Richard J. Malouf, D.D.S. v. the State of Texas Ex Rels. Christine Ellis, D.D.S. and Madelayne Castillo ( 2024 )


Menu:
  •           Supreme Court of Texas
    ══════════
    No. 22-1046
    ══════════
    Richard J. Malouf, D.D.S.,
    Petitioner,
    v.
    The State of Texas ex rels. Christine Ellis, D.D.S. and Madelayne
    Castillo,
    Respondents
    ═══════════════════════════════════════
    On Petition for Review from the
    Court of Appeals for the Eighth District of Texas
    ═══════════════════════════════════════
    JUSTICE YOUNG, joined by Justice Lehrmann, dissenting.
    What do robots and lawyers have in common? Maybe more than
    we would care to admit, but at least one answer is that only robots and
    lawyers could read the statute at issue the way the Court does today. The
    Court purports to do so in the name of textualism. But a textualist’s
    obligation is to construe a statute in its context, giving it the meaning an
    ordinary English speaker would have given it at the time it was enacted.
    The Court instead imposes an implausible reading that no one would have
    given it when it was written. Today’s reading at best adopts a post hoc
    construction of the sort that good lawyers scrambling for an escape hatch
    might concoct for their clients.
    Specifically, the Court holds that Dr. Malouf did not violate Texas
    Human Resources Code § 36.002(8). Chapter 36 is titled “Health Care
    Program Fraud Prevention.” Section 36.002 is titled “Unlawful Acts” and
    provides that
    [a] person commits an unlawful act if the person: . . .
    (8) makes a claim under a health care program and
    knowingly fails to indicate the type of license and the
    identification number of the licensed health care provider
    who actually provided the service[.]
    Tex. Hum. Res. Code § 36.002(8). Dr. Malouf submitted nearly 2,000
    claims to the State that falsely listed his own “identification number”
    rather than “the identification number of the licensed health care
    provider who actually provided the service.” Did he commit what the
    statute calls an “unlawful act”?
    The Court says that he did not. True, he failed to provide the
    identification numbers of the dentists who actually provided the services
    at his dental chains, and instead listed someone (himself) who certainly
    did not provide those services. That sounds bad. But, the Court says, not
    to worry: Dr. Malouf implicitly provided those dentists’ license type (i.e.,
    “dentist”) because, as it turns out, Malouf is also a “dentist.” According
    to the Court, a lie about who “actually provided the service” is just as good
    as the truth, so long as the unnamed person who did it was a dentist.
    How could the Court misread the statute so badly? How could it
    read the text that I quoted above and think that the legislature was
    indifferent to knowing “who actually provided the service” for which the
    State is being billed? It is because the Court does not engage in a
    “context-sensitive interpretation of [the statute] as a whole.” United
    States v. Palomares, 
    52 F.4th 640
    , 649 (5th Cir. 2022) (Oldham, J.,
    2
    concurring). It instead zeroes in on the word “and” to justify giving the
    statute a meaning that its context will not remotely bear. I hope the
    Court is not serious about what it says, because if it is, every statute,
    contract, deed, will, ordinance, or other document will now be subject to
    a hyper-literal insistence on how to read the word “and”—and will often
    still get it wrong. It is the Court, not I, who makes “and” mean “or”— a
    checklist using “and” to link requirements now is just stating two mere
    options. Fun days ahead—at least for lawyers who bill by the hour.
    The canons of construction are the essential tools for interpreting
    legal documents. But like the tools of every trade, the canons must be
    wielded with reference to their object. Our goal is to understand the
    meaning of a text in its context. Common English usages—like the fact
    that sometimes there is no semantic difference between choosing “and”
    rather than “or,” as we all know—need not be sacrificed at the altar of
    textualism. Such a sacrifice does no honor to its purported deity. I fear
    that the Court’s approach reflects a turn to a false god—one who tempts
    with the lure of easy answers and happy outcomes—while disavowing the
    hard work of faithfully and accurately discerning a text’s true meaning.
    The result today is that Dr. Malouf walks away scot-free. Among
    those who will be surprised by this result is Dr. Malouf. The argument
    that the Court adopts is his “alternative argument,” as the Court
    acknowledges. See ante at 13–14. His far more modest lead argument
    merely asserts that there are fact questions about whether he
    “knowingly” listed the wrong provider, so the Court should send the case
    back for trial. Id. at 13. Unlike the lead argument, the “alternative” is a
    kill-shot—one on which he spends scant pages in both his opening and
    3
    reply brief, compared to the many pages devoted to his lead argument.
    The Court should not have fallen for it, and I doubt that Dr. Malouf or his
    counsel thought that we would. But as is often said at legal conferences
    and when lawyers tell their war stories, one never really knows what a
    court will do. Today’s decision should be added to the lore.
    I respectfully dissent.
    I
    We all agree that this case turns on the text of the Medicaid Fraud
    Prevention Act. Specifically, the statute says that it is unlawful to
    “make[] a claim under a health care program and knowingly fail[] to
    indicate the type of license and the identification number of the licensed
    health care provider who actually provided the service.” Tex. Hum. Res.
    Code § 36.002(8) (emphasis added). The case turns on this question: what
    does the italicized “and” mean?
    In my view, “and” plays its normal role of joining both prongs. The
    statute creates a short checklist of two things (not just one or the other)
    that a provider must list: the license type + the identification number.
    Failing to “indicate” either of them violates the statute, just like failing to
    put both ham and cheese on a sandwich would violate the Court’s
    hypothetical deli order: “Don’t forget to put ham and cheese on my
    sandwich.” Ante at 22. In our new age of artificial intelligence, I suppose
    that a robot waiter or a robot cook (or should I say “and a robot cook”?)
    would feel justified in serving a sandwich as soon as either ham or cheese
    is placed between slices of bread. But a human would regard the order
    as incomplete and would feel no guilt in sending it back.
    The conjunctive meaning of the stated statutory requirements is
    4
    clear from the statute’s text, context, and textually expressed function.
    But the Court insists on an arid reading that would make even a 1950s
    high-school English teacher blush. Treating the “and” as really meaning
    “or”—that the provider can list one or the other to escape any
    consequence—is grammatically permissible (barely), as with the
    concomitant sandwich in the deli. But it is not a remotely reasonable
    reading and gives no hint of pursuing an accurate rather than a
    tendentious interpretation of the statute.
    A
    As I read it, “and” conveys its normal grammatical meaning and
    plays its normal role—it imposes a joint requirement by listing two things
    (A and B) that a provider must indicate. But suppose for the moment
    that the Court would accept the dual-requirement reading if the
    legislature instead had used “or” in the statute. Even under the dubious
    assumption that “or” would satisfy the Court,1 that does not mean that
    “and” means anything different in this context. We have properly held
    that “and” and “or” generally are not interchangeable. In re Brookshire
    Grocery Co., 
    250 S.W.3d 66
    , 69–70 (Tex. 2008). They are, of course,
    usually distinct in meaning: “in a legal instrument, and joins a
    conjunctive list to combine items, while or joins a disjunctive list to create
    alternatives.” Conjunctive/Disjunctive Canon, Black’s Law Dictionary
    (11th ed. 2019).
    “Not A, not B, and not C,” however, is logically equivalent to “not
    1 [Narrator: The Court would not.    If it will not accept “and,” it would
    not accept “or,” but would make the very same argument in the photographic
    negative, saying if the legislature wanted both, it would have said “and!” ]. See
    also infra note 3.
    5
    (A, B, or C).” Linguistic context thus enables us to “move back and forth
    between disjunctive and conjunctive propositions as long as we are
    mindful about negations, as well as ‘our p’s and q’s.’ ” R.E. Houser, Logic
    as a Liberal Art: An Introduction to Rhetoric and Reasoning 343 (2020).
    Therefore, as Chief Justice Greenhill put it for the Court, we have also
    recognized that “there may be circumstances which call for such a
    construction” in which “and” is construed to mean “or,” even if we try hard
    to avoid those constructions. Bayou Pipeline Corp. v. R.R. Comm’n, 
    568 S.W.2d 122
    , 125 (Tex. 1978); see also De Sylva v. Ballentine, 
    351 U.S. 570
    ,
    573 (1956) (“the word ‘or’ is often used as a careless substitute for the
    word ‘and’; that is, it is often used in phrases where ‘and’ would express
    the thought with greater clarity”); Bryan A. Garner, Garner’s Modern
    English Usage 49 (4th ed. 2016) (“and is frequently misused for or where
    a singular noun, or one of two nouns, is called for”).2
    Depending on its statutory context, therefore, “and” can have
    several meanings. Some may be the opposite of how that word normally
    functions; some may simply be interchangeable with the word “or.” When
    that happens, a court does not rewrite “and” to mean “or”—that is what it
    meant all along. It is basic to our language that the same word can mean
    2 This linguistic phenomenon is not merely an academic or logical trifle,
    but in fact occurs in parlance ranging from the mundane to the literally divine.
    Did Jesus mean that someone who “left” his “children, for the kingdom of God’s
    sake,” but who refused to leave his “house, or parents, or brethren, or wife” for
    that cause will still be richly rewarded? See Luke 18:29–30 (“Verily I say unto
    you, There is no man that hath left house, or parents, or brethren, or wife, or
    children, for the kingdom of God’s sake, Who shall not receive manifold more
    in this present time, and in the world to come life everlasting.”); cf. Luke 14:26
    (“If any man come to me, and hate not his father, and mother, and wife, and
    children, and brethren, and sisters, yea, and his own life also, he cannot be my
    disciple.” (emphasis added)).
    6
    different things or function in different ways, so we rely on context to
    discern the applicable meaning. Sometimes that meaning is so evidently
    clear that we barely notice. “He tapped the mouse” and “he caught the
    mouse” give the word “mouse” two very different meanings—although
    both sentences could deploy either meaning.            This point is so
    commonplace as to be truly banal.
    Particularly relevant here, “and” can be used in “a distributive (or
    several) sense as well as a joint sense.” Bryan A. Garner, Garner’s
    Dictionary of Legal Usage 639 (3d ed. 2011) (emphasis added). The Court
    chooses the distributive sense: no problem unless a claimant knowingly
    fails to provide both his license type and his identification number. See
    ante at 32. Sometimes this use is the only reasonable one. Judge Willett
    offered this example: “ ‘Do not mix heat, fuel, and oxygen’ instructs the
    reader to prevent the unity of all three ingredients unless she wants a
    fire.” Palomares, 52 F.4th at 653 (Willett, J., dissenting). Mixing any two
    is fine—no fire unless heat, fuel, and oxygen are present. So I readily
    agree that the Court’s reading—that there is no statutory violation unless
    the claimant (1) fails to provide her license type and (2) fails to provide
    her identification number—is grammatically possible.         But if three
    colleagues will get into trouble in any combination, one could say “Do not
    mix Adam, Ben, and Cole” without meaning that it is fine to have two but
    not all three of them. I take the Court to agree with this basic principle.
    Ante at 21–22.
    The examples and counterexamples are tiresome because they are
    inexhaustible. That very point, however, proves that context is what
    matters. The ham-sandwich example hardly stands alone. To take
    7
    another, suppose a dentist (maybe even Dr. Malouf—or at least someone
    using his identification number) tells a patient to “brush and floss your
    teeth.” Or, to inject the negative, “you’ll be paying dental bills if you forget
    to brush and floss your teeth.” Even simply “don’t forget to brush and
    floss.” One who brushes without flossing will pay a price—gingivitis or
    worse—for giving the dentist’s advice a bizarre but grammatically
    tolerable meaning.
    I suppose that the legislature could commit itself to drafting only
    asyndetic statutes—avoiding conjunctions at all costs and using
    structure, subparts, and other language to eliminate any contrary
    grammatical reading. And sure, the legislature could have written this
    statute to more directly say what it meant.3 Greater clarity is always
    3 The Court thinks it is attacking me by saying that “[i]f the Legislature
    mistakenly used the term ‘and’ instead of ‘or’ in Section 36.002(8), it is up to
    the Legislature—not the courts—to amend the statute to fix that mistake.”
    Ante at 29 n.19.
    The Court mistakes my point. I agree that courts are not in the business
    of correcting drafting errors (at least those that are not scrivener’s errors, see
    Antonin Scalia & Bryan A. Garner, Reading Law: The Interpretation of Legal
    Texts 134–35 (2012)). But this statute contains no drafting (or scrivener’s) error.
    As drafted, it means that a provider must indicate both the license type and the
    actual provider’s identification number. As I explain below, the word “and” (like
    many words) can mean different things in different contexts, and in this context,
    the Court’s reading is unreasonable. In other words, I hardly propose to
    (improperly) “fix” some substantive legislative “mistake,” but instead to
    (properly) apply the statute as the legislature wrote it, in light of its statutory
    context and the statute’s textually expressed function.
    Regardless of all that, I doubt that the alternate phrasing would “fix” the
    legislature’s supposed “mistake.” If the statute replaced “and” with “or,” the
    parties would still be before us. The State would argue that a knowing failure
    to provide either the license type or the identification number violates the
    statute. Dr. Malouf would argue that “or” gives claimants a choice: so long as
    8
    desirable and nearly always possible. (For judicial opinions, too—not
    just statutes.) But courts cannot “demand (or in truth expect) that [the
    legislature] draft in the most translucent way possible.” Pulsifer v.
    United States, 
    144 S. Ct. 718
    , 729 (2024).
    Statutes end up as they do for a myriad of reasons—speed as the
    session comes to an end, compromise in merging House and Senate
    versions, desire to minimize revisions to existing laws, the fusion of
    competing versions of a text, human frailty, and so many others. True,
    such circumstances sometimes lead to an enactment that unambiguously
    requires something the legislature likely did not want—and when that
    happens, we must follow the actual law. But when we interpret the law
    in the first place, we are not required to give the legislature the least
    charitable reading we can. Indeed, we are not authorized to do so. We
    must instead “ ‘ascertain and give effect to the Legislature’s intent,’ ” and
    we do so by “enforc[ing] the plain meaning of statutory text, informed by
    its context.” Hegar v. Health Care Serv. Corp., 
    652 S.W.3d 39
    , 43 (Tex.
    2022) (emphasis added) (quoting In re D.S., 
    602 S.W.3d 504
    , 514 (Tex.
    2020)). After all, “[w]ords in a vacuum mean nothing. Only in the context
    of the remainder of the statute can the true meaning of a single provision
    be made clear.” McLane Champions, LLC v. Hous. Baseball Partners,
    LLC, 
    671 S.W.3d 907
    , 920 (Tex. 2023) (quoting Bridgestone/Firestone,
    Inc. v. Glyn-Jones, 
    878 S.W.2d 132
    , 133 (Tex. 1994)). Specifically in
    the claimant provides the license type or the identification number, there is no
    violation. We would still have to resolve the question if the legislature made the
    single wording switch. See Pulsifer v. United States, 
    144 S. Ct. 718
    , 729 (2024)
    (“[W]e doubt that substituting ‘or’ for ‘and’ would have delivered us from
    interpretive controversy.”).
    9
    statutes like this one—where the use of “and” within a statement is at
    issue—“context may drive such a statement in either direction.” Pulsifer,
    144 S. Ct. at 729 n.5 (offering examples using an identical linguistic
    structure but where “and” will bear opposite meanings).
    B
    So if context is indispensable to determining meaning—and the
    Court at least says that it admits this, ante at 6, 23–27—the case should
    be easy. The Court’s reading is unreasonable, and the answer to why that
    is so “lie[s] in considering the [statute’s] text in its legal context.” Pulsifer,
    144 S. Ct. at 731.
    Context comes in many forms. Some are irrelevant, but those
    drawn from the text itself are certainly proper for courts to use. More
    to the point, we cannot smuggle in impermissible grounds just by calling
    something “context.”      But the full text is always legitimate.          When
    interpreting a statute to resolve another “and-or” dispute, for example,
    we referred to a “succeeding clause” as one way to contextualize the
    meaning of “and.” Bd. of Ins. Comm’rs v. Guardian Life Ins. Co. of Tex.,
    
    180 S.W.2d 906
    , 909 (Tex. 1944). Here, the succeeding clause is this
    phrase: “of the licensed health care provider who actually provided the
    service.” Tex. Hum. Res. Code § 36.002(8). This phrase modifies both the
    (1) license-type and (2) identification-number prongs. See ConocoPhillips
    Co. v. EPA, 
    612 F.3d 822
    , 839 (5th Cir. 2010) (“Nouns joined by
    coordinating conjunctions are usually treated as a single, compounded
    unit, and a postmodifying prepositional phrase is most naturally read to
    modify that single unit.”).
    The successive phrase contextualizes how we should construe the
    10
    word “and.” The statute tells a claimant to provide the license type and
    identification number to enable the State to know the true identity “of the
    licensed health care provider who actually provided the service.” Tex.
    Hum. Res. Code § 36.002(8) (emphasis added). Providing only one of those
    two requirements contravenes this clear textual mandate.
    The two required data points are not substitutes but are quite
    notably at opposite ends of the spectrum. The license type is the most
    general (“dentist”); the identification number is the most granular (one
    specific dentist and no other). The statute is openly and expressly an anti-
    fraud statute, too—not just one to punish fraud, or even just to detect
    fraud, but to prevent it altogether. Again, Chapter 36 of the Human
    Resources Code is titled “Health Care Program Fraud Prevention.” So is
    it really plausible that the legislature is indifferent about which of two
    fundamentally dissimilar data points are provided? Is it plausible that
    the legislature is indifferent to receiving false information about one data
    point, so long as it receives accurate information about the other—yet
    does not even care to know which one is true and which is false?
    The answer, of course, is no. Both data points, after all, could be
    useful in various anti-fraud efforts.      They could work together in
    individual cases as a kind of check—if a license type and identification
    number did not match, that would signal that something has gone awry,
    flagging the claim for more attention. Even taken separately, both data
    points could be useful in different ways. For example, given how many
    Medicaid claims are made, it would surely be useful to sometimes
    generate reports to see if there are outliers or patterns about the type of
    provider who performs specific kinds of treatments. If certain services
    11
    are normally provided by “dental hygienists,” running reports to see when
    they are provided by “dentists” could help identify anomalies, which
    might lead to further analysis, audits, improvements, or the like. Other
    circumstances—especially if there is an audit—might make the license
    type irrelevant, but make it very important to know the individual
    provider. Many of these purposes would not be possible if the form
    includes one data point but not the other—or, perhaps worse, if the form
    accurately includes one but falsely includes the other.
    So can anyone seriously think that the legislature just does not
    care if the data it demands is corrupted in this way? That the legislature
    only cares about getting one piece of accurate data for any individual
    claim, without any interest whatsoever in being able to reliably detect
    trends in specific practices, regions, or across the State? Reading the
    statute in such a way is puzzling at best.
    To be clear, all we are doing is reading the statute to see what the
    statute contemplates. But the Court reads the statute anachronistically—
    it relies on a current form that is not part of the statute, and reasons
    backwards to conclude that this later-adopted form reached back from the
    future to determine the meaning of the statute. See ante at 24–25 (relying
    on the “Medicaid-approved claim form”).
    Let me explain what is going on. The statute (which again is what
    matters) requires the license type and individual identification number.
    The statute applies to all Medicaid providers, not just dentists. As it
    turns out, at least for dental providers and during the time at issue, the
    Health and Human Services Commission could ascertain both required
    data points if given the “Texas Provider Identifier” number, so the then-
    12
    current claim form requested only that.4 It is easy to see how that could
    happen. Imagine that a statute demanded a license number and a date
    of birth, and that when the statute was enacted, nothing in the license
    revealed a birth date. But imagine that over time, the licensing authority
    began adding the birth date as the final digits of a license. At that point,
    asking for only the license number would satisfy both statutory
    4 As the Court explains, the Medicaid claim form at use here included
    only one box—the identification-number box—and did not have a place for
    claimants to separately indicate a provider’s license type. Ante at 15. Because
    the license type is linked to a provider’s identification number, I agree with the
    Court’s conclusion that the submission of an accurate identification number
    provided both pieces of information. Id. at 14–15.
    The record indicates, however, that the claim form in use during the
    relevant timeframe for this litigation (2007–2010) was “dental specific.” And in
    the current Texas Medicaid Provider Procedures Manual, dentists participating
    in the THSteps program are required to submit an ADA Dental Claim Form.
    Tex. Health & Hum. Servs., Texas Medicaid Provider Procedures Manual: Vol.
    1, Section 6: Claims Filing (2024). By submitting a “dental specific” form, one
    could argue that the claimant impliedly indicated the license type as “dental.”
    Would that be enough for the Court?
    The point, though, is that the Court’s holding would apply with equal
    force if the form included two boxes: one for the identification number and one
    for the license type. As it happens, the current claim form appears to ask for
    both. The Texas Medicaid Provider Procedures Manual requires a dental
    claimant to submit a unique provider identifier number and a taxonomy code for
    all paper claims. Id. “A taxonomy code is a unique 10-character code that
    designates [a medical provider’s] classification and specialization.” Find Your
    Taxonomy Code, Centers for Medicare & Medicaid Services, https://
    www.cms.gov/medicare/enrollment-renewal/providers-suppliers/health-care-
    taxonomy (last visited June 18, 2024). In other words, the taxonomy code is a
    unique number that identifies a provider’s license type. The manual then states
    why the claim form requires a taxonomy code in addition to the provider’s
    identifier number: the former is “used to crosswalk the [provider’s unique
    identifier number] to the billing provider.” Tex. Health & Hum. Servs., Texas
    Medicaid Provider Procedures Manual, supra.
    But good news, dentists: the Court has now dispensed with this
    requirement, despite how sensible and useful it likely is.
    13
    requirements. But if the licenses stopped including birth dates, then the
    form would need to ask for both.
    Both in the real circumstances of today and in my hypothetical,
    however, it remains important to accurately reflect both data points. In
    today’s case, for example, the form requested only the identification
    number because, if listed accurately, it would accurately generate both
    required data points.       Falsely listing the identification number
    guarantees that both required data points cannot be accurate. At most,
    as here, a false identification number might match the correct license
    type. (And in the dental world, it often will—“dentist” is hardly rare.) But
    at no point could the Commission ascertain both data points from the
    license type alone, no matter how a claimant provided that information.
    A false identification number certainly cannot generate an accurate
    identification number.
    Yet under the Court’s construction, a claimant may just make up
    the identification number, or use someone else’s, or leave it blank—as
    long as he somewhere scribbles what his license type is or otherwise so
    indicates. Any of those actions ensure that the State will not know the
    identity of the person “who actually provided” the medical services—the
    one thing that the statute makes abundantly and expressly clear it wants.
    Yet the Court excludes such falsehoods from the statute’s prohibitions,
    and says that all the State needs to know is that some anonymous
    “dentist” did the work—maybe the one whose identification number is
    used, maybe not. Who knows? That really narrows it down. How helpful.
    The Court, in other words, says that “indicat[ing]” the “license
    type” is all the statute requires—form or no form. This case shows the
    14
    consequences of that view. When a particular identification number
    embeds both data points, as with the “TPI” that the then-current form
    requested, see ante at 15–16, the truth about both is revealed with one
    accurate number. Telling a lie will often accurately generate the license
    type, but never the identification number. The Court thinks that the
    legislature is fine with the lie—that it unambiguously approved the lie.
    The Court invokes statutory context to defend this remarkable
    conclusion in three ways: (1) that the construction that I advance is
    allegedly surplusage, id. at 24–25; (2) that the statute’s use of the word
    “or” in nearby provisions proves that it uses “and” the way the Court
    claims, id. at 25–27; and (3) that the statute is not stated as an
    “affirmative command,” id. at 27 n.19. That these are the best arguments
    just proves that there are no good arguments.
    1
    First, the Court argues that both the license type and the
    identification number of the person who actually provided the medical
    service are not necessary, so reading the statute to require both would
    “result[] in superfluity,” id. at 24, because the claim form only requires
    the identification number, which (if accurately supplied) necessarily
    provides both pieces of information, id. at 24–25.
    As I have just described, I accept the point as far as it goes: an
    accurate identification number would supply both pieces of information.
    But the converse is never true. Providing just an accurate license type
    is to fail to provide an accurate identification number (using any
    mechanism other than actually providing an accurate identification
    number, of course—the very thing that both the form and the statute
    15
    expressly request, and what the Court says can be ignored). Giving the
    Commission only the license type would, as here, leave the Commission
    in the dark about who actually performed the service—either forever or
    only after substantial effort and expenditure of time and resources to
    get at the truth.
    But again, to understand what the statute means, who cares what
    the form requires?     The form—which an agency adopted after the
    legislature enacted the statute—tells us nothing about the statute’s
    meaning. I can imagine one scenario where the fact that the form only
    asks for the identification number might matter: to a dentist who
    accurately listed that number. If the State were to later seek to impose
    penalties on such a dentist for not separately listing a license type—which
    the form does not request and which is embedded in the identification
    number the provider supplies—it might well violate due-process
    principles. See, e.g., Mosley v. Tex. Health & Hum. Servs. Comm’n, 
    593 S.W.3d 250
    , 262–69 (Tex. 2019) (holding that due process forbids the
    government from insisting even on correct legal requirements when the
    government has misled the regulated party about what they are). But no
    one is holding Dr. Malouf accountable for not separately listing the license
    types of the providers at his dental chains—the State seeks to hold him
    accountable for not listing the providers’ actual identification numbers,
    which both the form and the statute demand.
    The Court is wrong to collapse the identification-number and
    license-type requirements for another reason: the legislature is perfectly
    free to impose overlapping requirements. Creating an account on most
    any website requires someone to enter a new password twice, just to make
    16
    sure there was no typo; overlapping informational requirements can
    likewise minimize error or promote accuracy in other contexts. 5 There
    are likely many other reasons why the legislature might choose to require
    more than the bare minimum to achieve a valid regulatory objective, such
    as detecting fraud or other problems (or, more benignly, to ensure that
    payment gets to the right place as rapidly as possible). It is beyond this
    Court’s authority to invalidate or minimize such a legislative choice
    simply because a hypothetical set of facts would render that choice
    meaningless. See BankDirect Cap. Fin., LLC v. Plasma Fab, LLC, 
    519 S.W.3d 76
    , 86 (Tex. 2017) (noting that “we read unambiguous statutes as
    written, ‘not as they make the most policy sense’ ” (quoting Combs v.
    Health Care Servs. Corp., 
    401 S.W.3d 623
    , 629 (Tex. 2013))); MCI
    Telecomms. Corp. v. Am. Tel. & Tel. Co., 
    512 U.S. 218
    , 231 n.4 (1994)
    (noting that courts “are bound, not only by the ultimate purposes [the
    legislature] has selected, but by the means it has deemed appropriate,
    and prescribed, for the pursuit of those purposes”).
    The real facts here prove the point.           Providing an accurate
    identification number may turn out to satisfy both requirements—which
    5 As further examples of why more information may be required in a form
    than what appears necessary at first glance, consider that when a provider
    enrolls in Texas Medicaid, he or she enrolls in one of four enrollment types:
    Individual, Group, Performing Provider, or Facility. The Medicaid scheme
    requires some licensees to enroll in certain categories—for example, “dieticians,
    licensed vocational nurses, occupational therapists, registered nurses, and
    speech therapists” must enroll in the Individual category. The Medicaid scheme
    also requires that some providers enroll in the Performing Provider category
    whenever that individual “is seeking enrollment under a group.” Whatever the
    underlying policy rationales were, however, it is entirely improper for courts to
    vitiate the legislature’s choices simply because they make little policy sense.
    Separation of powers demands more; it is the courts’ job to say what the law is,
    not what it should be.
    17
    is presumably why the form was structured as it was—but this case
    involves a dentist who provided an inaccurate number on thousands of
    claims. There is, in short, no “superfluity” here.
    2
    Second, the Court invokes the presumption of consistent usage—
    that the statute’s disjunctive use of the word “or” in nearby provisions
    supports reading “and” to have a conjunctive meaning (or “distributive
    sense”) here. Ante at 25–27. Even assuming that the Court correctly
    categorizes the various uses of various conjunctions, the canon has no
    role to play in this case.
    What is the canon? In Colorado County v. Staff, the Court described
    it by quoting a statute: “Stated another way, ‘words and phrases that
    have acquired a technical or particular meaning, whether by legislative
    definition or otherwise, shall be construed accordingly.’ ” 
    510 S.W.3d 435
    ,
    452 (Tex. 2017) (brackets omitted) (quoting Tex. Gov’t Code § 311.011(b)).
    Defined terms, for example, usefully allow the legislature to use a single
    term to convey a concept that would otherwise require tedious repetition
    of lengthy, specialized meanings.
    This basis does not remotely support the Court’s theory that
    provisions like § 36.002(10), which use “or” disjunctively, make its
    construction of the word “and” in § 36.002(8) reasonable. As far as I know,
    neither this Court nor the U.S. Supreme Court has ever applied the
    presumption of consistent usage to the word “and.” To the contrary, the
    Supreme Court recently noted the novelty of such an argument in this
    very context, rejecting the applicability of such a presumption “to words
    as ubiquitous and . . . sometimes context-dependent as ‘and’ and ‘or.’ ”
    18
    Pulsifer, 144 S. Ct. at 735.6
    Understandably so: “and” and “or” are the exact opposite of words
    that take on a technical or particular meaning, whether by statutory
    definition, context, or otherwise. As the Supreme Court put it, “[t]he
    principle is mostly applied to terms with some heft and distinctiveness.”
    Id. (using “principal activity” and “money remuneration” as examples).
    Frankly, it is hard to imagine a less technical, substantive, particularized,
    hefty, or distinctive word than “and.”
    Trying to force a “consistent usage” discipline on the legislature’s
    uses of conjunctions, particularly in sentences with highly complex
    structures, is also troubling because we know that the presumption of
    consistent usage “is so often disregarded,” which is why it “is particularly
    defeasible by context.” Antonin Scalia & Bryan A. Garner, Reading Law:
    The Interpretation of Legal Texts 171 (2012); see also S.C. v. M.B., 
    650 S.W.3d 428
    , 445 (Tex. 2022) (“the consistent-use canon depends heavily
    on context”).
    Without the “defeasib[ility]” of this canon, we probably could not
    have the canon in the first place. The canon, after all, is an aid in
    reaching the meaning the legislature actually adopted, not a way for
    courts to punish the legislature for being less punctilious than members
    of this Court might (sometimes) demand. In other words, we use the
    6 To  quote the Court more fully, it observed that the petitioner in
    Pulsifer “breaks new ground in applying the [presumption of consistent usage]
    to words as ubiquitous and (as shown above) sometimes context-dependent as
    ‘and’ and ‘or.’ ” 144 S. Ct. at 735. Amazingly, the Supreme Court of Texas now
    chooses to till the same “new ground,” and even quotes Pulsifer for the general
    principle, see ante at 26, without mentioning that Pulsifer pulverized the
    attempt to do so here.
    19
    canon because it makes sense. When the legislature repeatedly uses a
    particularized term and gives no reason to think that any of those uses
    bear a different meaning, it would disrespect the legislature to interpret
    the same word differently. The same is true in ordinary speech. Someone
    who says “the president” to refer to the president of the school board six
    times in a conversation probably is not referring to President Biden in her
    seventh usage—unless context shows a changed meaning (such as the
    seventh usage coming an hour later and after someone else starts talking
    about national politics).
    We thus presume that a use of the same term is purposeful—that
    drafters use the same term to mean the same thing, just as anyone
    typically does in ordinary speech. But as with ordinary speech, it is just
    a rebuttable presumption for statutory interpretation—drafters often
    “use different words to denote the same concept,” so statutory context
    (with a little common sense sprinkled in) is essential. Scalia & Garner,
    supra, at 170 (emphasis added). Forcing the same term to bear the same
    meaning when context refutes consistent usage is just as bad as giving
    terms different meanings when nothing in the context suggests any such
    variant. This defeasibility principle applies even to specialized terms,
    much less to a conjunction, for goodness’ sake.7
    7 The Court claims that I would “only” apply the canon to terms that have
    a technical or specialized meaning, not conjunctions. Ante at 26 n.18. I am
    perfectly happy to assume that, in some contexts, the canon of consistent usage
    might apply to conjunctions. My point transcends all that: courts should wield
    the doctrine carefully. It should never be used to justify adopting an otherwise
    acontextual reading of a term. And because conjunctions are so far away from
    the kinds of words whose repetition implies shared meaning, they are among the
    least likely to warrant application of the canon (or, in Justice Scalia’s term, the
    20
    Examples of statutes that illustrate the danger of whipping out
    the consistent-usage canon on conjunctions are almost endless. Here is
    one from the Transportation Code. Vehicles’ headlights must be turned
    on “(1) at nighttime; and (2) when light is insufficient or atmospheric
    conditions are unfavorable so that a person or vehicle on the highway is
    not clearly discernible at a distance of 1,000 feet ahead.” Tex. Transp.
    Code § 547.302(a) (emphasis added).            Under the Court’s reasoning,
    because that section uses the word “or” disjunctively, we can reasonably
    construe “and” conjunctively. So drivers must use lights only when both
    (1) and (2) are present, even though the law obviously commands that
    lights be used in either situation, independent of the other. No rational,
    law-abiding citizen would read the statute as not requiring lights in heavy
    fog or pouring rain during the day. See State v. Gammill, 
    442 S.W.3d 538
    ,
    541 (Tex. App.—Dallas 2014, pet. ref’d) (holding that, when viewing “the
    statute as a whole, the plain meaning of the text imposes a duty to display
    lights during two alternative time periods”). But someone convicted
    under this provision for a daytime violation now has the prestige of the
    Supreme Court of Texas itself to argue that the statute unambiguously
    precludes any duty to have the lights on.
    Here is another example. Section 48.02 of the Penal Code is titled
    “Prohibition of the Purchase and Sale of Human Organs.” Tex. Penal
    Code § 48.02 (emphasis added). Under the Court’s reasoning, that title
    suggests that the statute would prohibit only the purchase and sale of
    organs; a seller of organs who did not first purchase those organs is in the
    most likely where the canon is “defeasible”). So I am where the U.S. Supreme
    Court is—applying the canon to conjunctions like “and” is unprecedented and
    weird, but I need not disclaim the possibility. See Pulsifer, 144 S. Ct. at 735–36.
    21
    clear. Such a construction makes no sense, as the statutory text (enacted
    at the same time as the title) reflects—it punishes one who “knowingly or
    intentionally offers to buy, offers to sell, acquires, receives, sells, or
    otherwise transfers any human organ for valuable consideration.” Id.
    § 48.02(b) (emphasis added).8 The Court ties itself in knots about this
    example, see ante at 28 n.19 (the fourth paragraph of the footnote), but
    again misses the point. The same legislature enacted both the title and
    the text in the same bill, which shows that the legislature does not feel
    quite as bound to “consistent usage” of conjunctions as the Court now
    thinks it ought to.
    The larger point, of course, is that there are many contexts in
    which there is no real difference between “or” and “and.” Because of that
    linguistic truism, the legislature was not really inconsistent in any
    meaningful way in any of these examples, and certainly not here.
    3
    The Court also argues that I cannot be right because the statute
    does not affirmatively require two pieces of information, but instead
    deems “wrongful” a “fail[ure] to indicate the provider’s identification
    number and license type.” Ante at 27 n.19. Semantics. The following
    two circumstances are not different: (1) affirmatively requiring two
    things to avoid punishment and (2) punishing a failure to provide only
    one of two things. Either way—because it is in fact just one way, written
    differently—the statute here requires both.
    8 We  have ways of dealing with statutory titles that conflict with
    statutory text, of course. But because I do not read conjunctions the way the
    Court insists on doing, I find no conflict here. In any event, the point I make is
    not substantive—it is about how the legislature uses conjunctions.
    22
    C
    Part of statutory context is what the statute tells us about its role
    in a larger statutory scheme. “Purpose” has a bad name because of
    “purposivism”—the school of thought that, without any particular textual
    anchor, determines at a high level of generality what the “purpose” of a
    statute is and then forces the text to conform to that discovered purpose.
    See, e.g., Scalia & Garner, supra, at 19; accord Pulsifer, 144 S. Ct. at 737
    (“No law pursues its . . . purposes at all costs.”) (brackets omitted)
    (quoting Luna Perez v. Sturgis Pub. Schs., 
    598 U.S. 142
    , 150 (2023)). This
    historic abuse of purpose is unfortunate for many reasons, not least this:
    “The term purposivism suggests, wrongly, that its supposed antonym—
    namely textualism—precludes consideration of a text’s purpose. This is
    not so. It is untrue that a textualist judge must ‘put on blinders that
    shield the legislative purpose from view.’ ” Scalia & Garner, supra, at
    20 (quoting William D. Popkin, An Internal Critique of Justice Scalia’s
    Theory of Statutory Interpretation, 
    76 Minn. L. Rev. 1133
    , 1142 (1992)).
    To the contrary, purpose, “in its concrete manifestations as deduced from
    close reading of the text,” is utterly essential to true textualism. 
    Id.
    Understood in this light, “[t]he evident purpose of what a text seeks to
    achieve is an essential element of context that gives meaning to words.”
    
    Id.
     (emphasis added); see also Tex. Dep’t of Transp. v. City of Sunset
    Valley, 
    146 S.W.3d 637
    , 642 (Tex. 2004) (noting that “[w]e also consider
    the objective the law seeks to obtain” when construing statutes).
    Put another way, a statute’s purpose, as revealed by the text’s
    plain meaning, is just another part of the statute’s legal context.
    Statutorily expressed purpose can helpfully eliminate alternatives that,
    23
    while grammatically possible, are deemed unreasonable because they are
    inconsistent with the statutory text.
    Here, the statutory text reveals both a general and specific
    purpose, which provides essential context that requires rejecting Dr.
    Malouf’s reading. Start at the top, with the title, which I have mentioned
    before. I wholly agree that the “title of a statutory provision cannot
    override the plain meaning of the underlying text,” but “a title can at least
    ‘inform the inquiry into the Legislature’s intent.’ ” Brown v. City of
    Houston, 
    660 S.W.3d 749
    , 754 (Tex. 2023) (quoting TIC Energy & Chem.,
    Inc. v. Martin, 
    498 S.W.3d 68
    , 75 (Tex. 2016)).            The heading to
    Chapter36 of the Human Resources Code was recently amended to read:
    “Health Care Program Fraud Prevention.” Act of May 16, 2023, 88th
    Leg., R.S., S.B. 745, § 2. It was similar as originally enacted: “AN ACT
    relating to the prevention of Medicaid fraud.” Act of May 27, 1995, 74th
    Leg., R.S., ch. 824, H.B. 2523. The legislature’s overarching motive is
    pretty obvious: to avoid squandering limited resources, it wants to pay
    only valid claims, including for treatments performed only by those
    licensed under the Medicaid scheme. The State does not want to pay for
    unauthorized medical services, and to that end has chosen to minimize
    the number of fraudulent claims by making it easier to detect fraud and
    by penalizing claimants who make fraudulent claims or claims that
    violate the anti-fraud requirements.
    The claim-reporting requirements—and the heavy consequences
    of violating them—are part of the effort to “prevent” fraud. Knowing the
    identity “of the licensed health care provider who actually provided the
    service” is one of the legislature’s specifically enumerated means of
    24
    accomplishing that end. Tex. Hum. Res. Code § 36.002(8). Knowing the
    healthcare provider’s identity greatly facilitates determining the claim’s
    legitimacy in a cost-effective and efficient manner. According to the
    Court, though, the State has really asked for nothing more than a
    provider’s license type. The Court’s holding today tells the State (and
    providers) that a complete lie—writing in some other person’s number
    who did not provide the treatment—is treated as compliance, just as long
    as that other person has the same license type.
    This reading fundamentally—and, I must say, rather obviously—
    botches the whole thing. Giving the State nothing but “license type”—
    how many dentists are there?—reads the text in a way that essentially
    renders the most important part (the identity of the actual provider) a
    dead letter. The Court’s interpretation impedes the statutory goals and
    function. Telling the State that it cannot require the provision of an
    accurate identification number (so long as the license types match up—
    but how would the State know that if it does not know who the actual
    provider is?) makes it harder for the State to verify that the claim is in
    all respects proper, and makes it harder to conduct the sort of anti-fraud
    monitoring that I described above.
    The Court’s reading of this fraud-prevention statute is one that
    makes fraud easier. The statute’s textually derived purpose confirms
    yet again that the only reasonable way to construe the statute is to
    require claimants to provide both pieces of information (which, in this
    context, is achieved by giving an accurate identification number, but is
    not achieved by giving only an accurate license type).
    The Court recasts the statutory purpose as “preventing fraudulent
    25
    harm to the Medicaid program.” Ante at 32. As long as the fraud does
    not disrupt the State’s ability “to properly process claims and distribute
    the appropriate amount of funds to the provider,” the statutory purpose
    is to not punish those who make false claims. Id.
    This argument fails for at least two reasons. First, even accepting
    the Court’s formulation, the “harm” to the State extends beyond paying
    unauthorized claims.      The State is harmed because it lacks the
    information that it needs to investigate whether a claim is authorized in
    the first place. If all the State knows is that some anonymous dentist
    did the work, it will either pay up despite being in the dark or have to
    determine (1) who actually performed the services and (2) whether the
    claim is otherwise authorized. When that inefficient and costly process
    is multiplied by the millions of Texans enrolled in Medicaid, it is easy to
    see why the legislature demanded information to enable cost-effective
    and efficient ways to verify claims or detect patterns of noncompliance.9
    So even if the State ultimately determines that a particular claim is
    authorized, incomplete or false information necessarily harms its ability
    “to properly process claims.”
    Second, and more fundamentally, it is quite dangerous to suggest
    that some lies are no big deal. Even if the procedures were authorized,
    providing false information about them is a big deal, and not only because
    of the indirect costs that such false information imposes. Yes, the parties
    9 There were over five million people enrolled in Medicaid in Texas in
    2022. Tex. Health & Hum. Servs., Texas Medicaid and CHIP Full Benefit
    Caseload By Risk Group By County—State Fiscal Year 2022 (2023),
    https://www.hhs.texas.gov/sites/default/files/documents/enrollment-by-county-
    final-sfy-2022.xlsm (last visited June 18, 2024)
    26
    have stipulated that properly qualified dentists performed the procedures
    in this case. If one conceives of the harm as limited to the delta between
    what the State actually paid and what it would have paid had the forms
    told the truth, then the lies may have been “harmless.” But we are not
    talking about tort or contract damages. The lie here is a violation of an
    important regulatory-enforcement law that requires accuracy for different
    reasons.
    Securities laws enforced by the government provide a useful
    analogy. When Congress passed the Investment Advisers Act of 1940, it
    “empower[ed] the courts to enjoin any practice which operates ‘as a fraud
    or deceit,’ ” but did not “intend[] to require proof of . . . actual injury to
    clients.” SEC v. Cap. Gains Rsch. Bureau, Inc., 
    375 U.S. 180
    , 192 (1963).
    Similarly, the Securities Act of 1933 “makes unlawful the making of
    untrue statements of material fact or the omissions of such a fact.” United
    States v. Tallant, 
    547 F.2d 1291
    , 1296 (5th Cir. 1977). It is the making of
    the untrue statement that is unlawful, “not the occurrence of a dollar loss
    as a result of the actions, statements, or omissions.” 
    Id.
     Put another way,
    “a violation of the Securities Act is [not] a result-oriented crime.” Cook v.
    State, 
    824 S.W.2d 634
    , 638 (Tex. App.—Dallas 1991), pet. ref’d, 
    828 S.W.2d 11
     (Tex. Crim. App. 1992) (per curiam). At least for government
    enforcement, securities laws protect the integrity of the markets—they
    do not just target actual financial losses caused by a lack of integrity.
    Likewise, the State legitimately demands that the Medicaid-
    reimbursement system be one of integrity. The statute does not just
    target general government “fraud”—it requires compliance with specific
    27
    anti-fraud and fraud-prevention requirements.10 Remarkably, however,
    intentional lies to the government that are material to its management
    of a massive and expensive program turn out to be of no great importance
    to the Court, which holds that § 36.002(8) was designed only to target
    those who ultimately receive more money than they would have received
    if they had told the truth. (And even this standard seems insufficient to
    support the Court’s judgment, because at least some of the false
    information supplied on the forms was apparently written to obtain
    money more quickly than would have been possible if the correct
    information had been supplied—for example, when the actual providers
    did not yet even have an identification number.)
    * * *
    Remember that all of this comes just because of the Court’s root
    canal of the word “and.” The foregoing reasons explain why, as a matter
    10 But suppose “fraud” as generally defined is the only thing that matters.
    As the Court notes, the Government Code defines fraud as “an intentional
    deception or misrepresentation made by a person with the knowledge that the
    deception could result in some unauthorized benefit to that person or some other
    person.” Tex. Gov’t Code § 531.1011(4) (emphasis added). So even if it were just
    standard government “fraud” at issue, the general definition still clearly
    contemplates that some frauds will not ultimately “result in some unauthorized
    benefit.” Id. The punishable act is not the realization of an unauthorized
    benefit, but the “intentional deception or misrepresentation.” Id.
    After all, unlike private plaintiffs, the government does not need to
    establish an actionable injury to bring an enforcement action; the violation of
    law is itself sufficient. See, e.g., Universal Brands, Inc. v. Philip Morris Inc., 
    546 F.2d 30
    , 34 (5th Cir. 1977) (“A mere showing by the private plaintiff of a
    violation of the anti-trust laws has no actionable significance because, while in
    a government action there need be established only an antitrust violation, a
    private litigant ‘must not only show the violation of the antitrust laws, but
    show also the impact of the violations upon him.’ ” (internal quotation mark
    omitted) (quoting Credit Bureau Reps., Inc. v. Retail Credit Co., 
    476 F.2d 989
    ,
    992 (5th Cir. 1973))).
    28
    of statutory construction, it is wrong for the Court to have interpreted the
    word as it did.
    That my reading of the statute aligns with the State’s does not
    mean that I think the statute cannot be abused. Maybe it was abused
    here. Dr. Malouf’s strongest point is not his argument that the statute
    does not even really care about knowing the “actual” provider. Nor is it
    his contention that the lies he told on 1,842 false claim forms did not
    really harm the State. His strongest point is instead that because all the
    procedures would have been authorized and paid for, the State is using
    the law as a sledgehammer against a gnat. Really, the State seeks $16
    million for a bunch of forms that were all wrongly filled out in exactly the
    same way, none of which was used to actually rob the treasury of even $1
    that should not have been paid? I hasten to add that I know nothing of
    the underlying investigation or negotiations, but it seems excessive.
    The Court’s solution is every bit as excessive. The meaning of
    “and” cannot turn on a collateral matter like whether the total penalty for
    these false claims was $1,000 or $16 million. The words of a statute mean
    what they mean. Giving this statute an excessively parsimonious reading
    does not fix enforcement proceedings that are excessively grasping. The
    law has other and better ways to solve that sort of problem—assuming it
    is one here—without rewriting a statute. Being over-penalized raises
    potential claims under our due-course clause or, perhaps most clearly,
    under the provision of our Constitution promising that “[e]xcessive bail
    shall not be required, nor excessive fines imposed, nor cruel or unusual
    punishment inflicted.” Tex. Const. art. I, § 13 (emphasis added).
    Dr. Malouf, however, has not invoked these constitutional
    29
    protections. The Court should not find a backdoor way to give him aid or
    comfort when he refuses to knock at the front door.11
    One might also argue that the State’s construction harshly
    penalizes claimants who inadvertently provide the wrong license type or
    identification   number     via   “unintentional     technical,    clerical,   or
    administrative errors.” Tex. Gov’t Code § 531.1011(4) (excluding such
    “errors” from the definition of fraud).        But the statute covers that
    possibility, too—it only punishes claimants who “knowingly” make claims
    without the required information. Tex. Hum. Res. Code § 36.002(8). In
    other words, the legislature included a mens rea element to prevent
    penalizing mere negligence—and remember, this is Dr. Malouf’s lead
    argument, for which he requests a remand.12 But any desire to hold the
    11 I take no position on the merits of any such contention, although I am
    quite open to them if over-penalizing is shown. My only point is if anything is
    wrong with the State’s case it is not its interpretation of the word “and.”
    12 The Court declines to resolve Dr. Malouf’s lead argument because it
    rules for him on his alternative argument. See ante at 14 n.13. But because I
    reject that argument, I must resolve whether summary judgment for the State
    was improper with respect to whether Dr. Malouf knowingly failed to provide
    his identification number and license type.
    I would mostly affirm on this ground, too. Dr. Malouf testified that he
    generally did not know that his clinic was providing false information. This
    testimony is probably enough to create a fact issue as to Dr. Malouf’s mental
    state—i.e., whether he genuinely did not know that his clinic was filing false
    claim forms. As to others, he testified that he knew his clinic was providing
    the wrong identification number, but thought that it was doing so based on prior
    approval from Texas Medicaid. In other words, Dr. Malouf admits to knowingly
    making false claims—he just thought that his conduct was excused. The
    statute, however, does not require “specific intent to commit an unlawful act
    under Section 36.002 . . . to show that a person acted ‘knowingly.’ ” Tex. Hum.
    Res. Code § 36.0011(b). Put another way, the statute does not excuse telling lies
    in good faith, so even if we credit Dr. Malouf’s testimony that he thought it was
    30
    State to its burden of proof has nothing to do with reading the statute to
    not require the specified information in the first place.
    The legislature struck a careful balance between two competing
    objectives: enacting strong protections against fraud while simultaneously
    excluding honest mistakes from the statute’s reach.                The Court’s
    approach disrupts that balance, departing from the fundamental
    principle that courts “enforce a statute as written, and avoid construing
    individual provisions of a statute in isolation from the statute as a whole.”
    Hlavinka v. HSC Pipeline P’ship, LLC, 
    650 S.W.3d 483
    , 491 (Tex. 2022)
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    D
    The Court also indulges in substantial dicta concerning the rule
    of lenity—dicta because, amazingly, the Court holds that the only
    reasonable interpretation of the statute is the one that I have shown to
    be utterly unreasonable, ante at 33, and with only one reasonable
    interpretation, there is no work for the rule of lenity to perform. I would
    not apply the rule of lenity either—because the only reasonable reading
    reaches the result contrary to the Court’s. But if the Court insists on
    addressing the rule of lenity, it should at least do so accurately. It is
    fine to falsely report that he was the provider, he still knowingly did it.
    With respect to the first batch of claim forms (those where Dr. Malouf
    allegedly did not know that his clinic was filing false claim forms), therefore, I
    would reverse and remand for the trial court to determine which (if any) forms
    qualify for the first batch and, as to those forms, let a factfinder evaluate the
    credibility of Dr. Malouf’s general denial. As to the second batch of claim forms
    (those where Dr. Malouf knowingly lied but believed he had the right to do so),
    I would affirm the judgment below that renders judgment for the State. I
    disagree with the Court as to both batches, and thus must dissent in the entirety
    of the judgment.
    31
    fortunate that all that discussion, see ante at 7–13, 33, is dicta.13
    The Court is mostly right in stating that, in cases of ambiguity, the
    rule of lenity requires courts to construe penal statutes narrowly and in
    favor of the accused. I also agree that the rule of lenity is not relevant
    absent ambiguity. But not just any ambiguity will do; after all, “most
    statutes are ambiguous to some degree.” Muscarello v. United States, 
    524 U.S. 125
    , 138 (1998).
    To the contrary, courts across the country, including this Court,
    apply the rule of lenity only in extreme cases. The U.S. Supreme “Court
    has repeatedly emphasized that a court must find not just ambiguity but
    ‘grievous ambiguity’ before resorting to the rule of lenity.” Shular v.
    United States, 
    589 U.S. 154
    , 167 (2020) (Kavanaugh, J., concurring). In
    other words, “the rule of lenity only applies if, after considering text,
    structure, history, and purpose, there remains a grievous ambiguity or
    uncertainty in the statute . . . such that the Court must simply guess as
    to what [the legislature] intended.” Barber v. Thomas, 
    560 U.S. 474
    , 488
    (2010) (emphasis added) (internal quotation marks omitted). We have
    likewise said that the rule applies only when there is “grave doubt as to
    the intention of the legislature.” Gulf, Colo. & Santa Fe Ry. Co. v. Dwyer,
    13 The Court starts by opining at great length on the rule of lenity, then
    agrees that the rule of lenity does not apply unless a statute is ambiguous, then
    deems this statute unambiguous, and thus concludes that the rule of lenity
    does not apply. Pulsifer reflects the sounder approach—to address lenity only
    at the end, and—if the statute is unambiguous—to decline further
    consideration of the rule of lenity for that reason, without any extraneous
    discursions into that doctrine. See 144 S. Ct. at 737 (“The two possible readings
    thus reduce to one—leaving no role for lenity to play.”). The Court’s contrary
    approach is akin to a lengthy discourse on the proper headwear for the rain,
    and only then looking out the window and seeing the sun.
    32
    
    19 S.W. 470
    , 471 (Tex. 1892) (emphasis added).14 The Court of Criminal
    Appeals applies the rule of lenity “when the proper construction of a
    statute is in insoluble doubt.” Diruzzo v. State, 
    581 S.W.3d 788
    , 802 n.22
    (Tex. Crim. App. 2019) (emphasis added); see also Cuellar v. State, 
    70 S.W.3d 815
    , 819 n.6 (Tex. Crim. App. 2002) (noting that it is
    constitutionally permissible to consider the rule of lenity only when
    absolutely necessary to resolve statutory ambiguity). The Fifth Circuit
    takes the same approach: “The rule of lenity . . . should be reserved for
    those situations in which a reasonable doubt persists about a statute’s
    intended scope even after resort to the language and structure, legislative
    history, and motivating policies of the statute.” United States v. Orellana,
    14 Contrary to the Court’s accusation that this quote reflects “[c]herry-
    picking one of our oldest decisions on the topic,” ante at 10 n.11, this Court has
    never suggested that we apply the rule of lenity before first applying traditional
    methods of interpretation to resolve superficial doubts about the meaning of
    statutory terms. The Court’s own citations (which seem to have no great concern
    with “old[] decisions”) prove the point. In Estes v. State, for example, the Court
    observed that “if doubt existed as to the intention of the legislature in the two
    preceding sections” of the statute in question, “that doubt [was] removed by
    considering them with [another section] which, in prescribing what shall be a
    sufficient indictment for the offense,” revealed the legislature’s intention
    “beyond a doubt.” 
    10 Tex. 300
    , 309 (1853). We then reiterated that “the
    intention of the legislature is manifest by considering the several provisions of
    the law in their natural connection as reflecting their meaning one upon the
    other,” thus placing “the proper construction of the statute . . . beyond a question
    by the application of [the rule of lenity].” 
    Id.
    “Cherry-pick[ed]” or otherwise, it is hardly an incorrect statement of
    Texas law. Unsurprisingly, this Court runs a bit low on cases specifically
    addressing what level of ambiguity is required to justify applying the rule of
    lenity—we construe penal statutes quite infrequently compared to other courts.
    Those that do regularly construe such statutes, however, apply the rule of lenity
    only in cases of grave ambiguity. I would not purport to chart a different
    course—and especially not in a case where the Court itself admits that the rule
    of lenity plays no role regardless of the level of ambiguity at issue.
    33
    
    405 F.3d 360
    , 371 (5th Cir. 2005) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    Words like “grave,” “grievous,” and “insoluble”—repeated in case
    after case, court after court, century after century—do some real work.
    The rule of lenity is not a special gift to one side of the case—a sort of
    strict-scrutiny of penal-law construction. It is a “break glass in case of
    ambiguity,” an absolute last resort when nothing else helps—not context,
    not the canons, not history and tradition, not statutory history. The rule
    of lenity means that if it would truly be a coin flip, we do not flip the coin
    but instead give the call to the defendant.
    But even if there were some ambiguity here, it is not remotely a
    “grave,” “grievous,” or “insoluble” ambiguity that escapes meaning. No
    coin-flipping needed. To the contrary, the text, structure, and purpose of
    this statute resolve the question. I hope that the lower courts do not draw
    from the Court’s dicta today that the rule of lenity is suddenly a vibrant
    force ready to slay statutory requirements that are otherwise clear.
    *   *    *
    “[T]extualists believe that meaning is a function of the way
    speakers use language in particular circumstances.” John F. Manning,
    The Absurdity Doctrine, 
    116 Harv. L. Rev. 2387
    , 2457 (2003). Courts must
    construe statutes with the knowledge that “words mean what they
    conveyed to reasonable people at the time they were written.” Scalia &
    Garner, supra, at 16. So “it is a ‘fundamental principle of statutory
    construction (and, indeed, of language itself) that the meaning of a word
    cannot be determined in isolation, but must be drawn from the context in
    which it is used.’ ” Yates v. United States, 
    574 U.S. 528
    , 537 (2015) (quoting
    Deal v. United States, 
    508 U.S. 129
    , 132 (1993)). This includes statutory
    context and purpose, the latter of which “must be derived from the text,
    34
    not from extrinsic sources such as legislative history or an assumption
    about the legal drafter’s desires.” Scalia & Garner, supra, at 56.
    The Court does not follow these principles today. Its “textualism”
    ignores the statutory context and expressed purposes underlying the
    Medicaid Fraud Prevention Act’s language. The rule of lenity has no role
    to play here, both because the statute is not ambiguous and because, even
    if it were, it would not be triggered as a first impulse.
    But if the Court is right and I am wrong, then buckle up. As I show
    next, if this statute means what the Court says, then a huge host of
    statutes do not mean what anyone has thought they meant.
    II
    The foregoing reasons are sufficient in and of themselves to merit
    my dissent. But the Court’s approach to statutory construction is also
    problematic because of multiple Texas and federal laws that use the
    terms “and” and “or” interchangeably.15 I mention those statutes for two
    15 As noted above, see supra at 5–6 & n.2, it is not just statutes that use
    “and” and “or” interchangeably. English speakers in non-legal and legal
    contexts have used one word when the other would not meaningfully change the
    phrase’s meaning or when the other word would seem better.
    To thee and thine hereditary ever
    Remain this ample third of our fair kingdom;
    No less in space, validity, and pleasure,
    Than that conferr’d on Goneril.
    William Shakespeare, King Lear act 1, sc. 1, l. 88–91 (emphasis added).
    The Texas Pattern Jury Charges also use “and” when “or” could do. For
    example, in deciding whether a nuisance is temporary, a jury must determine
    if the injury is “such that any anticipated recurrence would be only occasional,
    irregular, intermittent, and not reasonably predictable.” Comm. on Pattern
    Jury Charges, State Bar of Tex., Texas Pattern Jury Charges: General
    Negligence, Intentional Personal Torts & Workers’ Compensation PJC 12.4
    35
    reasons. First, their mere existence proves the point that I have made
    above—that these conjunctions are often used in such a transposable
    way. Statutes must therefore be read within their context, which always
    “includes common sense.” Morath v. Lampasas Indep. Sch. Dist., 
    686 S.W.3d 725
    , 738 (Tex. 2024) (quoting Biden v. Nebraska, 
    143 S. Ct. 2355
    ,
    2379 (2023) (Barrett, J., concurring)). Second, these statutes’ existence
    amplifies the threat of today’s decision—if this statute can be treated as
    the Court does, what is next? I hope, instead, that today is a one-off, and
    that the Court returns to the older tradition of relying on text within
    context, “includ[ing] common sense.”
    I start with just a few Texas statutes (and mention quite a few
    others—but still just the tip of the iceberg—in footnote 16, infra).
    Chapter 2 of the Texas Family Code generally forbids county clerks from
    issuing marriage licenses “if either applicant . . . fails to submit proof of
    age and identity.” § 2.009(a). Applying today’s logic, a county clerk
    (2022) (emphasis added). Under the Court’s reasoning today, a temporary
    nuisance must be all of those adjectives, even though all need not be found. See
    Schneider Nat. Carriers, Inc. v. Bates, 
    147 S.W.3d 264
    , 272 (Tex. 2004) (holding
    that a nuisance is “temporary if it is ‘occasional, intermittent or recurrent’ ”
    (emphasis added) (quoting Bayouth v. Lion Oil Co., 
    671 S.W.2d 867
    , 868 (Tex.
    1984))); see also Huynh v. Blanchard, ___ S.W.3d ___, 
    2024 WL 2869423
    , *18
    (Tex. June 7, 2024) (noting a jury’s finding that a “nuisance [was] ‘occasional,
    irregular, [and] intermittent’ ”).
    Our very own rules of procedure use “and” when context (and this Court’s
    routine practice) shows that it means “or.” See Tex. R. App. P. 52.8(a) (requiring
    an appellate court to deny relief “[i]f the court determines from the petition and
    any response and reply that the relator is not entitled to the relief sought”
    (emphasis added)). Under the Court’s reasoning, Rule 52.8(a) would not permit
    this Court to deny relief until it considered the petition, the response, and the
    reply. But in practice, this Court routinely denies relief without seeing a response
    or a reply to the petition for review. Today, the Court holds the legislature to a
    higher standard than the one to which we hold ourselves.
    36
    could issue a marriage license if an applicant submitted proof of identity
    but not age (or vice versa), even though the statute requires applicants
    to submit both pieces of information (sound familiar?). 
    Id.
     § 2.002(2)
    (requiring applicants to submit “proof of identity and age” in their
    application for a marriage license (emphasis added)).
    Chapter 312 of the Texas Health and Safety Code applies to
    agreements with a “medical and dental unit.” § 312.003. Under the
    Court’s reasoning, Chapter 312 would only apply to agreements with a
    unit that provided both medical and dental services, even though the
    statute is clearly intended to apply to agreements with medical or dental
    units.     See Tex. Educ. Code § 61.003(5) (specifying that the term
    “[m]edical and dental unit” includes both medical and dental schools).
    Consider also Chapter 65 of the Texas Parks and Wildlife Code,
    which “governs the taking, possession, and sale of alligators.” § 65.002
    (emphasis added). Under the Court’s approach, that chapter would
    punish someone who took, possessed, and sold an alligator—but one who
    took, possessed, and gifted an alligator would be beyond the statute’s
    reach. Yet viewed in context, the Code contemplates regulating all three
    activities, independent of the others—it permits the Parks and Wildlife
    Commission to regulate the “limits, size, means, methods, and places in
    which it is lawful to take or possess alligators,” among other things. Id.
    § 65.003(4) (emphasis added).16
    16 Besides those discussed in this part of my opinion, many other Texas
    statutes contain similar grammatical ambiguities. Here is but a sample: Tex.
    Fin. Code § 152.107(f) (providing that a money services licensee loses its
    license if it “fails to submit the completed annual report and pay the annual
    license fee and any late fee due within the time prescribed by [the statute]”
    37
    Federal law is no different. For example, 
    49 U.S.C. § 28301
    (b)
    provides that the preceding section “does not apply to . . . (A) an
    independently owned and operated railroad not exceeding one hundred
    miles in length; (B) an electric street railroad; and (C) an electric
    interurban railroad.”       Read in context, the Code does not require a
    railroad to satisfy (A), (B), and (C) to be exempted; rather, all three kinds
    of railroads are exempt. The Court’s reasoning would rationalize the
    (emphasis added)); 
    id.
     § 392.304(a)(6) (providing that a debt collector may not
    use “a written communication that fails to indicate clearly the name of the debt
    collector and the debt collector’s street address or post office box and telephone
    number if the written notice refers to a delinquent consumer debt” (emphasis
    added)); Tex. Lab. Code § 205.016 (providing certain penalties for a
    reimbursing employer “who fails to pay a reimbursement on the date on which
    the reimbursement is due, or who fails to submit records and reports, as
    prescribed by the commission” (emphasis added)); Tex. Loc. Gov’t Code
    § 83.004(a) (permitting a county judge to declare the office of county treasurer
    vacant “[i]f a person elected to the office . . . fails to provide an adequate bond
    as required by [statute] and to take the official oath on or before assuming the
    office (emphasis added)); Tex. Occ. Code § 651.460(a) (providing that “[a]
    person violates this chapter if the person . . . (2) fails to retain and make
    available to the commission, on request, copies of all price lists, written notices,
    embalming documents, and memoranda of agreement required by this
    chapter” (emphasis added)); Tex. Parks & Wild. Code § 12.603 (providing that
    the Parks and Wildlife Department can refuse to issue permits to applicants
    who “fail[] to submit . . . (1) a completed application . . . (2) the required permit
    fee; (3) accurate reports as applicable; and (4) any additional information that
    the department determines is necessary to process the application” (emphasis
    added)); Tex. Penal Code § 21.09(2) (providing that a person commits an
    offense if he or she knowingly “fondles or touches the anus or genitals of an
    animal in a manner that is not a generally accepted and otherwise lawful
    animal husbandry or veterinary practice, including touching through clothing”
    (emphasis added)); Tex. Tax Code § 181.001(a) (imposing a tax on one who
    “(1) manufactures or produces cement in, or imports cement into, the state;
    and (2) distributes or sells the cement in intrastate commerce or uses the
    cement in the state” (emphasis added)).
    38
    opposite result.17
    The Court also departs from the reasoning used by courts around
    the country. Just this term, the U.S. Supreme Court noted that courts
    should resolve ambiguity “by reviewing text in context.” Pulsifer, 144
    S. Ct. at 726. The Court rejected Pulsifer’s interpretation not because it
    was grammatically impermissible, but because it would “make[] a hash
    of the scheme Congress devised.” Id. at 735. Or, as this Court recently
    described Pulsifer, “requiring A, B, and C, each, provides a safety valve
    for otherwise stricter sentences, while requiring only one or two of the
    three would allow more violent criminals to be released sooner and
    seriously rupture the sentencing system.” Bd. of Regents of Univ. of Tex.
    Sys. v. IDEXX Labs., Inc, ___ S.W.3d ___, 
    2024 WL 2983170
    , *5 (Tex. June
    14, 2024). Yet here, the Court embraces a construction that ruptures the
    statutory scheme by insisting on a dubious definition of “and” even
    though only the State’s interpretation is consistent with the statutory
    protection against Medicaid fraud. It is hard to read these two opinions
    from our Court issued one week apart and make sense of them both.
    Likewise, state supreme courts across the country refer to
    statutory context and common sense when giving meaning to
    conjunctions. See People v. Allen, 
    968 N.W.2d 532
    , 538 n.16 (Mich. 2021)
    (holding that “the context mandates a disjunctive reading of ‘and’ ”
    because a conjunctive construction would have created a result
    inconsistent with the rest of the statutory scheme); State v. Irby, 967
    17 For further federal examples of statutes that disprove (and would be
    threatened by) the Court’s reasoning, see the Solicitor General’s Pulsifer
    briefing. She includes dozens. Pulsifer itself quoted 
    34 U.S.C. § 20101
    (f) as
    an example. See 144 S. Ct. at 728.
    
    39 N.W.2d 389
    , 395 (Minn. 2021) (“in limited circumstances, ‘and’ can be
    read in a several, that is, disjunctive, sense based on context and the
    specific way the word is used”). We should too.
    *   *    *
    The legislature can fix the specific error the Court makes today.
    It could amend the statute to use different language to affirmatively and
    expressly require both the license type and the identification number (or
    whatever else it may want). But how can the legislature solve the larger
    problem that the Court has created—a problem, as the foregoing
    discussion reflects, that permeates every part of our statutory law? If
    the judiciary is now going to read laws that are as clear in their scope as
    this one to mean something quite different than what they say, the
    legislature will not only have to scrub all new legislation, but will also
    have to race to check all the existing laws. Perhaps a review of legislation
    is no terrible thing—but to force the legislature to go on Conjunction
    Patrol at the cost of other legislative priorities seems to be a questionable
    way to treat a coordinate branch.
    Because I disagree with the Court’s articulation of the law and its
    result—a conjunction I use with meaning—I must respectfully dissent.
    Evan A. Young
    Justice
    OPINION FILED: June 21, 2024
    40
    

Document Info

Docket Number: 22-1046

Filed Date: 6/21/2024

Precedential Status: Precedential

Modified Date: 6/23/2024