Baldwin v. United States ( 2020 )


Menu:
  •                   Cite as: 589 U. S. ____ (2020)            1
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    HOWARD L. BALDWIN, ET UX. v. UNITED STATES
    ON PETITION FOR WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED
    STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT
    No. 19–402.   Decided February 24, 2020
    The petition for a writ of certiorari is denied.
    JUSTICE THOMAS, dissenting from the denial of certiorari.
    Under Chevron deference, courts generally must adopt an
    agency’s interpretation of an ambiguous statute if that in-
    terpretation is “reasonable.” Chevron U. S. A. Inc. v. Natu-
    ral Resources Defense Council, Inc., 
    467 U.S. 837
    , 844
    (1984). Usually, the agency interprets the statute before
    any court has considered the question. But sometimes, the
    agency advances an interpretation after a court has already
    weighed in. In the latter instance, we have held that it “fol-
    lows from Chevron” that a court must abandon its previous
    interpretation in favor of the agency’s interpretation unless
    the prior court decision holds that the statute is unambigu-
    ous. National Cable & Telecommunications Assn. v. Brand
    X Internet Services, 
    545 U.S. 967
    , 982 (2005).
    This petition asks us to reconsider Brand X. In 1992, the
    Ninth Circuit interpreted a deadline for requesting a refund
    from the Internal Revenue Service (IRS). See Anderson v.
    United States, 
    966 F.2d 487
    , 489 (interpreting 
    26 U.S. C
    .
    §7502). Nineteen years later—and two months after peti-
    tioners claim to have mailed their paperwork to the IRS—
    the Treasury Department adopted a different interpreta-
    tion through an informal rulemaking.             See 26 CFR
    § 301.7502–1(e)(2)(i) (2012). When petitioners sued the IRS
    to recover their refund, the Ninth Circuit followed Brand X,
    deferred to the agency’s new interpretation, and rejected
    petitioners’ claim. 
    921 F.3d 836
    , 843 (2019).
    2                   BALDWIN v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    Although I authored Brand X, “it is never too late to ‘sur-
    rende[r] former views to a better considered position.’ ”
    South Dakota v. Wayfair, Inc., 585 U. S. ___, ___ (2018)
    (THOMAS, J., concurring) (slip op., at 1) (quoting McGrath v.
    Kristensen, 
    340 U.S. 162
    , 178 (1950) (Jackson, J., concur-
    ring)). Brand X appears to be inconsistent with the Consti-
    tution, the Administrative Procedure Act (APA), and tradi-
    tional tools of statutory interpretation. Because I would
    revisit Brand X, I respectfully dissent from the denial of
    certiorari.
    I
    My skepticism of Brand X begins at its foundation—
    Chevron deference. In 1984, a bare quorum of six Justices
    decided Chevron. The Court reasoned that “if [a] statute is
    silent or ambiguous with respect to the specific issue, the
    question for the court is whether the agency’s answer is
    based on a permissible construction of the 
    statute.” 467 U.S., at 843
    . The decision rests on the fiction that silent or
    ambiguous statutes are an implicit delegation from Con-
    gress to agencies. 
    Id., at 843–844.
    Chevron is in serious
    tension with the Constitution, the APA, and over 100 years
    of judicial decisions.1
    A
    Chevron compels judges to abdicate the judicial power
    without constitutional sanction. The Vesting Clause of Ar-
    ticle III gives “[t]he judicial Power of the United States” to
    “one supreme Court, and . . . such inferior Courts as the
    Congress may from time to time ordain and establish.” §1.
    ——————
    1 As I have previously noted, Chevron arguably sets out an “interpre-
    tive too[l]” and so may not be entitled to stare decisis treatment. Perez v.
    Mortgage Bankers Assn., 
    575 U.S. 92
    , 114, n. 1 (2015) (opinion concur-
    ring in judgment) (citing C. Nelson, Statutory Interpretation 701 (2011)).
    The same can be said of National Cable & Telecommunications Assn. v.
    Brand X Internet Services, 
    545 U.S. 967
    (2005).
    Cite as: 589 U. S. ____ (2020)            3
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    As I have previously explained, “the judicial power, as orig-
    inally understood, requires a court to exercise its independ-
    ent judgment in interpreting and expounding upon the
    laws.” Perez v. Mortgage Bankers Assn., 
    575 U.S. 92
    , 119
    (2015) (opinion concurring in judgment). The Framers an-
    ticipated that legal texts would sometimes be ambiguous,
    and they understood the judicial power “to include the
    power to resolve these ambiguities over time” in judicial
    proceedings. 
    Ibid. The Court’s decision
    in Chevron, how-
    ever, “precludes judges from exercising that judgment.”
    Michigan v. EPA, 
    576 U.S. 743
    , ___ (2015) (THOMAS, J.,
    concurring) (slip op., at 2) (quoting 
    Perez, supra, at 119
    (THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment)).
    Chevron also gives federal agencies unconstitutional
    power. Executive agencies enjoy only “the executive
    Power.” Art. II, §1. But when they receive Chevron defer-
    ence, they arguably exercise “[t]he judicial Power of the
    United States,” which is vested in the courts. Chevron can-
    not be salvaged by saying instead that agencies are “en-
    gaged in the ‘formulation of policy.’ ” 
    Michigan, supra
    , at
    ___ (THOMAS, J., concurring) (slip op., at 3) (quoting Chev-
    
    ron, supra, at 843
    ). If that is true, then agencies are uncon-
    stitutionally exercising “legislative Powers” vested in Con-
    gress. See Art. I, §1.
    This apparent abdication by the Judiciary and usurpa-
    tion by the Executive is not a harmless transfer of power.
    The Constitution carefully imposes structural constraints
    on all three branches, and the exercise of power free of those
    accompanying restraints subverts the design of the Consti-
    tution’s ratifiers. The Constitution shielded judges from
    both the “external threats” of politics and “the ‘internal
    threat’ of ‘human will’ ” by providing tenure and salary pro-
    tections during good behavior and by insulating judges from
    the process of writing the laws they are asked to interpret.
    
    Perez, supra, at 120
    (THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment)
    (quoting P. Hamburger, Law and Judicial Duty 507, 508
    4                BALDWIN v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    (2008)). The Constitution also restricted the legislative
    power by dividing it between two Houses that check each
    other, one of which was kept close to the people through bi-
    ennial elections. See Department of Transportation v. As-
    sociation of American Railroads, 
    575 U.S. 43
    , 74 (2015)
    (THOMAS, J., concurring in judgment). When the Executive
    exercises judicial or legislative power, however, it does so
    largely free of these safeguards. The Executive is not insu-
    lated from external threats, and it is by definition an agent
    of will, not judgment. The Executive also faces election less
    frequently than do Members of the House, and its power is
    vested in a single person.
    Perhaps worst of all, Chevron deference undermines the
    ability of the Judiciary to perform its checking function on
    the other branches. The Founders expected that the Fed-
    eral Government’s powers would remain separated—and
    the people’s liberty secure—only if the branches could check
    each other. The Judiciary’s checking power is its authority
    to apply the law in cases or controversies properly before it.
    See 
    Michigan, supra
    , at ___, n. 1 (THOMAS, J., concurring)
    (slip op., at 4, n. 1); 
    Perez, supra, at 124
    –126 (THOMAS, J.,
    concurring in judgment). When the Executive is free to dic-
    tate the outcome of cases through erroneous interpreta-
    tions, the courts cannot check the Executive by applying the
    correct interpretation of the law.
    B
    Chevron deference appears to be inappropriate in many
    cases for another reason: It is likely contrary to the APA,
    “which [Chevron] did not even bother to cite.” United States
    v. Mead Corp., 
    533 U.S. 218
    , 241 (2001) (Scalia, J., dissent-
    ing). The APA provides that, “[t]o the extent necessary to
    decision and when presented, the reviewing court shall de-
    cide all relevant questions of law, interpret constitutional
    and statutory provisions, and determine the meaning or ap-
    plicability of the terms of an agency action.” 
    5 U.S. C
    . §706.
    Cite as: 589 U. S. ____ (2020)             5
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    When the APA was enacted, the meaning of a statute was
    considered a question of law. The Court recognized as much
    in Trust of Bingham v. Commissioner, 
    325 U.S. 365
    (1945),
    writing that questions about “the meaning of the words of
    [the statute]” were “questions of law,” 
    id., at 371.
    See also
    Brown, Fact and Law in Judicial Review, 56 Harv. L. Rev.
    899, 901 (1943); J. Thayer, Preliminary Treatise on Evi-
    dence at the Common Law 193 (1898). Moreover, §706
    “places the court’s duty to interpret statutes on an equal
    footing with its duty to interpret the Constitution, and
    courts never defer to agencies in reading the Constitution.”
    Duffy, Administrative Common Law in Judicial Review, 77
    Texas L. Rev. 113, 194 (1998). Finally, the deferential
    standards of review elsewhere in the APA—which require
    courts to “hold unlawful and set aside agency action, find-
    ings, and conclusions found to be . . . arbitrary, capricious,
    an abuse of discretion . . . [or] unsupported by substantial
    evidence,” §706(2)—do not mention statutory interpreta-
    tion. See 
    id., at 194.
    Even if Chevron raised no constitu-
    tional concerns, these statutory arguments give rise to se-
    rious doubts about Chevron’s legitimacy.
    C
    In the past, I have left open the possibility that “there is
    some unique historical justification for deferring to federal
    agencies.” 
    Michigan, supra
    , at ___ (concurring opinion)
    (slip op., at 4). It now appears to me that there is no such
    special justification and that Chevron is inconsistent with
    accepted principles of statutory interpretation from the
    first century of the Republic.
    For most of the 19th century, there was no general
    federal-question jurisdiction. Instead, review was available
    in a common-law action, under certain limited grants of
    federal-question jurisdiction, or by extraordinary writ (such
    as a writ of mandamus). Bamzai, The Origins of Judicial
    Deference to Executive Interpretation, 126 Yale L. J. 908,
    6                BALDWIN v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    948 (2017).
    When 18th- and 19th-century courts decided questions of
    statutory interpretation in common-law actions or under
    federal-question jurisdiction, they did not apply anything
    resembling Chevron deference. Judges interpreted statutes
    according to their independent judgment. For example, in
    a lawsuit involving a federal land patent, the Court simply
    “inquire[d] whether the statute, rightly construed, defeated
    [the respondent’s] otherwise perfect right to the patent.”
    Johnson v. Towsley, 
    13 Wall. 72
    , 88 (1871); see also 
    id., at 91.
    When courts disagreed with the Executive’s interpreta-
    tion, they gave no weight to it. See United States v. Dick-
    son, 
    15 Pet. 141
    , 161–162 (1841) (Story, J., for the Court).
    Courts did apply traditional interpretive canons that ac-
    corded respect to certain contemporaneous, consistent in-
    terpretations of statutes by executive officers. See 
    Bamzai, supra, at 933
    –947. In perhaps its most famous articulation,
    the Court wrote that “[i]n the construction of a doubtful and
    ambiguous law, the contemporaneous construction of those
    who were called upon to act under the law, and were ap-
    pointed to carry its provisions into effect, is entitled to very
    great respect.” Edwards’ Lessee v. Darby, 
    12 Wheat. 206
    ,
    210 (1827). The Court continued to apply this approach
    throughout the 19th century. See, e.g., United States v.
    State Bank of N. C., 
    6 Pet. 29
    , 39–40 (1832) (“[T]he construc-
    tion which we have given to the terms of the ac[t] is that
    which is understood to have been practically acted upon by
    the government, as well as by individuals, ever since its en-
    actment. . . . We think the practice was founded in the true
    exposition of the terms and intent of the act: but if it were
    susceptible of some doubt, so long an acquiescence in it
    would justify us in yielding to it as a safe and reasonable
    exposition”); Surgett v. Lapice, 
    8 How. 48
    , 68 (1850) (simi-
    lar). And when the interpretation “has not been uniform,”
    Cite as: 589 U. S. ____ (2020)                   7
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    the Court declined to give weight to executive interpreta-
    tions. See Merritt v. Cameron, 
    137 U.S. 542
    , 552 (1890).2
    This practice is consistent with the more general princi-
    ple of “liquidation,” in which consistent and longstanding
    interpretations of an ambiguous text could fix its meaning.
    See Stuart v. Laird, 1 Cranch 299, 309 (1803) (“[I]t is suffi-
    cient to observe, that practice and acquiescence under [a
    statute] for a period of several years, commencing with the
    organization of the judicial system, affords an irrefutable
    answer, and has indeed fixed the construction”); see also
    Respublica v. Roberts, 2 Dall. 124, 125 (Pa. 1791); Minnis v.
    Echols, 
    12 Va. 31
    , 36 (1808) (opinion of Roane, J.); Packard
    v. Richardson, 
    17 Mass. 122
    , 144 (1821); Nelson, Stare De-
    cisis and Demonstrably Erroneous Precedents, 
    87 Va. L
    . Rev. 1, 14–21 (2001). Chevron is not a species of liquida-
    tion because it “give[s] administrative agencies substan-
    tially more freedom to depart from settled understandings.”
    Nelson, Originalism and Interpretive Conventions, 70 U.
    Chi. L. Rev. 519, 551–552, n. 137 (2003). But the existence
    of liquidation by nonexecutive actors confirms that “the
    pedigree and contemporaneity of the interpretation” mat-
    tered in the early Republic, not the mere fact that it was an
    interpretation by the Executive. 
    Bamzai, supra, at 916
    .
    The standard applied in mandamus cases might appear
    to be a forerunner of Chevron deference, but the comparison
    dissipates upon close examination. In mandamus cases,
    courts generally would not second-guess legal interpreta-
    tions made “in the discharge of any official duty, partaking
    in any respect of an executive character,” but they would
    “enforce the performance of a mere ministerial act.” Ken-
    dall v. United States ex rel. Stokes, 
    12 Pet. 524
    , 610 (1838).
    ——————
    2 The phrasing and substance of these canons vary, and I express no
    opinion on their details, such as whether congressional acquiescence in
    a longstanding interpretation was required. See P. Hamburger, Is Ad-
    ministrative Law Unlawful? 583, n. 24 (2014).
    8                BALDWIN v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    The “application of th[is] mandamus standard was a conse-
    quence solely of the form of relief requested,” not a require-
    ment that courts defer to the Executive’s reasonable inter-
    pretation of a statute. Bamzai, 126 Yale L. J., at 958. The
    Court even acknowledged in mandamus cases that “[i]f a
    suit should come before this Court, which involved the con-
    struction of any of these laws, the Court certainly would not
    be bound to adopt the construction given by the head of a
    department.” Decatur v. Paulding, 
    14 Pet. 497
    , 515 (1840);
    see also United States ex rel. Dunlap v. Black, 
    128 U.S. 40
    ,
    48–49 (1888).
    The rule in Chevron thus differs from historical practice
    in at least four ways. First, it requires deference regardless
    of whether the interpretation began around the time of the
    statute’s enactment (and thus might reflect the statute’s
    original meaning). Second, it requires deference regardless
    of whether an agency has changed its position. Third, it
    requires deference regardless of whether the agency’s inter-
    pretation has the sanction of long practice. And fourth, it
    applies in actions in which courts historically have inter-
    preted statutes independently.
    II
    Even if Chevron deference were sound, I have become in-
    creasingly convinced that Brand X was still wrongly de-
    cided because it is even more inconsistent with the Consti-
    tution and traditional tools of statutory interpretation than
    Chevron.
    A
    By requiring courts to overrule their own precedent
    simply because an agency later adopts a different interpre-
    tation of a statute, Brand X likely conflicts with Article III
    of the Constitution. The Constitution imposes a duty on
    judges to exercise the judicial power. 
    See supra, at 2
    . That
    power is to be exercised “for the purpose of giving effect to
    Cite as: 589 U. S. ____ (2020)             9
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    the will of the Legislature; or, in other words, to the will of
    the law.” Osborn v. Bank of United States, 
    9 Wheat. 738
    ,
    866 (1824) (Marshall, C. J., for the Court). But Brand X
    directs courts to give effect to the will of the Executive by
    depriving judges of the ability to follow their own precedent.
    This rule raises grave Article III concerns, no less than if it
    allowed judges to substitute their policy preferences for the
    original meaning of a statute.
    The Article III duty to decide cases even when the Exec-
    utive disagrees with the conclusion has long been recog-
    nized by this Court. In a statutory interpretation case in
    1841, the Court acknowledged “the uniform construction
    given to the act . . . ever since its passage, by the Treasury
    Department,” but stated that “if it is not in conformity to
    the true intendment and provisions of the law, it cannot be
    permitted to conclude the judgment of a Court of justice.”
    
    Dickson, 15 Pet., at 161
    . Justice Story, writing for the
    Court, admonished that
    “it is not to be forgotten, that ours is a government of
    laws, and not of men; and that the Judicial Department
    has imposed upon it, by the Constitution, the solemn
    duty to interpret the laws, in the last resort; and how-
    ever disagreeable that duty may be, in cases where its
    own judgment shall differ from that of other high func-
    tionaries, it is not at liberty to surrender, or to waive
    it.” 
    Id., at 162.
    Brand X is in serious tension with this understanding of
    Article III.
    Brand X takes on the constitutional deficiencies of Chev-
    ron and exacerbates them. Chevron requires judges to sur-
    render their independent judgment to the will of the Exec-
    utive, 
    see supra, at 3
    ; Brand X forces them to do so despite
    a controlling precedent. Chevron transfers power to agen-
    cies, 
    see supra, at 3
    ; Brand X gives agencies the power to
    10               BALDWIN v. UNITED STATES
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    effectively overrule judicial precedents. Chevron with-
    draws a crucial check on the Executive from the separation
    of powers, 
    see supra, at 4
    ; Brand X gives the Executive the
    ability to neutralize a previously exercised check by the Ju-
    diciary. But, with this said, there is no need to question
    Chevron in order to recognize the heightened constitutional
    harms wrought by Brand X.
    B
    Brand X also seems to be strongly at odds with tradi-
    tional tools of statutory interpretation. As discussed above,
    early federal courts afforded weight to longstanding execu-
    tive interpretations of a law that were made contemporane-
    ously with its passage and that were uniformly maintained.
    
    See supra, at 5
    –8. Brand X, however, mandates deference
    to an executive interpretation that is neither contempora-
    neous nor settled.
    Under traditional rules of statutory interpretation, this
    Court declined to give weight to late-arising or inconsistent
    statutory interpretations by the Executive. In Merritt v.
    Cameron, for example, the Court rejected an interpretation
    offered by the Executive because there was no “long and un-
    interrupted . . . departmental construction . . . as will bring
    the case within the rule announced at an early day in this
    court, and followed in very many 
    cases.” 137 U.S., at 552
    ;
    see also United States v. Alabama Great Southern R. Co.,
    
    142 U.S. 615
    , 621 (1892). Even if only to resolve the ten-
    sion with our traditional approach to statutory interpreta-
    tion, we should revisit Brand X.
    III
    Regrettably, Brand X has taken this Court to the preci-
    pice of administrative absolutism. Under its rule of
    deference, agencies are free to invent new (purported) inter-
    pretations of statutes and then require courts to reject
    their own prior interpretations. Brand X may well follow from
    Cite as: 589 U. S. ____ (2020)          11
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    Chevron, but in so doing, it poignantly lays bare the flaws
    of our entire executive-deference jurisprudence. Even if the
    Court is not willing to question Chevron itself, at the very
    least, we should consider taking a step away from the abyss
    by revisiting Brand X.