City of League City, Texas v. Jimmy Changas, Inc. ( 2023 )


Menu:
  •           Supreme Court of Texas
    ══════════
    No. 21-0307
    ══════════
    City of League City, Texas,
    Petitioner,
    v.
    Jimmy Changas, Inc.,
    Respondent
    ═══════════════════════════════════════
    On Petition for Review from the
    Court of Appeals for the Fourteenth District of Texas
    ═══════════════════════════════════════
    JUSTICE YOUNG, concurring.
    It should not be so hard for a citizen of Texas to know the answer
    to the following question: “If I make a contract with a city and it breaches
    the contract, will the courts vindicate my claim?” The response, alas,
    will often boil down to this: We won’t know until six or seven years after
    the breach, at which point the courts will have balanced some factors
    and parsed a statute limited to torts. At that point, either all will be
    well, or else it will be a total loss. “But good luck,” a lawyer might tell a
    client, “and here’s my bill.”
    Such a conversation may well have happened in this case many
    years ago when the contractual negotiations were underway—not so
    long ago, but long enough that our leading immunity cases were not even
    on the books. Those cases, as the Court today ably explains, require us
    to determine whether a municipality’s challenged action was either
    governmental or proprietary. In making that determination, we are
    supposed to ask (1) whether the classifications listed in § 101.0215(a) of
    the Texas Civil Practice & Remedies Code provide any “guidance,” and
    if not, (2) whether the action otherwise meets the common-law definition
    of “governmental function,” as expounded through the four Wasson
    factors. No party has asked us to reassess our prior decisions, and I
    agree with the Court that, under the rather meandering process that
    those precedents compel, League City has failed to show that its contract
    with Jimmy Changas satisfies either inquiry.
    I suspect, however, that the City could not satisfy any reasonable
    standard to immunize itself from Jimmy Changas’ claim. I thus write
    separately because it is not clear to me that we are even asking the right
    questions in this breach-of-contract context. This area of law has long
    bedeviled us, and I do not propose to solve all of it today. Instead, my goal
    is to discuss how we got here, propose a way to distinguish between
    governmental and proprietary contracts that would simplify many cases,
    and suggest that, in an appropriate future case, it is not too late for us
    to systematically reconsider our precedents.
    I
    Many of the cases that the Court cites today were built on
    substantial confusion and fundamental disagreement about the nature
    of immunity and how it relates to breach-of-contract claims.
    Unfortunately, but perhaps predictably, that confusion and disagreement
    have grown into an analytical framework derived from two very different
    2
    legal standards—one from a statute and the other from common law. I
    doubt the relevance of the former and the correctness of our current
    understanding of the latter.
    A
    Start with the first step—the statutory one. There, our current
    practice is to consult the Texas Tort Claims Act to determine whether a
    municipality is entitled to immunity for contract claims. See Tex. Civ.
    Prac. & Rem. Code § 101.0215(a)–(b).
    Why would we do such a thing? Certainly not because the statute
    commands it. To the contrary, we are fully aware that the Act’s “statutory
    definitions and designations apply expressly to tort claims,” Wasson Ints.,
    Ltd. v. City of Jacksonville (Wasson II), 
    559 S.W.3d 142
    , 146 (Tex. 2018),
    “but not for claims for breach of contract,” ante at 6 (emphasis added).
    The statute’s tort limitation is just the most obvious of several
    reasons that make it problematic to apply its “governmental functions”
    list in the contract context. I will start there by adding that the statutory
    limitation was no accident. Since 1987, our Constitution has expressly
    authorized the legislature to “define for all purposes those functions of a
    municipality that are to be considered governmental and those that are
    proprietary, including reclassifying a function’s classification assigned
    under prior statute or common law.” Tex. Const. art. XI, § 13 (emphasis
    added). Despite that broad “all purposes” authority, the legislature
    cabined its definitions to tort claims that same year. See Act of Sept. 2,
    1987, 70th Leg., 1st C.S., ch. 2, § 3.02, 
    1987 Tex. Gen. Laws 37
    , 47–48
    (codified at Tex. Civ. Prac. & Rem. Code § 101.0215(a)).1
    1   I readily accept for this case and in general that our precedent makes
    3
    To be clear, when the legislature acts in ways that displace the
    common law—which is typically within its power and something our
    Constitution specifically invites here—the courts’ duty is to follow the
    legislative choice. Indeed, as a general matter, today’s judiciary should
    be extremely cautious about using its common-law authority to innovate
    in areas where the legislature has been particularly active.                   See
    Elephant Ins. Co., LLC v. Kenyon, 
    644 S.W.3d 137
    , 157–59 (Tex. 2022)
    (Young, J., concurring); Am. Nat’l Ins. Co. v. Arce, __ S.W.3d __, 
    2023 WL 3134718
    , at *17 (Tex. 2023) (Young, J., concurring).
    The circumstances before us today, however, are exactly the
    opposite. The legislature had clear authority to displace the common
    law and unambiguously exercised it, but only as to torts. We must credit
    the legislature with acting purposefully, and as a “text-centric Court,”
    Ojo v. Farmers Group, Inc., 
    356 S.W.3d 421
    , 441 (Tex. 2011) (Willett, J.,
    concurring), I cannot help but think that we should draw a very different
    lesson from the legislature’s choice: that it intended not to displace the
    common law with respect to contract claims against municipalities. The
    legislature could have made the Tort Claims Act list fully applicable in
    any or every context, but instead unambiguously limited it. I would
    the governmental-or-proprietary distinction dispositive. The Court is quite right
    that this distinction is longstanding for tort claims. Ante at 7 n.3. But as I note
    below, no comparable history undergirds its use in contract claims. We first
    suggested it just seven years ago. See Wasson Ints., Ltd. v. City of Jacksonville,
    
    489 S.W.3d 427
    , 439 (Tex. 2016) (“[W]e have never decided whether the
    distinction between governmental and proprietary acts . . . applies to breach-of-
    contract claims against municipalities.”). The ink is barely dry. Whether there
    are additional grounds that might justify or require finding that governmental
    immunity does not apply to a governmental unit in the contract context is an
    interesting question that goes beyond the scope of my opinion today.
    4
    respect that limitation until the legislature says otherwise. A patient
    should not take a pill with breakfast or lunch when the doctor prescribed
    one at dinner; a court should not expand a law’s scope to an area its text
    expressly refuses to reach. In neither context is more necessarily better.
    A second reason to respect the textual limitation (although, in
    truth, the first should be enough) is that the legislature’s choice to leave
    the common-law process intact in the contract context is quite sound. A
    laundry list of governmental (and thus immunized) functions for tort
    claims—and only tort claims—makes eminently good sense.2
    Tort and contract claims, after all, are fundamentally different.
    Future tort liability is a matter of risk, not certainty. Whether a tort will
    happen, how often it will happen, and the consequences of its happening
    cannot truly be known—only feared. Governmental immunity for torts
    removes at least most liability risks for activities and projects that the
    legislature may wish to encourage—like city-funded “parks and zoos,”
    “museums,” “recreational facilities,” “swimming pools,” “parking facilities,”
    “firework displays,” Tex. Civ. Prac. & Rem. Code §§ 101.0215(a)(13), (14),
    (23), (25), (27), and the like. Cities are more likely to undertake such
    activities if the cost of doing so need not include (or at least may largely
    discount) the uncertain future costs that ordinary tort liability would
    bring. To take a (literal) concrete example: Building a swimming pool is
    2  More specifically, the functions listed in § 101.0215(a), which are
    deemed “governmental,” are brought within the Tort Claims Act, meaning that
    immunity is also waived—if and to the extent the claim can survive the
    gauntlet that the Tort Claims Act itself imposes. See Rattray v. City of
    Brownsville, 
    662 S.W.3d 860
    , 865–69 (Tex. 2023) (describing many of the
    manifold procedural and substantive requirements that burden Tort Claims
    Act, but not ordinary, litigation).
    5
    a positive good for a community, but even responsibly done, the frequency
    and consequences of injuries and accidents are unpredictable. A city with
    limited resources may reasonably choose not to go forward when it is
    faced with the prospect of sudden, substantial, repeated, and enduring
    tort liability.   That basis for hesitation, however, should be largely
    obviated by the statutory classification in § 101.0215(a)(23), which
    ensures that damages from a city swimming pool or other recreational
    facility will be imposed only if and to the extent the Tort Claims Act
    itself authorizes it.
    Contracts are an entirely different matter. Unlike tort liability,
    contract liability can be more readily foreseen. Opening a swimming
    pool to the public poses a wildly different kind of liability risk than
    entering into a contract to install one. A city can do the latter with far
    more certainty and awareness of the attendant risks and potential
    liability. Indeed, just like any private party, a city can negotiate a
    contract’s terms and conditions up front—and, importantly here, define
    or limit the remedies available to each party in the event of a breach.
    See Tooke v. City of Mexia, 
    197 S.W.3d 325
    , 332 (Tex. 2006) (“By entering
    into a contract, a governmental entity . . . voluntarily bind[s] itself like
    any other party to the terms of the agreement . . . .”); Charles Fried,
    Contract as Promise: A Theory of Contractual Obligation 1 (1981) (“The
    promise principle . . . is that principle by which persons may impose on
    themselves obligations where none existed.”).          Analyzing a city’s
    entitlement to immunity for contract claims, in other words, is an
    inherently different endeavor than analyzing one based in tort. The
    incentives, mental states, foreseeability, and remedies will often differ.
    6
    See, e.g., Sw. Bell Tel. Co. v. DeLanney, 
    809 S.W.2d 493
    , 494–95 (Tex.
    1991); Formosa Plastics Corp. USA v. Presidio Eng’rs and Contractors,
    Inc., 
    960 S.W.2d 41
    , 44–45 (Tex. 1998).
    For these reasons, I am not puzzled by the legislature’s express
    limitation of its “governmental-versus-proprietary” list to suits “under
    this chapter”—that is, the Tort Claims Act. Tex. Civ. Prac. & Rem. Code
    § 101.0215(a). For the same reasons, it is not obvious to me that the
    Tort Claims Act can even “aid our inquiry” all that much for breach-of-
    contract claims. Wasson Ints., Ltd. v. City of Jacksonville (Wasson I),
    
    489 S.W.3d 427
    , 439 (Tex. 2016). Whatever their similarities, their
    differences are greater. The former cannot safely inform the latter, just
    as a chef unfamiliar with Texas chili should not consult his bouillabaisse
    recipe for guidance on the ground that both are stews.
    B
    Happily, the potential misdirection the Tort Claims Act can create
    when it is conscripted into service for contract cases is at least limited
    in its scope. As this case demonstrates, if the statute’s definitions or one
    of its thirty-six enumerated functions cannot provide us any “guidance,”
    we move to the second step: applying the common law.
    Here, the problem is not so much whether the common law applies
    but how we have come to apply it.3             To determine whether a
    municipality’s action is governmental (and thus immunized), our cases
    direct us to apply a four-factor test, asking (1) whether the city’s act was
    mandatory or discretionary, (2) whether it was for the benefit of the
    3 The recognition of sovereign immunity is within the proper common-
    law domain of the courts. See Wasson I, 489 S.W.3d at 432. If the courts
    recognize immunity, then it is up to the legislature to waive it or not.
    7
    general public or only its residents, (3) whether the city was acting on
    its own behalf or the State’s, and (4) whether the city’s act, if otherwise
    proprietary, was sufficiently related to a governmental function.
    Wasson II, 559 S.W.3d at 150–54.
    Today’s case, fortunately, serves as a fairly straightforward
    example of how a city can flunk each factor. But that does not mean it
    will always be so easy. As with most multifactored tests, the Wasson
    factors can point us in different directions,4 and I am unsure how to
    measure one against the other in the event of a conflict. Cf. Bendix
    Autolite Corp. v. Midwesco Enters., Inc., 
    486 U.S. 888
    , 897 (1988) (Scalia,
    J., concurring in judgment) (likening balancing tests to “judging whether
    a particular line is longer than a particular rock is heavy”); National
    Pork Producers Council v. Ross, 
    143 S. Ct. 1142
    , 1160 (2023) (opinion of
    Gorsuch, J.) (questioning how courts can weigh economic and
    noneconomic costs and benefits under the Pike balancing test in a
    dormant Commerce Clause analysis and concluding that such a balance
    is “insusceptible to resolution by reference to any juridical principle”).
    Potentially worse, counting the factors for and against could give
    the mistaken impression that the immunity analysis is reducible to
    simple arithmetic. Three against one or one against three provides only
    an illusion of being closer to the correct answer. These factors are, by
    their nature, incommensurable—a fact enjoyed perhaps only by the
    4 See Wasson II, 559 S.W.3d at 154; see also Hayes St. Bridge Restoration
    Grp. v. City of San Antonio, 
    570 S.W.3d 697
    , 705–06 (noting that one factor
    supported a “proprietary” classification while the other three supported a
    “governmental” classification). Indeed, if a multifactored test were incapable
    of pointing in different directions, there would seem be to be no point in having
    more than one factor.
    8
    equivocating law student on exam day, but not by any judge, litigant, or
    member of the public who seeks more clarity in the law.5
    To be sure, Wasson II instructs that when “some factors . . . point
    to one result while others point to the opposite result,” we “should
    consider immunity’s nature and purpose and the derivative nature of a
    city’s access to that protection.” 559 S.W.3d at 154. I must confess,
    however, that I do not quite know what that statement means or what
    rule of decision it provides for our trial judges, who must make the legal
    call in the first instance. More importantly, I doubt that a Texan about
    to form a contract with a city (or a Texan who already did so and now
    finds that city in breach) will be able to know with much confidence
    whether immunity applies or not.
    Similarly lacking, I am afraid, is any confidence we may have in
    the potential answers the Wasson factors could produce. It seems entirely
    possible that even when the factors all point in the same direction, it
    could be the same wrong direction.           Consider, for instance, a city’s
    decision to create a police force.          Jurists and laymen alike would
    intuitively (and rightly) regard that decision to be quintessentially
    governmental. The Wasson factors, though, might deem such an act
    proprietary. A city is not mandated to create a police force (factor 1); the
    police force would primarily benefit city residents by virtue of its limited
    jurisdiction, which is why the city’s residents pay for it (factor 2); and
    5 As Justice Blacklock eloquently puts it, “When the factors themselves
    become the inquiry—as seems to have happened—the underlying concepts
    recede into the mist, and we lose sight of what we are really asking and why we
    are asking it.” Post at 5–6 (BLACKLOCK, J., dissenting). This comment applies
    here and to so many other areas of the law that currently rely on balancing tests.
    9
    that primary responsibility for funding its own police force, as well as
    its local chain of command, shows that the city would primarily be acting
    on its own behalf, not the State’s (factor 3).6
    One could perhaps argue (under factor 4) that a police force is
    “sufficiently related” to a governmental function. Relying on that escape
    hatch, though, only illustrates my point. It would be strange indeed to
    say that something is “sufficiently related” to a governmental function
    after it fails the first three factors of a test purporting to suss out
    whether it is “governmental.” Relying on the last factor, in other words,
    is essentially circular: it openly depends on already knowing what is
    “governmental” to determine whether something is “governmental.”7
    I have a sneaking suspicion that the “four-factor” test turns out
    to be a one-factor test and that—voila!—the paramount fourth “factor”
    6 To be sure, this particular example assumes that I have understood
    factor 3 correctly. Based on our precedent, it is also unclear to me whether this
    factor requires us to look at the municipality’s intentions or the effects of its
    decisions. Compare Wasson II, 559 S.W.3d at 151 (considering whether
    nonresidents benefitted from a city’s decision) with id. (looking to the record to
    determine the city’s “primary objective”).
    7  One can easily imagine other examples where the factors mislead more
    than facilitate the ultimate governmental-or-proprietary inquiry. How about
    another classic governmental function: levying property taxes. Because the
    State opts not to levy such taxes, doing so is a municipal choice (factor 1). Those
    taxes fund municipal entities and primarily benefit their own residents, as with
    schools and streets (factor 2). In levying such taxes, a city could not claim to do
    so on behalf of the State, which does not assess property taxes, and the collected
    taxes do not go to the State’s fisc (other than temporarily, in some cases) (factor
    3). Maybe, again, the fourth factor could bat clean-up, but if so, what work do
    the first three achieve? How much weight should they receive in such instances?
    Is the fourth one doing anything other than stating “yes, this is governmental”—
    easy for taxes or police, but harder in other cases? If we cannot trust the first
    three factors in “easy” cases, why should we trust them in hard ones?
    10
    is revealed as just another disguise for our ancient nemesis: Ye Olde
    Know-It-When-I-See-It Test.
    C
    My thoughts thus far are admittedly rather pessimistic, but I
    proceed mindful of Chesterton’s fence. The benefit of raising these issues
    in today’s case is that we can explore them without any risk of tearing
    down a fence that was built for a good but unknown or forgotten reason.
    Nonetheless, I doubt that the status quo reflects our best ability
    to distinguish between governmental and proprietary in the contract
    context. That governmental-or-proprietary distinction, I acknowledge,
    has a long historical pedigree with respect to tort claims. See City of
    Galveston v. Posnainsky, 
    62 Tex. 118
    , 130–31 (1884).                But it is of
    surprisingly recent vintage with respect to contract claims. See Wasson I,
    489 S.W.3d at 439. Indeed, it was only nineteen years before Wasson I
    that this Court appears to have first endorsed the antecedent premise
    that governmental units are entitled to immunity for contract claims just
    as they are for tort claims. See Fed. Sign v. Tex. S. Univ., 
    951 S.W.2d 401
     (1997). I mention this not to challenge the use of the dichotomy—
    our precedent, as fresh as it may be, prescribes its use. Instead, while I
    accept it as our current precedent, I think that it probably is too early to
    conclude that the only way that immunity might be lacking in a contract
    case is if entering into it qualifies as a city’s “proprietary” action.8
    8 This is not to mention, of course, that the legislature has already waived
    any local-government immunity for certain classes of contract claims. See Tex.
    Loc. Gov’t Code §§ 271.151(2), .152 (waiving, for example, such immunity for
    contracts involving the provision of goods or services). In 2005, when the
    legislature enacted Chapter 271, it was unclear what immunity (if any)
    municipalities had for breach-of-contract claims, so the waiver avoided any
    11
    But for today, I proceed on the premise that the governmental-or-
    proprietary question will be dispositive. Given that principle, we should
    at least ensure that the nature of the claim does not become ultimately
    obscured by labels.     In other words, when we begin classifying a
    municipality’s acts as either “governmental” or “proprietary,” we ought to
    still account for the inherent differences between tort and contract claims.
    Perhaps one way to improve our current approach, as Justice
    Blacklock suggests, is to jettison the Wasson factors and simply deploy
    our “good judgment and practical knowledge” while applying the
    governmental–proprietary dichotomy. Post at 6. Indeed, as he sees it,
    regaining “a coherent theory” in this area of the law will require a more
    “firmly grounded” understanding of “the concepts conveyed by the words
    ‘governmental’ and ‘proprietary’” and applying them accordingly. Post
    at 4. And perhaps building a common-law basis for this distinction in a
    series of cases will generate rules, not mere factors, that will provide the
    requisite clarity and predictability that the citizens and cities of Texas
    all deserve. I would welcome the endeavor.
    That said, I cannot shake the notion that any rule or set of rules
    would characterize League City’s contract with Jimmy Changas as a
    decidedly proprietary action. And so I propose a different rule: that a
    contract is proprietary if it asks a market participant to do the very kind
    of thing it could contractually bind itself to do with non-governmental
    market participants. The contract in this case—memorializing financial
    incentives to build a restaurant—reflects no material difference from a
    consequences of the confusion. See H. Rsch. Org., Bill Analysis, H.B. 2039
    (April 20, 2005).
    12
    potential contract between similarly situated private parties.
    To test this view, suppose that Jimmy Changas’ counterparty was
    not a governmental entity but instead a commercial developer. Such a
    developer might offer incentives to Jimmy Changas to build a restaurant
    in its development. Why? To increase the desirability and thus the value
    of its homes and commercial spaces, to attract other commercial tenants
    to a shopping plaza, to serve as an amenity for employees that would help
    entice companies to open an office, or for other similar reasons. I would
    think that such an offer (if accepted) would be a standard commercial
    agreement. If Jimmy Changas performed and the private developer
    refused to do so, we would treat the dispute as an ordinary breach-of-
    contract action. We would not tell Jimmy Changas that the contract was
    illusory and that its dedication of resources to this project rather than
    others that it might otherwise have preferred was for nothing.9
    My dissenting colleague, on the other hand, reaches the opposite
    conclusion and makes a strong argument that Jimmy Changas is no more
    than a “participant in a government-benefits program” and a “beneficiary
    of government largesse, not a counterparty in a commercial exchange”
    “in which private parties might engage for their mutual benefit.” Post
    at 7–8. As with so much else in Justice Blacklock’s opinion, I largely
    agree with this insight, but in my view, the inquiry he describes is
    antecedent to the one on which I focus.
    9Like other legal rules, future cases may be required to refine this one,
    were the Court ever to adopt it. For example, determining the proper level of
    generality to assess whether a contract with a city is analogous to one that
    could be made with a private counterparty might require further elaboration.
    But I doubt that any such difficulty would appear in this case, and maybe not
    in many others, either.
    13
    Specifically, if we determine that a “contract,” despite its name, is
    nothing but an exercise of public spending or “largesse,” that would end
    our inquiry. We would never reach the immunity question at all because
    such a relationship, even if dressed up in contractual garb, would not
    truly be contractual. Whatever arguments a beneficiary of “largesse”
    might make if the munificence were to dry up, those arguments would not
    sound in contract if there was no true contractual relationship. In such
    a case, as Justice Blacklock notes, we would first turn to the public law
    creating the government program. Post at 8. Other areas of law, such as
    the procedural due-process jurisprudence on government benefits, might
    well apply, too.10
    But if we pass that antecedent step, it becomes a contract case.
    Here, substituting the developer in my hypothetical for League City
    suggests to me that Jimmy Changas was not the beneficiary of “largesse”
    but was engaged in commercial activity. The focus on the contractual
    counterparty—who will bear all the risk if a city is able to slip out of its
    deal—is proper. To a city, everything it does will seem governmental; to
    10 There is substantial disagreement about whether (or the extent to
    which) the government must follow the strictures of due process when it makes
    a decision regarding benefits that it is under no duty to provide—benefits that
    “are sometimes referred to as government largesse.” John E. Nowak & Ronald
    D. Rotunda, Constitutional Law 540 (5th ed. 1995). The key question in such
    cases is whether these benefits constitute “property”—a question I briefly
    address in Part II, infra. For purposes of answering that question in the due-
    process context, the U.S. Supreme Court has circled around the concept of
    “entitlement,” e.g., Bd. of Regents v. Roth, 
    408 U.S. 564
    , 577–78 (1972), what
    some could easily transpose as a contractual promise, e.g., Nowak & Rotunda,
    supra, at 542 (“[An] entitlement also may come from statutory law [or] formal
    contract terms . . . .”). If such entitlements can be characterized as contracts
    at all, it is probable that they are situated quite differently for immunity
    purposes from “contracts” of the traditional sort.
    14
    a hammer, everything seems like a nail. But it will not seem that way
    to a business entering into a contract (just as my thumb does not feel
    like a nail when my hammer strikes it).
    That said, Justice Blacklock is surely correct that “[g]overnment-
    sponsored ‘economic development’ programs are no stranger to political
    controversy” and that newly elected officials may not want to be bound
    by their predecessors’ policy decisions as reflected in the contracts that
    arise from such programs. Post at 3. But I disagree that the promises
    made and memorialized in writing by a municipality can just be undone
    by nothing more than the whims of the political process. The law has
    other ways to mitigate the profligacy of poor leadership without heaping
    all the consequences of a poor choice on the contractual counterparty. 11
    In one statutory waiver of immunity for contract claims, for example, the
    legislature has chosen to enact limitations on the damages recoverable
    from a municipality. See, e.g., Tex. Loc. Gov’t Code § 271.153(a)(4)–(b)(2).
    Of course, any party to a contract may negotiate for such limitations of
    liability. If cities do not do so as a matter of course, nothing stops the
    legislature from enacting such a blanket term, whether as a default or
    as mandatory, for these kinds of contracts. Nor is it clear that the
    11  The justification for municipal power to restrict individual rights by
    force of law is that municipal corporations reflect local self-government. That
    self-government premise renders quite doubtful any wholesale immunization of
    municipal corporations for their leaders’ improvident contractual undertakings.
    On the contrary, if unwise decisions generate no real consequences, the
    incentives for rigorous self-government cannot help but diminish. And, little
    by little, wise exercises of self-government will be punished, too; all local
    governments will have to pay more for a contract if some of them can renege.
    After all, how will a business be able to distinguish honorable municipalities
    whose word is their bond from those who will abandon agreements when short-
    term political or fiscal agendas make doing so convenient?
    15
    common law of government contracts would not have similar effects,
    allowing both parties to negotiate in the light of the law.
    The upshot of all this is that if we abandon the Wasson factors but
    keep the governmental–proprietary distinction, as Justice Blacklock
    and I both propose, the application will look much different for contracts
    cases. And because many if not most of the contracts that municipalities
    enter into will be ones that private parties can similarly make, like the
    one between League City and Jimmy Changas here, those contracts will
    be correctly deemed proprietary and no immunity will attach. Cf. Gates
    v. City of Dall., 
    704 S.W.2d 737
    , 739 (Tex. 1986) (noting that “proprietary
    functions have subjected municipal corporations to the same duties and
    liabilities as those incurred by private persons and corporations”). It is
    one thing to diffuse public goods and common resources; it is quite
    another     to   make   bargained-for      promises    to   specific   entities.
    Differentiating between the two, I think, would be an example of “good
    judgment and practical knowledge of how the world works.” Post at 6.
    II
    Many additional pages could illustrate with much more detail how
    governmental immunity in the breach-of-contract context is far from
    settled (if not unsettling). Reasonable minds can and will differ on what
    immunity (if any) municipalities can claim in such cases. Opinions from
    Justices of this Court have run the gamut, ranging from a categorical
    immunity rule, to no immunity at all, to someplace in between.12 I cannot
    12See, e.g., Tex. Nat. Res. Conservation Comm’n v. IT-Davy, 
    74 S.W.3d 849
    , 857 (Tex. 2002) (categorical immunity rule); Fed. Sign, 
    951 S.W.2d at 418
    (Enoch, J., dissenting) (no immunity at all); 
    id. at 412
     (Hecht, J., concurring)
    (some place in between).
    16
    say which is right without further consideration and briefing on the issue,
    of course, but given the inability of our current factor-ridden framework
    to generate consistent and predictable results, I doubt stare decisis will
    stand as an insurmountable barrier to a thorough recalibration of our
    approach. Thus, to the extent a future case asks us to reconsider our
    precedents, I offer a few tentative observations, intended not as any
    great effort to plumb the depths of this contentious and cacophonous
    area of the law, but instead as a modest offer of potential points of
    consideration if and when the occasion calls for it.
    First, the fact that we are dealing with a municipal corporation
    might simplify our analysis. As a learned colleague on the federal bench
    recently opined, “at common law, both in England and the early American
    Republic, incorporated entities were not entitled to sovereign immunity.”
    Springboards to Educ., Inc. v. McAllen Indep. Sch. Dist., 
    62 F.4th 174
    ,
    191 (5th Cir. 2023) (Oldham, J., concurring).13 Whatever the support for
    that (some might say) proposed federal common-law rule,14 I find the
    13 Coincidentally, the full Springboards panel also expressed frustration
    with precedent that mandated—you guessed it—a multifactor-balancing test
    for immunity. Compare 
    id., at 179
     (noting that the immunity factors derived
    from Clark v. Tarrant Cny., 
    798 F.2d 736
     (5th Cir 2019), have been “fairly
    described as having all the precision of a blunderbuss”) (internal quotations
    and citations omitted), with 
    id. at 187
     (Oldham, J., concurring) (calling the
    factors “cumbersome” and proposing “a new single-factor test: Was the entity
    asserting state sovereign immunity considered ‘the State’ in 1789?”).
    14Compare Ann Woolhandler, Interstate Sovereign Immunity, Sup. Ct.
    Rev. 249, 261 (2006) (“[T]he [U.S. Supreme] Court might have treated the
    immunities as matters of federal constitutional or federal common law.”), with
    Caleb Nelson, Sovereign Immunity as a Doctrine of Personal Jurisdiction, 
    115 Harv. L. Rev. 1559
    , 1565–66 (2002) (positing that state sovereign immunity is
    a “concept . . . relevant to personal jurisdiction”); William Baude, Sovereign
    Immunity and the Constitutional Text, 
    103 Va. L. Rev. 1
    , 8–22 (2017) (arguing
    17
    general principle to be helpful at least as a rebuttable presumption.
    Municipal corporations are not remotely sovereign, of course, even as a
    matter of Texas common law. But just like individual human beings,
    corporations could be treated as such when performing roles delegated to
    them by the State. In such instances, if the presumption against being
    “the State” is rebutted, immunity would apply in the ordinary course.
    Second, aside from what we have said, perhaps we should consider
    what the People have said about when the government (including the
    State itself) must compensate private parties: “No person’s property
    shall be taken . . . without adequate compensation.” Tex. Const. art. I,
    § 17. And as we have observed before, the Texas Takings Clause itself
    “waives immunity for suits,” City of Dallas v. VSC, LLC, 
    347 S.W.3d 231
    , 236 (Tex. 2011), and applies to all property (real or personal), Gulf,
    C. & S.F. Ry. Co. v. Fuller, 
    63 Tex. 467
    , 469 (1885). Thus, when a
    municipality accepts property under a contract and refuses to pay for
    them, such an action might amount to a raw, compensable taking.15
    Third, and finally, sprinkled about our immunity opinions are
    various appeals to pragmatism, including that immunity should shield
    that sovereign immunity is a “constitutional backdrop” and thus a form of
    common law that “can’t be changed because of the properly limited nature of
    Articles I and III”).
    15  Cf. Fed. Sign, 
    951 S.W.2d at 415
     (Hecht, J., concurring) (“The State
    may not take property without compensation, but it may determine how its
    Branches will participate in deciding its contractual disputes.”); John
    Echeverria, Public Takings of Public Contracts, 
    36 Vt. L. Rev. 517
    , 530 (2012)
    (“[I]f the government has not only impaired the contract interest but deprived
    the party of her contract remedy, then the party’s protected interests have been
    destroyed and allowing the takings claim to go forward is necessary to protect
    those interests.”).
    18
    the public from the costs of their government’s “improvident actions.” If
    “improvidence” typifies actions sounding in ordinary negligence, this
    rationale may make sense for torts. But as I noted above, I doubt it
    applies as much to a governmental entity’s breach of contract. 16 A deal
    may turn out to be less good than hoped, but negotiated contracts can
    always have adequate foresight.           A momentary lapse in judgment
    resulting in a tort is unlike the conscious, studied decision to make a
    promise—or, for that matter, to break one. Granting immunity to obviate
    the consequences of “improvident” governmental actions, then, cannot be
    the only answer. The public—whom we have sought to “shield”—always
    retains the option of not electing improvident officials.          Judicially
    relieving those officials’ improvidence, by contrast, means that the only
    party to suffer any consequences is the one who entered into the contract.
    No governmental unit—especially in Texas, where promises really
    matter—should be able to evade its obligations so capriciously.
    *   *    *
    With these observations, I respectfully concur and await another
    case in which the Court may appropriately revisit the principles of
    immunity as they apply to contract claims against municipalities.
    Evan A. Young
    Justice
    OPINION FILED: June 9, 2023
    16 We have used such reasoning several times in suits against
    governmental entities for breach of contract. E.g., Tooke, 197 S.W.3d at 332;
    City of Houston v. Williams, 
    353 S.W.3d 128
    , 134 (Tex. 2011); Zachry Const.
    Corp. v. Port of Houston Auth. of Harris Cnty., 
    449 S.W.3d 98
    , 121 (Tex. 2014)
    (Boyd, J., dissenting); Wasson I, 489 S.W.3d at 432.
    19