Ipsen v. Diamond Tree Experts , 2020 UT 30 ( 2020 )


Menu:
  •                  This opinion is subject to revision before final
    publication in the Pacific Reporter
    
    2020 UT 30
    IN THE
    SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF UTAH
    DAVID SCOTT IPSEN,
    Appellant,
    v.
    DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.,
    Appellee.
    No. 20181052
    Heard December 11, 2019
    Filed May 20, 2020
    On Direct Appeal
    Third District, Salt Lake
    The Honorable Andrew H. Stone
    No. 160904449
    Attorneys:
    James L. Ahlstrom, Steven R. Glauser, Salt Lake City, for appellant
    Barbara K. Berrett, Zachary C. Myers, Salt Lake City, for appellee
    JUSTICE HIMONAS authored the opinion of the Court, in which
    CHIEF JUSTICE DURRANT and JUSTICE PETERSEN joined.
    ASSOCIATE CHIEF JUSTICE LEE filed a dissenting opinion, in which
    JUSTICE PEARCE joined.
    JUSTICE HIMONAS, opinion of the Court:
    INTRODUCTION
    ¶1 A core principle of tort law is that we each owe “a duty to
    exercise reasonable care” if our “conduct presents a risk of harm to
    others.” Air & Liquid Sys. Corp. v. DeVries, 
    139 S. Ct. 986
    , 993 (2019)
    (quoting RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIABILITY FOR PHYSICAL &
    EMOTIONAL HARM § 7 (AM. LAW. INST. 2005)). To be sure, there are
    a multitude of exceptions to this principle, the professional rescuer
    rule that we adopted in Fordham v. Oldroyd, 
    2007 UT 74
    , 171 P.3d
    IPSEN v. DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.
    Opinion of the Court
    411, being but one. That rule provides that “a person does not owe
    a duty of care to a professional rescuer for injury that was sustained
    by the very negligence that occasioned the rescuer’s presence and
    that was within the scope of hazards inherent in the rescuer’s
    duties.”
    Id. ¶ 13
    (emphasis added).
    ¶2 Today, we hold that the professional rescuer rule extends
    no further than Fordham’s definite and careful formulation and that
    a person does owe a duty of care to a professional rescuer for injury
    that was sustained by the gross negligence or intentional tort that
    caused the rescuer’s presence. Accordingly, we partially reverse
    and remand this case to the district court to allow it to adjudicate
    Ipsen’s gross negligence claims.1
    BACKGROUND2
    ¶3 A mulch fire occurred on the property of appellee,
    Diamond Tree Experts, Inc. In the week before the mulch fire, there
    had been at least two other fires on the property. And ten days
    before the mulch fire, a representative from the Salt Lake County
    Health Department told Diamond Tree that the mulch on its
    property was piled too high and that Diamond Tree needed to
    reduce it. Diamond Tree did not comply, meaning that at the time
    of the fire, it was in knowing violation of several ordinances—
    including the fire code—and of industry standards regarding the
    safe storage of mulch.
    ¶4 David Scott Ipsen was one of the firefighters who
    responded to the mulch fire. While working by the fire engine, and
    away from the fire, a thick cloud of smoke and embers engulfed
    him, leaving him unable to breathe. Ipsen sustained severe and
    permanent injuries—injuries that prevented him from returning to
    his job as a firefighter.
    ¶5 Ipsen sued Diamond Tree in district court for gross
    negligence, intentional harm, and negligent infliction of emotional
    distress. Diamond Tree moved for summary judgment, claiming
    that it owed no duty to Ipsen under Utah’s professional rescuer
    rule, which says that “a person does not owe a duty of care to a
    __________________________________________________________
    1 We do not opine on the sufficiency of the allegations that Ipsen
    brings against Diamond Tree. That is for the district court to
    evaluate on remand.
    2 On appeal from an order for summary judgment, we view “the
    facts and all reasonable inferences . . . in the light most favorable to
    the nonmoving party.” Espenschied Transp. Corp. v. Fleetwood Servs.,
    
    2018 UT 32
    , ¶ 3 n.1, 
    422 P.3d 829
    (citation omitted) (internal
    quotation marks omitted).
    2
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 30
                            Opinion of the Court
    professional rescuer for injury that was sustained by the very
    negligence that occasioned the rescuer’s presence and that was
    within the scope of hazards inherent in the rescuer’s duties.”
    Fordham v. Oldroyd, 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 13, 
    171 P.3d 411
    . The district court
    agreed with Diamond Tree and dismissed Ipsen’s claim for three
    main reasons. First, it held that under Fordham, Diamond Tree
    owed Ipsen no duty of care, even if Diamond Tree’s underlying
    conduct was egregious carelessness or violated ordinances. Second,
    the district court found that all the injuries that Ipsen alleged were
    inherent in firefighting. Third, the district court held that although
    Fordham does not immunize intentional behavior from liability,
    Ipsen had not established a genuine dispute of fact about an
    intentional behavior on Diamond Tree’s part.
    ¶6 Ipsen appealed. We exercise jurisdiction under Utah Code
    section 78A-3-102(3)(j).
    STANDARD OF REVIEW
    ¶7 “We review a grant of summary judgment for correctness.
    We give no deference to the district court’s legal conclusions and
    consider whether the court correctly decided that no genuine issue
    of material fact existed.” Heslop v. Bear River Mut. Ins. Co., 
    2017 UT 5
    , ¶ 15, 
    390 P.3d 314
    (citations omitted) (internal quotation marks
    omitted).
    ANALYSIS
    ¶8 In Fordham v. Oldroyd, we announced the professional
    rescuer rule. Under that rule, “a person does not owe a duty of care
    to a professional rescuer for injury that was sustained by the very
    negligence that occasioned the rescuer’s presence and that was
    within the scope of hazards inherent in the rescuer’s duties.” 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 13, 
    171 P.3d 411
    . Ipsen asks us to limit this rule so that
    professional rescuers can recover in tort for injuries stemming from
    gross negligence, intentional torts, and the violation of statutes and
    ordinances. Based on public policy, we hold that the Fordham’s
    professional rescuer rule does not apply in cases of gross
    negligence and intentional torts.3 A person thus does owe a duty of
    __________________________________________________________
    3 The dissent posits that the issue of duty in cases of intentional
    tortious misconduct is not “presented.” Infra ¶ 29 n.17. But the
    district court ruled on it, and one of the parties briefed the issue.
    Supra ¶ 5. We see no reason to ignore it. Moreover, as we find that
    gross negligence does not fall within Fordham’s professional rescuer
    rule, it is mere common sense that the more severe case of
    intentional torts does not fall within it either. “But Moses said to
    (continued . . .)
    3
    IPSEN v. DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.
    Opinion of the Court
    care to a professional rescuer for injuries sustained by gross
    negligence or an intentional tort causing the rescuer’s presence.
    Our holding is based on the vast difference in culpability and the
    considerably greater deterrence considerations gross negligence
    and intentional torts present compared to ordinary negligence.
    ¶9 “[C]ommon law is an aggregation of judicial expressions
    of public policy.”
    Id. ¶ 4.
    One area of the common law that is
    especially appropriate for “judicial public policy judgments” is the
    law of torts, and specifically the assignment of legal duty.4 Id.; Yazd
    v. Woodside Homes Corp., 
    2006 UT 47
    , ¶ 17, 
    143 P.3d 283
    (“Legal duty
    . . . is the product of policy judgments applied to relationships.”).
    The existence of a legal duty reflects this court’s conclusion, “on the
    basis of the mores of the community,” William L. Prosser, Palsgraf
    Revisited, 52 MICH. L. REV. 1, 15 (1953), that “the sum total” of the
    policy considerations say that “the plaintiff is [or is not] entitled to
    protection,” Univ. of Denver v. Whitlock, 
    744 P.2d 54
    , 57 (Colo. 1987)
    (second alteration in original) (citation omitted).
    ¶10 The general rule, as we outline at the beginning of this
    opinion, is that “we all have a duty to exercise care when engaging
    in affirmative conduct that creates a risk of physical harm to
    others.” B.R. ex rel. Jeffs v. West, 
    2012 UT 11
    , ¶ 21, 
    275 P.3d 228
    . We
    carve out exceptions to the existence of duty only in “categories of
    cases implicating unique policy concerns that justify” doing so.
    Id. In considering
    whether to make an exception, we rely on factors
    such as the foreseeability or likelihood of injury, public policy as to
    which party can best bear the loss occasioned by the injury, and
    __________________________________________________________
    the Lord, ‘If the Israelites will not listen to me, why would Pharaoh
    listen to me . . . ?’” Exodus 6:12. We see no reason to leave litigants
    in limbo about such a natural logical conclusion.
    4  We are not the “exclusive arbiters of public policy.” Fordham,
    
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 5. Our public policy pronouncements yield to those
    of the Utah Legislature. But, “[w]hen policy considerations bear on
    a subject lodged firmly within the court’s sphere, like the common
    law, it is entirely appropriate for the court to make the policy
    judgments necessary to get the law right.” Yazd v. Woodside Homes
    Corp., 
    2006 UT 47
    , ¶ 20, 
    143 P.3d 283
    . We have done so in numerous
    tort law cases. See, e.g., Nixon v. Clay, 
    2019 UT 32
    , ¶ 21, 
    449 P.3d 11
    ;
    Fordham, 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 6; Yazd, 
    2006 UT 47
    , ¶ 26. And we do so
    again today.
    4
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 30
                            Opinion of the Court
    other general policy considerations. Normandeau v. Hanson Equip.,
    Inc., 
    2009 UT 44
    , ¶ 19, 
    215 P.3d 152
    .5
    ¶11 In Fordham, we determined, based on public policy,6 that
    “a person does not owe a duty of care to a professional rescuer for
    injury that was sustained by the very negligence that occasioned
    the rescuer’s presence and that was within the scope of hazards
    __________________________________________________________
    5 The parties have not briefed us on the foreseeability or
    likelihood of injury of professional rescuers due to gross negligence
    or intentional acts. That said, as we express below, we think that
    general policy considerations are determinative here.
    6   The dissent argues that in Fordham, this court “rooted” the
    “professional rescuer rule” in “the doctrine of primary assumption
    of risk.” Infra ¶ 32. But the Fordham court relied on policy
    considerations only. Fordham, 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶¶ 7, 16; see also
    id. ¶ 25
    (Wilkins, A.C.J., concurring and dissenting) (“[A] third rationale
    became necessary to support the adoption of a professional rescuer
    rule. That rationale, relied on by my colleagues and the court of
    appeals in this case, is public policy.”). The court’s discussion of
    “assumption of the risk” was only meant to explain “why we have
    less to fear from an accusation that a professional rescuer rule is
    little more than assumption of the risk in disguise.”
    Id. ¶ 10.
    And
    although the dissent can attempt to re-write Fordham’s reasoning to
    include the assumption of risk doctrine, infra ¶ 32 n.18, it is clearly
    evident that the Fordham court discussed the doctrine for the
    limited reason of rebuffing concerns about the professional
    rescuer’s doctrine in other jurisdictions. Fordham, 
    2007 UT 74
    ,
    ¶¶ 12–13. Indeed, in Rutherford v. Talisker Canyons Finance, Co., LLC,
    
    2019 UT 27
    , 
    445 P.3d 474
    , our recent exploration of the assumption
    of risk doctrine, which canvased our state’s case law about it, the
    Fordham opinion is nowhere to be found.
    The dissent also contends that although the question in Fordham
    was one of policy, “the policy inquiry under our case law is
    centered on the question of implied consent.” Infra ¶ 46. But the
    Fordham majority opinion does not even include the phrase
    “implied consent,” nor any discussion of this concept. Instead, this
    court focused on the need to assure the public’s ability to use
    professional rescuers’ services “without fear of exposing their
    assets to compensate their rescuer in the event of injury,” Fordham,
    
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 7, and on the proposition that “the consequences of
    one’s inattention do not include the compensation of those on
    whom all of us collectively confer the duty to extricate us from our
    distress.”
    Id. ¶ 8
    . 
    We therefore reject the dissent’s attempt to imply
    otherwise.
    5
    IPSEN v. DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.
    Opinion of the Court
    inherent in the rescuer’s duties.” 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 13. We explained
    that the public policy underlying this exception is that “firefighters
    and police officers have a relationship with the public that calls on
    them to confront certain hazards as part of their professional
    responsibilities.”
    Id. ¶ 7.
    And “[i]t would be naive to believe that
    fire and police professionals will be called on to draw on their
    training in meeting only those hazards brought on by prudent acts
    gone awry.”
    Id. ¶12 The
    question we must answer today is whether the policy
    that supports a duty carve-out7 for professional rescuers’ suits for
    injuries stemming from negligence also supports a carve-out for
    their claims for injuries arising from gross negligence and
    intentional torts.8
    ¶13 The two public policy concerns that drove us to apply the
    professional rescuer rule to negligence in Fordham are culpability
    and deterrence.9 And because these two concerns do not apply
    __________________________________________________________
    7 The dissent argues that in this opinion we “establish[] an
    exception to Fordham.” Infra ¶ 43. That argument misses the mark.
    Fordham is the exception to the general rule that we all have a duty
    to exercise reasonable care. All we do today is clearly delineate
    Fordham’s boundaries.
    8 Fordham’s formulation of the professional rescuer rule only
    referenced negligence. 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 13. The district court here
    found our statement in Fordham to be a broad determination of lack
    of duty towards professional rescuers, “[r]egardless of whether [a
    person’s] conduct was negligent, reckless, [or] indifferent.” It was
    not.
    9 We recently decided in Nixon that a person’s state of mind does
    not affect the imposition of a duty in the context of the contact-
    sports exception. Specifically, we held that “voluntary participants
    in sports owe no duty to avoid contact that is inherent in the activity
    they are engaged in.” 
    2019 UT 32
    , ¶ 15. We found that the
    imposition of duty should not hinge on a participant’s mental state,
    because such a standard is “unnecessary and potentially
    problematic as applied to some sports.”
    Id.
    ¶ 22.
    We explained that
    in some sports, “intentional conduct is expected and even
    encouraged,” and that creating a duty of care for reckless or
    intentional conduct, “could impose liability on players for simply
    playing the game as it is designed and expected to be played.”
    Id. ¶ 23.
                                                          (continued . . .)
    6
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 30
                            Opinion of the Court
    when it comes to gross negligence and intentional torts, they
    compel the opposite result here.
    ¶14 First, sound public policy advised us in Fordham that the
    “consequences of one’s inattention” do not create a duty to
    compensate “those on whom all of us collectively confer the duty
    to extricate us from our distress.”
    Id. ¶ 8
    (emphasis added). But
    gross negligence and intentional torts implicate far more than mere
    inattention; they involve severe levels of culpability. Gross
    negligence is “the failure to observe even slight care; it is
    carelessness or recklessness to a degree that shows utter indifference
    to the consequences that may result.” Atkin Wright & Miles v.
    Mountain States Telephone & Telegraph Co., 
    709 P.2d 330
    , 335 (Utah
    1985) (emphasis added) (internal quotation marks omitted)
    (quoting Robinson Ins. & Real Estate, Inc. v. Sw. Bell Tel. Co., 366 F.
    Supp. 307, 311 (W.D. Ark. 1973)); see also Penunuri v. Sundance
    Partners, Ltd., 
    2017 UT 5
    4, ¶ 35, 
    423 P.3d 1150
    . And intentional
    __________________________________________________________
    Perhaps our language in Nixon was too slackly cabined. That is
    lamentable because the dissent now attempts to strip this language
    from its context and make it sweep more broadly. Infra ¶¶ 35, 40-41.
    But Nixon’s conclusion is irrelevant to the professional rescuers’
    rule for two reasons. First, in sports, a rule attributing liability
    based on a participant’s state of mind might impose it even if a
    participant played “by the rules.” But in the professional rescuers’
    context, any grossly negligent or intentional behavior is not a part
    of the accepted behavior in a well-ordered society. Although the
    dissent resists this obvious difference, infra ¶ 49, Fordham’s
    exception was expressly limited to situations resulting from one’s
    inattention. 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 8. The dissent argues that this limit is
    only “the net effect of our holding,” infra ¶ 49, but misses that this
    court expressly held this “broadly shared value about the workings
    of a well-ordered society” is the rationale from which Fordham
    emanates. Fordham, 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 8.
    Second, sports are governed by a separate set of rules than
    societal activities that may require the presence of professional
    rescuers. Tort duty in sports is governed by courts, as the dissent
    mentions, but there are other mechanisms to adjudicate one’s
    tortious behavior during a sporting event. The rules of most—if not
    all—sports impose penalties on individuals and teams. But there
    are no such rules that protect professional rescuers from one’s gross
    negligence or intentional tort. Courts, then, are the only institutions
    with authority to do so. And in exercising that authority to decide
    whether to impose a duty toward professional rescuers, it is proper
    for courts to evaluate the relevance and weight of one’s state of
    mind.
    7
    IPSEN v. DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.
    Opinion of the Court
    tortious conduct goes even beyond that. Atkin Wright & 
    Miles, 709 P.2d at 335
    ; see also Wagner v. State, 
    2005 UT 54
    , ¶ 32, 
    122 P.3d 599
    (explaining that “[t]he intent with which tort liability is concerned
    . . . is an intent to bring about a result which will invade the
    interests of another in a way that the law forbids.”) (citation
    omitted) (first alteration in original). So, although gross negligence
    differs only in degree from ordinary negligence, Negligence,
    BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 1134 (11th ed. 2019), that difference in
    degree is large and matters. “[T]he workings of [our] well-ordered
    society” include a “widely held belief that one is not exposed to tort
    liability for negligence requiring rescue.” Fordham, 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 8.
    But they do not include such belief when the degree of negligence
    is egregious, and even less so when the actions that requiring
    professional rescuers’ assistance were intentional.
    ¶15 The second policy concern in Fordham was that negligent
    people might be reluctant to call professional rescuers if they knew
    they could be liable for the rescuers’ resulting injuries.
    Id. But because
    people who act with gross negligence or intentionally are
    an order or two of magnitude more culpable than those who act
    negligently, they are unlikely to call professional rescuers in the
    first place. Imagine the emergency call: “911, I was utterly callous
    about setting (or deliberately set) my neighbor’s house on fire, and
    I’d like to report myself.” Pure fantasy. Thus, we are not seriously
    concerned that appreciably fewer of these individuals will call for
    help if we do not extend the professional rescuer rule to their
    situation.
    ¶16 For these very reasons, courts in other jurisdictions have
    differentiated between negligence on the one hand and gross
    negligence and intentional torts on the other. They have generally
    held that “[w]hile the fireman’s rule may provide a shield of
    liability for defendants in cases involving ordinary negligence, it is
    not a license to act with impunity or without regard for the
    [professional rescuer’s] well-being.” Lambert v. Schaefer, 
    839 S.W.2d 27
    , 29 (Mo. Ct. App. 1992) (citation omitted) (internal quotation
    marks omitted). This “recognition of moral fault as a component of
    public policy is a common principle of tort law.” Carson v. Headrick,
    
    900 S.W.2d 685
    , 690–91 (Tenn. 1995) (holding that the rule does not
    extend to injuries caused by “intentional, malicious, or reckless acts
    of a citizen”).10
    __________________________________________________________
    10 Courts around the country have articulated varied versions
    and scopes of the professional rescuer rule. However, almost all the
    courts that have addressed whether the professional rescuer rule
    (continued . . .)
    8
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 30
                             Opinion of the Court
    ¶17 According to the dissent, there is a “very real difficulty” in
    distinguishing negligence from gross negligence. The dissent uses
    colorful language to explain that the difference is one of degree
    only—the existence of which is left to the fact finder to decide. Infra
    ¶¶ 44–45. The distinction we clarify today, the dissent warns us,
    “will swallow the rule we adopted in Fordham,” infra ¶ 45,
    presumably allowing for professional rescuers to flood the courts
    with claims, by merely adding “a vituperative epithet” to their
    filing. Infra ¶ 45.
    ¶18 This slippery-slope argument is unpersuasive. This court
    has long dealt with the difference between negligence and gross
    negligence. See, e.g., Atkin Wright & 
    Miles, 709 P.2d at 335
    . We have
    explained that “[w]hile negligence generally connotes the failure to
    observe due care, gross negligence and recklessness are the failure
    to observe even slight care.” Bingham v. Roosevelt City Corp., 
    2010 UT 37
    , ¶ 44, 
    235 P.3d 730
    (citation omitted) (internal quotation
    marks omitted). And we have repeatedly found that it is possible
    to determine whether one was grossly negligent on summary
    judgment. See, e.g., Penunuri, 
    2017 UT 5
    4, ¶¶ 35–40; Blaisdell v.
    Dentrix Dental Sys., Inc., 
    2012 UT 37
    , ¶ 15, 
    284 P.3d 616
    .11
    __________________________________________________________
    applies to gross negligence and intentional torts have concluded
    similarly to us today—that it does not. See, e.g., Gaither v. Metro.
    Atlanta Rapid Transit Auth., 
    510 S.E.2d 342
    , 345 (Ga. Ct. App. 1998)
    (“A firefighter’s or police officer’s job does not include assuming
    the general risk of harm from a person’s wil[l]ful and wanton or
    malicious conduct.”); Labrie v. Pace Membership Warehouse, Inc., 
    678 A.2d 867
    , 869 (R.I. 1996) (limiting the application of the rule to
    “crisis created by a defendant’s ordinary negligence”); see also, e.g.,
    BPS, Inc. v. Parker, 
    47 S.W.3d 858
    , 862 (Ark. 2001); Thomas v. Pang,
    
    811 P.2d 821
    , 825 (Haw. 1991); Fox v. Hawkins, 
    594 N.E.2d 493
    , 498
    (Ind. Ct. App. 1992); State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Hill, 
    775 A.2d 476
    , 484–87 (Md. Ct. Spec. App. 2001); Torchik v. Boyce, 
    905 N.E.2d 179
    , 181–82 (Ohio 2009); Thomas v. CNC Invs., L.L.P., 
    234 S.W.3d 111
    ,
    120–21 (Tex. App. 2007); Goodwin v. Hare, 
    436 S.E.2d 605
    , 606 (Va.
    1993); This policy preference is also exhibited by legislatures in
    several states that have codified the professional rescuer rule but
    have not extended its effect to gross negligence and intentional
    torts. See, e.g., MICH. COMP. LAWS § 600.2967; N.H. REV. STAT.
    § 507:8-h.
    11 The dissent points to one case to substantiate its argument
    that our general rule is that “the grossness of a party’s negligence
    will be a matter left to the eye of the fact-finder.” Infra ¶ 45. But that
    (continued . . .)
    9
    IPSEN v. DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.
    Opinion of the Court
    ¶19 The dissent maintains that we should not treat negligence
    and gross negligence differently just because of their difference in
    degree. Infra ¶ 45. But in another context—that of liability
    waivers—this court has found that the difference between ordinary
    and gross negligence does matter.12 On public policy grounds, we
    have disallowed liability waivers for grossly negligent acts while
    permitting those that release liability stemming from negligent
    acts.13 See, e.g., Hawkins v. Peart, 
    2001 UT 94
    , ¶ 9, 
    37 P.3d 1062
    ,
    superseded by statute on other grounds as stated in Penunuri v. Sundance
    Partners, Ltd., 
    2013 UT 22
    , 
    301 P.3d 984
    (noting that a liability release
    “is always invalid if it applies to harm wilfully inflicted or caused
    by gross or wanton negligence” (citation omitted)).
    ¶20 We are not the only court to make this distinction. See, e.g.,
    City of Santa Barbara v. Superior Court, 
    161 P.3d 1095
    , 1097 (Cal. 2007)
    __________________________________________________________
    case, Norman v. Utah Hotel Co., stands for that proposition only in
    that particular instance and certainly establishes no general rule. 
    206 P. 556
    , 560 (Utah 1922) (“As we view it, in order to hold that the
    evidence in this case is insufficient to establish gross negligence, as
    a matter of law, we would be compelled to depart from the uniform
    holdings of this court that, under the circumstances here disclosed, the
    question is one of fact for the jury and not one of law for the court.”
    (emphasis added)).
    12 Moreover, Norman—the case that the dissent uses to argue
    that gross negligence is a matter for the fact finder—presents an
    ancient yet pertinent example of this difference, which the dissent
    so vividly resists. Norman addressed the case of a gratuitous
    bailment that requires a party “to exercise slight care only” which
    meant they would be “liable only for what, in law, is termed to be
    gross negligence.”
    Id. at 559.
    In other words, we recognized that a
    gratuitous bailer would not be liable for any ordinary negligence
    but would be liable for gross negligence.
    13 The dissent concedes our point but claims the difference in
    context make our analogy irrelevant. Infra ¶ 45 n.22. But analogies
    only require “similar[ity] in some ways.” Analogy, BLACK’S LAW
    DICTIONARY (11th ed. 2019). Requiring identical circumstances
    obviates our ability to use analogies. Our use of liability waivers is
    in response to the dissent’s unsupported argument that our
    distinction between ordinary and gross negligence “will swallow
    the rule we adopted in Fordham.” See infra ¶ 45. We pointed out that
    this court and many others have adopted this distinction in other
    contexts, where such horrific predictions have not materialized.
    The dissent prefers to not respond to this point, which we can only
    assume means that it concedes its validity.
    10
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 30
                            Opinion of the Court
    (“[A]n agreement made in the context of sports or recreational
    programs or services, purporting to release liability for future gross
    negligence, generally is unenforceable as a matter of public
    policy.”); Wolf v. Ford, 
    644 A.2d 522
    , 525 (Md. 1994) (“[A] party will
    not be permitted to excuse its liability for intentional harms or for
    the more extreme forms of negligence, i.e., reckless, wanton, or
    gross.”); Rafferty v. Merck & Co., Inc., 
    92 N.E.3d 1205
    , 1218–19 (Mass.
    2018) (“[W]hile a party may contract against liability for harm
    caused by its negligence, it may not do so with respect to its gross
    negligence or, for that matter, its reckless or intentional conduct”
    and “[i]mplicit in both our common and statutory law, then, is a
    long-standing public policy that, although we may be willing in
    certain circumstances to excuse ordinary negligence, we will not
    tolerate the reckless disregard of the safety of others.” (citation
    omitted) (internal quotation marks omitted)); Shelby Mut. Ins. Co. v.
    City of Grand Rapids, 
    148 N.W.2d 260
    , 262 (Mich. Ct. App. 1967)
    (“[A] party may contract against liability for harm caused by his
    negligence in performance of a contractual duty, [but] he may not
    do so with respect to his gross negligence.”); Sommer v. Fed. Signal
    Corp., 
    593 N.E.2d 1365
    , 1370 (N.Y. 1992) (“It is the public policy of
    this State . . . that a party may not insulate itself from damages
    caused by grossly negligent conduct.” (citations omitted)); Adams
    v. Roark, 
    686 S.W.2d 73
    , 75 (Tenn. 1985) (“While the case law and
    announced public policy of Tennessee favors freedom to contract
    against liability for negligence, it does not favor contracting against
    liability for gross negligence, and such an agreement is
    unenforceable.” (citations omitted)). And state legislatures have
    made the same differentiation in other contexts. See, e.g., MASS.
    GEN. LAWS ch. 229, § 2 (railroads not liable for negligence for
    causing death of trespasser but liable for reckless conduct); MICH.
    COMP. LAWS § 257.606a (ordering that governmental immunity
    from duty for highway maintenance “does not apply to actions
    which constitute gross negligence.”).
    ¶21 Much like the dissent here, litigants in California raised a
    slippery-slope argument in the liability waiver context. They
    argued that voiding liability waivers for grossly negligent behavior
    would “prove unworkable, or that application of such a standard
    would frustrate the proper termination of suits on summary
    judgment or foster untoward liability.” City of Santa 
    Barbara, 161 P.3d at 1107
    . The California Supreme Court rejected this argument,
    holding that “it does not appear that the application of a gross
    11
    IPSEN v. DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.
    Opinion of the Court
    negligence standard, as defined in California,[14] has a tendency to
    impair the summary judgment process or confuse juries and lead
    to judgments erroneously imposing liability.” Quite the opposite:
    “[t]hese statutes reflect the sound legislative judgment that, under
    a gross negligence standard, meritless suits will typically be
    disposed of by summary judgment; that when a case goes to trial[,]
    the jury, instructed on this standard, will be less likely to confuse
    injury with fault;” and that “verdicts reflecting such confusion will
    be more readily reversed, whether by the trial or appellate court,
    than under an ordinary negligence standard.”
    Id. at 1108
    (citation
    omitted) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    ¶22 We agree with this reasoning. We have no reason to
    believe, nor are we presented with evidence from the parties, the
    dissent, or our sister states that, unlike with liability waivers,
    limiting the professional rescuer’s rule to negligence will swallow
    the rule in litigation about the potential grossness of negligent acts.
    ¶23 The dissent also writes expansively about the
    compensation that “people who work in dangerous jobs” receive.
    Infra ¶ 34 n.19. But the parties have not briefed this point, and
    nothing in the record supports it. Moreover, many professional
    rescuers volunteer their time and efforts. See, e.g., State v. Alonzo,
    
    973 P.2d 975
    , 977 (Utah 1998) (police volunteer); State v. Graham,
    
    2011 UT App 332
    , ¶ 20, 
    263 P.3d 569
    (volunteer fire department);
    Fox v. Brigham Young Univ., 
    2007 UT App 406
    , ¶ 3, 
    176 P.3d 446
    (volunteer emergency medical technicians). We have not excluded
    them from the Fordham exception, but other jurisdictions have
    diverging decisions about the matter. Compare Roberts v. Vaughn,
    
    587 N.W.2d 249
    , 252 (Mich. 1998) (holding that the professional
    rescuer’s rule does not apply to volunteers on public policy
    grounds), with Waggoner v. Troutman Oil Co., Inc., 
    894 S.W.2d 913
    ,
    916 (Ark. 1995) (holding that the rule does apply to volunteers on
    public policy grounds), and Buchanan v. Prickett & Son, Inc., 
    279 N.W.2d 855
    , 860 (Neb. 1979) (holding that the rule does apply to
    volunteers under assumption-of-the-risk principles). The dissent’s
    compensation argument does not apply to volunteer professional
    rescuers, but the harsh consequence of the dissent’s suggested
    expansion of the Fordham professional rescuer’s rule most certainly
    would. The dissent concedes this point, but contends “we could
    easily reserve any decision on [volunteer rescuers] for a case in
    which it arises.” Infra ¶ 34 n.19. The dissent’s move makes
    __________________________________________________________
    14 California defines gross negligence as the “failure to exercise
    even slight care, or an extreme departure from the ordinary
    standard of conduct.” City of Santa 
    Barbara, 161 P.3d at 1106
    .
    12
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 30
                            Opinion of the Court
    Fordham’s rule even more complex. Moreover, where does that
    leave the rule in the case of a future professional rescuer who shows
    they did not receive any additional hazardous compensation? Yet
    a further complication of the rule?
    ¶24 Ipsen also asks us to hold that the Fordham professional
    rescuer rule does not apply when the presence of professional
    rescuers is required because of a violation of an ordinance or
    statute. We decline that invitation. We hold that violations of
    ordinances or statutes on their own are not enough to infer that a
    duty exists.15 As we explain above, our public policy considerations
    are shaped in connection with the degree of carelessness that
    precipitated the actions requiring the presence of the professional
    rescuers. In violating an ordinance or statute, one’s conduct might
    be negligent, grossly negligent, or intentional. Narrowing the
    professional rescuer rule in the way that Ipsen proposes would
    allow suits for even minor infractions and violations. This would
    generate litigation when there has been only ordinary negligence,
    which would be against the rule’s rationale.
    ¶25 In sum, we decline to extend Fordham’s professional
    rescuer rule any further. The professional rescuer rule applies only
    when the relevant action was ordinarily negligent and “within the
    scope of hazards inherent in the rescuer’s duties.” Fordham, 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 13. But a person has a duty towards professional rescuers
    in cases of gross negligence and intentional acts, and professional
    rescuers may recover against them in such circumstances.
    __________________________________________________________
    15 Ipsen also argues that his injuries, even if caused by mere
    negligence, do not fall within the Fordham exception as they are not
    inherent in firefighting. The district court treated the inherency
    inquiry as a question of law and determined that Ipsen’s injury—
    smoke inhalation—is inherent in firefighting. Ipsen argues that this
    is a question of fact, which should be determined on case-by-case
    examination. This argument fails because “duty is a question of law
    determined on a categorical basis.” West, 
    2012 UT 11
    , ¶ 25. More
    specifically, we “analyze each pertinent factor in the duty analysis
    at a broad, categorical level for a class of defendants without
    focusing on the particular circumstances of a given case.” Mower v.
    Baird, 
    2018 UT 29
    , ¶ 16, 
    422 P.3d 837
    (citation omitted) (internal
    quotation marks omitted). The inherency of the injury is a factor in
    the duty analysis under Fordham and is a question of law. We find
    no reason to treat it differently than any other duty factor and reject
    the notion that it should be adjudged factually and case-by-case.
    We thus reject Ipsen’s argument on this point and affirm the district
    court’s ruling that Ipsen’s injury was inherent in firefighting.
    13
    IPSEN V. DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    ¶26 Because the district court held that Fordham’s exception to
    duty extends to gross negligence, it did not determine whether
    Ipsen’s claims about Diamond Tree’s conduct amount to gross
    negligence. We reverse the district court’s decision in this regard
    and remand the case to the district court to rule whether Diamond
    Tree’s actions were grossly negligent, creating a duty to Ipsen.16
    CONCLUSION
    ¶27 We clarify that the professional rescuer rule we adopted in
    Fordham is tethered to its own language. We hold that a person
    owes professional rescuers a duty of care when that person’s gross
    negligence or intentional tort triggers the rescuers’ presence. We
    thus partially reverse the summary judgment order and remand
    the case to the district court for adjudication in accordance with this
    opinion.
    ASSOCIATE CHIEF JUSTICE LEE, dissenting:
    ¶28 Diamond Tree is charged with “gross negligence” in
    committing fire code and other violations that led to the
    spontaneous combustion of merchandise (mulch) piled on its
    business property. David Scott Ipsen was a firefighter called to put
    out the fire. He suffered injuries from smoke inhalation and
    ultimately retired when he was unable to continue his work. He
    then filed suit against Diamond Tree in tort, asserting that its acts
    of “gross negligence” were the cause of his injuries. The district
    court dismissed this claim, concluding that Diamond Tree owed no
    duty to Ipsen under the “professional rescuer rule” adopted in
    Fordham v. Oldroyd, 
    2007 UT 74
    , 
    171 P.3d 411
    .
    ¶29 I would affirm. I find the question presented to be
    controlled by our analysis in Fordham and reinforced by our more
    recent decision in Nixon v. Clay, 
    2019 UT 32
    , 
    449 P.3d 11
    . These cases
    establish that the duty inquiry here is based on the doctrine of
    primary assumption of risk as informed by the principle of implied
    consent. As applied here, these doctrines tell us that there is no duty
    in a case like this one because smoke inhalation from fighting
    __________________________________________________________
    16 The district court did rule that Fordham’s exception does not
    cover intentional torts but held that Ipsen did not show that
    Diamond Tree’s actions were intentional. Ipsen did not challenge
    these findings in his briefing, only impliedly in oral argument.
    Given the district court’s application of the correct legal rule, we
    affirm the district court order in that regard.
    14
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 30
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    fires—whether set negligently or by a higher level of negligence we
    might call “gross”17—is “inherent” in the voluntary acts of a
    firefighter.
    ¶30 I respectfully dissent on the grounds that (1) the rationale
    and standards in Fordham and Nixon foreclose the imposition of a
    duty; and (2) the majority’s attempts to distinguish these cases are
    unpersuasive.
    I
    ¶31 In Fordham v. Oldroyd, we established the “professional
    rescuer rule” in Utah, holding that “a person does not owe a duty
    of care to a professional rescuer for injury that was sustained by the
    very negligence that occasioned the rescuer’s presence and that was
    within the scope of hazards inherent in the rescuer’s duties.” 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 13, 
    171 P.3d 411
    . We rendered that ruling in recognition of
    the fact that the injury at issue in that case “was within the scope of
    those risks inherent in the professional rescuer’s duties.”
    Id. ¶ 6.
    Noting that “firefighters and police officers have a relationship
    with the public that calls on them to confront certain hazards as
    part of their professional responsibilities,” we held that there was
    no duty in tort that arises in the exercise of those duties.
    Id. ¶ 7.
    We
    found it “naive to believe that fire and police professionals will be
    called on to draw on their training in meeting only those hazards
    __________________________________________________________
    17 The majority announces a rule establishing a duty that arises
    in cases of “gross negligence” or “intentional torts.” But the latter
    question (of a duty in cases of intentional misconduct) is not
    presented by the facts of this case, and I see no reason to reach it
    here.
    The majority reaches this question on the grounds that “the
    district court ruled on it, and one of the parties briefed the issue.”
    Supra ¶ 8 n.3. But the majority itself affirms the district court’s
    determination that Ipsen did not show that any of Diamond Tree’s
    actions were intentional. See supra ¶ 26 n.16. It also concedes that
    “Ipsen did not challenge these findings in his briefing.” Supra ¶ 26
    n.16. So there is no intentional tort at issue in this case, and thus no
    reason to decide whether intentional torts fall within Fordham’s
    professional rescuer rule.
    The majority responds by asserting that the decision to
    recognize a gross negligence exception to Fordham must logically
    lead to an exception for intentional torts. Supra ¶ 8 n.3. This
    “common sense” proposition, supra ¶ 8 n.3, may hold for some
    forms of gross negligence and intentional torts, but not others. I
    would thus reserve this question for a case in which it is squarely
    presented.
    15
    IPSEN v. DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    brought on by prudent acts gone awry.”
    Id. And we
    accordingly
    held that professional rescuers are owed no tort duty by those they
    are duty-bound—and compensated—to protect.
    ¶32 We rooted this holding in the doctrine of primary
    assumption of risk.18
    Id. ¶¶ 13–15.
    Because the officer plaintiff in
    Fordham was in the course of a “seemingly usual activity for a
    highway patrol trooper at an accident scene” when he was injured
    (by an automobile accident caused by a negligent driver), we held
    that the professional rescuer rule established an exception to the
    general rule imposing a duty of reasonable care.
    Id. ¶ 15.
    And we
    emphasized that “[t]he nature of the rescuer-rescued relationship
    is one that contemplates allocation of costs across society generally
    for injuries sustained by professional rescuers.”
    Id. ¶ 17.
        ¶33 The Fordham rule was admittedly announced in the context
    of an allegation of mere negligence. But the terms of and rationale
    for our holding sweep more broadly—in a manner that covers the
    gross negligence alleged in this case. A firefighter’s “relationship
    with the public” anticipates that he will be asked to fight fires set
    by a wide range of acts of carelessness. And there is no room for a
    conclusion that a fire like the one at issue here—set by careless
    disregard of the fire code and other regulations in a business that
    surely desired not to have its merchandise go up in smoke—is
    somehow outside the “scope of those risks inherent in” firefighting.
    __________________________________________________________
    18 The majority insists that “the Fordham court relied on policy
    considerations only,” asserting that the discussion of assumption
    of risk in that case “was only meant to explain why ‘we have less
    to fear from an accusation that a professional rescuer rule is little
    more than assumption of the risk in disguise.’” Supra ¶ 11 n.6
    (quoting Fordham v. Oldroyd, 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 10, 
    171 P.3d 411
    ). But
    this wasn’t all we said about assumption of risk in Fordham. We also
    explained that primary assumption of risk is “an alternative
    expression for the proposition” that “there was no duty owed or
    there was no breach of an existing duty.” Fordham, 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 12
    (internal quotation marks and citation omitted). And we went on
    to hold that the defendant in that case “owed no duty” because
    “imposing one would offend sound public policy.”
    Id. ¶ 14.
    The
    public policy analysis in Fordham, in other words, is inextricably
    intertwined with the assumption of risk analysis. Invocation of the
    one hardly forecloses reliance on the other. And both lines of
    analysis appear in Fordham, the majority’s insistence
    notwithstanding.
    16
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 30
                           Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    The fighting of such fires is surely a “seemingly usual activity” for
    a firefighter.19
    ¶34 The line between “mere negligence” and “gross
    negligence” is a thin one. And a firefighter who arrives on the scene
    of a fire is not stopping to ask about the level of egregiousness of
    the negligence that caused the fire. It is therefore “naive to believe”
    that firefighters “will be called on to draw on their training in
    meeting only those hazards brought on by” mere negligence. See
    id. ¶ 7.
       ¶35 This conclusion is reinforced by our decision in Nixon v.
    Clay, 
    2019 UT 32
    , 
    449 P.3d 11
    . In Nixon we applied the doctrine of
    __________________________________________________________
    19 People who work in dangerous jobs like firefighting are
    compensated by the market for these risks. Their salaries are higher
    than those with otherwise comparable, but less dangerous jobs.
    This is what economists call “hazard pay.” See W. Kip Viscusi, Job
    Safety, in THE CONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA OF ECONOMICS 490, 490–91
    (David R. Henderson, ed., 2nd ed. 2007) (describing the “extra pay
    for job hazards” as “establish[ing] the price employers must pay for
    an unsafe workplace” and explaining that “[t]hese wage premiums
    are the amount workers insist on being paid for taking risks”);
    James C. Robinson, Hazard Pay in Unsafe Jobs: Theory, Evidence, and
    Policy Implications, 64 MILBANK Q. 650, 652 (1986) (explaining that
    according to “[m]ainstream economic theory,” “competitive
    pressures in the labor market force firms with unsafe jobs to pay
    extra-high wages” because if “a negative job characteristic of one
    kind (dangerous conditions) is not balanced by a positive
    characteristic of another kind (high wages, good fringe benefits,
    etc.) the job will not be filled”). Hazard pay is thus rooted in the
    theory of “compensating differentials” which traces its origin to
    Adam Smith.
    Id. at 652;
    see also Rueda v. Utah Labor Comm’n, 
    2017 UT 5
    8, ¶ 180 n.7, 
    423 P.3d 1175
    (Lee, A.C.J., separate opinion)
    (explaining how “an employee called upon to work with lead paint
    on a daily basis is likely receiving higher compensation in the form
    of hazard pay because of the known risks associated with that
    employment” as opposed to “an office worker” who “is likely
    compensated in accordance with the low risks associated with
    office employment”).
    Volunteer rescuers of course receive no such hazard pay. See
    supra ¶ 23. But the assumption of risk rationale discussed above is
    merely supported by, and not dependent on this point. Contra supra
    ¶ 23. Regardless, this case does not involve a volunteer rescuer, and
    we could easily reserve any decision on that fact pattern for a case
    in which it arises.
    17
    IPSEN v. DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    primary assumption of risk in holding that there is no duty in the
    context of voluntary interactions occurring as a result of the
    inherent risks of a sport. We said that this decision “involves a
    policy determination (based on implied consent) that there is no
    basis for the imposition of a duty in tort.”
    Id. ¶ 26
    n.6. And we cited
    Fordham for the proposition that “this doctrine is alive and well in
    our law.”
    Id. ¶36 In
    reaching this conclusion we declined to establish a
    “contact sports exception” per se. We rejected the “majority rule,”
    which stated that there is no duty for injuries incurred in a “contact
    sport” except where the tortfeasor acted “willfully or recklessly.”
    Id. ¶¶ 9–10.
    Instead we established a “simpler framework” focused
    purely on the primary assumption of risk doctrine.
    Id. ¶ 10.
    Citing
    the Restatement (Second) of Torts section 50 comment b, we noted
    that “[c]ontact . . . is a known and accepted risk of many sports.”
    Id. ¶ 19.
    And we held that there is no duty arising from contacts that
    are a result of “voluntary participation in sports.”
    Id. ¶ 21.
        ¶37 In so concluding we held that the tortfeasor’s “state of
    mind” is “not a necessary element” of the inquiry into the existence
    of a duty in tort.
    Id. ¶ 10.
    We held that “the ‘intentional or reckless’
    conduct standard” was “unnecessary and potentially problematic
    as applied to some sports.”
    Id. ¶ 22.
    “In sports like football, rugby,
    ice hockey, and other high-contact sports,” we noted that “contact
    between players is often simultaneously intentional or reckless and
    inherent in the game.”
    Id. And we
    therefore specified that the duty
    inquiry is not tied to the tortfeasor’s state of mind but instead to
    “inherency.”
    Id. ¶ 25.
        ¶38 “The inherency inquiry,” we explained, “is an outgrowth
    of our longstanding doctrine of primary assumption of risk.”
    Id. ¶ 26
    . And that doctrine, in turn, “is rooted in a principle of implied
    consent”—the notion “that participants implicitly consent to
    dangers that are inherent in the activity they voluntarily participate
    in.”
    Id. “For such
    dangers,” we held that “the doctrine of primary
    assumption of risk provides that there is no duty, and thus no
    liability, in tort.”
    Id. ¶39 Nixon
    thus provides that “the dispositive question” is
    “whether the contact that caused the injury was either an essential
    or inherent part of participation in a sport voluntarily engaged in
    by the parties.”
    Id. ¶ 30.
    “And that inquiry should be rooted in the
    implied consent basis for the doctrine of primary assumption of
    risk.”
    Id. “The ultimate
    question,” then, “is whether the contact that
    caused the injury” was such “that a person engaging in the activity
    could be said to have impliedly consented to the contact.”
    Id. 18 Cite
    as: 
    2020 UT 30
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    ¶40 The premises of our Nixon opinion further reinforce the
    application of the Fordham rule to cases involving allegations of
    gross negligence. Under Nixon the key inquiry is a matter of
    inherency under the doctrine of primary assumption of risk. And
    inherency is a question of implied consent. Nixon establishes that a
    tortfeasor’s state of mind is not the controlling question. Acts that
    cause injuries can be “simultaneously . . . reckless and inherent in”
    a voluntary activity.
    Id. ¶ 22.
    So the “dispositive question” is
    “whether the contact that caused the injury was either an essential
    or inherent part of participation in” a voluntary activity.
    Id. ¶ 30.
    That forecloses Ipsen’s position.
    ¶41 That also follows from the “implied consent” rationale in
    Nixon. Firefighters impliedly consent to the risk of smoke
    inhalation in the course of their jobs. Smoke inhalation is one of the
    central risks of firefighting.20 It is surely inherent in the job. And the
    inherency doesn’t disappear when the fire is caused by a
    heightened level of negligence.
    ¶42 I would resolve this case on these grounds. I find these
    conclusions dictated by Fordham and Nixon. And I would thus
    affirm the district court’s decision dismissing Ipsen’s tort claim.
    II
    ¶43 The majority disagrees. It establishes an exception to
    Fordham and imposes a duty for fires set by gross negligence. It says
    that “[t]he two public policy concerns that drove us to apply the
    professional rescuer rule to negligence in Fordham are culpability
    and deterrence.” Supra ¶ 13. And it holds that there is a duty to a
    firefighter in tort where a fire is set by gross negligence because
    such activity “involve[s] severe levels of culpability”—“far more”
    than mere negligence—and raises no concerns of deterring people
    from calling the fire department for help. Supra ¶¶ 14–15. I agree
    __________________________________________________________
    20 See P.W. Brandt-Rauf et al., Health hazards of firefighters:
    exposure assessment, 45 BRIT. J. INDUS. MED. 606, 606 (1988)
    (discussing various toxic chemical components of smoke from
    common burning materials and explaining that these “hazardous
    byproducts of combustion are encountered during the normal
    occupational activities of firefighters” as attested by various studies)
    (emphasis added); Tee L. Guidotti & Veronica M. Clough,
    Occupational Health Concerns of Firefighting, 13 ANN. REV. PUB.
    HEALTH 151, 151 (1992) (explaining that the “acute hazards of
    firefighting, primarily trauma, thermal injury, and smoke inhalation[]
    are obvious” (emphases added)).
    19
    IPSEN v. DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    with the latter point.21 But I don’t think the concern for deterrence
    is the driving consideration. And the line between mere negligence
    and gross negligence is too thin for me to agree with the court’s first
    point.
    ¶44 As this court long ago recognized, “accordion words like
    ‘mere negligence’ and ‘gross negligence’ or ‘wanton negligence’
    suggest comparisons only and give no absolute rule for guidance.”
    __________________________________________________________
    21 While I agree with the conclusion that imposing tort liability
    for gross negligence doesn’t raise deterrence concerns, I disagree
    with the majority about why that is. The majority says that “people
    who act with gross negligence” are “unlikely to call professional
    rescuers in the first place.” Supra ¶ 15. It bases that conclusion on
    the specter of a 911 call in which the caller reports that he was
    “utterly callous about setting” a “neighbor’s house on fire” and is
    calling “to report [him]self.” Supra ¶ 15. Because such a call is
    “[p]ure fantasy,” the majority says that it is thus “not seriously
    concerned that appreciably fewer of these individuals will call for
    help” if we subject them to tort liability through imposition of a
    duty to professional rescuers. Supra ¶ 15. I agree that the call
    imagined by the majority is fantasy. But I don’t think that means
    that people won’t call to report fires set by those who were utterly
    callous.
    For one thing, fires are often reported by people who have no
    idea how it was started—by someone other than the one who
    started it, for example. For another, even the person who started
    the fire may have no clear sense of whether his acts will ultimately
    be deemed to cross the thin line between ordinary and gross
    negligence. Like the firefighter who arrives on the scene, he “is not
    stopping to ask about the level of egregiousness of the negligence
    that caused the fire,” supra ¶ 34, before calling 911. And even if the
    person who set the fire knew he was grossly negligent, he could
    still decide it is worth it to call the fire department to mitigate any
    damage to his property—despite the prospect that he might
    ultimately be liable for any injuries to responding firefighters.
    Lastly, the person who set the fire would have no reason to confess
    to being “utterly callous” in setting the fire. That is “[p]ure fantasy”
    for all sorts of reasons, not the least of which is that the degree of
    any culpability in setting a fire is not the point of the 911 call. See
    supra ¶ 15.
    My bottom line is that I think the 911 call will often get made
    even for fires set by gross negligence. I thus disagree with the
    premise of the majority’s deterrence analysis but agree that the
    imposition of tort liability here would not raise meaningful
    deterrence concerns.
    20
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 30
                            Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    State v. Lingman, 
    91 P.2d 457
    , 466 (Utah 1939). The tenuous nature
    of the distinction has been recognized by numerous courts and
    commentators. Prosser commented on the “vague and
    impracticable” nature of the distinction between “degrees of
    negligence.” W. PAGE KEATON ET AL., PROSSER AND KEATON ON THE
    LAW OF TORTS § 34, at 210–11 (5th ed. 1984) [hereinafter PROSSER ON
    TORTS]. In his view, as in mine, “‘gross’ negligence is merely the
    same thing as ordinary negligence, ‘with the addition,’ as Baron
    Rolfe once put it, ‘of a vituperative epithet.’” Id.; see also Stanulonis
    v. Marzec, 
    649 F. Supp. 1536
    , 1543 (D. Conn. 1986) (describing the
    distinction between mere negligence, gross negligence, and
    recklessness as “the difference between ‘a fool, a damned fool, and
    a God-damned fool’”) (quoting W. PROSSER ET AL., TORTS 207 (6th
    ed. 1976)).
    ¶45 The “very real difficulty of drawing satisfactory lines of
    demarcation” thus “justifies the rejection of the distinctions in most
    situations.” PROSSER ON TORTS § 34, at 211. For these reasons the
    grossness of a party’s negligence will be a matter left to the eye of
    the factfinder. See Norman v. Utah Hotel Co., 
    206 P. 556
    , 560 (Utah
    1922) (“[T]he question [of gross negligence] is one of fact for the
    jury and not one of law for the court.”). That problem opens up the
    real possibility that the exception we establish today will swallow
    the rule we adopted in Fordham. Most allegations of negligence can
    be recast as gross negligence. All it takes is the addition of “a
    vituperative epithet.” For that reason I do not agree that the mere
    difference in degree between the two forms of negligence “matters”
    here.22 Supra ¶ 14. I see little difference as a matter of culpability.
    __________________________________________________________
    22 I do not dispute that our law has recognized this distinction
    in other areas—such as where we have disallowed liability waivers
    for gross negligence while permitting them for ordinary
    negligence. Supra ¶ 19. But the fact that we have recognized this
    distinction elsewhere hardly requires us to do so here. Admittedly,
    the general concept of assumption of risk is implicated in both
    contexts. But the question implicated by the liability waiver context
    is different from the one presented in the professional rescuer
    setting. In the first context we are deciding whether and when
    private parties are allowed to contract out of underlying duties in
    tort. In the second we are determining, in the first instance, what
    the scope of those underlying tort duties should be. The line-drawing
    problem arises in both contexts. But the fact that we have tried to
    draw the line in the first context tell us nothing about whether we
    should endorse it in the second.
    21
    IPSEN v. DIAMOND TREE EXPERTS, INC.
    Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    ¶46 Culpability, moreover, is not the controlling consideration
    in our case law. Fordham and Nixon root the duty inquiry in the
    doctrine of primary assumption of risk. The question of whether to
    endorse a duty in tort is surely a question of “policy,” as the
    majority states. Supra ¶ 9. But the policy inquiry under our case law
    is centered on the question of implied consent. And for reasons
    explained above we should conclude that smoke inhalation from
    fighting fires is an inherent part of the job—and one that Ipsen
    impliedly consented to in entering into this profession.
    ¶47 The tortfeasor’s state of mind is not controlling under
    Nixon. The majority concedes the general point but opines that the
    “conclusion is irrelevant to the professional rescuers’ rule for two
    reasons.” Supra ¶ 13 n.9. First the court tries to distinguish sports
    and firefighting in terms of what is “part of the accepted behavior”
    of these activities. Supra ¶ 13 n.9. It says that sports may involve
    reckless or even intentional contact that is within the expected
    course of the game, but “in the professional rescuers’ context, any
    grossly negligent . . . behavior is not a part of the accepted behavior
    in a well-ordered society.” Supra ¶ 13 n.9. Then the court seeks to
    draw a distinction based on who governs these activities. It asserts
    that “sports are governed by a separate set of rules than societal
    activities that may require the presence of professional rescuers,”
    and concludes that, by contrast, courts are “the only institutions
    with authority” to “protect professional rescuers from [] gross
    negligence,” and therefore can properly “evaluate the relevance
    and weight of one’s state of mind” to the duty imposed. Supra ¶ 13
    n.9.
    ¶48 I see no basis for these distinctions. They are circular. And
    the court’s holding is an effective override of our case law.
    ¶49 The scope of “accepted behavior” in the activities covered
    by our tort law is precisely the question presented for our decision.
    We have held that that question turns on whether the conduct
    giving rise to injury is “inherent” in a voluntary activity. So we can
    hold that gross negligence that causes smoke inhalation is “not a
    part of the accepted behavior” tolerated by our tort law in this
    setting. And we can claim to distinguish that from sports, where
    reckless and even intentional contact is “accepted.” But that is just
    the net effect of our holding today. It is not a basis for a decision.23
    __________________________________________________________
    23 The majority seeks to refute the assertion that its analysis on
    this point is circular, pointing to the Fordham court’s reliance on
    “broadly shared value[s] about the workings of a well-ordered
    (continued . . .)
    22
    Cite as: 
    2020 UT 30
                             Lee, A.C.J., dissenting
    ¶50 The second point is similarly problematic. There is no
    distinction in who “governs” the two activities for purposes of our
    decision in this case. Sports are not “governed” by a separate
    institution when it comes to duty in tort law. They are governed by
    the courts. And this court decided on the scope of “accepted
    behavior” in sports in Nixon—in holding that there was no duty in
    tort arising out of activity that is inherent in voluntary sports. So
    again there is no distinction to be made. “Courts . . . are the only
    institutions with authority to” govern the “societal activities that
    may require the presence of professional rescuers.” Supra ¶ 13 n.9.
    But we are also “institutions with authority to” govern sports—
    insofar as we are deciding on the kind of sporting activity that gives
    rise to tort liability.24
    ¶51 The majority’s attempts to distinguish Fordham and Nixon
    are accordingly unpersuasive. Faithful application of these
    decisions can only lead to one conclusion.
    ¶52 We should apply our precedents and affirm the decision
    dismissing Ipsen’s claims. The majority’s contrary conclusion is
    unfaithful to our decisions in Fordham and Nixon. And the opinion
    in this case will effectively unravel the holding in Fordham in light
    of the thin line between negligence and gross negligence.
    __________________________________________________________
    society” in establishing the professional rescuer’s exception. See
    supra ¶ 13 n.9 (quoting Fordham, 
    2007 UT 74
    , ¶ 8). But again, that
    was not the sole basis for our analysis in Fordham. The “broadly
    shared value[s]” that we cited in Fordham rested on principles of
    primary assumption of risk and implied consent. See supra ¶ 13 n.9.
    These policy considerations, in other words, were not freestanding;
    they were underpinned by specific legal doctrines regarding the
    imposition of duty. So my point about circularity stands. The
    majority has presented no grounds for abandoning those
    underlying doctrines in its decision today.
    24 The majority’s only response to this problem is its assertion
    that “there are other mechanisms to adjudicate one’s tortious
    behavior during a sporting event,” since the rules of the game will
    “impose penalties on individuals and teams” where rules
    violations result in injury. Supra ¶ 13 n.9. That’s fine as far as it goes.
    But the cited mechanisms don’t impose tort duties or provide a
    means of compensation for victims.
    23