by consent in the
    commonwealth; nor under the dominion of any will or
    restraint of any law, but what that legislative shall enact
    according to the trust put in it.” 
    Id., §22, at
    13.4
    This philosophy permeated the 18th-century political
    scene in America. A 1756 editorial in the Boston Gazette,
    for example, declared that “Liberty in the State of Nature”
    was the “inherent natural Right” “of each Man” “to make a
    free Use of his Reason and Understanding, and to chuse
    that Action which he thinks he can give the best Account
    of,” but that, “in Society, every Man parts with a Small
    Share of his natural Liberty, or lodges it in the publick
    Stock, that he may possess the Remainder without Con-
    troul.” Boston Gazette and Country Journal, No. 58, May
    10, 1756, p. 1. Similar sentiments were expressed in
    public speeches, sermons, and letters of the time. See 1 C.
    ——————
    4 Locke’s theories heavily influenced other prominent writers of the
    17th and 18th centuries. Blackstone, for one, agreed that “natural
    liberty consists properly in a power of acting as one thinks fit, without
    any restraint or control, unless by the law of nature” and described civil
    liberty as that “which leaves the subject entire master of his own
    conduct,” except as “restrained by human laws.” 1 Blackstone 121–122.
    And in a “treatise routinely cited by the Founders,” Zivotofsky v. Kerry,
    ante, at 5 (THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in
    part), Thomas Rutherforth wrote, “By liberty we mean the power,
    which a man has to act as he thinks fit, where no law restrains him; it
    may therefore be called a mans right over his own actions.” 1 T. Ruth-
    erforth, Institutes of Natural Law 146 (1754). Rutherforth explained
    that “[t]he only restraint, which a mans right over his own actions is
    originally under, is the obligation of governing himself by the law of
    nature, and the law of God,” and that “[w]hatever right those of our
    own species may have . . . to restrain [those actions] within certain
    bounds, beyond what the law of nature has prescribed, arises from
    some after-act of our own, from some consent either express or tacit, by
    which we have alienated our liberty, or transferred the right of direct-
    ing our actions from ourselves to them.” 
    Id., at 147–148.
                     Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)            9
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    Hyneman & D. Lutz, American Political Writing During
    the Founding Era 1760–1805, pp. 100, 308, 385 (1983).
    The founding-era idea of civil liberty as natural liberty
    constrained by human law necessarily involved only those
    freedoms that existed outside of government. See Ham-
    burger, Natural Rights, Natural Law, and American
    Constitutions, 102 Yale L. J. 907, 918–919 (1993). As one
    later commentator observed, “[L]iberty in the eighteenth
    century was thought of much more in relation to ‘negative
    liberty’; that is, freedom from, not freedom to, freedom
    from a number of social and political evils, including arbi-
    trary government power.” J. Reid, The Concept of Liberty
    in the Age of the American Revolution 56 (1988). Or as
    one scholar put it in 1776, “[T]he common idea of liberty is
    merely negative, and is only the absence of restraint.” R.
    Hey, Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty and the
    Principles of Government §13, p. 8 (1776) (Hey). When the
    colonists described laws that would infringe their liberties,
    they discussed laws that would prohibit individuals “from
    walking in the streets and highways on certain saints
    days, or from being abroad after a certain time in the
    evening, or . . . restrain [them] from working up and man-
    ufacturing materials of [their] own growth.” Downer, A
    Discourse at the Dedication of the Tree of Liberty, in 1
    
    Hyneman, supra, at 101
    . Each of those examples involved
    freedoms that existed outside of government.
    B
    Whether we define “liberty” as locomotion or freedom
    from governmental action more broadly, petitioners have
    in no way been deprived of it.
    Petitioners cannot claim, under the most plausible
    definition of “liberty,” that they have been imprisoned or
    physically restrained by the States for participating in
    same-sex relationships. To the contrary, they have been
    able to cohabitate and raise their children in peace. They
    10                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    have been able to hold civil marriage ceremonies in States
    that recognize same-sex marriages and private religious
    ceremonies in all States. They have been able to travel
    freely around the country, making their homes where they
    please. Far from being incarcerated or physically re-
    strained, petitioners have been left alone to order their
    lives as they see fit.
    Nor, under the broader definition, can they claim that
    the States have restricted their ability to go about their
    daily lives as they would be able to absent governmental
    restrictions. Petitioners do not ask this Court to order the
    States to stop restricting their ability to enter same-sex
    relationships, to engage in intimate behavior, to make
    vows to their partners in public ceremonies, to engage in
    religious wedding ceremonies, to hold themselves out as
    married, or to raise children. The States have imposed no
    such restrictions. Nor have the States prevented petition-
    ers from approximating a number of incidents of marriage
    through private legal means, such as wills, trusts, and
    powers of attorney.
    Instead, the States have refused to grant them govern-
    mental entitlements. Petitioners claim that as a matter of
    “liberty,” they are entitled to access privileges and benefits
    that exist solely because of the government. They want,
    for example, to receive the State’s imprimatur on their
    marriages—on state issued marriage licenses, death certif-
    icates, or other official forms. And they want to receive
    various monetary benefits, including reduced inheritance
    taxes upon the death of a spouse, compensation if a spouse
    dies as a result of a work-related injury, or loss of consor-
    tium damages in tort suits. But receiving governmental
    recognition and benefits has nothing to do with any un-
    derstanding of “liberty” that the Framers would have
    recognized.
    To the extent that the Framers would have recognized a
    natural right to marriage that fell within the broader
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)                  11
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    definition of liberty, it would not have included a right to
    governmental recognition and benefits. Instead, it would
    have included a right to engage in the very same activities
    that petitioners have been left free to engage in—making
    vows, holding religious ceremonies celebrating those vows,
    raising children, and otherwise enjoying the society of
    one’s spouse—without governmental interference. At the
    founding, such conduct was understood to predate gov-
    ernment, not to flow from it. As Locke had explained
    many years earlier, “The first society was between man
    and wife, which gave beginning to that between parents
    and children.” Locke §77, at 39; see also J. Wilson, Lec-
    tures on Law, in 2 Collected Works of James Wilson 1068
    (K. Hall and M. Hall eds. 2007) (concluding “that to the
    institution of marriage the true origin of society must be
    traced”). Petitioners misunderstand the institution of
    marriage when they say that it would “mean little” absent
    governmental recognition. Brief for Petitioners in No. 14–
    556, p. 33.
    Petitioners’ misconception of liberty carries over into
    their discussion of our precedents identifying a right to
    marry, not one of which has expanded the concept of “lib-
    erty” beyond the concept of negative liberty. Those prece-
    dents all involved absolute prohibitions on private actions
    associated with marriage. Loving v. Virginia, 
    388 U.S. 1
    (1967), for example, involved a couple who was criminally
    prosecuted for marrying in the District of Columbia and
    cohabiting in Virginia, 
    id., at 2–3.5
    They were each sen-
    ——————
    5 The suggestion of petitioners and their amici that antimiscegenation
    laws are akin to laws defining marriage as between one man and one
    woman is both offensive and inaccurate. “America’s earliest laws
    against interracial sex and marriage were spawned by slavery.” P.
    Pascoe, What Comes Naturally: Miscegenation Law and the Making of
    Race in America 19 (2009). For instance, Maryland’s 1664 law prohibit-
    ing marriages between “ ‘freeborne English women’ ” and “ ‘Negro
    Sla[v]es’ ” was passed as part of the very act that authorized lifelong
    12                   OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    tenced to a year of imprisonment, suspended for a term of
    25 years on the condition that they not reenter the Com-
    monwealth together during that time. 
    Id., at 3.6
    In a
    similar vein, Zablocki v. Redhail, 
    434 U.S. 374
    (1978),
    involved a man who was prohibited, on pain of criminal
    penalty, from “marry[ing] in Wisconsin or elsewhere”
    because of his outstanding child-support obligations, 
    id., at 387;
    see 
    id., at 377–378.
    And Turner v. Safley, 
    482 U.S. 78
    (1987), involved state inmates who were prohib-
    ited from entering marriages without the permission of the
    superintendent of the prison, permission that could not be
    granted absent compelling reasons, 
    id., at 82.
    In none of
    those cases were individuals denied solely governmental
    ——————
    slavery in the colony. 
    Id., at 19–20.
    Virginia’s antimiscegenation laws
    likewise were passed in a 1691 resolution entitled “An act for suppress-
    ing outlying Slaves.” Act of Apr. 1691, Ch. XVI, 3 Va. Stat. 86 (W.
    Hening ed. 1823) (reprint 1969) (italics deleted). “It was not until the
    Civil War threw the future of slavery into doubt that lawyers, legisla-
    tors, and judges began to develop the elaborate justifications that
    signified the emergence of miscegenation law and made restrictions on
    interracial marriage the foundation of post-Civil War white suprem-
    acy.” 
    Pascoe, supra, at 27
    –28.
    Laws defining marriage as between one man and one woman do not
    share this sordid history. The traditional definition of marriage has
    prevailed in every society that has recognized marriage throughout
    history. Brief for Scholars of History and Related Disciplines as Amici
    Curiae 1. It arose not out of a desire to shore up an invidious institu-
    tion like slavery, but out of a desire “to increase the likelihood that
    children will be born and raised in stable and enduring family units by
    both the mothers and the fathers who brought them into this world.”
    
    Id., at 8.
    And it has existed in civilizations containing all manner of
    views on homosexuality. See Brief for Ryan T. Anderson as Amicus
    Curiae 11–12 (explaining that several famous ancient Greeks wrote
    approvingly of the traditional definition of marriage, though same-sex
    sexual relations were common in Greece at the time).
    6 The prohibition extended so far as to forbid even religious ceremo-
    nies, thus raising a serious question under the First Amendment’s Free
    Exercise Clause, as at least one amicus brief at the time pointed out.
    Brief for John J. Russell et al. as Amici Curiae in Loving v. Virginia,
    O.T. 1966, No. 395, pp. 12–16.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)            13
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    recognition and benefits associated with marriage.
    In a concession to petitioners’ misconception of liberty,
    the majority characterizes petitioners’ suit as a quest to
    “find . . . liberty by marrying someone of the same sex and
    having their marriages deemed lawful on the same terms
    and conditions as marriages between persons of the oppo-
    site sex.” Ante, at 2. But “liberty” is not lost, nor can it be
    found in the way petitioners seek. As a philosophical
    matter, liberty is only freedom from governmental action,
    not an entitlement to governmental benefits. And as a
    constitutional matter, it is likely even narrower than that,
    encompassing only freedom from physical restraint and
    imprisonment. The majority’s “better informed under-
    standing of how constitutional imperatives define . . .
    liberty,” ante, at 19,—better informed, we must assume,
    than that of the people who ratified the Fourteenth
    Amendment—runs headlong into the reality that our
    Constitution is a “collection of ‘Thou shalt nots,’ ” Reid v.
    Covert, 
    354 U.S. 1
    , 9 (1957) (plurality opinion), not “Thou
    shalt provides.”
    III
    The majority’s inversion of the original meaning of
    liberty will likely cause collateral damage to other aspects
    of our constitutional order that protect liberty.
    A
    The majority apparently disregards the political process
    as a protection for liberty. Although men, in forming a
    civil society, “give up all the power necessary to the ends
    for which they unite into society, to the majority of the
    community,” Locke §99, at 49, they reserve the authority
    to exercise natural liberty within the bounds of laws estab-
    lished by that society, 
    id., §22, at
    13; see also Hey §§52,
    54, at 30–32. To protect that liberty from arbitrary inter-
    ference, they establish a process by which that society can
    14                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    adopt and enforce its laws. In our country, that process is
    primarily representative government at the state level,
    with the Federal Constitution serving as a backstop for
    that process. As a general matter, when the States act
    through their representative governments or by popular
    vote, the liberty of their residents is fully vindicated. This
    is no less true when some residents disagree with the
    result; indeed, it seems difficult to imagine any law on
    which all residents of a State would agree. See Locke §98,
    at 49 (suggesting that society would cease to function if it
    required unanimous consent to laws). What matters is
    that the process established by those who created the
    society has been honored.
    That process has been honored here. The definition of
    marriage has been the subject of heated debate in the
    States. Legislatures have repeatedly taken up the matter
    on behalf of the People, and 35 States have put the ques-
    tion to the People themselves. In 32 of those 35 States,
    the People have opted to retain the traditional definition
    of marriage. Brief for Respondents in No. 14–571, pp. 1a–
    7a. That petitioners disagree with the result of that pro-
    cess does not make it any less legitimate. Their civil
    liberty has been vindicated.
    B
    Aside from undermining the political processes that
    protect our liberty, the majority’s decision threatens the
    religious liberty our Nation has long sought to protect.
    The history of religious liberty in our country is familiar:
    Many of the earliest immigrants to America came seeking
    freedom to practice their religion without restraint. See
    McConnell, The Origins and Historical Understanding of
    Free Exercise of Religion, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 1409, 1422–
    1425 (1990). When they arrived, they created their own
    havens for religious practice. 
    Ibid. Many of these
    havens
    were initially homogenous communities with established
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           15
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    religions. 
    Ibid. By the 1780’s,
    however, “America was in
    the wake of a great religious revival” marked by a move
    toward free exercise of religion. 
    Id., at 1437.
    Every State
    save Connecticut adopted protections for religious freedom
    in their State Constitutions by 1789, 
    id., at 1455,
    and, of
    course, the First Amendment enshrined protection for the
    free exercise of religion in the U. S. Constitution. But that
    protection was far from the last word on religious liberty
    in this country, as the Federal Government and the States
    have reaffirmed their commitment to religious liberty by
    codifying protections for religious practice. See, e.g., Reli-
    gious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993, 107 Stat. 1488, 
    42 U.S. C
    . §2000bb et seq.; Conn. Gen. Stat. §52–571b (2015).
    Numerous amici—even some not supporting the
    States—have cautioned the Court that its decision here
    will “have unavoidable and wide-ranging implications
    for religious liberty.” Brief for General Conference of
    Seventh-Day Adventists et al. as Amici Curiae 5. In our
    society, marriage is not simply a governmental institution;
    it is a religious institution as well. 
    Id., at 7.
    Today’s
    decision might change the former, but it cannot change
    the latter. It appears all but inevitable that the two will
    come into conflict, particularly as individuals and churches
    are confronted with demands to participate in and endorse
    civil marriages between same-sex couples.
    The majority appears unmoved by that inevitability. It
    makes only a weak gesture toward religious liberty in a
    single paragraph, ante, at 27. And even that gesture
    indicates a misunderstanding of religious liberty in our
    Nation’s tradition. Religious liberty is about more than
    just the protection for “religious organizations and persons
    . . . as they seek to teach the principles that are so ful-
    filling and so central to their lives and faiths.” 
    Ibid. Religious liberty is
    about freedom of action in matters of
    religion generally, and the scope of that liberty is directly
    correlated to the civil restraints placed upon religious
    16                   OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    practice.7
    Although our Constitution provides some protection
    against such governmental restrictions on religious prac-
    tices, the People have long elected to afford broader pro-
    tections than this Court’s constitutional precedents man-
    date. Had the majority allowed the definition of marriage
    to be left to the political process—as the Constitution
    requires—the People could have considered the religious
    liberty implications of deviating from the traditional defi-
    nition as part of their deliberative process. Instead, the
    majority’s decision short-circuits that process, with poten-
    tially ruinous consequences for religious liberty.
    IV
    Perhaps recognizing that these cases do not actually
    involve liberty as it has been understood, the majority
    goes to great lengths to assert that its decision will ad-
    vance the “dignity” of same-sex couples. Ante, at 3, 13, 26,
    28.8 The flaw in that reasoning, of course, is that the
    Constitution contains no “dignity” Clause, and even if it
    did, the government would be incapable of bestowing
    dignity.
    Human dignity has long been understood in this country
    to be innate. When the Framers proclaimed in the Decla-
    ration of Independence that “all men are created equal”
    ——————
    7 Concerns about threats to religious liberty in this context are not
    unfounded. During the hey-day of antimiscegenation laws in this
    country, for instance, Virginia imposed criminal penalties on ministers
    who performed marriage in violation of those laws, though their reli-
    gions would have permitted them to perform such ceremonies. Va.
    Code Ann. §20–60 (1960).
    8 The majority also suggests that marriage confers “nobility” on indi-
    viduals. Ante, at 3. I am unsure what that means. People may choose
    to marry or not to marry. The decision to do so does not make one
    person more “noble” than another. And the suggestion that Americans
    who choose not to marry are inferior to those who decide to enter such
    relationships is specious.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)           17
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    and “endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable
    Rights,” they referred to a vision of mankind in which all
    humans are created in the image of God and therefore of
    inherent worth. That vision is the foundation upon which
    this Nation was built.
    The corollary of that principle is that human dignity
    cannot be taken away by the government. Slaves did not
    lose their dignity (any more than they lost their humanity)
    because the government allowed them to be enslaved.
    Those held in internment camps did not lose their dignity
    because the government confined them. And those denied
    governmental benefits certainly do not lose their dignity
    because the government denies them those benefits. The
    government cannot bestow dignity, and it cannot take it
    away.
    The majority’s musings are thus deeply misguided, but
    at least those musings can have no effect on the dignity of
    the persons the majority demeans. Its mischaracteriza-
    tion of the arguments presented by the States and their
    amici can have no effect on the dignity of those litigants.
    Its rejection of laws preserving the traditional definition of
    marriage can have no effect on the dignity of the people
    who voted for them. Its invalidation of those laws can
    have no effect on the dignity of the people who continue to
    adhere to the traditional definition of marriage. And its
    disdain for the understandings of liberty and dignity upon
    which this Nation was founded can have no effect on the
    dignity of Americans who continue to believe in them.
    *     *     *
    Our Constitution—like the Declaration of Independence
    before it—was predicated on a simple truth: One’s liberty,
    not to mention one’s dignity, was something to be shielded
    from—not provided by—the State. Today’s decision casts
    that truth aside. In its haste to reach a desired result, the
    majority misapplies a clause focused on “due process” to
    afford substantive rights, disregards the most plausible
    18               OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    understanding of the “liberty” protected by that clause,
    and distorts the principles on which this Nation was
    founded. Its decision will have inestimable consequences
    for our Constitution and our society.      I respectfully
    dissent.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)                  1
    ALITO, J., dissenting
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    _________________
    Nos. 14–556, 14-562, 14-571 and 14–574
    _________________
    JAMES OBERGEFELL, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–556               v.
    RICHARD HODGES, DIRECTOR, OHIO
    DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH, ET AL.;
    VALERIA TANCO, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–562                   v.
    BILL HASLAM, GOVERNOR OF
    TENNESSEE, ET AL.;
    APRIL DEBOER, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–571                 v.
    RICK SNYDER, GOVERNOR OF MICHIGAN,
    ET AL.; AND
    GREGORY BOURKE, ET AL., PETITIONERS
    14–574              v.
    STEVE BESHEAR, GOVERNOR OF
    KENTUCKY
    ON WRITS OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF
    APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
    [June 26, 2015]
    JUSTICE ALITO, with whom JUSTICE SCALIA and JUSTICE
    THOMAS join, dissenting.
    Until the federal courts intervened, the American people
    were engaged in a debate about whether their States
    should recognize same-sex marriage.1 The question in
    ——————
    1I   use the phrase “recognize marriage” as shorthand for issuing mar-
    2                   OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ALITO, J., dissenting
    these cases, however, is not what States should do about
    same-sex marriage but whether the Constitution answers
    that question for them. It does not. The Constitution
    leaves that question to be decided by the people of each
    State.
    I
    The Constitution says nothing about a right to same-sex
    marriage, but the Court holds that the term “liberty” in
    the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment
    encompasses this right. Our Nation was founded upon the
    principle that every person has the unalienable right to
    liberty, but liberty is a term of many meanings. For clas-
    sical liberals, it may include economic rights now limited
    by government regulation.         For social democrats, it
    may include the right to a variety of government benefits.
    For today’s majority, it has a distinctively postmodern
    meaning.
    To prevent five unelected Justices from imposing their
    personal vision of liberty upon the American people, the
    Court has held that “liberty” under the Due Process
    Clause should be understood to protect only those rights
    that are “ ‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradi-
    tion.’ ” Washington v. Glucksberg, 
    521 U.S. 701
    , 720–721
    (1997). And it is beyond dispute that the right to same-sex
    marriage is not among those rights. See United States v.
    Windsor, 570 U. S. ___, ___ (2013) (ALITO, J., dissenting)
    (slip op., at 7). Indeed:
    “In this country, no State permitted same-sex mar-
    riage until the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court
    held in 2003 that limiting marriage to opposite-sex
    couples violated the State Constitution.         See
    Goodridge v. Department of Public Health, 440 Mass.
    ——————
    riage licenses and conferring those special benefits and obligations
    provided under state law for married persons.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)            3
    ALITO, J., dissenting
    309, 
    798 N.E.2d 941
    . Nor is the right to same-sex
    marriage deeply rooted in the traditions of other na-
    tions. No country allowed same-sex couples to marry
    until the Netherlands did so in 2000.
    “What [those arguing in favor of a constitutional
    right to same sex marriage] seek, therefore, is not the
    protection of a deeply rooted right but the recognition
    of a very new right, and they seek this innovation not
    from a legislative body elected by the people, but from
    unelected judges. Faced with such a request, judges
    have cause for both caution and humility.” Id., at ___
    (slip op., at 7–8) (footnote omitted).
    For today’s majority, it does not matter that the right to
    same-sex marriage lacks deep roots or even that it is
    contrary to long-established tradition. The Justices in the
    majority claim the authority to confer constitutional pro-
    tection upon that right simply because they believe that it
    is fundamental.
    II
    Attempting to circumvent the problem presented by the
    newness of the right found in these cases, the majority
    claims that the issue is the right to equal treatment.
    Noting that marriage is a fundamental right, the majority
    argues that a State has no valid reason for denying that
    right to same-sex couples. This reasoning is dependent
    upon a particular understanding of the purpose of civil
    marriage. Although the Court expresses the point in
    loftier terms, its argument is that the fundamental pur-
    pose of marriage is to promote the well-being of those who
    choose to marry. Marriage provides emotional fulfillment
    and the promise of support in times of need. And by bene-
    fiting persons who choose to wed, marriage indirectly
    benefits society because persons who live in stable, ful-
    filling, and supportive relationships make better citizens.
    It is for these reasons, the argument goes, that States
    4                    OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ALITO, J., dissenting
    encourage and formalize marriage, confer special benefits
    on married persons, and also impose some special obliga-
    tions. This understanding of the States’ reasons for recog-
    nizing marriage enables the majority to argue that same-
    sex marriage serves the States’ objectives in the same way
    as opposite-sex marriage.
    This understanding of marriage, which focuses almost
    entirely on the happiness of persons who choose to marry,
    is shared by many people today, but it is not the traditional
    one. For millennia, marriage was inextricably linked to
    the one thing that only an opposite-sex couple can do:
    procreate.
    Adherents to different schools of philosophy use differ-
    ent terms to explain why society should formalize mar-
    riage and attach special benefits and obligations to per-
    sons who marry.         Here, the States defending their
    adherence to the traditional understanding of marriage
    have explained their position using the pragmatic vocabu-
    lary that characterizes most American political discourse.
    Their basic argument is that States formalize and promote
    marriage, unlike other fulfilling human relationships, in
    order to encourage potentially procreative conduct to take
    place within a lasting unit that has long been thought to
    provide the best atmosphere for raising children. They
    thus argue that there are reasonable secular grounds for
    restricting marriage to opposite-sex couples.
    If this traditional understanding of the purpose of mar-
    riage does not ring true to all ears today, that is probably
    because the tie between marriage and procreation has
    frayed. Today, for instance, more than 40% of all children
    in this country are born to unmarried women.2 This de-
    ——————
    2 See, e.g., Dept. of Health and Human Services, Centers for Disease
    Control and Prevention, National Center for Health Statistics, D.
    Martin, B. Hamilton, M. Osterman, S. Curtin, & T. Matthews, Births:
    Final Data for 2013, 64 National Vital Statistics Reports, No. 1, p. 2
    (Jan. 15, 2015), online at http://www.cdc.gov/nchs/data/nvsr/nvsr64/
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)                   5
    ALITO, J., dissenting
    velopment undoubtedly is both a cause and a result of
    changes in our society’s understanding of marriage.
    While, for many, the attributes of marriage in 21st-
    century America have changed, those States that do not
    want to recognize same-sex marriage have not yet given
    up on the traditional understanding. They worry that by
    officially abandoning the older understanding, they may
    contribute to marriage’s further decay. It is far beyond
    the outer reaches of this Court’s authority to say that a
    State may not adhere to the understanding of marriage
    that has long prevailed, not just in this country and others
    with similar cultural roots, but also in a great variety of
    countries and cultures all around the globe.
    As I wrote in Windsor:
    “The family is an ancient and universal human in-
    stitution. Family structure reflects the characteristics
    of a civilization, and changes in family structure and
    in the popular understanding of marriage and the
    family can have profound effects. Past changes in the
    understanding of marriage—for example, the gradual
    ascendance of the idea that romantic love is a prereq-
    uisite to marriage—have had far-reaching conse-
    quences. But the process by which such consequences
    come about is complex, involving the interaction of
    numerous factors, and tends to occur over an extended
    period of time.
    “We can expect something similar to take place if
    same-sex marriage becomes widely accepted. The
    long-term consequences of this change are not now
    known and are unlikely to be ascertainable for some
    ——————
    nvsr64_01.pdf (all Internet materials as visited June 24, 2015, and
    available in Clerk of Court’s case file); cf. Dept. of Health and Human
    Services, Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, National Center
    for Health Statistics (NCHS), S. Ventura, Changing Patterns of Non-
    martial Childbearing in the United States, NCHS Data Brief, No. 18
    (May 2009), online at http://www.cdc.gov/ nchs/ data/databrief/db18.pdf.
    6                 OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ALITO, J., dissenting
    time to come. There are those who think that allow-
    ing same-sex marriage will seriously undermine the
    institution of marriage. Others think that recogni-
    tion of same-sex marriage will fortify a now-shaky
    institution.
    “At present, no one—including social scientists, phi-
    losophers, and historians—can predict with any cer-
    tainty what the long-term ramifications of widespread
    acceptance of same-sex marriage will be. And judges
    are certainly not equipped to make such an assess-
    ment. The Members of this Court have the authority
    and the responsibility to interpret and apply the Con-
    stitution. Thus, if the Constitution contained a provi-
    sion guaranteeing the right to marry a person of the
    same sex, it would be our duty to enforce that right.
    But the Constitution simply does not speak to the is-
    sue of same-sex marriage. In our system of govern-
    ment, ultimate sovereignty rests with the people, and
    the people have the right to control their own destiny.
    Any change on a question so fundamental should be
    made by the people through their elected officials.”
    570 U. S., at ___ (dissenting opinion) (slip op., at 8–10)
    (citations and footnotes omitted).
    III
    Today’s decision usurps the constitutional right of the
    people to decide whether to keep or alter the traditional
    understanding of marriage. The decision will also have
    other important consequences.
    It will be used to vilify Americans who are unwilling to
    assent to the new orthodoxy. In the course of its opinion,
    the majority compares traditional marriage laws to laws
    that denied equal treatment for African-Americans and
    women. E.g., ante, at 11–13. The implications of this
    analogy will be exploited by those who are determined to
    stamp out every vestige of dissent.
    Cite as: 576 U. S. ____ (2015)            7
    ALITO, J., dissenting
    Perhaps recognizing how its reasoning may be used, the
    majority attempts, toward the end of its opinion, to reas-
    sure those who oppose same-sex marriage that their rights
    of conscience will be protected. Ante, at 26–27. We will
    soon see whether this proves to be true. I assume that
    those who cling to old beliefs will be able to whisper their
    thoughts in the recesses of their homes, but if they repeat
    those views in public, they will risk being labeled as bigots
    and treated as such by governments, employers, and
    schools.
    The system of federalism established by our Constitu-
    tion provides a way for people with different beliefs to live
    together in a single nation. If the issue of same-sex mar-
    riage had been left to the people of the States, it is likely
    that some States would recognize same-sex marriage and
    others would not. It is also possible that some States
    would tie recognition to protection for conscience rights.
    The majority today makes that impossible. By imposing
    its own views on the entire country, the majority facili-
    tates the marginalization of the many Americans who
    have traditional ideas. Recalling the harsh treatment of
    gays and lesbians in the past, some may think that turn-
    about is fair play. But if that sentiment prevails, the Na-
    tion will experience bitter and lasting wounds.
    Today’s decision will also have a fundamental effect on
    this Court and its ability to uphold the rule of law. If a
    bare majority of Justices can invent a new right and im-
    pose that right on the rest of the country, the only real
    limit on what future majorities will be able to do is their
    own sense of what those with political power and cultural
    influence are willing to tolerate. Even enthusiastic sup-
    porters of same-sex marriage should worry about the scope
    of the power that today’s majority claims.
    Today’s decision shows that decades of attempts to
    restrain this Court’s abuse of its authority have failed. A
    lesson that some will take from today’s decision is that
    8                OBERGEFELL v. HODGES
    ALITO, J., dissenting
    preaching about the proper method of interpreting the
    Constitution or the virtues of judicial self-restraint and
    humility cannot compete with the temptation to achieve
    what is viewed as a noble end by any practicable means. I
    do not doubt that my colleagues in the majority sincerely
    see in the Constitution a vision of liberty that happens to
    coincide with their own. But this sincerity is cause for
    concern, not comfort. What it evidences is the deep and
    perhaps irremediable corruption of our legal culture’s
    conception of constitutional interpretation.
    Most Americans—understandably—will cheer or lament
    today’s decision because of their views on the issue of
    same-sex marriage. But all Americans, whatever their
    thinking on that issue, should worry about what the ma-
    jority’s claim of power portends.
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 14-556

Judges: Kennedy

Filed Date: 6/26/2015

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 10/19/2024

Authorities (57)

Varnum v. Brien ( 2009 )

Hernandez v. Robles ( 2006 )

Murphy v. Ramsey ( 1885 )

San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez ( 1973 )

Orr v. Orr ( 1979 )

McDonald v. City of Chicago ( 2010 )

Wilson v. Ake ( 2005 )

Baker v. State ( 1999 )

Califano v. Westcott ( 1979 )

Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey ( 1992 )

Washington v. Glucksberg ( 1997 )

Republican Party of Minnesota v. White ( 2002 )

Smelt v. County of Orange ( 2005 )

Bishop v. Oklahoma Ex Rel. Edmondson ( 2006 )

Lochner v. New York ( 1905 )

arthur-bruno-smelt-christopher-david-hammer-v-county-of-orange-california ( 2006 )

Munn v. Illinois ( 1877 )

Pierce v. Society of Sisters ( 1925 )

Ferguson v. Skrupa ( 1963 )

Dragovich v. United States Department of the Treasury ( 2011 )

View All Authorities »

Cited By (340)

Sara Myers, Eric A. Seiff v. Eric Schneiderman ( 2017 )

Rodney Burr v. Attorney General Delaware ( 2016 )

Kyresha Lefever v. Lanesha Matthews ( 2021 )

Kyresha Lefever v. Lanesha Matthews ( 2021 )

Jennifer Marie Treto v. Sandra Lilibeth Ortega Treto ( 2020 )

In re Adoption of Yasmin S. ( 2021 )

In re Adoption of Yasmin S. ( 2021 )

In re Adoption of Yasmin S. ( 2021 )

United States v. Corrinne Brown ( 2021 )

In re Adoption of Yasmin S. ( 2021 )

In re Adoption of Yasmin S. ( 2021 )

In re Adoption of Yasmin S. ( 2021 )

State of Iowa v. Brian De Arrie McGee ( 2021 )

In re Adoption of Yasmin S. ( 2021 )

In re Adoption of Yasmin S. ( 2021 )

Anita L Sheardown v. Janine Guastella ( 2018 )

In re Adoption of Yasmin S. ( 2021 )

In re Adoption of Yasmin S. ( 2021 )

In re Adoption of Yasmin S. ( 2021 )

SCHNEDLER v. PLATT ( 2019 )

View All Citing Opinions »