Doug Satterfield v. Breeding Insulation Company - Concurring/Dissenting ( 2008 )


Menu:
  •                     IN THE SUPREME COURT OF TENNESSEE
    AT KNOXVILLE
    January 8, 2008 Session
    DOUG SATTERFIELD v. BREEDING INSULATION COMPANY ET AL.
    Appeal by Permission from the Court of Appeals, Eastern Section
    Circuit Court for Blount County
    No. L-14000     W. Dale Young, Judge
    No. E2006-00903-SC-R11-CV - Filed September 9, 2008
    JANICE M. HOLDER, J., concurring and dissenting.
    I fully concur in the majority’s conclusion that Alcoa owed a duty to Ms. Satterfield to take
    reasonable steps to prevent her from suffering harm as a result of the risks created by the operation
    of Alcoa’s facility. I write separately to express my belief that any discussion of foreseeability in the
    context of duty encroaches upon the role of the finder of fact. In doing so, I will explain the
    considerations that I believe are relevant to a duty analysis.
    This Court has previously stated that the existence of a duty depends upon the presence of
    a relationship between the plaintiff and the defendant that justifies the imposition of a legal
    obligation on one of the parties. E.g., Staples v. CBL & Assocs., Inc., 
    15 S.W.3d 83
    , 92 (Tenn.
    2000) (Holder, J., concurring); Bradshaw v. Daniel, 
    854 S.W.2d 865
    , 869-70 (Tenn. 1993). Sections
    II and III of the majority opinion properly clarify that a duty to act reasonably generally arises out
    of the defendant’s risk-creating conduct rather than the relationship between the parties.
    Accordingly, in cases of misfeasance, i.e., cases in which the defendant has allegedly created a risk,
    there is no need to examine the relationship between the parties. See West v. E. Tenn. Pioneer Oil
    Co., 
    172 S.W.3d 545
    , 551 (Tenn. 2005). The existence of a relationship between the parties
    becomes relevant to our analysis of duty only if the plaintiff alleges that he or she was harmed as a
    result of the defendant’s nonfeasance. In other words, the relationship between the parties is
    important only insofar as it may provide an exception to the no-duty-to-rescue rule.
    Although I concur in the majority’s clarification of these issues, I am unable to agree with
    the remainder of the majority’s duty analysis. Specifically, I remain concerned about the role that
    foreseeability plays in the majority’s understanding of duty. Foreseeability enters the majority’s
    analysis in two related ways. First, foreseeability forms a part of the majority’s basic explanation
    of when a duty arises. For example, the majority states that “‘all persons have a duty to use
    reasonable care to refrain from conduct that will foreseeably cause injury to others.’” (quoting
    Burroughs v. Magee, 
    118 S.W.3d 323
    , 328 (Tenn. 2003); Bradshaw, 854 S.W.2d at 870) (emphasis
    added). Second, foreseeability is a key component of the public policy balancing test employed by
    the majority. Burroughs, 118 S.W.3d at 329; McCall v. Wilder, 
    913 S.W.2d 150
    , 153 (Tenn. 1995).
    As I have often stated, the foreseeability of an injury or risk is more properly considered an
    element of breach of duty or proximate cause. Hale v. Ostrow, 
    166 S.W.3d 713
    , 720 (Tenn. 2005)
    (Holder, J., concurring and dissenting); Staples, 15 S.W.3d at 93 (Holder, J., concurring); accord W.
    Jonathan Cardi, Purging Foreseeability: The New Vision of Duty and Judicial Power in the Proposed
    Restatement (Third) of Torts, 58 Vand. L. Rev. 739, 744-50 (2005). This observation is important
    primarily because the existence of duty is determined by courts as a matter of law while breach of
    duty and proximate cause are fact-based inquiries to be determined by juries. West, 172 S.W.3d at
    556 (Tenn. 2005) (observing that breach of duty and proximate causation are factual determinations);
    Staples, 15 S.W.3d at 89 (holding that existence of duty is a matter of law). By incorporating
    foreseeability into an analysis of duty, the majority transforms a factual question into a legal issue
    and expands the authority of judges at the expense of juries. Gipson v. Kasey, 
    150 P.3d 228
    , 231
    (Ariz. 2007); Cardi, supra, at 741. It is with good reason that determinations of breach of duty and
    proximate cause, and therefore foreseeability, have traditionally been entrusted to juries. See City
    of Elizabethton v. Sluder, 
    534 S.W.2d 115
    , 117 (Tenn. 1976) (noting that foreseeability is a jury
    issue). A collection of twelve people representing a cross-section of the public is better suited than
    any judge to make the common-sense and experience-based judgment of foreseeability. Cardi, supra,
    at 799-800; see also Thomas C. Galligan, Jr., A Primer on the Patterns of Negligence, 
    53 La. L
    . Rev.
    1509, 1527-28 (1993) (arguing that the determination of proximate cause requires a “visceral” and
    fact-specific judgment of what is fair and suggesting that juries are better equipped to make such
    judgments).
    The majority attempts to support the integration of duty and foreseeability by arguing that
    foreseeability plays a different role in the duty context than it does in the context of breach of duty
    or proximate cause. In support of its position, the majority cites to cases that propose a distinction
    between the foreseeability of a general threat of harm to others and the foreseeability of the specific
    harm suffered by the plaintiff. McCain v. Fla. Power Corp., 
    593 So. 2d 500
    , 502-04 (Fla.1992);
    Knoll v. Bd. of Regents of Univ. of Neb., 
    601 N.W.2d 757
    , 763 (Neb. 1999). According to these
    cases, the former analysis is relevant to duty while the latter is relevant to proximate cause. McCain,
    593 So. 2d at 502-04; Knoll, 601 N.W.2d at 763. The majority places this distinction in its own
    terms, stating, “For the purpose of determining whether a duty exists, the courts’ consideration of
    foreseeability is limited to assessing whether there is some probability or likelihood of harm that is
    serious enough to induce a reasonable person to take precautions to avoid it.”
    While I agree that the distinction between general and specific foreseeability can be made
    in theory, I disagree with the assertion that general foreseeability is relevant to duty. Insofar as the
    distinction between forms of foreseeability can be made, the general foreseeability of harm created
    by the defendant’s conduct is relevant to determining whether the defendant behaved reasonably–that
    is, whether the defendant breached his or her duty. Cardi, supra, at 746-47. The distinction should
    have little practical consequence, however, because the jury should be responsible for making both
    foreseeability determinations.
    However valid the distinction between general and specific foreseeability may be in theory,
    the distinction is difficult, if not impossible, to apply in practice. Consider, for instance, the facts
    2
    in the present case. Alcoa operated a facility that used materials containing asbestos and allegedly
    took no precautions to ensure that employees did not transfer asbestos outside the facility on their
    clothes. According to the majority, these facts pose two different questions: whether the “general”
    harm to people outside the facility was foreseeable and whether the “specific” harm to the daughter
    of one of its employees was foreseeable.
    In my view, these questions are so interrelated that they are virtually inseparable. If Alcoa
    creates a foreseeable risk to members of the public by allowing employees to leave its facility with
    asbestos on their clothes, then it also creates a foreseeable risk to a specific person, the daughter of
    an employee. The contrary is also true. If Alcoa’s behavior creates a foreseeable risk to the daughter
    of an employee, it will also create a foreseeable risk to other members of the public who come in
    contact with Alcoa’s employees. To answer one question is also to answer the other.
    By requiring judges to determine general foreseeability, the majority’s opinion forces trial
    judges to base their decision-making on a razor thin distinction and encourages judges to make
    factual determinations relevant to breach of duty. The majority’s formulation of the distinction is
    equally problematic because it requires courts to evaluate “whether there is some probability or
    likelihood of harm that is serious enough to induce a reasonable person to take precautions to avoid
    it.” In my view, any inquiry into the probability, likelihood, or foreseeability of harm, however the
    issue is framed, requires courts to draw overly fine distinctions and, worse yet, to encroach upon the
    proper function of juries.
    I would eliminate foreseeability from the duty analysis entirely and conclude that a duty of
    reasonable care arises whenever a defendant’s conduct poses a risk of harm to persons or property.
    This approach is consistent with the formulation of duty found in the Restatement (Third) of Torts.
    According to the latest version of the Restatement, “[a]n actor ordinarily has a duty to exercise
    reasonable care when the actor’s conduct creates a risk of physical harm.” Restatement (Third) of
    Torts: Liability for Physical Harm § 7(a) (Proposed Final Draft No. 1, 2005) [hereinafter Restatement
    (Third) of Torts]. Under this approach, the existence of a duty generally would be presumed as long
    as the plaintiff has alleged that he or she was harmed by the defendant’s conduct.
    Like the majority of the Court, I believe that in some cases public policy considerations may
    warrant a conclusion that a defendant owes no duty to a plaintiff despite the defendant’s creation of
    a risk of harm. Unlike the majority, I would not base the public policy analysis on foreseeability.
    I would follow the Restatement (Third) of Torts and conclude that “[i]n exceptional cases, when an
    articulated countervailing principle or policy warrants denying or limiting liability in a particular
    class of cases, a court may decide that the defendant has no duty or that the ordinary duty of
    reasonable care requires modification.” Restatement (Third) of Torts § 7(b). Under this framework,
    no-duty rules would be created “only when a court can promulgate relatively clear, categorical,
    bright-line rules of law applicable to a general class of cases.” Id. cmt. a. Furthermore, no-duty rules
    “should be articulated directly without obscuring references to foreseeability.” Id. cmt. j.
    As I understand it, the majority’s position is that foreseeability remains a useful concept in
    our public policy analysis because it serves as a stabilizing principle that prevents our duty analysis
    3
    from becoming “anarchic” or “free-floating.” In my view, however, this Court has shown itself to
    be quite capable of creating principled no-duty rules without reference to foreseeability. For
    example, in Blair v. Campbell, 
    924 S.W.2d 75
    , 76-78 (Tenn. 1996), we concluded that property
    owners owe no duty to protect a contractor from a property defect that the contractor has undertaken
    to repair. In Carson v. Headrick, 
    900 S.W.2d 685
    , 690 (Tenn. 1995), we concluded that citizens owe
    no duty of reasonable care to police officers responding to a call for assistance. In Ezell v. Cockrell,
    
    902 S.W.2d 394
    , 397-400 (Tenn. 1995), we reaffirmed the doctrine that public officials cannot be
    held liable for harms caused when the public official breaches a duty owed to the public at large.
    Each of these cases contains a straightforward discussion of the relevant policy considerations
    without discussing foreseeability or encroaching upon the jury’s role in resolving factual disputes.
    Furthermore, each decision is firmly grounded in common-law principles and avoids the sort of
    judicial excesses feared by the majority. Accordingly, I believe these three cases are consistent with
    the methodology recommended by the Restatement (Third) of Torts and represent an approach that
    is superior to the balancing test currently employed by the majority of the Court.
    Moreover, I am concerned that the current emphasis placed on foreseeability presents an
    opportunity for the sort of “free-floating” analysis that the majority wishes to avoid. The concept
    of foreseeability is a notoriously malleable and indefinite concept. See Thing v. La Chusa, 
    771 P.2d 814
    , 830 (Cal. 1989) (observing that “there are clear judicial days on which a court can foresee
    forever”); William H. Hardie, Jr., Foreseeability: A Murky Crystal Ball for Predicting Liability, 23
    Cumb. L. Rev. 349, 410 (1992/1993) (concluding that “[f]oreseeability has become so elastic as to
    lose all meaning”). As a consequence, reliance on foreseeability reduces the clarity and certainty of
    negligence law and gives judges such broad discretion that similarly situated parties may often be
    treated differently. Cardi, supra, at 740-41, 792-93. It is also possible that the broad discretion
    afforded by the majority’s foreseeability analysis can mask the policy considerations that actually
    motivate judicial decision-making. Gipson, 150 P.3d at 231; Cardi, supra, at 740-41, 792-93;
    Galligan, supra, at 1523 (explaining that judges should state public policy choices clearly without
    relying on malleable words like “foreseeable” or “unforseeable”). Adopting the Restatement (Third)
    of Torts would increase judicial transparency and clarity by requiring that judges frankly and openly
    discuss the policy considerations that underlie any no-duty determination.
    To be candid, I must acknowledge that my understanding of duty remains a minority position.
    I firmly believe, however, that analyzing foreseeability in the context of duty is inherently
    problematic and that the Restatement (Third) of Torts presents a wiser approach. It is my hope that
    this approach will eventually be adopted in Tennessee. Until that day arrives, I will remain unable
    to concur in this Court’s duty jurisprudence. Accordingly, I respectfully dissent.
    ___________________________________
    JANICE M. HOLDER, JUSTICE
    4