Berisha v. Lawson ( 2021 )


Menu:
  •                  Cite as: 594 U. S. ____ (2021)           1
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    SHKELZEN BERISHA v. GUY LAWSON, ET AL.
    ON PETITION FOR WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED
    STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE ELEVENTH CIRCUIT
    No. 20–1063.   Decided July 2, 2021
    The petition for a writ of certiorari is denied.
    JUSTICE THOMAS, dissenting from the denial of certiorari.
    In 2015, Guy Lawson published a book detailing the “true
    story” of how three Miami youngsters became international
    arms dealers. 
    973 F. 3d 1304
    , 1306 (CA11 2020). A central
    plot point involves the protagonists’ travels to Albania and
    subsequent run-ins with the “Albanian mafia,” a key figure
    of which, the book claims, is petitioner Shkelzen Berisha.
    The book performed well, and Lawson eventually sold the
    movie rights to Warner Bros., which made the feature film
    War Dogs.
    Unhappy with his portrayal, Berisha sued Lawson for
    defamation under Florida law. According to Berisha, he is
    not associated with the Albanian mafia—or any dangerous
    group—and Lawson recklessly relied on flimsy sources to
    contend that he was.
    The District Court granted summary judgment in favor
    of Lawson. Setting aside questions of truth or falsity, the
    court simply asked whether Berisha is a “public figure.”
    Why? Because under this Court’s First Amendment juris-
    prudence, public figures cannot establish libel without
    proving by clear and convincing evidence that the defend-
    ant acted with “ ‘actual malice’ ”—that is with knowledge
    that the published material “was false or with reckless dis-
    regard of whether it was false.” New York Times Co. v. Sul-
    livan, 
    376 U. S. 254
    , 280 (1964); accord, Gertz v. Robert
    Welch, Inc., 
    418 U. S. 323
    , 334–335, 342 (1974); Curtis Pub-
    2                    BERISHA v. LAWSON
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    lishing Co. v. Butts, 
    388 U. S. 130
    , 155 (1967). After con-
    cluding that Berisha is a public figure (or at least is one for
    purposes of Albanian weapons-trafficking stories), the court
    found that he had not satisfied this high standard. The
    Eleventh Circuit affirmed.
    Berisha now asks this Court to reconsider the “actual
    malice” requirement as it applies to public figures. As I ex-
    plained recently, we should. See McKee v. Cosby, 586 U. S.
    ___, ___ (2019) (opinion concurring in denial of certiorari)
    (slip op., at 2).
    This Court’s pronouncement that the First Amendment
    requires public figures to establish actual malice bears “no
    relation to the text, history, or structure of the Constitu-
    tion.” Tah v. Global Witness Publishing, Inc., 
    991 F. 3d 231
    ,
    251 (CADC 2021) (Silberman, J., dissenting) (emphasis de-
    leted). In fact, the opposite rule historically prevailed:
    “[T]he common law deemed libels against public figures to
    be . . . more serious and injurious than ordinary libels.”
    McKee, 586 U. S., at ___ (opinion of THOMAS, J.) (slip op., at
    7).
    The Court provided scant explanation for the decision to
    erect a new hurdle for public-figure plaintiffs so long after
    the First Amendment’s ratification. In Gertz, for example,
    the Court reasoned that public figures are fair targets be-
    cause “they invite attention and comment.” 
    418 U. S., at 345
    . That is, “public officials and public figures have vol-
    untarily exposed themselves to increased risk of injury from
    defamatory falsehood.” 
    Ibid.
     But it is unclear why expos-
    ing oneself to an increased risk of becoming a victim neces-
    sarily means forfeiting the remedies legislatures put in
    place for such victims. And, even assuming that it is some-
    times fair to blame the victim, it is less clear why the rule
    still applies when the public figure “has not voluntarily
    sought attention.” 
    378 F. Supp. 3d 1145
    , 1158 (SD Fla.
    2018); see also Rosanova v. Playboy Enterprises, Inc., 
    580 F. 2d 859
    , 861 (CA5 1978) (“It is no answer to the assertion
    Cite as: 594 U. S. ____ (2021)              3
    THOMAS, J., dissenting
    that one is a public figure to say, truthfully, that one doesn’t
    choose to be”).
    The lack of historical support for this Court’s actual-mal-
    ice requirement is reason enough to take a second look at
    the Court’s doctrine. Our reconsideration is all the more
    needed because of the doctrine’s real-world effects. Public
    figure or private, lies impose real harm. Take, for instance,
    the shooting at a pizza shop rumored to be “the home of a
    Satanic child sex abuse ring involving top Democrats such
    as Hillary Clinton,” Kennedy, ‘Pizzagate’ Gunman Sen-
    tenced to 4 Years in Prison, NPR (June 22, 2017),
    www.npr.org / section / thetwo-way / 2017 / 06 / 22 / 533941689/
    pizzagate-gunman-sentenced-to-4-years-in-prison. Or con-
    sider how online posts falsely labeling someone as “a thief,
    a fraudster, and a pedophile” can spark the need to set up
    a home-security system. Hill, A Vast Web of Vengeance,
    N. Y. Times (Jan. 30, 2021), www.nytimes.com/2021/01/30/
    technology/change-my-google-results.html. Or think of
    those who have had job opportunities withdrawn over false
    accusations of racism or anti-Semitism. See, e.g., Wemple,
    Bloomberg Law Tried To Suppress Its Erroneous Labor
    Dept. Story, Washington Post (Sept. 6, 2019), www.
    washingtonpost.com / opinions / 2019 / 09 / 06 / bloomberg-law-
    tried-suppress-its-erroneous-labor-dept-story.          Or read
    about Kathrine McKee—surely this Court should not re-
    move a woman’s right to defend her reputation in court
    simply because she accuses a powerful man of rape. See
    McKee, 586 U. S., at ___–___ (opinion of THOMAS, J.) (slip
    op., at 1–2).
    The proliferation of falsehoods is, and always has been, a
    serious matter. Instead of continuing to insulate those who
    perpetrate lies from traditional remedies like libel suits, we
    should give them only the protection the First Amendment
    requires. I would grant certiorari.
    Cite as: 594 U. S. ____ (2021)              1
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
    SHKELZEN BERISHA v. GUY LAWSON, ET AL.
    ON PETITION FOR WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED
    STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE ELEVENTH CIRCUIT
    No. 20–1063.   Decided July 2, 2021
    JUSTICE GORSUCH, dissenting from the denial of certio-
    rari.
    The Bill of Rights protects the freedom of the press not as
    a favor to a particular industry, but because democracy can-
    not function without the free exchange of ideas. To govern
    themselves wisely, the framers knew, people must be able
    to speak and write, question old assumptions, and offer new
    insights. “If a nation expects to be ignorant and free . . . it
    expects what never was and never will be. . . . There is no
    safe deposit for [liberty] but with the people . . . [w]here the
    press is free, and every man able to read.” Letter from T.
    Jefferson to C. Yancey (Jan. 6, 1816), in 10 The Writings of
    Thomas Jefferson 4 (P. Ford ed. 1899).
    Like most rights, this one comes with corresponding du-
    ties. The right to due process in court entails the duty to
    abide the results that process produces. The right to speak
    freely includes the duty to allow others to have their say.
    From the outset, the right to publish was no different. At
    the founding, the freedom of the press generally meant the
    government could not impose prior restraints preventing
    individuals from publishing what they wished. But none of
    that meant publishers could defame people, ruining careers
    or lives, without consequence. Rather, those exercising the
    freedom of the press had a responsibility to try to get the
    facts right—or, like anyone else, answer in tort for the inju-
    ries they caused.
    This principle extended far back in the common law and
    far forward into our Nation’s history. As Blackstone put it,
    2                    BERISHA v. LAWSON
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    “[e]very freeman has an undoubted right to lay what senti-
    ments he pleases before the public,” but if he publishes
    falsehoods “he must take the consequence of his own temer-
    ity.” 4 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of Eng-
    land 151–152 (1769). Or as Justice Story later explained,
    “the liberty of the press do[es] not authorize malicious and
    injurious defamation.” Dexter v. Spear, 
    7 F. Cas. 624
     (No.
    3,867) (CC RI 1825).
    This was “[t]he accepted view” in this Nation for more
    than two centuries. Herbert v. Lando, 
    441 U. S. 153
    , 158–
    159, and n. 4 (1979). Accordingly, “from the very founding”
    the law of defamation was “almost exclusively the business
    of state courts and legislatures.” Gertz v. Robert Welch,
    Inc., 
    418 U. S. 323
    , 369–370 (1974) (White, J., dissenting).
    As a rule, that meant all persons could recover damages for
    injuries caused by false publications about them. See Kur-
    land, The Original Understanding of the Freedom of the
    Press Provision of the First Amendment, 55 Miss. L. J. 225,
    234–237 (1985); J. Baker, An Introduction to English Legal
    History 474–475 (5th ed. 2019); Epstein, Was New York
    Times v. Sullivan Wrong? 
    53 U. Chi. L. Rev. 782
    , 801–802
    (1986); Peck v. Tribune Co., 
    214 U. S. 185
    , 189 (1909).
    This changed only in 1964. In New York Times Co. v.
    Sullivan, 
    376 U. S. 254
     (1964), this Court declared that
    public officials could no longer recover for defamation as
    everyone had for centuries. Now, public officials could pre-
    vail only by showing that an injurious falsehood was pub-
    lished with “ ‘actual malice.’ ” 
    Id.,
     at 279–280. Three years
    later, the Court extended its actual malice standard from
    “public officials” in government to “public figures” outside
    government. See generally Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts,
    
    388 U. S. 130
     (1967). Later still, the Court cast the net even
    wider, applying its new standard to those who have
    achieved “pervasive fame or notoriety” and those “limited”
    public figures who “voluntarily injec[t]” themselves or are
    “drawn into a particular public controversy.” Gertz, 418
    Cite as: 594 U. S. ____ (2021)            3
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    U. S., at 351. The Court viewed these innovations “over-
    turning 200 years of libel law” as “necessary to implement
    the First Amendment interest in ‘uninhibited, robust, and
    wide-open’ debate on public issues.” Dun & Bradstreet, Inc.
    v. Greenmoss Builders, Inc., 
    472 U. S. 749
    , 766 (1985)
    (White, J., concurring in judgment).
    Since 1964, however, our Nation’s media landscape has
    shifted in ways few could have foreseen. Back then, build-
    ing printing presses and amassing newspaper distribution
    networks demanded significant investment and expertise.
    See Logan, Rescuing Our Democracy by Rethinking New
    York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 81 Ohio St. L. J. 759, 794 (2020)
    (Logan). Broadcasting required licenses for limited air-
    waves and access to highly specialized equipment. See 
    ibid.
    Comparatively large companies dominated the press, often
    employing legions of investigative reporters, editors, and
    fact-checkers. See 
    id.,
     at 794–795. But “[t]he liberty of the
    press” has never been “confined to newspapers and period-
    icals”; it has always “comprehend[ed] every sort of publica-
    tion which affords a vehicle of information and opinion.”
    Lovell v. City of Griffin, 
    303 U. S. 444
    , 452 (1938); see also
    Sentelle, Freedom of the Press: A Liberty for All or a Privi-
    lege for a Few? 2013 Cato S. Ct. Rev. 15, 30–34. And thanks
    to revolutions in technology, today virtually anyone in this
    country can publish virtually anything for immediate con-
    sumption virtually anywhere in the world. Logan 803 (not-
    ing there are 4 billion active social media users worldwide).
    The effect of these technological changes on our Nation’s
    media may be hard to overstate. Large numbers of news-
    papers and periodicals have failed. See Grieco, Pew
    Research Center, Fast Facts About the Newspaper Indus-
    try’s Financial Struggles as McClatchy Files for Bank-
    ruptcy (Feb. 14, 2020), http://www.pewresearch.org/fact
    -tank/2020/02/14/fast-facts-about-the-newspaper-industrys
    -financial-struggles/. Network news has lost most of its
    viewers. Pew Research Center, Network Evening News
    4                    BERISHA v. LAWSON
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    Ratings (Mar. 13, 2006), https://www.journalism.org/
    numbers/network-evening-news-ratings/. With their fall
    has come the rise of 24-hour cable news and online media
    platforms that “monetize anything that garners clicks.” Lo-
    gan 800. No doubt, this new media world has many vir-
    tues—not least the access it affords those who seek infor-
    mation about and the opportunity to debate public affairs.
    At the same time, some reports suggest that our new media
    environment also facilitates the spread of disinformation.
    Id., at 804. A study of one social network reportedly found
    that “falsehood and rumor dominated truth by every metric,
    reaching more people, penetrating deeper . . . and doing so
    more quickly than accurate statements.” Id., at 804, n. 302;
    see Vosoughi, Roy, & Aral, The Spread of True and False
    News Online, Science Magazine, Mar. 9, 2018, pp. 1146–
    1151. All of which means that “the distribution of disinfor-
    mation”—which “costs almost nothing to generate”—has
    become a “profitable” business while “the economic model
    that supported reporters, fact-checking, and editorial over-
    sight” has “deeply erod[ed].” Logan 800.
    It’s hard not to wonder what these changes mean for the
    law. In 1964, the Court may have seen the actual malice
    standard as necessary “to ensure that dissenting or critical
    voices are not crowded out of public debate.” Brief in Oppo-
    sition 22. But if that justification had force in a world with
    comparatively few platforms for speech, it’s less obvious
    what force it has in a world in which everyone carries a
    soapbox in their hands. Surely, too, the Court in 1964 may
    have thought the actual malice standard justified in part
    because other safeguards existed to deter the dissemination
    of defamatory falsehoods and misinformation. Logan 794–
    795. In that era, many major media outlets employed fact-
    checkers and editors, id., at 795, and one could argue that
    most strived to report true stories because, as “the public
    gain[ed] greater confidence that what they read [wa]s true,”
    they would be willing to “pay more for the information so
    Cite as: 594 U. S. ____ (2021)            5
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    provided,” Epstein, 53 U. Chi. L. Rev., at 812. Less clear is
    what sway these justifications hold in a new era where the
    old economic model that supported reporters, fact-checking,
    and editorial oversight is disappearing.
    These questions lead to other even more fundamental
    ones. When the Court originally adopted the actual malice
    standard, it took the view that tolerating the publication of
    some false information was a necessary and acceptable cost
    to pay to ensure truthful statements vital to democratic
    self-government were not inadvertently suppressed. See
    Sullivan, 
    376 U. S., at
    270–272. But over time the actual
    malice standard has evolved from a high bar to recovery
    into an effective immunity from liability. Statistics show
    that the number of trials involving defamation, privacy, and
    related claims based on media publications has declined dra-
    matically over the past few decades: In the 1980s there were
    on average 27 per year; in 2017 there were 3. Logan 808–
    810 (surveying data from the Media Law Resource Center).
    For those rare plaintiffs able to secure a favorable jury ver-
    dict, nearly one out of five today will have their awards
    eliminated in post-trial motions practice. Id., at 809. And
    any verdict that manages to make it past all that is still
    likely to be reversed on appeal. Perhaps in part because
    this Court’s jurisprudence has been understood to invite ap-
    pellate courts to engage in the unusual practice of revisiting
    a jury’s factual determinations de novo, it appears just 1 of
    every 3 jury awards now survives appeal. Id., at 809–810.
    The bottom line? It seems that publishing without inves-
    tigation, fact-checking, or editing has become the optimal
    legal strategy. See id., at 778–779. Under the actual malice
    regime as it has evolved, “ignorance is bliss.” Id., at 778.
    Combine this legal incentive with the business incentives
    fostered by our new media world and the deck seems
    stacked against those with traditional (and expensive) jour-
    nalistic standards—and in favor of those who can dissemi-
    6                   BERISHA v. LAWSON
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    nate the most sensational information as efficiently as pos-
    sible without any particular concern for truth. See ibid.
    What started in 1964 with a decision to tolerate the occa-
    sional falsehood to ensure robust reporting by a compara-
    tive handful of print and broadcast outlets has evolved into
    an ironclad subsidy for the publication of falsehoods by
    means and on a scale previously unimaginable. Id., at 804.
    As Sullivan’s actual malice standard has come to apply in
    our new world, it’s hard not to ask whether it now even
    “cut[s] against the very values underlying the decision.”
    Kagan, A Libel Story: Sullivan Then and Now, 18 L. & Soc.
    Inquiry 197, 207 (1993) (reviewing A. Lewis, Make No Law:
    The Sullivan Case and the First Amendment (1991)). If en-
    suring an informed democratic debate is the goal, how well
    do we serve that interest with rules that no longer merely
    tolerate but encourage falsehoods in quantities no one could
    have envisioned almost 60 years ago?
    Other developments raise still more questions. In 1964,
    the Court may have thought the actual malice standard
    would apply only to a small number of prominent govern-
    mental officials whose names were always in the news and
    whose actions involved the administration of public affairs.
    Here again, the Court may have thought that allowing
    some falsehoods about these persons and topics was an ac-
    ceptable price to pay to ensure truthful statements vital to
    democratic self-government were not inadvertently sup-
    pressed. Perhaps the Court weighed the costs and benefits
    similarly when it extended the actual malice standard to
    the “pervasively famous” and “limited purpose public fig-
    ures.”
    But today’s world casts a new light on these judgments
    as well. Now, private citizens can become “public figures”
    on social media overnight. Individuals can be deemed “fa-
    mous” because of their notoriety in certain channels of our
    now-highly segmented media even as they remain un-
    known in most. See, e.g., Hibdon v. Grabowski, 195 S. W.
    Cite as: 594 U. S. ____ (2021)            7
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    3d 48, 59, 62 (Tenn. App. 2005) (holding that an individual
    was a limited-purpose public figure in part because he “en-
    tered into the jet ski business and voluntarily advertised on
    the news group rec.sport.jetski, an Internet site that is ac-
    cessible worldwide”). Lower courts have even said that an
    individual can become a limited purpose public figure
    simply by defending himself from a defamatory statement.
    See Berisha v. Lawson, 
    973 F. 3d 1304
    , 1311 (CA11 2020).
    Other persons, such as victims of sexual assault seeking to
    confront their assailants, might choose to enter the public
    square only reluctantly and yet wind up treated as limited
    purpose public figures too. See McKee v. Cosby, 586 U. S.
    ___, ___ (2019) (THOMAS, J., concurring in denial of certio-
    rari) (slip op., at 1). In many ways, it seems we have arrived
    in a world that dissenters proposed but majorities rejected
    in the Sullivan line of cases—one in which, “voluntarily or
    not, we are all public [figures] to some degree.” Gertz, 
    418 U. S., at 364
     (Brennan, J., dissenting) (brackets and inter-
    nal quotation marks omitted).
    Again, it’s unclear how well these modern developments
    serve Sullivan’s original purposes. Not only has the doc-
    trine evolved into a subsidy for published falsehoods on a
    scale no one could have foreseen, it has come to leave far
    more people without redress than anyone could have pre-
    dicted. And the very categories and tests this Court in-
    vented and instructed lower courts to use in this area—
    “pervasively famous,” “limited purpose public figure”—
    seem increasingly malleable and even archaic when almost
    anyone can attract some degree of public notoriety in some
    media segment. Rules intended to ensure a robust debate
    over actions taken by high public officials carrying out the
    public’s business increasingly seem to leave even ordinary
    Americans without recourse for grievous defamation. At
    least as they are applied today, it’s far from obvious
    whether Sullivan’s rules do more to encourage people of
    8                     BERISHA v. LAWSON
    GORSUCH, J., dissenting
    goodwill to engage in democratic self-governance or discour-
    age them from risking even the slightest step toward public
    life.
    “In a country like ours, where the people . . . govern them-
    selves through their elected representatives, adequate in-
    formation about their government is of transcendent im-
    portance.” Dun & Bradstreet, 
    472 U. S., at 767
     (White, J.,
    concurring in judgment). Without doubt, Sullivan sought
    to promote that goal as the Court saw the world in 1964.
    Departures from the Constitution’s original public meaning
    are usually the product of good intentions. But less clear is
    how well Sullivan and all its various extensions serve its
    intended goals in today’s changed world. Many Members of
    this Court have raised questions about various aspects of
    Sullivan. See, e.g., McKee, 586 U. S., at ___ (opinion of
    THOMAS, J.); Coughlin v. Westinghouse Broadcasting & Ca-
    ble, Inc., 
    476 U. S. 1187
     (1986) (Burger, C. J., joined by
    Rehnquist, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari); Gertz,
    
    418 U. S., at 370
     (White, J., dissenting); Rosenbloom v.
    Metromedia, Inc., 
    403 U. S. 29
    , 62 (1971) (Harlan, J., dis-
    senting); 
    id., at 78
     (Marshall, J., dissenting); Rosenblatt v.
    Baer, 
    383 U. S. 75
    , 92–93 (1966) (Stewart, J., concurring);
    see also Kagan, 18 L. & Soc. Inquiry, at 205, 209; Lewis &
    Ottley, New York Times v. Sullivan at 50, 64 De Paul
    L. Rev. 1, 35–36 (2014) (collecting statements from Justice
    Scalia). JUSTICE THOMAS does so again today. In adding
    my voice to theirs, I do not profess any sure answers. I am
    not even certain of all the questions we should be asking.
    But given the momentous changes in the Nation’s media
    landscape since 1964, I cannot help but think the Court
    would profit from returning its attention, whether in this
    case or another, to a field so vital to the “safe deposit” of our
    liberties.