State v. Houston , 2015 UT 36 ( 2015 )


Menu:
  •                    This opinion is subject to revision before
    publication in the Pacific Reporter
    
    2015 UT 36
    IN THE
    SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF UTAH
    STATE OF UTAH,
    Appellee,
    v.
    ROBERT CAMERON HOUSTON,
    Appellant.
    No. 20080625
    Filed February 24, 2015
    Second District, Farmington
    The Honorable Glen R. Dawson
    No. 0601700273
    Attorneys:
    Sean D. Reyes, Att‘y Gen., Christopher D. Ballard,
    Asst. Att‘y Gen., Salt Lake City, for appellee
    John P. Pace, Salt Lake City, for appellant
    JUSTICE NEHRING authored the opinion of the Court, in which
    JUSTICE PARRISH joined, CHIEF JUSTICE DURRANT joined except as to
    section II.F.2, and JUSTICE DURHAM joined in Part I.
    ASSOCIATE CHIEF JUSTICE LEE authored a concurring opinion.
    JUSTICE DURHAM authored a dissenting opinion, in which
    CHIEF JUSTICE DURRANT concurred in Part I.
    JUSTICE NEHRING, opinion of the Court:1
    INTRODUCTION
    ¶ 1 Robert Cameron Houston was seventeen and a half
    years old when he murdered R.E., a staff member of the
    1 Justice Nehring took part in this decision and authored this
    opinion prior to his retirement.
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    residential treatment center for youth where Mr. Houston was
    temporarily residing. The State charged Mr. Houston with
    aggravated murder, aggravated sexual assault, and rape.
    Mr. Houston pleaded guilty to aggravated murder, and the State
    agreed to drop the other charges.
    ¶ 2 The parties agreed to a sentencing hearing where a jury
    would determine whether Mr. Houston would be sentenced to life
    in prison without the possibility of parole or an indeterminate
    term of twenty years to life. Following the sentencing hearing,
    eleven of the twelve jurors voted to sentence Mr. Houston to life
    imprisonment without the possibility of parole.
    ¶ 3 On appeal Mr. Houston brings numerous constitutional
    challenges to his sentence. He also contends that his counsel
    rendered ineffective assistance of counsel during the sentencing
    proceeding in violation of the Sixth Amendment to the United
    States Constitution. After a careful review of the record, we
    conclude that Mr. Houston‘s sentence is constitutional, and his
    counsel was not ineffective. We therefore affirm the jury‘s
    sentence.
    BACKGROUND
    ¶ 4 Mr. Houston had a very difficult childhood, and he
    became an early juvenile offender and a troubled young adult.
    ¶ 5 Mr. Houston was born with a deformed ear, which left
    him almost completely deaf on one side and made it difficult for
    him to learn to talk. As a child, he struggled with this physical
    deformity and was also ridiculed by his peers for being
    overweight. Mr. Houston‘s parents fought often and eventually
    divorced, and his father was physically and verbally abusive.
    When his father left the home, Mr. Houston struggled emotionally
    over the separation. At age eight, Mr. Houston attempted suicide
    and was diagnosed with major depressive disorder. When he was
    twelve, he was sexually abused by his brother‘s friend for several
    months.
    ¶ 6 Mr. Houston committed several violent sexual offenses
    as a young teenager, which led to his placement in a residential
    treatment program for juvenile sex offenders. In 2003, at age
    fourteen, Mr. Houston attempted to rape his teenage stepsister at
    knifepoint. He was charged with aggravated sexual assault.
    Mr. Houston entered a guilty plea, though the record does not
    2
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           Opinion of the Court
    specify to what charge he pleaded. In February 2004, at age
    fifteen, Mr. Houston attempted to rape his aunt, also at knifepoint.
    Mr. Houston was charged with aggravated sexual assault and
    pleaded guilty, although the record again does not specify to what
    charge Mr. Houston pleaded. As a result of these violent sexual
    assaults, Mr. Houston was placed with Youth Health Associates
    (YHA), a residential treatment facility for juvenile sex offenders
    located in Clearfield, Utah.
    ¶ 7 The State also presented evidence that two months after
    Mr. Houston‘s arrival at YHA he allegedly attempted to sexually
    assault a female staff member. The staff worker fought back and
    was able to gain control. After the incident, Mr. Houston
    allegedly explained to other staff workers that he wanted to hurt
    and sexually assault her. Mr. Houston did not have a weapon
    during that incident.
    ¶ 8 On February 15, 2006, when Mr. Houston was seventeen
    years old, he committed the murder that led to this appeal. At
    that time, Mr. Houston resided at an independent living home
    associated with YHA.         It was snowing that night, and
    Mr. Houston did not want to walk the four blocks home from
    YHA to the independent living home. He asked R.E., a female
    staff worker, for a ride. Although it was against YHA‘s policy to
    give a ride in a personal vehicle to a resident, R.E. was
    sympathetic and did not want Mr. Houston to have to walk home
    in the bad weather.
    ¶ 9 When they arrived at the independent living home, R.E.
    followed Mr. Houston inside to sign the log book. As she turned
    to leave, Mr. Houston grabbed her from behind, covered her
    mouth with his hand, and held a knife to her throat. Mr. Houston
    then forced R.E. into his bedroom and ordered her to remove her
    clothing. R.E. told Mr. Houston that she was a virgin and that she
    did not want to have sexual intercourse. Mr. Houston responded
    angrily, and raped her. R.E. screamed and begged him to stop.
    Mr. Houston responded by pressing a knife to her throat. When
    R.E. continued to scream, Mr. Houston stabbed her in the side of
    the neck and sliced her throat. He then stabbed her repeatedly in
    the chest, side, and back. When R.E. continued to struggle,
    Mr. Houston attempted to kill her by snapping her neck. R.E.
    continued to scream, and Mr. Houston became scared and fled.
    3
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    ¶ 10 Mr. Houston climbed into R.E.‘s car and sped off. He
    drove into a house, which he later explained was an attempt to
    kill himself. Mr. Houston was arrested and taken to the hospital.
    He was interviewed by Detective Mike Valencia shortly after
    arrival. Mr. Houston confessed to attempting to kill R.E. and
    described in detail to the detective how he had tried to rip out
    R.E.‘s trachea to stop her from screaming. The detective noted
    that Mr. Houston was unemotional as he described the details of
    the crime.
    ¶ 11 Mr. Houston was charged with aggravated murder,
    aggravated sexual assault, and rape. In exchange for the State‘s
    promise to drop the other charges, Mr. Houston pleaded guilty to
    aggravated murder. The parties agreed that the sentencing
    hearing would be held before a jury. Following a five-day
    hearing, eleven of the twelve jurors voted to sentence
    Mr. Houston to life imprisonment without the possibility of
    parole (LWOP). After he was sentenced, Mr. Houston obtained
    new appointed counsel and subsequently filed a timely appeal to
    challenge his sentence. We stayed the case in anticipation of the
    ruling in a United States Supreme Court case, Miller v. Alabama,2
    and the parties provided supplemental briefing concerning the
    effect of Miller on Mr. Houston‘s case.
    ¶ 12 We have jurisdiction under Utah Code section 78A-3-
    102(3)(i).
    STANDARD OF REVIEW
    ¶ 13 We begin our discussion of the standard of review by
    noting that Mr. Houston did not preserve any of the issues
    presented on appeal. ―As a general rule, claims not raised before
    the trial court may not be raised on appeal‖3 unless a plain error
    occurred,4 exceptional circumstances warrant our review,5 or the
    defendant‘s attorney rendered ineffective assistance of counsel.6
    2   
    132 S. Ct. 2455
    (2012).
    3   State v. Holgate, 
    2000 UT 74
    , ¶ 11, 
    10 P.3d 346
    .
    4  
    Id. ¶¶ 11,
    13 (noting that to establish plain error, the
    defendant has the burden to show that ―(i) [a]n error exists; (ii) the
    error should have been obvious to the trial court; and (iii) the
    error is harmful, i.e., absent the error, there is a reasonable
    (con‘t.)
    4
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                             Opinion of the Court
    ¶ 14 The parties disagree about the standard of review that
    should apply to Mr. Houston‘s claims. Mr. Houston admits that
    none of his claims are preserved, and thus argues under both
    plain error and ineffective assistance of counsel doctrines.
    However, Mr. Houston also argues for two alternative,
    heightened standards of review. First, Mr. Houston contends that
    he was charged with a ―capital‖ offense, and therefore this court
    should apply a ―manifest prejudice‖ standard of review to each of
    his claims. Second, Mr. Houston argues that his sentence is
    unconstitutional and therefore he can challenge it on appeal as an
    ―illegal‖ sentence under Utah Rule of Criminal Procedure 22(e),
    and is thereby excused from the obligation to preserve issues for
    appeal. In support of his rule 22(e) argument, Mr. Houston cites
    State v. Candedo, in which this court interpreted rule 22(e) to
    permit review of certain unpreserved constitutional challenges.7
    ¶ 15 The State disagrees with Mr. Houston. First, the State
    contends that ―capital‖ review does not apply here because this is
    not a ―capital‖ case.8 According to the State, a ―capital‖ case is
    one where the death penalty is sought or imposed; because of his
    status as a juvenile, Mr. Houston was not, and could not have
    been, sentenced to death, and as such, ―capital‖ appellate review
    is not available. Second, the State argues that even if this court
    can reach Mr. Houston‘s unpreserved claims under rule 22(e),
    State v. Candedo was wrongly decided and should be overruled.
    In support of its effort to undo Candedo, the State argues that the
    opinion lacks sufficient analysis and citation to authority, creates
    an unjustifiable disparity between this court‘s treatment of
    unpreserved constitutional challenges to convictions and
    likelihood of a more favorable outcome‖ (alteration in original)
    (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    5   
    Id. ¶ 11.
       6   State v. Low, 
    2008 UT 58
    , ¶ 19, 
    192 P.3d 867
    .
    7 
    2010 UT 32
    , ¶ 13, 
    232 P.3d 1008
    (―[I]f an offender‘s sentence is
    unconstitutional, the sentence is not authorized by the ‗judgment
    of conviction,‘ and is therefore illegal.‖).
    8 The State also argues that, in any event, the ―manifest and
    prejudicial error standard is equivalent to plain error review.‖
    5
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    unpreserved constitutional challenges to sentences, and is
    inconsistent with the rule announced in State v. Yazzie.9
    ¶ 16 As we describe in greater detail below, we hold that each
    of Mr. Houston‘s constitutional challenges falls within the narrow
    scope of rule 22(e)‘s exception to the preservation of claims. We
    therefore decline the State‘s request to overrule our precedent in
    State v. Candedo. Under rule 22(e), we treat Mr. Houston‘s claims
    as if they had been preserved, reviewing conclusions of law for
    correctness and granting no deference to the district court.10
    Because rule 22(e) provides a higher standard than ―manifest
    prejudice‖ review, we decline to address Mr. Houston‘s
    alternative argument.
    ¶ 17 A claim of ineffective assistance of counsel is also an
    exception to our preservation doctrine.11          For ―ineffective
    assistance of counsel claims, we review a lower court's purely
    factual findings for clear error, but [we] review the application of
    the law to the facts for correctness.‖12
    ANALYSIS
    I. MR. HOUSTON PROPERLY BROUGHT FACIAL
    CONSTITUTIONAL CHALLENGES TO HIS SENTENCE
    UNDER UTAH RULE OF CRIMINAL PROCEDURE 22(e)
    ¶ 18 Utah Rule of Criminal Procedure 22(e) provides that
    ―[t]he court may correct an illegal sentence, or a sentence imposed
    in an illegal manner, at any time.‖ We hold that the rule
    encompasses facial constitutional challenges to the sentence that
    do not implicate a fact-intensive analysis. We also conclude that
    each of Mr. Houston‘s constitutional challenges to his sentence
    meets these criteria, and therefore his claims are properly brought
    under rule 22(e).
    ¶ 19 Under our traditional preservation doctrine, ―generally
    an appellant must properly preserve an issue in the district court
    9   
    2009 UT 14
    , ¶ 13, 
    203 P.3d 984
    .
    10   See State v. Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 13, 
    274 P.3d 919
    .
    11   Low, 
    2008 UT 58
    , ¶ 19.
    12 Archuleta v. Galetka, 
    2011 UT 73
    , ¶ 25, 
    267 P.3d 232
    (alteration
    in original) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    6
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                              Opinion of the Court
    before it will be reviewed on appeal.‖13 The issue must have been
    ―presented to the district court in such a way that the court has an
    opportunity to rule on [it].‖14 These preservation rules exist both
    to serve judicial economy and to prevent a defendant from failing
    to object to an issue in the hopes of reversal of a conviction on
    appeal.15 However, ―[o]ur preservation requirement is self-
    imposed and . . . . [c]onsequently, we exercise wide discretion
    when deciding whether to entertain or reject matters that are first
    raised on appeal.‖16 We have therefore recognized limited
    exceptions to the rule, including when the issue arises under
    exceptional circumstances or where a plain error has occurred.17
    ¶ 20 Rule 22(e) operates as another limited exception to the
    preservation doctrine.18 In State v. Candedo, we explained that the
    rule ―allows an appellate court to vacate [an] illegal sentence‖
    even if the legality of the sentence was never raised in the
    proceedings below.19 We stated that our preservation rules do not
    apply in the context of a rule 22(e) challenge ―because an illegal
    sentence is void and, like issues of jurisdiction [may be raised] at
    any time.‖20
    13 O’Dea v. Olea, 
    2009 UT 46
    , ¶ 15, 
    217 P.3d 704
    ; accord Patterson
    v. Patterson, 
    2011 UT 68
    , ¶ 12, 
    266 P.3d 828
    .
    14Patterson, 
    2011 UT 68
    , ¶ 12 (alteration in original) (internal
    quotation marks omitted).
    15 State v. Holgate, 
    2000 UT 74
    , ¶ 11, 
    10 P.3d 346
    ; see also State v.
    Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 19, 
    274 P.3d 919
    .
    16   Patterson, 
    2011 UT 68
    , ¶ 13.
    17   Holgate, 
    2000 UT 74
    , ¶¶ 11–13.
    18 Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 20; State v. Brooks, 
    908 P.2d 856
    , 860
    (Utah 1995) (―[R]ule 22(e) permits the court of appeals to consider
    the legality of a sentence even if the issue is raised for the first
    time on appeal.‖).
    19 
    2010 UT 32
    , ¶ 9, 
    232 P.3d 1008
    (internal quotation marks
    omitted).
    20   
    Id. (alteration in
    original) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    7
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    ¶ 21 While it is clear that the preservation rule does not apply
    to a defendant‘s challenge to an illegal sentence, we have had few
    occasions to discuss what constitutes an ―illegal sentence.‖ In
    State v. Yazzie, we adopted a definition of ―illegal sentence‖ from
    the United States Court of Appeals for the Tenth Circuit:
    [An illegal sentence is] one which is ambiguous with
    respect to the time and manner in which it is to be
    served, is internally contradictory, omits a term
    required to be imposed by statute, is uncertain as to
    the substance of the sentence, or is a sentence which
    the judgment of conviction did not authorize.21
    ¶ 22 In Candedo, we elaborated on this definition. We
    concluded that ―if an offender‘s sentence is unconstitutional, the
    sentence is not authorized by the ‗judgment of conviction,‘ and is
    therefore illegal.‖22 In that case, the district court placed
    Francisco Candedo on nine years‘ probation after he pleaded
    guilty to three felonies arising from his involvement in a
    fraudulent investment scheme.23 Rather than object to the length
    of his probation at sentencing, Mr. Candedo challenged on direct
    appeal the legality of the duration of his probation sentence
    under rule 22(e), arguing that his sentence violated his
    21 
    2009 UT 14
    , ¶ 13, 
    203 P.3d 984
    (alteration in original)
    (quoting United States v. Dougherty, 
    106 F.3d 1514
    , 1515 (10th Cir.
    1997)).
    22  
    2010 UT 32
    , ¶ 13. We disagree with the State that this
    definition is inconsistent with Yazzie, or that it is otherwise
    unsupported by legal authority. We squarely rejected these
    arguments in Candedo. See 
    id. ¶¶ 12–14.
    We also note that our
    holding in Candedo—that an illegal sentence encompasses an
    unconstitutional sentence—is consistent with the Tenth Circuit‘s
    definition and application of this term. See United States v. Groves,
    
    369 F.3d 1178
    , 1182 (10th Cir. 2004) (―Because the defendant
    reserved the right to appeal an ‗illegal sentence,‘ and because an
    unconstitutional sentence is ‗illegal,‘ we hold that the defendant is
    entitled to challenge his sentence . . . .‖); United States v. Lyman,
    261 F. App‘x 98, 100 (10th Cir. 2008) (noting that an
    unconstitutional sentence is an example of an illegal sentence).
    23   
    2010 UT 32
    , ¶ 1.
    8
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                                Opinion of the Court
    substantive due process rights under the United States
    Constitution.24 The court of appeals affirmed Mr. Candedo‘s
    sentence without reaching the merits of his constitutional claim.25
    On certiorari review, we determined that the court of appeals
    erred when it failed to reach Mr. Candedo‘s constitutional
    challenge.26 We concluded that ―[b]ecause an illegal sentence
    under rule 22(e) includes constitutional violations,‖ a defendant
    may raise arguments concerning the constitutionality of the
    sentence, even if unpreserved.27
    ¶ 23 We again considered the scope of rule 22(e) in State v.
    Prion, a case in which the defendant raised statutory and double
    jeopardy challenges to his sentence.28 We recognized that the
    Candedo ―formulation, if broadly construed, raises the prospect of
    abuse.‖29 We cautioned that such abuse could arise ―if rule 22(e)
    were construed broadly to sanction a fact-intensive challenge to
    the legality of a sentencing proceeding asserted long after the time
    for raising it in the initial trial or direct appeal.‖30 In considering
    the scope of the rule, we also explained that our rule 22(e) derived
    from a former Federal Rule of Criminal Procedure that authorized
    a court to correct illegal sentences.31 We recognized that federal
    courts traditionally limited challenges under the federal rule to
    attack sentences that exceeded the statutory maximum, violated
    double jeopardy, or were facially ambiguous or internally
    inconsistent.32 Some circuits appear to have recognized a broader
    24   
    Id. 25 Id.
       26   
    Id. ¶ 2.
       27 
    Id. ¶ 11.
    We nonetheless affirmed Mr. Candedo‘s sentence
    because we determined that it did not violate due process. 
    Id. ¶ 25.
       28   
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 10.
    29   
    Id. ¶ 20
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    30   
    Id. 31Id. ¶
    22; see FED. R. CRIM. P. 35(a) (1984). The federal rule
    was repealed in 1987. See Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 22 n.8.
    32   Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 22 (citing United States v. Pavlico, 961
    (con‘t.)
    9
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    application of the federal rule, such as when the sentence is
    generally ―in violation of the Constitution,‖33 is based on
    ―misinformation of a constitutional magnitude,‖34 or even when
    the sentence violates another federal rule.35
    ¶ 24 In Prion, we held that the defendant‘s statutory and
    double jeopardy challenges properly fell within the ambit of rule
    22(e).36 Such challenges attacked ―facial defects‖ that ―could
    F.2d 440, 443 (4th Cir. 1992), and Hill v. United States, 
    368 U.S. 424
    ,
    430 (1962)); see also State v. Higginbotham, 
    917 P.2d 545
    , 551 (Utah
    1996) (remanding to the trial court under rule 22(e) to correct a
    sentence enhancement made in violation of the statute).
    33 United States v. Hovsepian, 
    307 F.3d 922
    , 927–28 (9th Cir.
    2002); see also 
    Hill, 368 U.S. at 430
    (finding no illegal sentence
    under rule 35(a) when the sentence was not ―legally or
    constitutionally invalid in any other respect‖).
    34 United States v. Plain, 
    856 F.2d 913
    , 916 (7th Cir. 1988)
    (quoting United States v. Tucker, 
    404 U.S. 443
    , 447 (1972)
    (considering a rule 35 motion when a sentencing authority bases
    the sentencing decision on erroneous factual information)).
    35 Cook v. United States, 
    171 F.2d 567
    , 569 (1st Cir. 1948)
    (vacating a sentence that violated Federal Rule of Criminal
    Procedure 43 because the defendant was not present before the
    court when his sentence was increased).
    36  
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶¶ 23–24. The concurrence misreads our
    holding in Prion as limiting rule 22(e) challenges to only those
    permitted under the antecedent federal rule. Infra ¶¶ 114–31. But
    we nowhere stated that we were adopting the federal limitation.
    In fact, reading Prion to adopt such a limitation would require us
    to have overruled our earlier decisions in Candedo, 
    2010 UT 32
    ,
    and State v. Telford, 
    2002 UT 51
    , 
    48 P.3d 228
    (per curiam). In
    Candedo, we expressly found that the defendant‘s substantive due
    process claim fell within the scope of the rule:
    We therefore hold that the court of appeals erred
    in failing to reach the merits of Candedo‘s
    substantive due process challenge because the
    definition of illegal sentence under rule 22(e) is
    sufficiently broad to include constitutional
    violations that threaten the validity of the
    (con‘t.)
    10
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                             Opinion of the Court
    easily be corrected without the need for factual development in
    the original trial court.‖37 We therefore reviewed the defendant‘s
    claims on the merits, ultimately concluding that his sentence
    violated double jeopardy.38
    ¶ 25 Mr. Houston now brings a host of constitutional claims
    that we have not previously addressed under rule 22(e). Today,
    we draw on our previous decisions to articulate the standard for a
    criminal defendant who brings an unpreserved claim under rule
    22(e) that his or her sentence is illegal, and we reiterate the
    concern expressed in earlier cases that ―rule 22(e) claims must be
    narrowly circumscribed to prevent abuse.‖39
    ¶ 26 We therefore hold that under rule 22(e), a defendant
    may bring constitutional challenges that attack the sentence itself
    and not the underlying conviction,40 and which do so as a facial
    challenge rather than an as-applied inquiry.41 This standard
    sentence. This holding allows us to reach the
    merits of Candedo‘s claim . . . .
    
    2010 UT 32
    , ¶ 14. And in Telford, ―[a]lthough we rejected Telford‘s
    separation of powers and Eighth Amendment challenges to his
    sentence, we reached and considered the merits of those challenges
    under rule 22(e).‖ 
    Id. ¶ 11
    (citing Telford, 
    2002 UT 51
    , ¶¶ 3–4)
    (emphasis added). We would not denigrate our holdings in those
    cases as ―relatively unimportant.‖ Infra ¶ 121 n.1.
    37   Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 22.
    38   
    Id. ¶ 63.
       39   Candedo, 
    2010 UT 32
    , ¶ 9 (quoting Telford, 
    2002 UT 51
    , ¶ 5).
    40 See 
    Brooks, 908 P.2d at 859
    (―[A]n appellate court may not
    review the legality of a sentence under rule 22(e) when the
    substance of the appeal is . . . a challenge, not to the sentence itself,
    but to the underlying conviction.‖).
    41 The State argues that such a rule creates an unjustifiable
    disparity between unpreserved challenges to convictions and to
    sentences. To the extent that such a dichotomy exists, it is
    inherent in the rule itself, which allows illegal sentences to be
    challenged at any time. Moreover, our decision today limits that
    disparity by restricting constitutional challenges under the rule to
    only facial attacks.
    11
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    comports with previous rule 22(e) decisions of this court. For
    example, in State v. Telford, we permitted the defendant to bring
    some unpreserved constitutional challenges to his sentence under
    rule 22(e) while ruling that other constitutional claims did not
    properly fall within the scope of rule 22(e) review.42 We
    authorized the defendant‘s challenge to the indeterminate
    sentencing scheme under the separation of powers clause of the
    Utah Constitution.43 We also allowed claims under the cruel and
    unusual punishments clauses of the Utah and United States
    Constitutions, but only to the extent that the defendant argued for
    ―a per se violation.‖44 In contrast, we concluded that to the extent
    that the defendant contested the constitutionality ―as applied to his
    particular case, he impermissibly attempt[ed] to employ rule 22(e)
    to attack his underlying conviction.‖45 Similarly, we prohibited
    review of claims brought under the Sixth Amendment of the
    United Sates Constitution and article I, section 12 of the Utah
    Constitution because those clauses did not relate to sentencing.46
    ¶ 27 Limiting constitutional challenges to facial attacks serves
    judicial economy. As we recognized in Brooks, ―[w]hen the
    pertinent facts are undisputed and a purely legal question with
    respect to which the trial court has no discretion remains to be
    decided, nothing is to be gained by remanding the case to the trial
    court.‖47 The concurrence argues that our standard creates an
    unworkable rule because even facial challenges can be fact-
    42   
    2002 UT 51
    , ¶¶ 2–5.
    43   
    Id. ¶ 3.
       44 
    Id. ¶ 4;
    see Candedo, 
    2010 UT 32
    , ¶ 11 (recognizing that in
    Telford we reviewed separation of powers and cruel and unusual
    punishment challenges on their merits).
    45   Telford, 
    2002 UT 51
    , ¶ 7 (emphasis added).
    46Id. ¶ 6. We ultimately concluded that Mr. Telford‘s sentence
    did not amount to a constitutional violation. 
    Id. ¶¶ 3–4.
       
    47 908 P.2d at 860
    ; see also Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 20 (warning
    against permitting rule 22(e) to ―sanction a fact-intensive
    challenge‖); 
    id. ¶ 22
    (explaining that facial defects can easily be
    corrected by an appellate court without the need to remand for
    factual development).
    12
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                               Opinion of the Court
    intensive.48 But this argument also misses the mark. In this
    context, a fact-intensive analysis is one in which ―the pertinent
    legal facts‖ are disputed or unclear. But where there is a facial
    constitutional attack, the court need not delve into the record or
    make findings of fact. Instead, the court is tasked with resolving a
    legal issue. But that does not mean the analysis will be easy or
    devoid of any reference to facts. As the opinions in the present
    case demonstrate, analysis of a purely legal question is often
    difficult and warrants rigorous debate. The rule we articulate
    here is not untenable just because it requires hard work by the
    court.
    ¶ 28 In the end, finality of judgment and preservation of
    claims are important, but so too is a criminal defendant‘s right to
    endure only those sentences that can be constitutionally imposed.
    Because Mr. Houston facially attacks the constitutionality of the
    statute that authorized his sentence, we hold that he has properly
    challenged it as an ―illegal sentence‖ under Utah Rule of Criminal
    Procedure 22(e).49 We next turn to the merits of Mr. Houston‘s
    claims. For analytical clarity, we separate his claims into two
    categories. First, we address his facial constitutional claims, and
    we analyze the sentence for correctness under rule 22(e)‘s
    exception to preservation. Next, we address Mr. Houston‘s claims
    brought under the framework of ineffective assistance of counsel.
    We ultimately conclude that all of Mr. Houston‘s claims fail and
    therefore affirm his sentence of life without the possibility of
    parole.
    II. MR. HOUSTON‘S SENTENCE OF LIFE WITHOUT
    PAROLE DOES NOT VIOLATE THE UTAH OR
    THE UNITED STATES CONSTITUTION
    ¶ 29 We begin by addressing Mr. Houston‘s six constitutional
    challenges to his sentence. Mr. Houston argues that his sentence:
    (A) is unconstitutional under the United States Supreme Court
    case Apprendi v. New Jersey,50 (B) is unconstitutional because the
    48   Infra ¶¶ 128–29.
    49In light of this limiting construction, we decline the State‘s
    request for us to overrule our holding in Candedo, 
    2010 UT 32
    .
    50   
    530 U.S. 466
    (2000).
    13
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    sentencing statute does not contain a ―beyond a reasonable
    doubt‖ standard of proof, (C) violates the Utah uniform operation
    of laws clause and the United States Equal Protection Clause,
    (D) violates the due process clauses of the Utah and United States
    Constitutions, (E) violates the unnecessary rigor clause of the
    Utah Constitution, and (F) violates the cruel and unusual
    punishments clauses of the Utah and United States Constitutions.
    We take up each of these issues in turn.
    A. Mr. Houston’s Sentence Is not Unconstitutional
    Under Apprendi v. New Jersey
    ¶ 30 Mr. Houston first argues that Apprendi v. New Jersey51
    renders the sentencing statute unconstitutional.52 This claim is
    grounded in the Fifth and Sixth Amendments to the United States
    Constitution.    According to Mr. Houston, his sentence is
    unconstitutional because Apprendi mandates that ―any fact that
    increases the penalty for a crime beyond the prescribed statutory
    maximum must be submitted to a jury and proved beyond a
    reasonable doubt.‖
    ¶ 31 In Apprendi, the New Jersey statutory scheme permitted
    a judge to impose a sentence beyond the statutory maximum if
    the judge determined, by a preponderance of the evidence, that
    the defendant committed a hate crime.53 The United States
    Supreme Court held that this sentencing scheme was
    unconstitutional because ―any fact that increases the penalty for a
    crime beyond the prescribed statutory maximum must be submitted to
    a jury, and proved beyond a reasonable doubt.‖54
    51   
    Id. 52 The
    concurrence claims that this argument is not a facial
    challenge. Infra ¶ 128. But Mr. Houston argues that the
    sentencing statute violates Apprendi‘s constitutional protections by
    allowing the sentencer to impose LWOP, rather than the
    presumptive twenty year sentence, if the sentencer deems it
    appropriate. We conclude that this is a challenge on the face of
    the statute and not to Mr. Houston‘s particular circumstances.
    
    53 530 U.S. at 468
    –69.
    54   
    Id. at 490
    (emphasis added).
    14
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                             Opinion of the Court
    ¶ 32 Unlike in Apprendi, however, the sentencing statute
    under which Mr. Houston was sentenced does not require the
    judge to make factual findings that increase an offender‘s
    sentence. By pleading guilty to aggravated murder, Mr. Houston
    admitted all the facts relevant to the offense and became subject to
    any sentence authorized under Utah law.              Under Utah‘s
    sentencing statute, a juvenile defendant guilty of aggravated
    murder can be sentenced to either life with the possibility of
    parole or LWOP.55 There were no factual findings to be made by
    a jury, only a determination that LWOP would or would not be
    appropriate. Because the sentencing statute did not permit the
    jury to impose a sentence ―beyond the prescribed statutory
    maximum,‖ the Apprendi rule did not apply, and there is no
    violation.
    B. The Sentencing Statute Is not Constitutionally Defective
    for Failing to Include a ―Beyond a Reasonable Doubt‖ Standard
    ¶ 33 Mr. Houston next argues that the sentencing statute is
    invalid and unconstitutional because it does not articulate a
    standard of proof for sentencing.56 Relying on this court‘s
    decision in State v. Wood,57 Mr. Houston contends that Utah‘s
    sentencing scheme requires that a jury find ―beyond a reasonable
    doubt‖ that an LWOP sentence is justified and appropriate. We
    disagree.
    ¶ 34 We begin by examining the language of the sentencing
    statute at issue. Utah Code section 76-3-207 provides that ―the
    jury shall . . . determine whether the penalty of life in prison
    without parole shall be imposed . . . . The penalty of life in prison
    without parole shall only be imposed if the jury determines that
    the sentence of life in prison without parole is appropriate.‖58
    55See UTAH CODE § 76-3-207(5)(c) (2008). This statute was
    amended in 2010, but we cite to the version in effect at the time
    Mr. Houston was sentenced.
    56   See 
    id. 57 648
    P.2d 71 (Utah 1982).
    58   UTAH CODE § 76-3-207(5)(c) (2008).
    15
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    ¶ 35 In Wood, we interpreted an earlier version of this statute
    and held that, in order to impose a death sentence under this
    section, the sentencing authority must find that (1) the
    aggravating circumstances outweigh the mitigating circumstances
    beyond a reasonable doubt and (2) the sentence is justified and
    appropriate in the circumstances beyond a reasonable doubt.59
    Mr. Houston asks us to extend the Wood ―beyond a reasonable
    doubt‖ standard to LWOP sentences. We decline to do so.
    ¶ 36 We begin by noting that, unlike Mr. Houston‘s case,
    Wood was a death penalty case, and our holding in Wood was
    premised on the unique nature of a proceeding in which the
    defendant‘s life is at stake. We explained:
    We reject the proposition that the death penalty may
    be imposed when there is substantial doubt whether
    it should be. . . . ―Death[,] in its finality, differs from
    life imprisonment more than a hundred-year prison
    term differs from one of only a year or two. Because
    of that [qualitative] difference, there is a
    corresponding difference in the need for reliability
    in the determination that death is the appropriate
    punishment in a specific case.‖60
    Throughout the Wood opinion, we emphasized the ―irrevocable‖
    nature of a death sentence, and the corresponding degree of
    conviction that a judge or jury must have to impose it.
    ¶ 37 In State v. Bell, we returned to our holding in Wood in the
    context of a different sentencing statute.61 In Bell, the defendant
    argued that Utah‘s sentencing scheme for aggravated sexual
    assault was unconstitutional because it did not assign a burden of
    proof with respect to aggravating and mitigating circumstances in
    determining which of the mandatory presumptions should be
    imposed.62 We held that the burden of proof rule articulated in
    
    59 648 P.2d at 83
    .
    60 
    Id. at 80–81
    (quoting Woodson v. North Carolina, 
    428 U.S. 280
    ,
    305 (1976) (plurality opinion)).
    61   
    754 P.2d 55
    , 59 (Utah 1988).
    62   
    Id. at 57.
    16
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                              Opinion of the Court
    Wood does not apply when the jury is not considering death as a
    possible sentence.63 We explained that ―the choice of death, being
    unique, justifies requiring the most persuasive reasons and a high
    degree of subjective certainty. However, those reasons do not
    have great force in choosing one of three possible sentences, none
    of which has the finality of death.‖64
    ¶ 38 Because a death sentence is uniquely irrevocable and the
    most severe of all sentences, we have an interest in ensuring that
    no reasonable doubt remains before we authorize the taking of a
    human life. But, as we stated in Bell, outside this context, there
    are no ―clear considerations of fairness that militate in favor of a
    particular standard, except to the extent that one may quarrel with
    the wisdom of the statute—which is beyond our prerogative.‖65
    ¶ 39 Here, our legislature has determined that a jury may
    sentence a defendant to life without parole if it determines that
    the State has satisfied its burden to demonstrate that this is the
    ―appropriate‖ sentence to impose.66 Mr. Houston has not
    demonstrated that we are constitutionally required to interfere
    with the legislature‘s authority and write a ―beyond a reasonable
    doubt‖ standard into the sentencing statute.
    C. The Sentencing Statute Does not Violate the Equal Protection
    Clause or the Uniform Operation of Laws Clause
    ¶ 40 Mr. Houston next argues that the sentencing statute
    violates the uniform operation of laws clause of the Utah
    Constitution and the Equal Protection Clause of the United States
    Constitution because the statute ―provides no guidance to jurors
    in determining which sentence to impose.‖ This, he contends,
    creates a substantial probability of arbitrary sentencing and
    disproportionate penalties.
    ¶ 41 Because we have held that Utah‘s uniform operation of
    laws clause ―is at least as rigorous as the federal guarantee,‖67 we
    63   
    Id. at 59
    (distinguishing Wood).
    64   
    Id. 65 Id.
       66   See UTAH CODE § 76-3-207(5)(c) (2008).
    67   State v. Drej, 
    2010 UT 35
    , ¶ 33 n.5, 
    233 P.3d 476
    ; see also ABCO
    (con‘t.)
    17
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    first analyze Mr. Houston‘s claims under the Utah Constitution. If
    we determine that the statute survives scrutiny under Utah‘s
    uniform operation of laws provision, then we must conclude that
    it is constitutional under the United States Constitution‘s Equal
    Protection Clause as well.68
    ¶ 42 Mr. Houston contends that two juvenile defendants
    could commit aggravated murder, and, due to the lack of
    guidance in the statute, a jury could arbitrarily sentence one of the
    juvenile offenders to life with parole and sentence the other to life
    without parole. Mr. Houston argues that by failing to narrow in a
    principled way those who may receive life without parole, the
    statute disparately treats similarly situated offenders without a
    rational basis for the disparate treatment. We disagree.
    ¶ 43 The uniform operation of laws provision of our
    Constitution requires us to address three questions: (1) ―what, if
    any, classification is created under the statute,‖ (2) ―whether the
    classification imposes on similarly situated persons disparate
    treatment,‖ and (3) whether ―the legislature had any reasonable
    objective that warrants the disparity.‖69
    ¶ 44 Examining Utah‘s statute in light of these criteria, we
    conclude that it does not violate the uniform operation of laws
    clause because it creates no impermissible classifications and it
    treats all similarly situated defendants the same.
    ¶ 45 We begin by examining the plain language of the
    challenged sentencing statute ―to determine what classification[, if
    any,] is created by [the] legislative enactment.‖70 At the time of
    Mr. Houston‘s sentencing, the sentencing statute provided:
    If the jury is unable to reach a unanimous
    decision imposing the sentence of death, the jury
    Enters. v. Utah State Tax Comm’n, 
    2009 UT 36
    , ¶ 14, 
    211 P.3d 382
    (concluding that uniform operation of laws and Equal Protection
    claims need only be analyzed under the more rigorous Utah
    provision).
    68   Drej, 
    2010 UT 35
    , ¶ 33 n.5.
    69   
    Id. ¶ 34
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    70   
    Id. ¶ 35.
    18
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                             Opinion of the Court
    shall then determine whether the penalty of life in
    prison without parole shall be imposed . . . . The
    penalty of life in prison without parole shall only
    be imposed if the jury determines that the
    sentence of life in prison without parole is
    appropriate.71
    This statute classifies defendants into two categories—those
    eligible for a death sentence and those ineligible for a death
    sentence. And under the language of this statute, all defendants
    who are ineligible for a sentence of death are similarly situated
    and are treated equally—they are subject to a jury‘s determination
    that either a sentence of life with parole or a sentence of life
    without the possibility of parole is the more appropriate sentence
    based on the jury‘s evaluation of a particular case. Although it is
    true that two defendants who commit aggravated murder may
    receive different sentences from a jury, this is either because the
    defendants were not similarly situated (for example, one
    defendant committed a much more heinous crime) or the jury in
    the course of its deliberations finds it more ―appropriate‖ to
    sentence one defendant to a more lenient or more severe penalty.
    ¶ 46 We conclude that the sentencing statute treats all
    similarly situated defendants the same and it does not contain any
    impermissible classifications. It subjects all defendants guilty of
    aggravated murder to a jury‘s determination of what sentence is
    most ―appropriate‖ given the particular circumstances of each
    case. Mr. Houston‘s argument accordingly fails.
    D. The Statute Is not Unconstitutionally Vague Under
    the Due Process Clause of the Utah or the
    United States Constitutions
    ¶ 47 Mr. Houston also argues that the sentencing statute is
    unconstitutionally vague in violation of due process under the
    federal and state constitutions because it lacks clear standards to
    guide the jury in sentencing a defendant.               Specifically,
    Mr. Houston claims that the sentencing statute only advises the
    jury to impose an LWOP sentence if ―appropriate,‖ but it does not
    provide a standard of proof for aggravating factors, nor does it
    contain a standard for determining when LWOP is an
    71   UTAH CODE § 76-3-207(5)(c) (2008).
    19
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    ―appropriate‖ sentence.     He alleges that these deficiencies
    provided him with no notice as to whether pleading guilty would
    result in a life sentence with or without parole. Thus, he
    contends, the lack of standards created a ―roll of the dice‖ as to
    which sentence he would receive.
    ¶ 48 We agree that, standing alone, the statutory directive
    that an LWOP sentence may be imposed if ―appropriate‖ is
    troubling. The term ―appropriate‖ contributes little or nothing to
    the solemn task in which it plays a central role. ―Appropriate‖ is
    defined as ―specially suitable‖ or ―belonging peculiarly.‖72 But
    everyday experience may not equip a juror with the ability to
    determine when it is ―specially suitable‖ to imprison a juvenile for
    the remainder of his life. Nonetheless, ―we do not interpret the
    ‗plain meaning‘ of a statutory term in isolation.‖73 Instead, we
    ―determine the meaning of the text given the relevant context of
    the statute.‖74 The sentencing statute supplies guidance to the
    decision-maker by illustrating examples of aggravating and
    mitigating factors that should be considered in making this
    weighty decision.75 For example, the statute specifically lists ―the
    youth of the defendant at the time of the crime‖ as a mitigating
    factor to consider.76 Moreover, the sentencing authority is free to
    consider ―any other fact in mitigation of the penalty.‖77 We
    conclude that this guidance sufficiently contextualizes the
    ―appropriate‖ standard such that the statute is not
    unconstitutionally vague.78
    72  WEBSTER‘S THIRD NEW INTERNATIONAL DICTIONARY 106
    (1961).
    73   Olsen v. Eagle Mountain City, 
    2011 UT 10
    , ¶ 12, 
    248 P.3d 465
    .
    74   
    Id. 75 See
    UTAH CODE § 76-3-207(3), (4) (2008).
    76   
    Id. § 76-3-207(4)(e).
       77   
    Id. § 76-3-207(4)(g).
       78 Moreover, the trial judge instructed the jurors that it was
    their ―duty to consider all of the aggravating and mitigating
    evidence in determining the appropriate penalty.‖ The judge
    listed several mitigating factors that may be considered in
    (con‘t.)
    20
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                              Opinion of the Court
    E. Mr. Houston’s Sentence Does not Violate the
    Unnecessary Rigor Clause of the Utah Constitution
    ¶ 49 Mr. Houston also contends that his sentence violates
    Utah‘s unnecessary rigor clause because ―it constitutes
    unnecessary rigor to sentence a juvenile to die in prison with no
    hope of parole.‖ According to Mr. Houston, it is unconstitutional
    to impose the severe sentence of life without parole on a juvenile
    due to the immaturity, vulnerability, and undeveloped character
    associated with youth.79 Mr. Houston argues that LWOP for
    juveniles is particularly rigorous because juveniles do not pose a
    great threat to public safety and are amenable to rehabilitation.
    Although some of these observations about the nature of youth
    are almost certainly true, they do not implicate the nature and
    purpose of the unnecessary rigor clause.
    ¶ 50 Article I, section 9 of the Utah Constitution provides that
    ―[p]ersons arrested or imprisoned shall not be treated with
    unnecessary rigor.‖ This clause protects arrested or imprisoned
    individuals from the infliction of treatment during their
    confinement that is incompatible with the values of a civilized
    society.80 ―The restriction on unnecessary rigor is focused on the
    circumstances and nature of the process and conditions of
    sentencing, including Mr. Houston‘s youth and his capacity to
    appreciate the wrongfulness of his conduct. The judge also
    emphasized that the jury ―should not merely add up the number
    of aggravating and mitigating circumstances or factors, or
    otherwise apply a mechanical rule‖ to their consideration of the
    evidence. And finally, the judge explained that the presumptive
    sentence was life with the possibility of parole and that the
    ―burden rests upon the State to persuade [the jury] that a sentence
    of life in prison without parole [was] the appropriate sentence‖ to
    impose.
    79 The concurrence argues that this is an as-applied challenge.
    Infra ¶ 128. But Mr. Houston does not claim that LWOP
    constitutes unnecessary rigor given the specifics of his case; he
    argues that LWOP is unnecessarily rigorous when applied to any
    juvenile offender, regardless of the facts of the crime.
    80   State v. Perea, 
    2013 UT 68
    , ¶ 124, 
    322 P.3d 624
    .
    21
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    confinement,‖ not on ―the sentence imposed.‖81 This provision is
    targeted at eliminating ―unreasonably harsh, strict, or severe
    treatment‖ in prison such as ―being unnecessarily exposed to an
    increased risk of serious harm.‖82
    ¶ 51 We hold that the unnecessary rigor clause does not
    apply to Mr. Houston‘s challenge. Mr. Houston does not object to
    the conditions of his confinement, but rather the length of the
    sentence imposed by statute.         Although a defendant may
    challenge the length of his or her sentence as unconstitutional, this
    claim is more properly characterized as a cruel and unusual
    punishments claim and may not be brought under the
    unnecessary rigor clause.
    F. Mr. Houston’s Sentence Does not Violate the Cruel
    and Unusual Punishments Clause of the Utah
    or the United States Constitution
    1. Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause of the United States
    Constitution
    ¶ 52 Finally, Mr. Houston claims that sentencing a juvenile to
    LWOP violates the cruel and unusual punishments clauses of the
    Utah and United States Constitutions. In support of his federal
    argument, Mr. Houston cites three recent United States Supreme
    Court cases: Graham v. Florida, holding that it is unconstitutional
    to sentence a juvenile to LWOP for a nonhomicide crime;83 Roper
    v. Simmons, holding that it is unconstitutional to sentence a
    juvenile to death;84 and Miller v. Alabama, holding that it is
    unconstitutional to impose a mandatory LWOP sentence on a
    juvenile.85 Mr. Houston argues that the particular characteristics
    of youth undermine the penological basis for imposing an LWOP
    sentence, and that LWOP for a juvenile therefore constitutes cruel
    and unusual punishment.
    81   Dexter v. Bosko, 
    2008 UT 29
    , ¶ 17, 
    184 P.3d 592
    .
    82   
    Id. ¶ 19.
       83   
    560 U.S. 48
    , 82 (2010).
    84   
    543 U.S. 551
    , 578 (2005).
    85   
    132 S. Ct. 2455
    , 2475 (2012).
    22
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           Opinion of the Court
    ¶ 53 We recognize that there are unique characteristics of
    juveniles that distinguish them from adult offenders, and we
    conclude that Utah‘s sentencing statute treats juveniles in a
    manner that accounts for these unique characteristics. For
    example, a juvenile cannot be sentenced to death, regardless of the
    offense committed. LWOP is neither a mandatory sentence nor
    the presumptive sentence under Utah‘s sentencing statute. And
    the statute directs the sentencing authority to consider any
    relevant mitigating circumstances. We therefore hold that Utah
    Code section 76-3-207 is facially constitutional. We begin by
    addressing Mr. Houston‘s claim under the United States
    Constitution and then turn to Mr. Houston‘s argument under the
    Utah Constitution.
    ¶ 54 The Eighth Amendment to the United States
    Constitution provides: ―Excessive bail shall not be required, nor
    excessive fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments
    inflicted.‖86 We have recognized that ―[a] criminal punishment
    may be cruel and unusual when it is barbaric, excessive, or
    disproportional to the offense committed.‖87 Moreover, despite
    an evolving analytical framework, the fundamental principle of
    the Eighth Amendment remains unchanged:                  ―[C]riminal
    punishments are prohibited if they are excessive or contravene
    evolving standards of decency and human dignity.‖88 We also
    note, however, that sentencing statutes derive from a variety of
    often imprecise policy considerations. For this reason, we must
    accord ―substantial deference . . . to the prerogatives of legislative
    86 The Eighth Amendment‘s Cruel and Unusual Punishments
    Clause is incorporated against the states via the Due Process
    Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Robinson v. California, 
    370 U.S. 660
    , 675 (1962); State v. Herrera, 
    1999 UT 64
    , ¶ 33 n.13, 
    993 P.2d 854
    .
    87 State v. Mace, 
    921 P.2d 1372
    , 1377 (Utah 1996) (footnote
    omitted) (citing Solem v. Helm, 
    463 U.S. 277
    , 284 (1983)).
    88 State v. Lafferty, 
    2001 UT 19
    , ¶ 76, 
    20 P.3d 342
    (alteration in
    original) (internal quotation marks omitted); see also Trop v. Dulles,
    
    356 U.S. 86
    , 101 (1958) (―The [Eighth] Amendment must draw its
    meaning from the evolving standards of decency that mark the
    progress of a maturing society.‖).
    23
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    power ‗in determining the types and limits of punishments for
    crimes.‘‖89 For this reason, ―absent a showing that a particular
    punishment is cruelly inhumane or disproportionate, we are not
    apt to substitute our judgment for that of the legislature regarding
    the wisdom of a particular punishment or of an entire sentencing
    scheme.‖90
    ¶ 55 The United States Supreme Court has not ruled on
    whether the Eighth Amendment prohibits the imposition of
    LWOP for a juvenile convicted of homicide.91 But the Court
    considered related questions in Graham, Roper, and Miller. We
    find those cases instructive and determine that the Eighth
    Amendment does not prohibit the imposition of LWOP for a
    juvenile homicide offender.
    ¶ 56 We deferred our consideration of Mr. Houston‘s appeal
    while Miller v. Alabama was pending before the United States
    Supreme Court.92 In Miller, two defendants who had committed
    unrelated murders at the age of fourteen challenged an Alabama
    statute that mandated an LWOP sentence.93 The Supreme Court
    announced its decision in 2012, holding that a sentencing scheme
    that mandates an LWOP sentence for a juvenile constitutes cruel
    and unusual punishment under the United States Constitution.94
    The Court explained that the Eighth Amendment requires
    individualized sentencing procedures for juveniles so that the
    sentencing authority may consider the mitigating circumstances
    inherent in youth.95 Miller did not, however, categorically
    89State v. Bishop, 
    717 P.2d 261
    , 269 (Utah 1986) (quoting 
    Solem, 463 U.S. at 290
    ).
    90 
    Mace, 921 P.2d at 1377
    –78 (citation omitted) (internal
    quotation marks omitted).
    91  See 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    (explicitly reserving ruling on
    this issue).
    92 The parties provided supplemental briefing addressing the
    effects of the Miller decision on the instant case.
    93   
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2460
    .
    94   
    Id. at 2469.
       95    
    Id. at 2475
    (―Graham, Roper, and our individualized
    (con‘t.)
    24
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                              Opinion of the Court
    prohibit LWOP for juveniles.96 The Court explained that it ―[did]
    not foreclose a sentencer‘s ability‖ to sentence a juvenile convicted
    of homicide to LWOP.97
    ¶ 57 In Miller, the Supreme Court grounded its decision in an
    analysis of proportionality. The Court reiterated ―the basic
    precept of justice that punishment for crime should be graduated
    and proportioned to both the offender and the offense.‖98 This
    proportionality analysis implicated two lines of cases. The first
    involves ―categorical bans on sentencing practices based on
    mismatches between the culpability of a class of offenders and the
    severity of a penalty.‖99 In that line of cases, the Court struck
    down the death penalty for nonhomicide offenders,100 juveniles,101
    and individuals with severe mental disabilities.102 Using similar
    reasoning, the Court prohibited LWOP for juveniles who commit
    nonhomicide crimes.103 The second line of cases addresses the
    mandatory imposition of sentences—in other words, sentencing
    schemes that leave the sentencing authority without power to
    consider the individual circumstances of the offense or the
    offender.104    For example, the Court invalidated statutes
    prescribing a mandatory death penalty sentence.105            The
    sentencing decisions make clear that a judge or jury must have the
    opportunity to consider mitigating circumstances before imposing
    the harshest possible penalty for juveniles.‖).
    96   
    Id. at 2469.
       97   
    Id. Id. at
    2463 (quoting 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 560
    ) (internal quotation
    98
    marks omitted).
    99   
    Id. 100 Kennedy
    v. Louisiana, 
    554 U.S. 407
    , 469 (2008).
    101   
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 574
    –75.
    102   Atkins v. Virginia, 
    536 U.S. 304
    , 321 (2002).
    103   
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 75
    .
    104   
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2463
    –64.
    105Woodson v. North Carolina, 
    428 U.S. 280
    , 303 (1976) (plurality
    opinion).
    25
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    confluence of these two lines of precedent led the Miller Court to
    strike down Alabama‘s mandatory sentencing scheme imposing
    LWOP. The Court held that, as applied to juveniles, the
    punishment was severe and Alabama‘s statute did not allow for
    the consideration of possible mitigating factors.106 Therefore, the
    Court concluded that mandatory LWOP sentences for juveniles
    could not be sustained under the Eighth Amendment.107
    ¶ 58 Drawing from evidence in Graham and Roper, the Court
    explained that juveniles ―are constitutionally different from adults
    for purposes of sentencing.‖108 This is because ―juveniles have
    diminished culpability and greater prospects for reform,‖ and
    thus ―they are less deserving of the most severe punishments.‖109
    Roper and Graham identified three areas of ―significant gaps‖
    distinguishing juveniles from adults:
    First, children have a ―lack of maturity and
    underdeveloped sense of responsibility,‖ leading to
    recklessness, impulsivitity, and heedless risk-taking.
    Second, children ―are more vulnerable . . . to
    negative influences and outside pressures,‖
    including from their family and peers; they have
    limited ―contro[l] over their own environment‖ and
    lack the ability to extricate themselves from horrific,
    crime-producing settings.       And third, a child‘s
    character is not as ―well formed‖ as an adult‘s; his
    traits are ―less fixed‖ and his actions less likely to be
    ―evidence of irretrievabl[e] deprav[ity].‖110
    These conclusions were informed by science and social science
    research, including longitudinal studies and brain mapping.111
    These decisions also recognized that ―the distinctive attributes of
    106   
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2468
    –69.
    107   
    Id. at 2475
    .
    108   
    Id. at 2464.
       109   
    Id. (internal quotation
    marks omitted).
    110  
    Id. (alterations in
    original) (citations omitted) (quoting
    
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 569
    –70) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    111   
    Id. at 2464–65,
    2465 n.5.
    26
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                               Opinion of the Court
    youth diminish the penological justifications‖ for punishment,
    particularly regarding rehabilitation and retribution.112
    ¶ 59 But despite this evidence about the characteristics of
    youth, the Supreme Court has nonetheless narrowly limited its
    decisions. In Graham, the Court applied its ban on LWOP for
    juveniles only where the underlying offense was a nonhomicide
    crime.113    The Court distinguished homicide crimes from
    nonhomicide crimes on the basis of ―both moral culpability and
    consequential harm.‖114 Similarly, Miller declined to adopt a
    categorical bar to LWOP for juveniles; instead, the Court
    foreclosed only mandatory LWOP sentences because such
    sentences ―prohibit a sentencing authority from assessing whether
    the law‘s harshest term of imprisonment proportionately punishes
    a juvenile offender.‖115 And the Court recognized that there could
    be ―appropriate occasions‖ for imposing LWOP on a juvenile
    offender, rare as those circumstances may be.116 Moreover, the
    Court explained that it did ―not foreclose a sentencer‘s ability to
    [impose LWOP] in homicide cases,‖ so long as the sentencer
    ―take[s] into account how children are different, and how those
    differences counsel against irrevocably sentencing them to a
    lifetime in prison.‖117 Thus, though the penological justifications
    for LWOP may be diminished for a juvenile compared to an adult,
    such a sentence is not without justification in our criminal
    sentencing scheme.
    ¶ 60 We therefore agree with the Supreme Court and with the
    dissent118 that juveniles represent a unique class warranting
    special considerations in sentencing. We believe that the unique
    characteristics of youth are accounted for, both by Utah law and
    through federal constitutional protections. We note again that
    112   
    Id. at 2465.
       
    113 560 U.S. at 82
    .
    114   
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2465
    (citing 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 69
    –70).
    115   
    Id. at 2466.
       116   
    Id. at 2469.
       117   
    Id. 118 Infra
    ¶ 258.
    27
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    juveniles are not eligible for the death penalty, regardless of the
    offense committed, under both Utah law119 and the Supreme
    Court‘s decision in Roper.120 Similarly, state law121 and federal
    precedent122 prohibit LWOP for juveniles who commit a
    nonhomicide crime. And finally, as required by Miller, Utah‘s
    sentencing statute does not impose a mandatory LWOP sentence
    on juveniles.123 Instead, the statute provides a presumptive
    sentence of twenty years; LWOP may be imposed only if ten or
    more jurors agree it is appropriate.124
    ¶ 61 Importantly, our statutory scheme enables the kind of
    individualized sentencing determination that the Supreme Court
    has deemed necessary for serious offenses. Utah Code section
    76-3-207 permits the sentencer to consider any and all relevant
    factors which would affect the sentencing determination. The
    statute directs the sentencing authority to consider aggravating
    circumstances and mitigating factors, and it specifically provides
    a nonexhaustive list of each to aid the sentencer.125 In fact, the
    statute specifically directs the sentencer to consider ―the youth of
    the defendant at the time of the crime.‖126 We thus conclude that
    the statute meets the ―requirement of individualized sentencing
    for defendants facing the most serious penalties,‖127 and places
    particular emphasis on youth as a mitigating factor.
    119   UTAH CODE § 76-5-202(3)(e).
    120   
    543 U.S. 551
    .
    121 See, e.g., UTAH CODE § 76-5-302(6) (removing the possibility
    of LWOP for juveniles charged with aggravated kidnapping); 
    id. § 76-5-402(3)(b)(ii)
    (same for rape); 
    id. § 76-5-405(b)
    (same for
    aggravated sexual assault).
    122   
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 74
    .
    123   UTAH CODE § 76-3-207(5)(c) (2008).
    124   
    Id. 125 Id.
    § 76-3-207(3), (4).
    126   
    Id. § 76-3-207(4)(e).
       127   
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2460
    .
    28
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                            Opinion of the Court
    ¶ 62 We are not alone in this conclusion. The Supreme Court
    has explained that ―[i]n considering categorical bars to . . . life
    without parole, we ask as part of the analysis whether objective
    indicia of society‘s standards, as expressed in legislative
    enactments and state practice, show a national consensus against
    a sentence for a particular class of offenders.‖128 As the dissent
    notes, a great majority of states as well as the federal system
    permit LWOP sentences for juveniles.129 As of 2010, thirty-nine
    states allowed such sentences130 while only six jurisdictions
    affirmatively prohibited them.131 In looking to these as an
    indication of society‘s standards, we cannot conclude that the
    ―national consensus‖ favors the prohibition of LWOP for juveniles
    convicted of homicide.
    ¶ 63 In sum, we conclude that imposing LWOP on a juvenile
    convicted of homicide does not violate the Eighth Amendment‘s
    prohibition on cruel and unusual punishments. We therefore
    deny Mr. Houston‘s challenge under the United States
    Constitution.
    2. Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause of the Utah
    Constitution
    ¶ 64 We next turn to article I, section 9 of the Utah
    Constitution, which provides that ―cruel and unusual
    punishments [shall not] be inflicted.‖ In State v. Lafferty, we held
    that ―[a] criminal punishment is cruel and unusual under article I,
    section 9 if it is so disproportionate to the offense committed that
    it shock[s] the moral sense of all reasonable men as to what is
    right and proper under the circumstances.‖132 The concurrence
    128 
    Id. at 2470
    (quoting 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 61
    ; 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 563
    ) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    129   Infra ¶ 271.
    130Brief for Petitioner, Jackson v. Hobbs, 
    132 S. Ct. 2455
    (2012)
    (No. 10-9647), 
    2012 WL 92506
    , at *1a (combined case with Miller v.
    Alabama).
    
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 82
    (Alaska, Colorado, Montana, Kansas,
    131
    Kentucky, and Texas).
    132 Lafferty, 
    2001 UT 19
    , ¶ 73 (second alteration in original)
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    29
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    concludes that this determination merits no deference and should
    be repudiated because it is ―an unworkable standard.‖133 We do
    not agree. The basic concept of article I, section 9 flows from the
    precept of justice that punishment should be graduated and
    proportioned to both the offender and the offense. Like the
    Supreme Court, we recognize that ―[w]hile the State has the
    power to punish,‖ we must ―assure that this power be exercised
    within the limits of civilized standards.‖134 Fines, imprisonment,
    and even execution may be imposed depending upon the
    enormity of the crime.
    ¶ 65 Moreover, it would be inappropriate for us to deviate
    from our prior jurisprudence in the present case. Both the State
    and Mr. Houston have relied on the standard announced in
    Lafferty, and they have grounded their arguments in discussions
    of proportional punishment. The parties have not asked this court
    to consider the interpretation Justice Lee now advocates, and
    therefore the court does not have the benefit of adversarial
    briefing on the issue. As a general rule, we decline to rule or
    opine on issues that are not briefed by the parties.135 We therefore
    133  Infra ¶ 138. The concurrence bases its argument ―most
    fundamentally‖ on the fact that ―no majority opinion of this court
    has ever employed a state standard of proportionality that is
    distinct from the federal standard.‖ Infra ¶ 142; see also infra ¶ 145
    (arguing that because we have treated the state and federal
    standards as indistinguishable, there is ―no independent
    significance [for] the state standard‖ and ―thus no basis for stare
    decisis reliance‖). We fail to see how this supports the view that
    our prior pronouncements warrant no respect. While we are
    certainly not required to adopt a federal interpretation for our
    state provision, we likewise are not forbidden from doing so. Our
    jurisprudence does not garner precedential weight if, and only if,
    we adopt a standard that diverges from federal practice. Such a
    view contradicts our long-standing practice of looking to federal
    interpretation for guidance.
    134   
    Trop, 356 U.S. at 100
    .
    See Utah Safe to Learn–Safe to Worship Coal., Inc. v. State, 2004
    
    135 UT 32
    , ¶ 19, 
    94 P.3d 217
    (―The courts are not a forum for hearing
    academic contentions or rendering advisory opinions.‖ (internal
    (con‘t.)
    30
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                               Opinion of the Court
    find no reason to depart from the proportionality standard
    employed in Lafferty.136
    ¶ 66 Because we conclude that a punishment must be
    proportionate to the offense, we look to federal decisions as a
    guide in determining whether ―a particular punishment is cruelly
    inhumane or disproportionate.‖137 We therefore look to the
    characteristics of juveniles that set them apart from adult
    offenders. We again acknowledge the unique characteristics of
    youth—its impetuosity, vulnerability to outside influence, and
    potential for change.138 We also consider the penological goals of
    the sentence, recognizing that they may be diminished in the case
    of juveniles.139 But we do not conclude that these circumstances
    render LWOP cruel and unusual for juveniles as a class. Under
    Utah law, this severe sentence is only permitted for the gravest of
    offenses and requires at least ten members of the jury to
    quotation marks omitted)); State v. Ball, 
    685 P.2d 1055
    , 1061 (Utah
    1984) (declining to consider the scope of a state constitutional
    provision when the issues were not briefed by the parties because
    they ―deserve thorough treatment by counsel and careful
    consideration by the Court‖); see also Winward v. State, 
    2012 UT 85
    ,
    ¶ 18 n.4, 
    293 P.3d 259
    (recognizing that it would be ―imprudent to
    now resolve [an] extremely important issue without the benefit of
    adversarial briefing‖); State v. Baker, 
    2010 UT 18
    , ¶ 57, 
    229 P.3d 650
    (―[W]here the law . . . is unsettled and we are without the benefit
    of adversarial briefing on the subject, we would be ill-advised to
    resolve this case on that basis.‖).
    136 We also note that our conclusion that Mr. Houston‘s
    sentence does not violate proportionality principles, see infra
    ¶¶ 66–67, ultimately renders a decision on which standard to
    apply unnecessary in this case. Mr. Houston‘s challenge fails
    regardless of whether we apply the Lafferty proportionality
    analysis or Justice Lee‘s more limited originalist approach, infra
    ¶ 210.
    137 Lafferty, 
    2001 UT 19
    , ¶ 74 (internal quotation marks
    omitted).
    138   See 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2464
    .
    139   
    Id. at 2465.
    31
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    determine that, given the circumstances of the crime and the
    offender‘s background, LWOP is appropriate. Moreover, we note
    that a majority of our sister states as well as the federal system
    permit LWOP for juveniles convicted of the most heinous
    crimes.140 Applying a proportionality analysis, we conclude that
    the imposition of LWOP for juveniles convicted of homicide does
    not violate the Utah Constitution.
    ¶ 67 We reiterate the hope expressed by the Supreme Court
    that LWOP sentences for juveniles will be rare.141 It is the most
    severe sentence a judge or jury can impose on a juvenile, and it
    should be carefully considered and reserved for only the most
    severe crimes and most incorrigible juvenile offenders. But
    where, as here, we find no constitutional violation, we may not
    ―substitute our judgment for that of the legislature regarding the
    wisdom of a particular punishment.‖142 We therefore hold that
    Mr. Houston has not demonstrated that his LWOP sentence
    violates the cruel and unusual punishments clauses of either the
    Utah or United States Constitution.
    ¶ 68 Because we reject each of Mr. Houston‘s constitutional
    challenges to his sentence of life without parole, we conclude that
    Mr. Houston has failed to demonstrate that his sentence was
    unconstitutional and therefore illegal under Utah Rule of Criminal
    Procedure 22(e).
    III. MR. HOUSTON HAS FAILED TO ESTABLISH
    THAT HIS COUNSEL RENDERED
    INEFFECTIVE ASSISTANCE
    ¶ 69 On appeal, Mr. Houston presents seven claims of
    ineffective assistance of counsel during his sentencing proceeding.
    First, Mr. Houston argues that his counsel was ineffective for not
    objecting to certain statements made by the prosecutor in closing
    argument, and alternatively that the trial court plainly erred in
    failing to intervene. Second, he contends that his counsel was
    ineffective in failing to find and call certain mitigation expert
    witnesses. Third, Mr. Houston claims that his counsel was
    140   Supra ¶ 62.
    141   See 
    Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469
    .
    142   
    Mace, 921 P.2d at 1377
    –78.
    32
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                              Opinion of the Court
    deficient in conducting voir dire. Fourth, Mr. Houston argues
    that his counsel was ineffective for failing to seek a change of
    venue. Fifth, he claims his counsel was deficient for not objecting
    to certain testimony at the proceeding. Sixth, Mr. Houston
    contends that his counsel was deficient for not objecting to certain
    jury instructions. Finally, Mr. Houston argues that even if none of
    these errors alone is enough to constitute ineffective assistance of
    counsel, the cumulative effect of the errors should nonetheless
    undermine our confidence in the result of his sentencing
    proceeding. We determine that Mr. Houston has not established
    that his counsel provided ineffective assistance.
    ¶ 70 The right to counsel under the Sixth Amendment to the
    United States Constitution includes ―the right to the effective
    assistance of counsel.‖143 In Strickland v. Washington, the United
    States Supreme Court announced the two-part test for ineffective
    assistance of counsel claims.144 First, the defendant must show
    that ―his counsel rendered a deficient performance in some
    demonstrable manner, which performance fell below an objective
    standard of reasonable professional judgment.‖145 Second, the
    defendant must demonstrate ―that counsel‘s performance
    prejudiced the defendant.‖146 We have acknowledged ―the
    variety of circumstances faced by defense counsel [and] the range
    of legitimate decisions regarding how best to represent a criminal
    defendant.‖147 As a result, ―we must indulge in a strong
    presumption that counsel‘s conduct [fell] within the wide range of
    reasonable professional assistance, and that, under the
    143 McMann v. Richardson, 
    397 U.S. 759
    , 771 n.14 (1970); accord
    State v. Templin, 
    805 P.2d 182
    , 186 (Utah 1990).
    144   
    466 U.S. 668
    , 687 (1984).
    145   Id.; accord Archuleta v. Galetka, 
    2011 UT 73
    , ¶ 38, 
    267 P.3d 232
    .
    146Archuleta, 
    2011 UT 73
    , ¶ 38 (internal quotation marks
    omitted).
    147 
    Templin, 805 P.2d at 186
    (alteration in original) (internal
    quotation marks omitted).
    33
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    circumstances, the challenged action might be considered sound
    trial strategy.‖148
    ¶ 71 With this framework in mind, we now address each of
    Mr. Houston‘s ineffective assistance of counsel claims.
    A. Mr. Houston Has Failed to Demonstrate that His Counsel
    Was Ineffective when Counsel Did not Object to the
    Prosecutor’s Closing Argument or that the Trial
    Court Plainly Erred by Failing to Intervene
    ¶ 72 Mr. Houston argues that his counsel rendered ineffective
    assistance when counsel failed to object to statements made in the
    closing argument. Alternatively, Mr. Houston contends that the
    trial court committed plain error for allowing the statements
    during closing argument.149     Mr. Houston fails to make either
    showing.
    ¶ 73 During the sentencing proceeding, Mr. Houston‘s expert
    neuropsychologist testified that another doctor had diagnosed
    Mr. Houston with a ―conduct disorder‖ when he was an
    adolescent. On cross-examination, the prosecution asked the
    neuropsychologist if she, too, had concluded that Mr. Houston
    had a conduct disorder. The neuropsychologist explained that
    she did not conclude that Mr. Houston suffered from a conduct
    disorder because Mr. Houston was an adult when she evaluated
    him and ―conduct disorder‖ is not an available diagnosis for an
    adult. The prosecutor then asked the neuropsychologist if she
    believed     that   Mr. Houston     was    ―antisocial.‖      The
    neuropsychologist testified that Mr. Houston may show signs of
    being antisocial, but ultimately she did not conclude that he met
    the test for an antisocial diagnosis. The neuropsychologist also
    testified that she did not believe Mr. Houston suffered from
    psychopathy. In supporting her opinion, the neuropsychologist
    contrasted Mr. Houston with the well-known serial killer and
    psychopath Ted Bundy.
    148State v. Lenkart, 
    2011 UT 27
    , ¶ 25, 
    262 P.3d 1
    (alteration in
    original) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    149  Mr. Houston raises this argument under the plain error
    doctrine because he acknowledges that it was not preserved. See
    State v. Weaver, 
    2005 UT 49
    , ¶ 18, 
    122 P.3d 566
    .
    34
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                              Opinion of the Court
    ¶ 74 In closing argument, the prosecution emphasized the
    conduct disorder that Mr. Houston was diagnosed with as a child.
    Mr. Houston argues the State erroneously claimed that
    Mr. Houston still has the conduct disorder:
    I think it is important that you look at [the conduct
    disorder] diagnosis, because what does it say? That
    diagnosis says, yeah, [Mr. Houston] has depression,
    but he has a conduct disorder. That means he‘s a
    violent character. He‘s a criminal. And they had to
    take that into consideration as they dealt with him.
    Then the prosecution challenged the neuropsychologist‘s
    conclusion that Mr. Houston did not suffer from antisocial
    behavior as an adult:
    [The defense] expert didn‘t even look at [the conduct
    disorder] as antisocial behavior, . . . didn‘t even say
    that it was [antisocial] despite the fact that [Mr.
    Houston] had committed three violent acts.
    ¶ 75 Mr. Houston argues that his counsel was ineffective in
    failing to object to these statements. According to Mr. Houston,
    the State‘s closing argument was ―incorrect and inflammatory‖
    because the State ―effectively argued—with no basis in the record
    whatsoever—that [Mr.] Houston is antisocial pathologic,
    incurably violent.‖ By not objecting, moving to strike, or in any
    way addressing these statements, Mr. Houston contends that
    counsel left the jury ―free to equate [Mr.] Houston with Ted
    Bundy.‖ We disagree with Mr. Houston‘s characterization and
    conclusions.
    ¶ 76 First, Mr. Houston‘s counsel did not render ineffective
    assistance when he did not object to the prosecutor‘s statements.
    We have recognized that ―[c]ounsel for both sides have
    considerable latitude in their closing arguments. They have the
    right to fully discuss from their perspectives the evidence and all
    inferences and deductions it supports.‖150          Moreover, ―[a]
    prosecutor has the duty and right to argue the case based on the
    total picture shown by the evidence.‖151 When we review an
    150   State v. Dibello, 
    780 P.2d 1221
    , 1225 (Utah 1989).
    151   State v. Hales, 
    652 P.2d 1290
    , 1291 (Utah 1982) (internal
    (con‘t.)
    35
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    attorney‘s failure to object to a prosecutor‘s statements during
    closing argument, the question is ―not whether the prosecutor‘s
    comments were proper, but whether they were so improper that
    counsel‘s only defensible choice was to interrupt those comments
    with an objection.‖152 Here, we conclude that the prosecutor
    appropriately exercised his discretion to emphasize Mr. Houston‘s
    childhood diagnosis of conduct disorder, and to challenge the
    defense expert‘s conclusion that Mr. Houston did not suffer from
    an antisocial behavior disorder as an adult. The record contained
    evidence that Mr. Houston was a violent offender and had
    extensive history with the criminal justice system. The prosecutor
    was free to draw on this record evidence and question the
    conclusions of Mr. Houston‘s expert. The jury was informed that
    what lawyers ―say during their closing arguments is not
    evidence‖ and that the members of the jury should rely ―on [their]
    memory of the evidence‖ in reaching a sentencing decision.
    None of the prosecutor‘s statements were so inflammatory that
    ―counsel‘s only defensible choice was to interrupt those
    comments with an objection.‖153
    ¶ 77 We also disagree that the court plainly erred when it did
    not address the prosecutor‘s statements. We do not impose a
    duty on the courts ―to constantly survey or second-guess the
    nonobjecting party‘s best interests or trial strategy.‖154 As stated
    above, the prosecutor was free to emphasize Mr. Houston‘s past
    diagnosis. The prosecutor was also free to challenge the defense
    expert‘s conclusion that Mr. Houston was not antisocial.
    ¶ 78 Because we determine that neither Mr. Houston‘s
    counsel nor the trial judge had an obligation to object to the State‘s
    closing argument, we conclude that Mr. Houston has failed to
    meet his burden to show that the prosecutor‘s statements
    necessitate reversal.
    quotation marks omitted).
    152Bussard v. Lockhart, 
    32 F.3d 322
    , 324 (8th Cir. 1994)
    (emphasis added).
    153   
    Id. 154 State
    v. Labrum, 
    925 P.2d 937
    , 939 (Utah 1996).
    36
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                               Opinion of the Court
    B. Mr. Houston Has Failed to Show that His Counsel Was
    Ineffective in Selecting and Presenting Expert Witnesses
    ¶ 79 Mr. Houston‘s second claim of ineffective assistance of
    counsel concerns his attorney‘s selection and presentation of
    expert witnesses relevant to Mr. Houston‘s mitigation defense.
    Specifically, Mr. Houston claims that his counsel was ineffective
    in ―failing to retain experts qualified to (1) tell the jury why youth
    is a mitigating factor, (2) rebut self-serving testimony about the
    supervision provided at YHA, which fatally undermined
    counsel‘s primary theory, and (3) testify as to risk mitigation and
    rebut the state‘s future dangerousness theme.‖
    ¶ 80 ―[C]ounsel‘s decision to call or not to call an expert
    witness is a matter of trial strategy, which will not be questioned
    and viewed as ineffectiveness unless there is no reasonable basis
    for that decision.‖155 Thus, to demonstrate that his counsel was
    ineffective in retaining and presenting expert witnesses,
    Mr. Houston must ―rebut the strong presumption that under the
    circumstances, [counsel‘s] action might be considered sound trial
    strategy.‖156 This is because there are ―countless ways to provide
    effective assistance in any given case,‖ and ―[e]ven the best
    criminal defense attorneys would not defend a particular client in
    the same way.‖157
    ¶ 81 At the sentencing proceeding, Mr. Houston‘s counsel
    called a forensic neuropsychologist to testify about Mr. Houston‘s
    mental and emotional development. She explained to the jury
    that there were available treatments to help Mr. Houston confront
    his mental and emotional issues and to stop his violent reactions
    to his life circumstances. Our review of the record demonstrates
    that Mr. Houston‘s counsel did not act unreasonably in calling
    this qualified expert witness or in declining to call any additional
    expert witnesses on the same issue.
    155   State v. Tyler, 
    850 P.2d 1250
    , 1256 (Utah 1993).
    156Taylor v. State, 
    2007 UT 12
    , ¶ 73, 
    156 P.3d 739
    (internal
    quotation marks omitted).
    157   
    Strickland, 466 U.S. at 689
    .
    37
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    1. Mr. Houston Has Failed to Demonstrate that His Counsel Was
    Ineffective for not Calling a Human Development Expert
    ¶ 82 Mr. Houston first argues that his counsel should have
    called a ―human development‖ expert to testify about the effects
    of youth on the decision-making process. While such testimony
    may have been helpful to Mr. Houston‘s defense, we conclude
    that this testimony was not required, and it certainly was not
    ineffective for Mr. Houston‘s counsel not to retain an expert on
    this topic.
    ¶ 83 We have stated before that expert testimony is most
    helpful to explain topics that are ―beyond the common knowledge
    of ordinary jurors.‖158       Mr. Houston‘s counsel could have
    reasonably concluded that the jurors would understand from life
    experience that a seventeen-year-old‘s decision-making is not as
    reasoned as that of an adult. Moreover, throughout the sentencing
    procedure, Mr. Houston‘s counsel emphasized his youth in a
    manner that fell within the wide range of professionally
    competent assistance. Therefore, it was not essential for counsel
    to retain an expert on this issue.
    2. Mr. Houston Has Failed to Demonstrate that His Counsel Was
    Ineffective in Deciding not to Call an Expert to Testify About
    YHA‘s Failure to Treat and Supervise Mr. Houston
    ¶ 84 Mr. Houston next argues that his counsel was ineffective
    in failing to call an expert to testify that YHA‘s failure to properly
    treat and supervise Mr. Houston was the proximate cause of
    R.E.‘s murder. Mr. Houston argues that the result of his
    sentencing proceeding would have been different had his counsel
    called an expert to testify that had ―YHA followed industry
    standards, or enforced its own policies, the crime would not have
    occurred.‖ Our review of the record indicates that this claim fails
    for two reasons.
    ¶ 85 First, like Mr. Houston‘s prior claim, no expert was
    needed to present to the jury facts related to YHA‘s deficient
    treatment and supervision of Mr. Houston because such facts
    were not beyond the common knowledge of the jurors. During
    the proceeding, defense counsel successfully elicited this
    158   State v. Clopten, 
    2009 UT 84
    , ¶ 32, 
    223 P.3d 1103
    .
    38
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           Opinion of the Court
    information through questioning of the YHA staff members as
    well as Mr. Houston‘s case worker.159 For example, the jury heard
    evidence that YHA did not realize that Mr. Houston was skipping
    school; that Mr. Houston was engaged in sexual activity that may
    have resulted in his girlfriend‘s pregnancy; that Mr. Houston‘s
    therapist told YHA that she could not contact Mr. Houston for
    several months; and that Mr. Houston‘s mother was upset with
    the lack of communication from YHA. Thus, the jury was in a
    position to consider evidence of YHA‘s lack of supervision and
    treatment.
    ¶ 86 Second, given that testimony concerning YHA‘s
    treatment and supervision was already introduced at the
    proceeding, it is difficult for us to see how Mr. Houston‘s
    counsel‘s decision not to present expert testimony on this issue
    was unreasonable. Our review of the record demonstrates that
    counsel‘s decision not to seek an expert on this issue was the
    result of a strategic move consistent with the defense‘s theory that
    Mr. Houston deserved mercy in sentencing for having pleaded
    guilty and accepting responsibility for his own actions.
    Presenting an expert to blame Mr. Houston‘s crime on the YHA
    staff would have contradicted this theory.160 We therefore
    conclude that Mr. Houston has failed to demonstrate ineffective
    assistance of counsel regarding this issue.
    3. Mr. Houston Has Failed to Demonstrate that His Counsel Was
    Ineffective in Failing to Call a Different Risk Mitigation Expert
    ¶ 87 Mr. Houston also argues that his counsel should have
    called a different expert to address risk mitigation because the
    expert that Mr. Houston‘s counsel called was not sufficiently
    qualified to address these issues. Mr. Houston argues that had
    this testimony been presented to the jury, it would have made a
    159  See State v. Walker, 
    2010 UT App 157
    , ¶ 16, 
    235 P.3d 766
    (noting expert testimony is not critical when same information can
    be elicited on cross-examination).
    160 See 
    Strickland, 466 U.S. at 689
    (noting that to succeed on an
    ineffective assistance of counsel claim, ―the defendant must
    overcome the presumption that, under the circumstances, the
    challenged action might be considered sound trial strategy‖
    (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    39
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    difference in the outcome of his case because it would have
    rebutted the State‘s ―powerful future dangerousness‖ argument.
    Again, we disagree.
    ¶ 88 Our review of the record indicates that the expert
    Mr. Houston‘s counsel called was a licensed neuropsychologist
    with extensive experience in evaluating criminal defendants. She
    has a bachelor‘s degree in psychology and biology, and master‘s
    and doctoral degrees and postdoctoral training in neurobiology.
    She has evaluated criminal defendants since 1987, and has treated
    individuals with obsessive disorders and sexual dysfunctions
    since 1979. This experience indicates that the neuropsychologist
    was fully qualified to testify as an expert in this case.
    Mr. Houston has failed to demonstrate that his counsel‘s decision
    to call and rely on her testimony was unreasonable.
    ¶ 89 Mr. Houston has also failed to demonstrate that the
    neuropsychologist‘s performance was anything but thorough and
    competent. The record indicates that the neuropsychologist
    testified extensively about Mr. Houston‘s troubled background
    and the impact it had on his mental health. Although she testified
    that Mr. Houston was troubled, she also testified that current
    medications could treat his disorders and could ―really make a
    difference‖ in his mental and behavioral health.                The
    neuropsychologist also described in detail how Mr. Houston
    could benefit from cognitive behavioral therapy and how this
    type of therapy could help him to develop skills to stop his violent
    thoughts and reactions.         We thus conclude that the
    neuropsychologist adequately addressed the issue of risk
    mitigation and Mr. Houston‘s future dangerousness, and it was
    not unreasonable for Mr. Houston‘s counsel to rely on her
    testimony as sufficient.
    ¶ 90 At its core, we conclude that Mr. Houston‘s expert
    testimony claims are merely an assertion that appellate counsel
    would have called and retained different experts than those trial
    counsel decided to present to the jury. But we ―will not review
    counsel‘s tactical decisions simply because another lawyer, e.g.,
    appellate counsel, would have taken a different course.‖161
    161Parsons v. Barnes, 
    871 P.2d 516
    , 524 (Utah 1994) (internal
    quotation marks omitted).
    40
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                              Opinion of the Court
    Mr. Houston‘s counsel relied on a common understanding of
    youth and an expert‘s opinion of Mr. Houston‘s mental condition
    instead of calling an expert to explain general development in
    youth. And his counsel properly questioned YHA staff members
    to introduce evidence of its inadequate supervision instead of
    calling an expert to criticize it. These strategic decisions were not
    deficient and did not deprive Mr. Houston of his constitutional
    right to counsel. We therefore conclude that Mr. Houston has
    failed to prevail on any of his claims that his counsel rendered
    ineffective assistance in seeking, retaining, and presenting expert
    testimony at the sentencing proceeding.
    C. Mr. Houston Has Failed to Show His Counsel Was
    Ineffective During Voir Dire Questioning
    ¶ 91 Mr. Houston‘s next ineffective assistance of counsel
    claim centers on his counsel‘s questioning during the initial juror
    interviews. Mr. Houston contends that his ―[c]ounsel displayed a
    remarkable ignorance of the law, and rendered extraordinarily
    ineffective assistance when, during initial juror interviews,
    [counsel] surrendered the presumption favoring [a sentence of]
    life with parole.‖ Specifically, Mr. Houston argues that by asking
    the jurors if they could ―equally‖ consider imposing a sentence of
    life with parole and life without parole, Mr. Houston‘s counsel
    abandoned the directive that a juror should sentence a defendant
    to life with parole unless the State demonstrates that a sentence of
    life in prison without parole is more appropriate given the
    defendant‘s particular case. According to Mr. Houston, by failing
    to emphasize the favorable sentencing presumption, ―the jurors
    were free to vote for life without parole based upon any
    inclination, no matter how slight,‖ and ―this certainly undermines
    confidence in the result.‖ We disagree.
    ¶ 92 We recognize the importance of voir dire questioning as
    ―essential to choosing an impartial jury, and an impartial jury is as
    essential to a fair trial as is an impartial judge.‖162 Indeed, ―[v]oir
    dire is intended to provide a tool for counsel . . . to carefully and
    skillfully determine, by inquiry, whether biases and prejudices,
    latent as well as acknowledged, will interfere with a fair trial if a
    162   State v. Saunders, 
    1999 UT 59
    , ¶ 33, 
    992 P.2d 951
    .
    41
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    particular juror serves in it.‖163 While the jury selection process is
    of great importance, there are many ways to effectively question
    jurors, and there ―are a multitude of inherently subjective factors
    typically constituting the sum and substance of an attorney‘s
    judgments about prospective jurors.‖164 Given that ―jury selection
    is more art than science,‖165 ―trial counsel should be given
    considerable latitude in asking voir dire questions, especially in
    view of the fact that only counsel will, at the beginning, have a
    clear overview of the entire case and the type of evidence to be
    adduced.‖166 Thus, when reviewing an attorney‘s questioning
    and decision to keep or remove a particular juror, we must
    presume that counsel‘s choices were objectively reasonable, ―the
    product of a conscious choice or preference,‖ and ―constitute
    effective representation.‖167 Mr. Houston has failed to rebut this
    presumption.
    ¶ 93 First, Mr. Houston has failed to show that there was
    anything unreasonable about his counsel‘s questioning of the
    jurors.     During voir dire, Mr. Houston‘s counsel actively
    participated and asked the jurors a series of questions to probe
    their ability to serve as impartial jurors. These questions included
    whether the individuals could consider the life with parole and
    life without parole sentences equally, and whether they thought
    one sentence was too severe or one was too lenient. Our review of
    the record demonstrates that all of the jurors selected expressed
    openness to imposing either sentence presented to them and that
    they were committed to hearing all the evidence before making a
    decision.168 And the excerpts cited by Mr. Houston in his brief
    163   
    Id. ¶ 34
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    164   State v. Litherland, 
    2000 UT 76
    , ¶ 21, 
    12 P.3d 92
    .
    165   Id.
    166Saunders, 
    1999 UT 59
    , ¶ 34 (internal quotation marks
    omitted).
    167   Litherland, 
    2000 UT 76
    , ¶ 20.
    168For example, when Mr. Houston‘s counsel asked one juror
    whether life without parole was too severe, or if she felt life with
    parole was too light, she responded, ―Depends on what you guys
    present in front of us.‖ In response to a similar question, another
    (con‘t.)
    42
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           Opinion of the Court
    only bolster this conclusion. We determine that this openness
    does not mean the jurors were unable or unwilling to impose the
    presumptive sentence of life with parole, it simply indicates their
    ability and willingness to serve impartially.
    ¶ 94 Second, we conclude that any confusion that may have
    resulted from Mr. Houston‘s counsel‘s questions to the jurors was
    cured by the trial court‘s jury instruction to apply a presumption
    of life with parole, and by counsel‘s closing argument, which also
    emphasized this directive.        Immediately before conducting
    individual jury voir dire, the trial court advised the prospective
    jurors that the law favored a sentence of life with parole over life
    without parole:
    The jury will be presented with evidence for and
    against a penalty of life in prison without parole. It
    is presumed that an indeterminate prison term of
    not less than 20 years and which may be for life will
    be imposed upon the defendant unless the State
    persuades you that a penalty of life in prison
    without parole is the appropriate sentence in this
    case.
    ¶ 95 During closing argument, Mr. Houston‘s counsel
    reminded the jury that the presumptive sentence was life with
    parole and that the State bore the burden of persuading the jury
    that life without parole was the appropriate sentence. Finally, at
    the conclusion of the sentencing proceeding, the court instructed
    the jury that ―[t]he penalty of life without parole should only be
    imposed if the jury determines that such a sentence is
    appropriate‖ and that the ―burden rests upon the State to
    persuade [the jury] that a sentence of life in prison without parole
    juror responded, ―I think you have to learn what the
    circumstances are. You know, you really can‘t judge the person
    unless you hear all the details.‖ Other jurors explained that they
    would consider either sentence appropriate ―depending on the
    circumstances,‖ or ―depending on what we hear‖ about the
    evidence. Similarly, other jurors noted that they were willing to
    consider ―either [sentence] fairly‖ and that before the evidence
    was presented they ―couldn‘t say one way or the other right
    now.‖
    43
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    is the appropriate sentence in this case.‖ We are convinced that
    these instructions and reminders from counsel and the court were
    sufficient to cure any misperceptions that may have been created
    during Mr. Houston‘s counsel‘s voir dire questioning.169 Having
    concluded that Mr. Houston‘s counsel did not act unreasonably
    during voir dire questioning and that Mr. Houston has failed to
    show any prejudice from his performance, we reject this
    ineffective assistance of counsel claim.
    D. Mr. Houston Has Failed to Show His Counsel Rendered
    Ineffective Assistance by Failing to Seek a Change of Venue
    ¶ 96 Mr. Houston claims that his attorney rendered
    ineffective assistance of counsel by failing to seek a change of
    venue, or to ―even conduct a venue analysis‖ in Mr. Houston‘s
    case. Specifically, Mr. Houston contends that the negative pretrial
    media attention surrounding his case—including reports of
    gruesome details about the crime, sympathetic stories about the
    victim and her family, and ―community outcry‖ against violent
    sex offenders—made it impossible for Mr. Houston to have a fair
    proceeding in Davis County. We disagree.
    ¶ 97 Under Utah Rule of Criminal Procedure 29, a defendant
    who ―believes that a fair and impartial trial cannot be had in the
    jurisdiction where the action is pending‖ may ―ask to have the
    trial of the case transferred to another jurisdiction.‖170 Whether
    counsel should seek a change of venue is a question that must be
    evaluated under the ―totality of the circumstances.‖ 171 Relevant
    considerations may include ―(1) the standing of the victim and the
    accused in the community; (2) the size of the community; (3) the
    nature and gravity of the offense; and (4) the nature and extent of
    publicity.‖172 However, recognizing the benefits of hindsight, in
    posttrial evaluation ―the determinative question is whether [the]
    169See State v. Menzies, 
    889 P.2d 393
    , 401 (Utah 1994) (noting
    that an appellate court will ―generally presume that a jury will
    follow the instructions given [to] it‖).
    170   UTAH R. CRIM. P. 29(d)(1).
    171   State v. James, 
    767 P.2d 549
    , 552 (Utah 1989).
    172   
    Id. 44 Cite
    as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           Opinion of the Court
    defendant was ultimately tried by a fair and impartial jury.‖173
    This is because ―pretrial publicity—even pervasive, adverse
    publicity—does not inevitably lead to an unfair trial.‖174 And
    when a defendant challenges counsel‘s decision to seek a change
    of venue, the defendant must show that the pretrial media
    coverage was so prejudicial that it was objectively unreasonable
    for his counsel not to seek a change in venue.175 Mr. Houston has
    not made this showing.
    ¶ 98 Counsel selected twelve jurors and two alternates. The
    record demonstrates that five of the jurors selected had no
    knowledge of Mr. Houston and were not exposed to any
    information about the crimes committed. Of the nine jurors who
    had heard of the crime, seven indicated that they had not formed
    an opinion about what Mr. Houston‘s punishment should be, and
    two indicated that they had formed opinions.           However,
    subsequent explanations from those two jurors revealed that they
    had only formed an opinion about Mr. Houston‘s guilt—an issue
    that, because of Mr. Houston‘s plea, was not in dispute. Those
    jurors thus had not predetermined what Mr. Houston‘s
    punishment should be, only that some form of punishment was
    appropriate. Both jurors indicated that they could rely on the
    evidence to determine the appropriate sentence and would be fair
    and impartial in their decision-making.176             Moreover,
    173Lafferty v. State, 
    2007 UT 73
    , ¶ 42, 
    175 P.3d 530
    (alteration in
    original) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    174Codianna v. Morris, 
    660 P.2d 1101
    , 1111 (Utah 1983) (quoting
    Neb. Press Ass’n v. Stuart, 
    427 U.S. 539
    , 554 (1976)) (internal
    quotation marks omitted).
    175 See Archuleta, 
    2011 UT 73
    , ¶ 38 (stating that a defendant
    must show both objectively deficient performance and prejudice
    to prevail on a claim of ineffective assistance of counsel).
    176 During voir dire, one of the two jurors explained that she
    did not really understand the question because she did not realize
    until later that Mr. Houston had pleaded guilty. She stated that
    she did not have any opinion about what his sentence should be
    because ―you have to learn what the circumstances are. . . . [Y]ou
    can‘t judge the person unless you hear all the details.‖ The other
    juror explained that she had not formed an opinion because ―I
    (con‘t.)
    45
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    Mr. Houston‘s counsel asked detailed questions of all the jurors,
    and the jurors‘ voir dire answers demonstrated that they could be
    fair and impartial despite their exposure to any pretrial publicity.
    ¶ 99 Although Mr. Houston referenced several graphic and
    detailed newspaper articles about his case, he has failed to
    identify anything in the record that supports his claim that this
    pretrial coverage resulted in a biased juror or jury. While it may
    have been prudent for Mr. Houston‘s attorney to seek a change of
    venue due to the small community and concentrated media
    attention surrounding Mr. Houston‘s case, Mr. Houston‘s claim
    that this pretrial publicity affected his sentence is speculative at
    best. Because Mr. Houston has not shown that it was objectively
    unreasonable not to seek a change of venue or that counsel‘s
    decision resulted in an unfair sentencing proceeding, we conclude
    that this claim of ineffective assistance of counsel fails.
    E. Mr. Houston Has Failed to Demonstrate that Counsel Was
    Ineffective for not Objecting to Testimony From a Department
    of Corrections Officer that Mr. Houston Could Be Paroled
    Before Serving at Least Twenty Years in Prison
    ¶ 100 Mr. Houston next argues that his counsel was ineffective
    when he failed to object, move to strike, or seek a curative
    instruction to address the testimony from John Ford, an assistant
    director with the Utah Department of Corrections. Mr. Ford
    testified that if Mr. Houston was sentenced to life with parole,
    there was a chance that Mr. Houston could be released before
    serving at least a twenty-year prison term.
    ¶ 101 During the sentencing proceeding, Mr. Houston‘s
    counsel called Mr. Ford to testify about Utah‘s sentencing system
    and to explain to the jury the different treatment afforded inmates
    sentenced to life with parole and life without parole. Mr. Ford
    also explained that when an individual is sentenced to life with
    the possibility of parole, it is for an indeterminate term, meaning
    that after a period of time the Board of Pardons and Parole would
    hold a hearing to determine when an individual might be paroled.
    The Board of Pardons would also schedule a future hearing to
    revisit this determination.
    haven‘t heard . . . enough to.‖ She also stated that she could fairly
    consider either sentencing option.
    46
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                          Opinion of the Court
    ¶ 102 On cross-examination, the prosecutor asked Mr. Ford
    whether the Board of Pardons could release Mr. Houston before
    he served twenty years in prison if the jury chose to sentence him
    to life with parole. Mr. Ford responded, ―I don‘t think [the Board
    of Pardons] would ever consider doing that. Unless there‘s a
    medical [emergency] or unless [the defendant] is no longer a
    threat.‖ After this comment, the prosecutor and Mr. Ford had the
    following exchange:
    PROSECUTOR: So generally speaking, you would
    anticipate the person serve at least 20
    years?
    MR. FORD:      At least that and most likely it would
    be much more than that.
    PROSECUTOR: But     it‘s not a guarantee, clearly,
    because the Board of Pardons has great
    power?
    MR. FORD:      Yes.
    ¶ 103 To emphasize the unlikelihood of a release from prison
    before Mr. Houston served at least twenty years, Mr. Houston‘s
    counsel asked on redirect: ―It was asked whether or not I guess in
    theory somebody could be released prior to 20 years. In theory
    that‘s possible, but not likely?‖ Mr. Ford responded, ―Not likely.‖
    Mr. Houston‘s counsel then asked, ―Especially where you need a
    three-person majority [of the Board of Pardons] and you indicated
    that it‘s most likely that the person will spend much more than
    the 20 years in prison?‖ Mr. Ford responded, ―That‘s correct.‖
    ¶ 104 Mr. Houston argues that counsel was ineffective in
    responding to Mr. Ford‘s testimony. Specifically, Mr. Houston
    argues that counsel should have objected during the prosecutor‘s
    cross-examination of Mr. Ford, and that by bringing the issue back
    up on redirect, counsel only reinforced to the jury that
    Mr. Houston‘s early release was a viable possibility. We find
    nothing ineffective or prejudicial about Mr. Houston‘s counsel‘s
    response to Mr. Ford‘s testimony.
    ¶ 105 A formal objection and request for a curative instruction
    is not the only objectively reasonable response to unexpected or
    47
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    unfavorable testimony.177 As stated before, there are a variety of
    ways to competently represent a criminal defendant, and no one
    method is required for effective representation.178 Instead of
    objecting to the prosecutor‘s line of questioning, Mr. Houston‘s
    counsel decided to clarify on redirect and emphasize to the jury
    that the likelihood that Mr. Houston would be released early was
    extremely limited. When we consider this decision in light of the
    presumption of competence, we must conclude that
    Mr. Houston‘s counsel was not ineffective and that his decision to
    emphasize the limited chance of early release on redirect ―was the
    result of conscious trial strategy.‖179
    ¶ 106 We further conclude that Mr. Houston has failed to
    demonstrate any prejudice resulting from his attorney‘s response
    to Mr. Ford‘s testimony. Before sentencing, the judge instructed
    the jury to disregard any testimony about possible early release:
    ―[Y]ou are not to take into account any actions the Board of
    Pardons and Parole might take in the future. Future decisions of
    the Board are merely speculative and are irrelevant to a jury‘s
    determination of an appropriate sentence.‖ This instruction
    assures us that any improper weight that the jury may have
    assigned to this line of questioning was properly addressed and
    cured by the trial judge.180
    F. Mr. Houston Has Failed to Demonstrate that His Counsel Was
    Ineffective for not Objecting to the Alleged Double Counting
    of an Aggravating Factor in the Jury Instructions
    ¶ 107 Mr. Houston‘s next ineffective assistance of counsel
    argument stems from his counsel‘s failure to object to a series of
    177 See State v. Bullock, 
    791 P.2d 155
    , 160 (Utah 1989)
    (concluding trial counsel‘s decision not to object to unfavorable
    testimony did not constitute ineffective assistance of counsel).
    178   See 
    Templin, 805 P.2d at 186
    .
    179   
    Bullock, 791 P.2d at 160
    .
    180 See State v. Mead, 
    2001 UT 58
    , ¶ 50, 
    27 P.3d 1115
    (holding
    that a jury instruction cured any prejudice that may have resulted
    from the admission of improper testimony); see also 
    Menzies, 889 P.2d at 401
    (noting that an appellate court presumes that the jury
    follows its given instructions).
    48
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           Opinion of the Court
    jury instructions. Mr. Houston claims that by not objecting to
    these instructions, counsel allowed the jury to engage in an
    improper double counting of aggravating factors during
    sentencing. We disagree.
    ¶ 108 Jury instruction number 13 states in relevant part:
    During the sentencing proceeding, aggravating and
    mitigating evidence was presented to you with
    respect to the penalty to be imposed. You are
    instructed    that    the     terms    ―aggravating
    circumstances,‖     ―aggravating    factors,‖  and
    ―aggravating evidence,‖ used interchangeably, refer
    to evidence tending to show that the penalty of life
    without parole is appropriate.
    Jury instruction number 14 states that ―[t]he fact that
    [Mr. Houston] has pled guilty to the crime of Aggravated Murder
    is not an aggravating circumstance. . . . However, you may
    consider as aggravating circumstances the matters that were
    presented as aggravating circumstances in the charge against the
    defendant.‖ And finally, jury instruction number 15 lists ―rape‖
    and ―aggravated sexual assault‖ as two possible aggravating
    circumstances the jury could consider. ―Aggravated sexual
    assault‖ is defined as when an individual ―in the course of a
    rape . . . , causes bodily injury to the victim or uses or threatens
    the victim with the use of a dangerous weapon, such as a knife.‖
    Mr. Houston argues that these instructions created overlapping
    aggravating factors that skewed the weighing process in the
    minds of the jurors.
    ¶ 109 During the sentencing proceeding, the judge told the
    jury that it may find an aggravating circumstance if it concluded
    that ―[Mr. Houston] intentionally or knowingly caused the death
    of [the victim] while . . . engaged in the submission of or an
    attempt to commit rape or aggravated sexual assault.‖ The
    judge‘s instructions made clear that Mr. Houston was charged
    with and pleaded guilty to aggravated murder because he
    committed either rape or aggravated sexual assault, but not both.
    These aggravating factors were read to the jury in the alternative,
    and thus, the jury could find the presence of an aggravating
    circumstance if it concluded that either rape or sexual assault
    occurred. The instruction did not direct the jury to count these as
    49
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    Opinion of the Court
    separate aggravating factors, and thus, Mr. Houston‘s counsel did
    not err by not objecting to these instructions.
    ¶ 110 We further conclude that even if there was some
    confusion surrounding aggravating circumstances in the jury
    instructions, any confusion did not prejudice Mr. Houston
    because the jury was instructed to weigh the aggravating and
    mitigating circumstances not in terms of numbers, but rather in
    terms of ―how compelling or persuasive the evidence is when
    deciding an appropriate sentence.‖ To emphasize the directive
    that the jury should not merely count up the aggravating and
    mitigating circumstances, the trial court stated that ―any
    aggravating factor, standing alone, could be more persuasive than
    some or all of the mitigating factors in the case. On the other
    hand, one mitigating factor, standing alone, could be more
    persuasive than some or all of the aggravating factors.‖
    Therefore, even if Mr. Houston is correct in his assertion that the
    jurors counted the rape and sexual assault as two separate
    aggravating factors rather than finding the presence of one or the
    other, the jurors‘ ultimate decision was still based on what they
    found most compelling or persuasive considering the totality of
    the circumstances, not the mere number of aggravating factors
    present in the case. And in evaluating Mr. Houston‘s claim of
    prejudice, we must proceed ―on the assumption that the decision-
    maker is reasonably, conscientiously, and impartially applying
    the standards that govern the decision.‖181 We therefore conclude
    that Mr. Houston has failed to show that his counsel‘s
    performance was deficient or that any deficiency caused him
    prejudice.
    G. Mr. Houston Has not Demonstrated Cumulative Error that
    Undermines Our Confidence in His Sentence
    ¶ 111 Finally, Mr. Houston argues that we should reverse his
    sentence under the cumulative error doctrine because the
    ineffectiveness of counsel alleged above should undermine our
    confidence in the sentence. To evaluate a cumulative error claim,
    ―we consider all the identified errors, as well as any errors we
    assume may have occurred.‖182 However, ―[i]f the claims are
    181   
    Parsons, 871 P.2d at 530
    (internal quotation marks omitted).
    182   State v. Maestas, 
    2012 UT 46
    , ¶ 363, 
    299 P.3d 892
    (internal
    (con‘t.)
    50
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           Opinion of the Court
    found on appeal to not constitute error, or the errors are found to
    be so minor as to result in no harm, the doctrine will not be
    applied.‖183    Because we find that each of Mr. Houston‘s
    ineffective assistance of counsel claims fails, our confidence in the
    fairness of his sentence is not undermined. Therefore, we find no
    cumulative error.
    CONCLUSION
    ¶ 112 It is beyond contention that Mr. Houston‘s case is tragic.
    This is an extremely uncommon case where the jury, considering
    the mitigating circumstances inherent to Mr. Houston‘s youth,
    nevertheless concluded that life without the possibility of parole
    was the appropriate sentence for the crime committed. We hold
    that Mr. Houston properly brought constitutional challenges to
    his sentence under Utah Rule of Criminal Procedure 22(e);
    however, we conclude that each of his claims fails. We also hold
    that Mr. Houston has failed to demonstrate that he received
    ineffective assistance of counsel. We therefore affirm the jury‘s
    sentence of life in prison without the possibility of parole.
    quotation marks omitted).
    183 
    Id. (alteration in
    original) (internal quotation marks
    omitted).
    51
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ASSOCIATE CHIEF JUSTICE LEE, concurring in part and
    concurring in the judgment:
    ¶ 113 I concur in the opinion of the court in part and concur
    in the judgment affirming the conviction entered against
    Mr. Houston. I write separately, however, to express my
    disagreement with the majority on two principal points: (1) I
    would not deem Houston‘s challenge to his sentence to be
    properly presented under rule 22(e) of our rules of criminal
    procedure (but instead subject only to review for plain error); and
    (2) I would reject Houston‘s state constitutional challenge to his
    sentence based on an original understanding of the Utah
    Constitution, which categorically forecloses the proportionality
    challenge advanced in this case.
    I. PRESERVATION AND UTAH RULE OF
    CRIMINAL PROCEDURE 22(e)
    ¶ 114 Houston failed to raise a constitutional challenge to his
    sentence in the proceedings below. Despite that failure, the
    majority deems the constitutional claims advanced on appeal to
    be properly presented under rule 22(e) of the Utah Rules of
    Criminal Procedure. Supra ¶ 26. That provision expressly
    authorizes a court to ―correct an illegal sentence, or a sentence
    imposed in an illegal manner, at any time.‖ UTAH R. CRIM. P. 22(e).
    In recent cases, however, we have adopted limiting constructions
    of this rule. Most recently, in State v. Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , 
    274 P.3d 919
    , we noted that ―rule 22(e) is based on an antecedent in the
    federal rules,‖ and we limited our state rule to the traditional
    application of its federal antecedent. 
    Id. ¶ 22.
    Specifically, Prion
    held that a challenge to an ―illegal sentence‖ under rule 22(e) is
    limited to ―instances ‗when the sentence imposed exceeds the
    statutorily-authorized limits, violates the Double Jeopardy Clause,
    or is ambiguous or internally contradictory.‘‖ 
    Id. (quoting United
    States v. Pavlico, 
    961 F.2d 440
    , 443 (4th Cir. 1992)).
    ¶ 115 As the Prion opinion explained, this traditional
    limitation (imported from federal law) is aimed at striking ―a
    careful balance between the goal of correcting illegal sentences on
    one hand and . . . encouraging preservation and finality on the
    other.‖ 
    Id. Yet the
    Prion standard is not a subjective balancing test.
    Nor does it leave room for the standard embraced by the
    majority—of opening the door to unpreserved challenges to
    sentences that are ―facial‖ and not ―as-applied.‖ Supra ¶ 26.
    52
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    Instead, the standard we articulated in Prion is an objective one
    based on past practice under a parallel (but subsequently
    amended) federal rule. As stated plainly in Prion, rule 22(e) leaves
    room only for challenges to sentences that exceed statutory limits,
    that violate double jeopardy, or that are ambiguous or internally
    contradictory. Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 22.
    ¶ 116 The majority overrules this standard, replacing it with a
    standard allowing a ―facial challenge‖ to the constitutionality of a
    sentence but foreclosing ―fact-intensive,‖ ―as-applied‖ challenges.
    Supra ¶¶ 18, 23, 26. The court purports to find support for this
    standard in Prion and its antecedents. See supra ¶¶ 24–27 (citing
    Prion and also State v. Candedo, 
    2010 UT 32
    , 
    232 P.3d 1008
    ; State v.
    Telford, 
    2002 UT 51
    , 
    48 P.3d 228
    ; and State v. Brooks, 
    908 P.2d 856
    (Utah 1995)). But none of our prior opinions adopt the
    formulation established today.
    ¶ 117 Granted, the Prion opinion explained the rationale
    behind this limitation in terms that emphasized the downsides of
    opening the door to unlimited challenges to the constitutionality
    of a sentence. Our opinion warned, for example, of the abuse and
    anomaly that would ensue if our law ―elevate[d] challenges to
    sentencing proceedings over parallel challenges to the guilt phase
    of a trial.‖ Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 20. And we cautioned specifically
    against ―a fact-intensive challenge to the legality of a sentencing
    proceeding asserted long after the time for raising it in the initial
    trial or direct appeal.‖ 
    Id. But the
    quoted language was only an
    explanation of the policy basis for the standard we clarified in
    Prion; it was not the standard itself.
    ¶ 118 The Prion standard, rather, was the traditional
    formulation we imported from longstanding cases interpreting
    the federal rule incorporated into our rule 22(e)—encompassing
    only ―instances ‗when the sentence imposed exceeds the
    statutorily-authorized limits, violates the Double Jeopardy Clause,
    or is ambiguous or internally contradictory.‘‖ 
    Id. ¶ 22.
    The
    majority is mistaken in its assertion that Prion ―nowhere stated
    that we were adopting the federal limitation‖ as the holding of the
    court. Supra ¶ 24 n.35. We did so expressly, and repeatedly. See
    Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 21 (noting that ―[b]oth grounds‖ asserted by
    Prion ―to challenge his revised sentence are consistent with the
    traditional, established bases for a rule 22(e) motion,‖ and
    indicating that ―we accordingly reject the State‘s procedural
    argument notwithstanding our acknowledgement of the need for
    53
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    a narrow construction of the rule‖ (emphasis added)); see also 
    id. ¶ 23
    (―[Prion‘s] 22(e) motion . . . is one that comes within the
    traditional bounds of the rule, and we accordingly uphold it
    against the State‘s procedural attack.‖ (emphasis added)).
    ¶ 119 Our Candedo opinion cannot properly be read to
    support the majority‘s new standard. Candedo did not establish a
    standard dependent on the ―facial‖ or ―as-applied‖ nature of a
    constitutional challenge to a sentence. Instead, the opinion in
    Candedo simply reversed the court of appeals‘ determination that
    an ―illegal‖ sentence under rule 22(e) was limited to cases ―where
    either the sentencing court has no jurisdiction, or . . . the sentence
    is beyond the authorized statutory range.‖ 
    2010 UT 32
    , ¶ 10
    (alteration in original) (internal quotation marks omitted). And in
    so doing, Candedo stated generally that ―if an offender‘s sentence
    is unconstitutional, the sentence is not authorized by the
    ‗judgment of conviction,‘ and is therefore illegal.‖ 
    Id. ¶ 13.
    On that
    basis, Candedo held ―that the court of appeals erred in failing to
    reach the merits of Candedo‘s‖ constitutional challenge ―because
    the definition of illegal sentence under rule 22(e) is sufficiently
    broad to include constitutional violations that threaten the
    validity of the sentence.‖ 
    Id. ¶ 14.
    Our holding in Candedo,
    moreover, did not rest on a distinction between facial and as-
    applied challenges to a sentence.
    ¶ 120 Indeed, our constitutional analysis (upholding
    Candedo‘s sentence against a substantive due process attack)
    ultimately rejected both facial and as-applied challenges. See 
    id. ¶ 21
    (holding ―that Utah‘s probation statute generally, as well as
    the term of probation to which Candedo was sentenced, are
    rationally related to the state‘s legitimate interest‖); 
    id. ¶ 23
    (acknowledging that ―a defendant could successfully challenge a
    probation sentence that is truly arbitrary or discriminatory under
    the due process clause or prove that the probation statute is cruel
    and unusual, but such a case is not before us now‖). And as to the
    governing standard, the Candedo opinion effectively punted on the
    specific sorts of constitutional claims that could be cognizable
    under rule 22(e). While acknowledging the state‘s argument that
    rule 22(e) countenances only claims that a sentence is ―‗patently‘
    or ‗manifestly‘ illegal,‖ the Candedo court concluded that it was
    unnecessary to ―reach‖ that issue if the claims at issue failed on
    their merits. 
    Id. ¶ 14
    (concluding that there is no need to ―reach
    54
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    the issue of whether the sentence is ‗patently‘ or ‗manifestly‘
    illegal‖ if the claim fails on its ―merits‖).
    ¶ 121 Our earlier decision in Telford is to the same effect.
    There we acknowledged that Telford challenged his sentence ―on
    both per se and as applied grounds,‖ 
    2002 UT 51
    , ¶ 2; noted that
    rule 22(e) is a narrow exception to the rule of preservation,
    allowing only the ―correction of manifestly illegal sentences,‖ 
    id. ¶ 5;
    and stopped short of defining the limiting standard (of what
    is ―manifestly illegal‖) because the claims at issue clearly failed on
    their merits, 
    id. ¶ 6
    (rejecting claims under the Sixth Amendment
    and article I, section 12 of the Utah Constitution on the ground
    that these provisions provided ―no articulable basis for attacking
    [Telford‘s] sentence‖).184
    ¶ 122 The majority also cites State v. Brooks, 
    908 P.2d 856
    (Utah
    1995), in support of its new standard, supra ¶ 27, but the Brooks
    opinion is in line with the approach in Telford and Candedo. As the
    majority indicates, the Brooks opinion states that ―nothing is to be
    gained by remanding the case to the trial court‖ when ―the
    pertinent facts are undisputed and a purely legal question with
    respect to which the trial court has no discretion remains to be
    
    decided.‖ 980 P.2d at 860
    . But the Brooks opinion does not adopt
    the facial/as-applied distinction embraced by the majority. It
    simply holds that rule 22(e) may sometimes ―permit[] the court of
    appeals to consider the legality of a sentence even if the issue is
    raised for the first time on appeal,‖ while rejecting the
    applicability of the rule in the context of a claim that ―[i]n
    substance‖ challenges the underlying conviction and not the
    sentence. 
    Id. (explaining that
    Brooks‘s claim, while styled as a
    challenge to his sentence, was ultimately a challenge to his
    ―conviction for a lesser included offense‖).
    184 The point is not to suggest that the court did not decide
    whether the claims in Telford and Candedo were properly brought
    under rule 22(e). I am simply clarifying that the operative
    standard articulated in these cases was relatively unimportant, as
    the sentencing challenges at issue failed on their merits in any
    event. And, given the patchwork formulations in our cases at the
    time we decided Prion, it was essential that our opinion in that
    case seek to provide some clarity.
    55
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 123 I acknowledge the plausibility of the alternative
    readings of our prior cases advanced by the majority opinion. As
    that opinion suggests, the Candedo opinion may plausibly be read
    to have endorsed the viability of any ―constitutional violations
    that threaten the validity of the sentence.‖ See supra ¶ 24 n.35. As
    for Telford and Brooks, those opinions may also be understood to
    have interpreted rule 22(e) in a manner endorsing an operative
    legal standard—in Telford, the notion that the rule is limited to the
    correction of sentences that are ―manifestly illegal,‖ 
    2002 UT 51
    ,
    ¶ 5; and in Brooks, the principle that the rule encompasses
    challenges to sentences that are ―patently 
    illegal,‖ 908 P.2d at 860
    .
    ¶ 124 Yet these constructions of rule 22(e) are untenable. The
    broad formulation in Candedo would erase our rules of
    preservation for challenges to sentences and thereby treat
    sentencing proceedings as somehow more significant than trials.
    That makes no sense, as even the majority opinion today
    recognizes. And the standards in Telford and Brooks are
    unworkable. We can assess illegality; but ―patent‖ or ―manifest‖
    illegality are concepts inviting arbitrary decision-making.
    ¶ 125 Our Prion opinion filled the gap left by the competing
    standards set forth in our caselaw. Facing the untenably broad
    formulation in Candedo and the unworkable premises of Telford
    and Brooks, Prion was faced with the task of determining
    conclusively the scope of the rule 22(e) exception. And because
    the claims in Prion could not easily be brushed aside as meritless,
    we could not easily sidestep the issue of the appropriate standard
    under rule 22(e). In addressing this question, moreover, Prion
    clearly and expressly defined an objective standard under rule
    22(e)—a standard, as noted above, that tied our state rule to cases
    under its federal antecedent, and that limited the challenges
    countenanced by the rule to those attacking sentences that exceed
    statutory limits, that violate double jeopardy, or that are
    ambiguous or internally contradictory.185 Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 22.
    185The majority‘s principal attempt to justify its rejection of the
    standard set forth in Prion is its recognition of the federal
    antecedent to our state rule 22(e), combined with the assertion
    that some federal courts recognized a ―broader‖ principle under
    which a sentence ―generally ‗in violation of the Constitution‘‖ or
    (con‘t.)
    56
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                            A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 126 This holding was significant. It established an objective,
    historically rooted limitation on the broad terms of rule 22(e)—a
    limitation that was essential to preserving the policies and domain
    of the doctrine of preservation, and of avoiding the absurdity of a
    regime that would preference constitutional challenges to
    sentences over constitutional challenges to underlying convictions.
    See 
    id. ¶ 20
    (warning of the prospect of ―abuse‖ of a broad
    standard under rule 22(e), which would undermine the policies
    behind the law of preservation and would ―elevate challenges to
    sentencing proceedings over parallel challenges to the guilt phase
    of a trial‖).
    ¶ 127 Our decision in Prion was simple, straightforward, and
    unanimous. I would reaffirm it and apply it here. And I would
    accordingly deem Houston‘s challenges to his sentence uncovered
    by rule 22(e), as none of them involve a claim that his sentence
    exceeded statutory limits, violated double jeopardy, or was
    ―based on ‗misinformation of a constitutional magnitude‘‖ could
    have been subject to challenge under the federal rule. Supra ¶ 23.
    It is unsurprising that the general federal rule we embraced in
    Prion may have been subject to an occasional aberration or
    exception in the federal caselaw. That is also beside the point.
    Prion embraced a straightforward, objective standard limiting rule
    22(e) challenges to those attacking sentences that exceed statutory
    limits, that violate double jeopardy, or that are ambiguous or
    internally contradictory. Prion, 
    2012 UT 15
    , ¶ 22. We rooted that
    standard in the majority rule adopted in federal cases as we
    understood them. But the standard was clear and unmistakable; it
    was in no way a standard subject to expansion or extension if
    aberrational federal cases could be cited in the future (as in the
    majority opinion here).
    The point in invoking the federal caselaw is not to suggest that
    we are bound to follow it. Prion was based on the need to adopt
    an objective, limiting standard under rule 22(e). And the federal
    standard was the one we chose to fulfill that need.
    It is telling that even the majority does not adopt the standard
    set forth in the outlier federal cases that it cites. Instead, it adopts
    a new one of its own making, and in so doing it repudiates a
    square holding that is entitled to deference.
    57
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ambiguous or internally contradictory. Thus, I would analyze
    Houston‘s constitutional challenges to his sentence under a
    standard of plain error review, which is the standard that applies
    to an unpreserved challenge to a sentence that is not covered by
    rule 22(e).
    ¶ 128 I would also observe that the court‘s analysis is itself
    unfaithful to the standard it postulates. Some of Houston‘s
    challenges to his sentence seem to be ―as-applied‖ challenges. See
    supra ¶¶ 30–32 (addressing Houston‘s Apprendi challenge); supra
    ¶¶ 49–51 (addressing Houston‘s Unnecessary Rigor Clause
    challenge). These claims clearly implicate a degree of fact-
    intensive analysis. Even ―facial challenges,‖ moreover, may
    require fact-intensive analysis, in that such challenges require a
    litigant to ―establish that no set of circumstances exists under
    which the [statute] would be valid.‖ United States v. Salerno, 
    481 U.S. 739
    , 745 (1987).186 If this is the sort of claim the majority
    means to preserve under criminal rule 22(e), the court has not
    succeeded in adopting a ―limited‖ standard. It has instead opened
    the door to a broad range of claims that are quite often fact-
    intensive.
    ¶ 129 The back-and-forth between the majority and dissenting
    opinions is illustrative. The dissent cites extensive social science
    research in support of its conclusion that Houston‘s life-without-
    parole sentence is incompatible with the standard of
    proportionality that it advances. Infra ¶¶ 258–269 (cataloguing
    social science research on the nature of juvenile cognitive
    186 The majority opinion responds with the notion that ―the
    court need not delve into the record or make findings of fact‖ on a
    ―facial constitutional attack.‖ Supra ¶ 27. That strikes me as
    overstated. To establish that ―no set of circumstances exists‖ in
    which a sentencing provision could be valid, 
    Salerno, 481 U.S. at 745
    , factual questions could easily be implicated. This case is a
    prime example. If we are to gauge social science research in
    assessing the question of proportionality in sentencing, surely we
    could benefit from the presentation of evidence on the matter. On
    this question the competing opinions find it sufficient to rest on
    their own evaluations of social science, but that does not make the
    inquiry any less fact-intensive.
    58
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    functions and its impact on principles of retribution and
    rehabilitation). And the majority offers responses similarly
    invoking social science material. Supra ¶¶ 58–59 (addressing the
    special status of minors based on ―science and social science
    research, including longitudinal studies and brain mapping‖).
    With this background, it seems apparent that the cruel and
    unusual punishment challenge asserted by Houston is a fact-
    intensive one. For me, this underscores the untenable nature of
    the standard adopted by the court today. In time the court will be
    required to reject it, and replace it with a more workable one. I
    would avoid that problem by retaining the standard we
    articulated in Prion.
    ¶ 130 Finally, I would register a plea that we revisit this issue
    immediately through our rulemaking process. Our law as it
    stands under rule 22(e) as written is confusing, fuzzy, and
    perverse. The confusion is in the terms of the rule. The rule as it
    stands is a trap for an unwary litigant. We should not retain a rule
    that says one thing and means another. The fuzziness is in the
    court‘s standard as articulated today. There is no clear,
    established distinction between ―facial‖ and ―as-applied‖
    challenges to a sentence.187 So the standard we have adopted is
    sure to lead to uncertainty and arbitrary decisionmaking going
    forward. Lastly, the perversion is in a legal regime that suspends
    the law of preservation for ―facial‖ constitutional challenges to a
    sentence while retaining the law of preservation for parallel
    challenges to a conviction. That is backwards. If anything, an
    unconstitutional conviction ought to be more troubling.
    187 See Am. Fed’n of State, Cnty., & Mun. Emps. Council 79 v.
    Scott, 
    717 F.3d 851
    , 865 (11th Cir. 2013) (―[T]he line
    between facial and as-applied relief is a fluid one, and many
    constitutional challenges may occupy an intermediate position on
    the spectrum between purely as-applied relief and
    complete facial invalidation.‖); Richard H. Fallon, Jr., As-Applied
    and Facial Challenges and Third-Party Standing, 113 HARV. L. REV.
    1321, 1321 (2000) (―There is no single distinctive category of facial,
    as opposed to as-applied, litigation.‖).
    59
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 131 The majority‘s standard under rule 22(e) should not
    stand. We should amend the rule to address the significant
    problems that are highlighted by today‘s opinion.
    II. HOUSTON‘S CONSTITUTIONAL CLAIMS
    ¶ 132 For the above reasons, I would address Houston‘s
    constitutional claims under a plain error standard of review. And
    I would reject all of them under that standard, as Houston has not
    asserted—and cannot conceivably claim—that the sentence
    imposed runs afoul of established legal standards. See, e.g., State v.
    Nielsen, 
    2014 UT 10
    , ¶ 58, 
    326 P.3d 645
    (noting that for an error to
    be ―plain‖ it must be legal in nature, and an ―obvious‖ error ―not
    reasonably in dispute‖ (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    ¶ 133 That is as far as we need to go to resolve this case.
    Because my colleagues see the matter differently, however, and
    proceed to address the merits of Houston‘s claims as if they were
    covered by rule 22(e), it seems appropriate for me to meet their
    analysis on its own terms. In so doing, I would first note that
    assuming rule 22(e) to apply to Houston‘s claims, I would concur
    in the majority‘s analysis of Houston‘s federal constitutional
    claims. See supra ¶¶ 29–63, 69–108.
    ¶ 134 To the extent Houston is asserting a federal
    constitutional challenge to his sentence, we are of course bound to
    follow the precedents of the United States Supreme Court under
    the Eighth Amendment‘s Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause.
    And because those precedents appear to adopt a form of
    ―proportionality‖ review,188 we must apply that same standard
    188  The U.S. Supreme Court has invoked proportionality
    analysis in a number of its opinions. See Miller v. Alabama, 132 S.
    Ct. 2455, 2475 (2012) (striking down mandatory life without parole
    sentences for juveniles as violating the ―principle of
    proportionality‖ embedded in the Eighth Amendment); Graham v.
    Florida, 
    560 U.S. 48
    , 59 (2010) (holding that Eighth Amendment
    proportionality principle prohibits imposition of life without
    parole sentence on juvenile who did not commit homicide); Solem
    v. Helm, 
    463 U.S. 277
    , 284 (1983) (striking down life without parole
    sentence for nonviolent felony under recidivism statute, holding
    that the Eighth Amendment ―prohibits not only barbaric
    punishments, but also sentences that are disproportionate to the
    crime committed‖). But the ―precise contours‖ of the
    (con‘t.)
    60
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    here in assessing Houston‘s federal constitutional claim. I concur
    in the majority opinion‘s analysis as it applies to this federal
    claim. I would reject Houston‘s Eighth Amendment argument for
    the reasons set forth in the court‘s opinion. See supra ¶¶ 52–63.
    ¶ 135 Houston‘s state constitutional claim is another matter.
    To the extent Houston is challenging his sentence under article I,
    section 9 of the Utah Constitution, it is our prerogative and
    responsibility to articulate the applicable legal standard. And on
    that point my grounds for rejecting Houston‘s constitutional
    challenge to his sentence extend beyond those set forth in the
    majority opinion.
    ¶ 136 Unlike the majority, I would not assume that the Utah
    Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause incorporates a standard
    of proportionality authorizing appellate courts to second-guess a
    lawfully imposed sentence on grounds of excessiveness. Supra
    ¶ 64.189 And unlike the dissent, infra ¶¶ 213–251, I would not
    proportionality standard are somewhat ―unclear.‖ Harmelin v.
    Michigan, 
    501 U.S. 957
    , 998 (1991) (Kennedy, J., concurring in part
    and concurring in the judgment). In Harmelin, the lead opinion
    (authored by Justice Scalia, and joined by Chief Justice Rehnquist)
    concluded that Solem was wrongly decided, and that the Eighth
    Amendment‘s Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause did not
    incorporate a principle of proportionality or excessiveness. See 
    id. at 961–94
    (1991) (lead opinion of Scalia, J.). In a separate
    concurrence, Justice Kennedy (joined by two other members of the
    court) indicated an inclination to adopt a limited notion of ―gross‖
    proportionality. See 
    id. at 1005
    (Kennedy, J., concurring in part and
    concurring in the judgment). Thus, the federal caselaw appears to
    be ―evolving,‖ as we indicated in State v. Mace, 
    921 P.2d 1372
    , 1377
    n.4 (Utah 1996) (asserting that ―[o]ur use of the term
    ‗disproportional‘ . . . is not meant to express any view on the
    status of this evolving jurisprudence, nor is the meaning of the
    term at issue in the present case‖). Yet we are bound to follow the
    court‘s holdings—particularly, of relevance here, the decisions in
    Graham and Miller, which consider ―objective indicia of society‘s
    standards‖ and a court‘s ―independent judgment‖ in evaluating a
    ―categorical‖ challenge to the constitutionality of a sentencing
    scheme as applied to juveniles. 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 61
    .
    I would also stop short of expressing any ―hope . . . that
    189
    LWOP sentences for juveniles will be rare.‖ Supra ¶ 67. That
    (con‘t.)
    61
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    interpret article I, section 9 to authorize this court to consult our
    ―humanitarian instincts,‖ infra ¶ 255, or our sense of ―evolving
    standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing
    society.‖ Infra ¶ 213.
    ¶ 137 Instead, based on the original meaning of the text of
    article I, section 9, I would conclude that the Utah Constitution
    forbids only those modes of punishment that were repudiated as
    ―cruel‖ at the time of the adoption of this provision and that are
    ―unusual‖ in the sense of being contrary to established practice.
    And I would accordingly reject Houston‘s state constitutional
    claim on grounds narrower than those embraced by the majority.
    ¶ 138 First, I would repudiate the dicta in this court‘s prior
    interpretations of article I, section 9, which articulate an
    unworkable standard and accordingly do not merit deference
    under the doctrine of stare decisis. Second, I would adopt an
    originalist conception of article I, section 9—a standard that leaves
    no room for proportionality analysis and prohibits only those
    methods of punishment that are so barbaric or cruel that they
    were barred by longstanding law or practice. Finally, applying
    this standard, I would reject Houston‘s state constitutional claim
    because he raises no challenge to the method of his punishment
    but only challenges his term of confinement on grounds of
    proportionality.
    A. Utah Supreme Court Precedent
    ¶ 139 In State v. Herrera, 
    1999 UT 64
    , ¶ 39, 
    993 P.2d 854
    , this
    court asserted that the Utah Constitution‘s prohibition of cruel
    and unusual punishments encompasses a principle of
    proportionality. In the Herrera court‘s words, ―a criminal
    punishment is cruel and unusual‖ under article I, section 9 ―if the
    punishment is so disproportionate to the offense committed that it
    shock[s] the moral sense of all reasonable men as to what is right
    and proper under the circumstances.‖ 
    Id. ¶ 33
    (alteration in
    original) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    sounds well and good as a matter of humanitarian empathy. But it
    strikes me as beyond our role as judges to express ―hope‖ for any
    particular outcome—as to jury verdicts, damages awards, or
    criminal sentences—in the proceedings that we review on appeal.
    62
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 140 A threshold question for me is whether to afford stare
    decisis deference to the standard set forth in Herrera. Such
    deference is a presumptive starting point. See Austad v. Austad, 
    269 P.2d 284
    , 290 (Utah 1954). And for good reason. ―The doctrine of
    stare decisis is ingrained in our law and is entitled to serious
    consideration.‖ 
    Id. ―The reason
    underlying [this doctrine] is that
    people should know what their legal rights are as defined by
    judicial precedent, and having conducted their affairs in reliance
    on such rights, ought not to have them swept away by judicial
    fiat.‖ 
    Id. ¶ 14
    1 Yet the presumption of stare decisis is rebuttable. And it
    is rebutted where its reliance-based justification is not implicated,
    as where the precedent in question adopted a standard that is
    vague or unworkable. State v. Menzies, 
    889 P.2d 393
    , 399 (Utah
    1994). I would decline to defer to the Herrera standard on two
    principal grounds.
    ¶ 142 First and most fundamentally, no majority opinion of
    this court has ever employed a state standard of proportionality
    that is distinct from the federal standard. Herrera articulated a
    state standard, but it did so in a manner that simply parroted the
    governing federal standard. Thus, in applying the above-quoted
    standard of proportionality, the Herrera court cited precedent
    applying the federal standard and concluded that the federal
    standard ―appl[ied] with equal force to our consideration of
    Herrera‘s claims under the cruel and unusual punishment[s]
    clause of the Utah Constitution.‖ 
    1999 UT 64
    , ¶ 38.
    ¶ 143 In support of the standard it employed, the Herrera
    court cited State v. Mace, 
    921 P.2d 1372
    , 1377–78 (Utah 1996). 
    1999 UT 64
    , ¶ 38. And the ―cruel and unusual punishments‖ analysis in
    Mace is expressly and exclusively restricted to the Eighth
    Amendment. 
    Mace, 921 P.2d at 1376
    (―Mace has not separately
    briefed his state constitutional claim, and we do not reach it.‖).190
    190 In any event, our opinion in Mace is at best weak support
    for a general proportionality standard even as a matter of federal
    law. There we did expressly acknowledge a ―proportionality‖
    standard in the U.S. Supreme Court‘s opinion in Solem v. Helm,
    
    463 U.S. 277
    (1983). But we also acknowledged the feeble
    (con‘t.)
    63
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    That likewise holds for the other majority opinion cited in
    Herrera—State v. Copeland, 
    765 P.2d 1266
    , 1270 (Utah 1988).
    Copeland‘s proportionality analysis was also federal in nature, as
    was the proportionality analysis in the other majority opinions
    from which Copeland‘s standards emanate. See 
    id. (citing State
    v.
    Hanson, 
    627 P.2d 53
    , 56 (Utah 1981) (federal Eighth Amendment
    claim; citing, in turn, State v. Nance, 
    438 P.2d 542
    , 544 (Utah 1968)
    (articulating Eighth Amendment proportionality standard under
    Weems v. United States, 
    217 U.S. 349
    (1910))).
    ¶ 144 There is one other authority cited in Herrera for the state
    standard of proportionality that it adopted. See Herrera, 
    1999 UT 64
    ¶ 33 (citing State v. Gardner, 
    947 P.2d 630
    , 633 (Utah 1997)). But
    the cited portion of Gardner is to an opinion that was in the
    minority on that point—an opinion of Justice Durham, joined only
    by Justice Stewart. See 
    Gardner, 947 P.2d at 653
    . A majority of the
    court declined to embrace the Gardner court‘s state constitutional
    analysis. See 
    id. (opinion of
    Zimmerman, A.C.J., expressing the
    view that the case could be dealt with on federal grounds, while
    declining to ―reach the Utah constitutional issues dealt with by
    Justice Durham so sweepingly and at such length‖); 
    id. at 657
    (opinion of Russon, J., joined by Howe, J.) (indicating the view
    that the sentence in question was constitutional, while asserting
    that the state constitutional question was not properly before the
    court given that the defendants ―presented their oral arguments
    solely under the Eighth Amendment to the United States
    Constitution‖).
    foundation of the Solem standard as a matter of federal
    constitutional law, noting as follows:
    [T]wo sitting justices of the United States Supreme
    Court have articulated the view that the Eighth
    Amendment does not embody a proportionality
    requirement for sentences in noncapital cases, and
    . . . three other justices would forbid only sentences
    that are ―grossly disproportionate‖ to the crime
    committed. Our use of the term ―disproportional‖ in
    the text is not meant to express any view on the
    status of this evolving jurisprudence, nor is the
    meaning of the term at issue in the present case.
    
    Mace, 921 P.2d at 1377
    n.4.
    64
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 145 Thus, no majority of this court has ever adopted an
    independent standard of proportionality under article I, section 9
    of the Utah Constitution. For the most part we have simply
    conflated the state and federal standards and treated them as
    indistinguishable—a determination that gives no independent
    significance to the state standard, and thus no basis for stare decisis
    reliance. And the sole exception to that rule is Gardner, in which a
    majority of the court refused to embrace any independent state
    standard. For that reason this is a case where the presumption in
    favor of stare decisis deference is rebutted, as no litigant could
    properly identify any independent standard under article I,
    section 9 that goes beyond a restatement of the binding federal
    standard.
    ¶ 146 The second reason for rejecting Herrera is that the
    standard it identifies is a hazy and unworkable one. This is
    another ground rebutting the presumption of stare decisis.191 An
    unpredictable legal standard is simply not one that litigants can
    use as a guidepost in organizing their affairs. For that reason
    courts have long held that unworkable precedents do not qualify
    for stare decisis deference.192 This court‘s precedents on
    proportionality in sentencing are an archetype of unworkability.
    That fact is reflected in the federal decisions on which our own
    cases are based193 and in legal commentary.194
    191See, e.g., Utah Dep’t of Transp. v. Admiral Beverage Corp., 
    2011 UT 62
    , ¶¶ 36–42, 
    275 P.3d 208
    (overruling Ivers v. Utah Dep’t of
    Transp., 
    2007 UT 19
    , 
    154 P.3d 802
    , both because it was ―wrongly
    decided‖ and because its holding was ―unworkable in practice‖).
    192 Id.; see also Payne v. Tennessee, 
    501 U.S. 808
    , 842–43 (1991)
    (Souter, J., concurring) (―In prior cases, when this Court has
    confronted a wrongly decided, unworkable precedent calling for
    some further action by the Court, we have chosen not to
    compound the original error, but to overrule the precedent.‖);
    Swift & Co. v. Wickham, 
    382 U.S. 111
    , 116 (1965) (overruling prior
    caselaw and noting that it ―should not be kept on the books in the
    name of stare decisis once it is proved to be unworkable in
    practice‖).
    193See 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 102
    (Thomas, J. dissenting) (―The
    categorical proportionality review the Court employs . . . lacks a
    (con‘t.)
    65
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 147 This problem is highlighted by the formulation set forth
    in the dissenting opinion in this case. Quoting the Nevada
    Supreme Court, the dissent proposes a standard of
    proportionality that would turn ―‗largely, if not entirely, upon the
    humanitarian instincts of the judiciary‘‖—a standard that openly
    acknowledges that ―‗[w]e have nothing to guide us in defining
    what is cruel and unusual apart from our consciences,‘‖ or in
    other words, the ―‗mosaic of our beliefs, our backgrounds and the
    degree of our faith in the dignity of the human personality.‘‖ Infra
    ¶ 255 (quoting Naovarath v. State, 
    779 P.2d 944
    , 947 (Nev. 1989)).
    No part of that formulation could sustain any reasonable reliance
    interests. No criminal defendant or prosecutor could reliably
    divine what the ―consciences‖ or ―beliefs‖ of the judges assessing
    a particular sentencing practice might dictate in any anticipated
    trial or appeal. The proportionality standard as formulated by the
    dissent is the very definition of unworkability. It cannot possibly
    sustain any reasonable reliance interests, and thus has no claim to
    stare decisis.
    B. An Originalist View of Article I, Section 9
    ¶ 148 For the above reasons, I would not feel bound to follow
    our prior pronouncements on the meaning of article I, section 9.
    Instead, I would take a fresh look at the important question of the
    meaning of the Utah Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause. In
    principled foundation.‖); 
    Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 1001
    (Kennedy, J.,
    concurring in part and concurring in the judgment) (noting that
    the court‘s precedents on proportionality ―lack clear objective
    standards to distinguish between sentences for different terms of
    years‖); Roper v. Simmons, 
    543 U.S. 551
    , 616 n.8 (2005) (Scalia, J.,
    dissenting) (―The votes in today‘s case demonstrate that the
    offending of selected lawyers‘ moral sentiments is not a
    predictable basis for law—much less a democratic one.‖).
    194  See Bradford R. Clark, Constitutional Structure, Judicial
    Discretion, and the Eighth Amendment, 81 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1149,
    1159 (2006) (asserting that prevailing proportionality standard is
    highly discretionary and impossible to predict, given that it ―rests
    on little more than the subjective opinion of five Justices‖ as to
    ―the moral and penological propriety of the challenged
    punishment‖).
    66
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    so doing, I would employ an originalist method of interpreting
    the Utah Constitution.
    ¶ 149 ―Our state and federal constitutions are not just
    supreme; they are organic or constitutive, in that they establish
    the fundamental ground rules for lawmaking and fixed bulwarks
    against potential tyrannies of the majority.‖ State v. Walker, 
    2011 UT 53
    , ¶ 35, 
    267 P.3d 210
    (Lee, J., concurring). The founding
    purpose of the U.S. Constitution was to ―form[ ] the fundamental
    and paramount law of the nation,‖ by establishing ―certain limits
    not to be transcended‖ and ―designed to be permanent.‖ Marbury
    v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 176–77, 178 (1803) (―[T]hat those
    limits may not be mistaken, or forgotten, the constitution is
    written.‖). And the Utah Constitution serves a similar function. It
    establishes the foundations of our state government, and the
    fundamental rights of our citizens.
    ¶ 150 This is the premise of originalism in constitutional
    interpretation. We implement the principles of the constitution as
    originally adopted because that is the very point of having a
    written constitution. When judges seize the discretion to amend
    and adapt the provisions of the constitution, those principles
    cease to be the ―paramount law of the nation.‖ 
    Id. at 177.
    Or at
    least they can no longer be thought of as ―permanent‖ rules that
    are ―not to be transcended.‖ 
    Id. at 176.
    Thus, ―originalism is not
    just a wise starting point; it is the beginning and end of the judge‘s
    function, and an essential limitation on judicial power.‖ Walker,
    
    2011 UT 53
    , ¶ 34 (Lee, J., concurring).
    ¶ 151 The originalist understands the value—and even the
    inevitability—of adaptation of the law over time. Thus, the case
    for originalism is not, as is sometimes assumed, an insistence that
    the founding generation had a monopoly on wisdom.195 Instead,
    the originalist simply recognizes and respects the means by which
    our laws are supposed to adapt under the terms of the
    195 See, e.g., Thurgood Marshall, Reflections on the Bicentennial of
    the United States Constitution, 101 HARV. L. REV. 1, 1–2 (1987) (―I do
    not believe that the meaning of the Constitution was forever
    ‗fixed‘ at the Philadelphia Convention. Nor do I find the wisdom,
    foresight, and sense of justice exhibited by the framers
    particularly profound.‖).
    67
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    constitution. Such means are twofold: (a) amendment of the
    constitution through the super-majoritarian procedures set forth
    in its provisions196 and (b) the implementation of policies
    embraced by the people through their representatives in the
    political branches of government—by the adoption of statutes,
    regulations, and other laws within the limitations prescribed in
    the constitution.
    ¶ 152 These and other forms of legal adaptation refute a
    common critique of originalism—that it shackles society to rule by
    a ―dead hand.‖197 As these examples illustrate, the originalist does
    196 See U.S. CONST. art. V (―The Congress, whenever two thirds
    of both Houses shall deem it necessary, shall propose
    Amendments to this Constitution, or, on the Application of the
    Legislatures of two thirds of the several States, shall call a
    Convention for proposing Amendments, which, in either Case,
    shall be valid to all Intents and Purposes, as Part of this
    Constitution, when ratified by the Legislatures of three fourths of
    the several States, or by Conventions in three fourths thereof, as
    the one or the other Mode of Ratification may be proposed by the
    Congress . . . .‖); UTAH CONST. art. XXIII, § 1 (―Any amendment or
    amendments to this Constitution may be proposed in either house
    of the Legislature, and if two-thirds of all the members elected to
    each of the two houses, shall vote in favor thereof, such proposed
    amendment or amendments shall be entered on their respective
    journals with the yeas and nays taken thereon; and the Legislature
    shall cause the same to be published in at least one newspaper in
    every county of the state, where a newspaper is published, for two
    months immediately preceding the next general election, at which
    time the said amendment or amendments shall be submitted to
    the electors of the state for their approval or rejection, and if a
    majority of the electors voting thereon shall approve the same,
    such amendment or amendments shall become part of this
    Constitution.‖).
    197 Justice William J. Brennan, Jr., Speech to the Text and
    Teaching Symposium, Georgetown University, Washington, D.C.,
    Oct. 12, 1985, in ORIGINALISM: A QUARTER CENTURY OF DEBATE 55
    (Steven G. Calabresi ed., 2005) (―[T]he genius of the Constitution
    rests not in any static meaning it might have had in a world that is
    dead and gone, but in the adaptability of its great principles to
    (con‘t.)
    68
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    not consign our society to a static regime stuck in the founding
    era. He simply demands that change be effected in the manner
    and by the means prescribed by the constitution.198 And he is
    attuned to the perils of unelected judges overriding the terms of a
    document whose very purpose was to establish fixed limitations
    on our government, by means reserved to the people through the
    process of constitutional amendment.199
    ¶ 153 Thus, the words ―cruel and unusual‖ ―must be taken to
    mean what they meant to the minds of the voters of the state
    when the provision was adopted.‖ Tintic Standard Mining Co. v.
    Utah Cnty., 
    15 P.2d 633
    , 637 (Utah 1932). This is the approach to
    cope with current problems and current needs.‖); Michael S.
    Moore, A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation, 58 S. CAL. L. REV.
    277, 357 (1985) (―The dead hand of the past ought not to govern,
    for example, our treatment of the liberty of free speech, and any
    theory of interpretation that demands that it does is a bad
    theory.‖).
    198 Am. Bush v. City of South Salt Lake, 
    2006 UT 40
    , ¶ 66, 
    140 P.3d 1235
    (Parrish, J., majority opinion) (noting that ―[s]ocial values
    and public opinion . . . fluctuate over time,‖ but that the
    appropriate response is for the people to address such problems
    ―through legislative enactments or even to amend our
    constitution‖); 
    id. ¶¶ 79,
    82 (Durrant, J., concurring) (noting that it
    is ―enticing to adopt an interpretive technique whereby we, as
    judges, look to our own attitudes and views to discern the
    contours of the protective boundary erected by our state
    constitution,‖ but explaining that this approach ―is more akin to
    dictating than judging‖).
    199 See Walker, 
    2011 UT 53
    , ¶ 30 (Lee, J., concurring) (explaining
    that the ―barriers to amendment of our laws are by design,‖ and
    that ―[m]embers of the public are entitled to rely on and organize
    their affairs around the law as positively enacted—unless and
    until the law is amended or repealed‖); Am. Bush, 
    2006 UT 40
    , ¶ 66
    (Parrish, J., majority opinion) (explaining that ―[i]t is not our
    place‖ to ―substitut[e] our own value judgment for that of the
    people of Utah when they drafted and ratified the constitution,‖
    while noting that this does not amount to ―interpreting our
    constitution‖).
    69
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    constitutional interpretation that this court has embraced—with a
    few notable exceptions200—for most of its history.201
    200 Compare Soc’y of Separationists, Inc. v. Whitehead, 
    870 P.2d 916
    , 921 n.6 (Utah 1993) (―We have encouraged parties briefing
    state constitutional issues to use . . . sister state law . . . and policy
    arguments in the form of economic and sociological materials to
    assist us in arriving at a proper interpretation of the provision in
    question.‖), with Am. Bush, 
    2006 UT 40
    , ¶ 12 n.3 (―We have
    intentionally excluded the consideration of policy arguments
    suggested by Soc’y of Separationists v. Whitehead, 
    870 P.2d 916
    , 921
    n.6 (Utah 1993). . . . [O]ur duty is not to judge the wisdom of the
    people of Utah in granting or withholding constitutional
    protections but, rather, is confined to accurately discerning their
    intent.‖). See also State v. Tiedemann, 
    2007 UT 49
    , ¶¶ 32, 37, 
    162 P.3d 1106
    (citing Soc’y of Separationists‘s standard regarding
    ―policy arguments in the form of economic and sociological
    materials‖ as a proper basis for state constitutional interpretation,
    while asserting that ―[h]istorical arguments . . . do not represent a
    sine qua non in constitutional analysis‖); State v. Hoffmann, 2013 UT
    App 290, ¶ 52 & n.8, 
    318 P.3d 225
    (noting tension between
    Tiedemann‘s comment about historical analysis and American
    Bush‘s holding on the same point).
    201   See Jeremy M. Christiansen, Some Thoughts on Utah
    Originalism: A Response, 2014 UTAH L. REV. ONLAW 1, 5–6 & nn.
    26–36, 9–10 & nn.59–64 (citing and discussing this court‘s
    approach to constitutional interpretation over time, and
    concluding that the prevailing approach has largely been
    originalist (citing Richardson v. Treasure Hill Mining Co., 
    65 P. 74
    , 81
    (Utah 1901) (interpreting article XII, section 18 by examining ―[the
    framers‘] discussions upon this subject[] [i]n the official report of
    the proceedings of the constitutional convention‖); Ritchie v.
    Richards, 
    47 P. 670
    , 679 (Utah 1896) (per Batch, J.) (interpreting the
    secret ballot provision of article IV, section 8 and choosing the
    meaning of ―secret‖ that was ―in harmony with public thought
    and expression respecting the ballot systems at the time of and
    before the holding of the constitutional convention‖); State v.
    Elliott, 
    44 P. 248
    , 251 (Utah 1896) (discerning the intent ―of the
    framers of our fundamental law‖ in determining the scope of the
    ―writ of quo warranto‖ in article VIII, section 4)).
    70
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                            A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 154 We should reinforce the originalist method of
    interpretation in this case. We should construe the terms of
    article I, section 9 as originally understood when that provision
    was adopted in 1896. And we should expressly repudiate the
    methodology of the dissent to the extent it rests on a review of
    ―policy arguments in the form of economic and sociological
    materials,‖ see ¶ 219 (citing Soc’y of Separationists, Inc. v. Whitehead,
    
    870 P.2d 916
    , 921 n.6 (Utah 1991)), or an assertion of the heady
    prerogative of making constitutional law by the imposition of our
    ―humanitarian instincts‖ ―spring[ing] from the mosaic of our
    beliefs.‖ Infra ¶ 255.202 That is the antithesis of an originalist
    interpretation of the constitutional text.
    ¶ 155 A constitution rooted in ―evolving standards‖ arising
    out of a judge‘s ―humanitarian instincts‖ is no constitution at all.
    Or at least it is not a ―written‖ constitution capable of ―form[ing]
    the fundamental and paramount law of the nation,‖ or of
    establishing ―certain limits not to be transcended‖ and ―designed
    to be permanent.‖ Marbury, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) at 176, 177.
    ¶ 156 As judges we take an oath to uphold and defend the
    constitution.203 That oath must mean something. It should be
    understood to protect the fundamental rights of our citizens. It
    means nothing of the sort if its content is dependent on the
    ―humanitarian instincts‖ or ―beliefs‖ of the judge or panel of
    judges a litigant happens to draw in a judicial proceeding. No two
    judges are identical. Each of us possesses a different set of
    ―instincts‖ and ―beliefs.‖ Surely the constitution was not meant to
    vary from case to case in accordance with the judge or panel
    assigned to a particular case. To make good on the promise of a
    written document securing fundamental, permanent rights, the
    constitution must mean what it originally meant.204
    202To its credit, the dissent also considers historical materials
    in its analysis. Infra ¶¶ 214–17, 227–50. But the dissent‘s
    originalism falls short, for reasons discussed below.
    203 UTAH CONST. art. IV, § 10 (prescribing an oath, to be taken
    by all ―officers made elective or appointive by this Constitution or
    by the laws made in pursuance thereof, to ―support, obey and
    defend‖ the United States and Utah Constitutions).
    204   The ―evolving standards‖ approach has one thing going for
    (con‘t.)
    71
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 157 I would accordingly reject the ―evolving‖ anti-
    originalist approach endorsed by the dissent. Instead, I would
    adopt an interpretation of article I, section 9 rooted in the
    understanding of this provision that prevailed in the late
    nineteenth century. For reasons explored below, I would conclude
    that that understanding does not deputize the courts to second-
    guess punishments they deem excessive or lacking in
    proportionality, but only to proscribe methods of punishment
    historically rejected as barbaric or torturous. I would base that
    conclusion on the text and structure of article I, section 9; the
    history and understanding of this provision‘s federal and state
    counterparts at the time of its adoption in the late nineteenth
    century; and the drafting history and post-ratification history of
    this provision.
    1. Text and Structure of Article I, Section 9
    ¶ 158 Article I, section 9 provides that ―[e]xcessive bail shall
    not be required; excessive fines shall not be imposed; nor shall
    cruel and unusual punishments be inflicted.‖ UTAH CONST. art. I,
    § 9. The structure and language of this provision cut against an
    interpretation that would authorize the courts to assess the
    proportionality of a sentence, and suggest instead an inquiry into
    the nature or the method of punishment.
    ¶ 159 The first cue from the terms of this provision is
    structural. In its first two clauses, article I, section 9 expressly calls
    for proportionality review—by proscribing ―[e]xcessive bail‖ and
    ―excessive fines.‖ The essence of excessiveness, after all, is
    it; it is transparent. But a standard of constitutionality that
    expressly depends on the ―humanitarian instincts‖ or ―beliefs‖ of
    the judge(s) assigned to a particular case is incoherent. The oath
    that we take to uphold the constitution confirms that it is
    supposed to mean something concrete and objectively discernible.
    We thwart that premise—and replace it with an insistence that the
    constitution will mean different things in different courtrooms—
    when we repudiate originalism and insist on our right to see that
    the constitution evolves as a living document over time.
    72
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                                A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    comparison.205 So the prohibition of excessive bail or fines is an
    express invocation of a principle of proportionality.206
    ¶ 160 Significantly, however, section 9 limits review of a
    criminal punishment‘s excessiveness to bail and fines. For
    punishments, the Utah Constitution (like the Eighth Amendment)
    says nothing of excessiveness; it prohibits only those punishments
    that are ―cruel and unusual.‖ That is significant. Where three sets
    of parallel clauses use two distinct formulations, the clear
    implication is that a difference is intended. The qualifiers ―cruel
    and unusual‖ would be ―an exceedingly vague and oblique way‖
    of communicating what article I, section 9 communicates directly
    in the two preceding clauses—proportionality. See Harmelin v.
    Michigan, 
    501 U.S. 957
    , 977 (1991) (lead opinion of Scalia, J.)
    (offering a parallel conclusion under the U.S. Constitution).207
    205   See infra ¶ 162.
    206 See, e.g., Bullock v. Goodall, 7 Va. (3 Call) 44, 49–50 (1801)
    (noting that the ―excessive fines‖ clause of the Virginia
    Constitution works to limit the discretion of courts to impose fines
    by ensuring that such discretion ―is not . . . exercised arbitrarily,
    but justly; so as to impose a fine commensurate to the offence and
    injury‖); Earl of Devon’s Case, 11 State Trials 133, 136 (1689)
    (condemning a ―fine of thirty thousand pounds‖ as ―excessive
    and exorbitant‖).
    207 The noscitur canon of construction, infra ¶ 224, yields no
    support for the dissent‘s contrary view. This canon resolves
    ambiguities in a term in a statutory list by importing points of
    parallelism among other terms in the list. See Thayer v. Wash. Cnty.
    Sch. Dist., 
    2012 UT 31
    , ¶ 15, 
    285 P.3d 1143
    ; Beecham v. United States,
    
    511 U.S. 368
    , 371 (1994). For that reason, however, the canon has
    no application where there is no ambiguity to resolve, or where
    the provision on its face is lacking in parallelism. Both problems
    are present here. The phrase ―cruel and unusual‖ clause is
    decidedly distinct from—and unparallel with—the ―excessive
    fines‖ and ―excessive bail‖ clause. Thus, I see no basis for the
    dissent‘s approach—deeming this canon to extend to two
    adjectives (excessive), which are grammatically and structurally
    limited to the nouns they modify (bail and fines), to modify a
    (con‘t.)
    73
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 161 Clearly ―cruel and unusual‖ is not the same as
    ―excessive.‖ The relevant (nineteenth century) sense of ―cruel‖ is
    ―[d]isposed to give pain,‖ ―barbarous.‖ WEBSTER‘S COMMON
    SCHOOL DICTIONARY 82 (1892).208 Tellingly, the dissent does not
    point out any attested usage of the word ―cruel‖ that reflects the
    notion of proportionality. The same goes for ―unusual.‖ In the
    relevant time period, that term was understood simply as ―not
    usual; uncommon; rare.‖ 
    Id. at 393.
    Thus, a punishment is ―cruel
    and unusual‖ if it is rare or uncommon in its barbarousness or
    tendency to cause pain. That has nothing to do with its
    proportionality in relation to the underlying offense.
    ¶ 162 ―Excessive[ness],‖ on the other hand, is an
    unmistakable reference to the principle of proportionality.
    Historically, this term was understood to mean ―[b]eyond any
    given degree, measure or limit, or beyond the common measure
    or proportion‖ and ―[b]eyond the laws of morality and religion, or
    beyond the bounds of justice, fitness, propriety, expedience or
    utility.‖ WEBSTER‘S AMERICAN DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH
    LANGUAGE 314 (3d ed. 1830) (emphasis added); see also WEBSTER‘S
    COMMON SCHOOL DICTIONARY 118 (defining ―excess‖ as
    ―intemperance; the amount by which one thing exceeds another‖).
    This underscores the structural point highlighted above. Where
    article I, section 9 employs a term encompassing proportionality
    review in two of its clauses but not in the third, the message
    seems clear: Excessiveness or proportionality review is limited to
    judicial consideration of bail and fines, and does not extend more
    broadly to punishments.
    ¶ 163 The dissent deems this distinction ―unnatural,‖
    ―incongruous,‖ and ―‗anomalous.‘‖ Infra ¶ 224 (quoting 
    Solem, 463 U.S. at 289
    ). And, citing cases interpreting the Eighth Amendment
    of the U.S. Constitution, the dissent asserts that ―[t]he Supreme
    third noun (punishments) already modified by its own adjectives
    (cruel and unusual).
    208See also WEBSTER‘S AMERICAN DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH
    LANGUAGE 210 (3d ed. 1830) (defining ―cruel‖ as ―[d]isposed to
    give pain to others, in body or mind; willing or pleased to
    torment, vex, or afflict; inhuman; destitute of pity, compassion or
    kindness; fierce; ferocious; savage; barbarous; hard-hearted‖).
    74
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                            A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    Court has long held . . . that . . . the Eighth Amendment prohibits
    disproportionate punishments.‖ Infra ¶ 217 (citing Weems v.
    United States, 
    217 U.S. 349
    , 366 (1910); 
    Solem, 463 U.S. at 290
    ; O’Neil
    v. Vermont, 
    144 U.S. 323
    , 331–32, 339–40 (1892) (Field, J.,
    dissenting)). I disagree on both points. As to precedent, the cases
    endorsed by the dissent have been called into question more
    recently. See supra ¶ 134 n.5 (describing the impact of the opinions
    in Harmelin on the analysis in Solem). The lead opinion in the
    court‘s more recent pronouncements under the Eighth
    Amendment, moreover, persuasively refutes the supposed
    ―anomal[y]‖ of limiting the excessiveness inquiry to the terms
    with which it is connected (bail and fines):
    The logic of the matter is quite the opposite. If ―cruel
    and       unusual        punishments‖         included
    disproportionate     punishments,      the     separate
    prohibition of disproportionate fines (which are
    certainly punishments) would have been entirely
    superfluous. When two parts of a provision (the
    Eighth Amendment) use different language to
    address the same or similar subject matter, a
    difference in meaning is assumed.
    ....
    But, it might be argued, why would any rational
    person be careful to forbid the disproportionality of
    fines but provide no protection against the
    disproportionality of more severe punishments?
    Does not the one suggest the existence of the other?
    Not at all. There is good reason to be concerned that
    fines, uniquely of all punishments, will be imposed
    in a measure out of accord with the penal goals of
    retribution and deterrence. Imprisonment, corporal
    punishment, and even capital punishment cost a
    State money; fines are a source of revenue. As we
    have recognized in the context of other constitutional
    provisions,    it    makes    sense    to   scrutinize
    governmental action more closely when the State
    stands to benefit.
    
    Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 978
    n.9 (lead opinion of Scalia, J.).
    ¶ 164 This is entirely in line with our Utah caselaw, which has
    long embraced the canon of independent meaning (or, in other
    75
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    words, a presumption against superfluous language). See, e.g.,
    Hi-Country Prop. Rights Grp. v. Emmer, 
    2013 UT 33
    , ¶ 24, 
    304 P.3d 851
    ; Vota v. Ohio Copper Co., 
    129 P. 349
    , 353 (Utah 1912). Under this
    canon, the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause should not be
    presumed to be superfluous. It should be assumed to have
    independent meaning. And in order to give it such meaning, we
    must presume that it does more than restate the bar on ―excessive
    fines‖ in more general terms.
    ¶ 165 For these reasons, the language and structure of the
    Utah Constitution are incompatible with the proportionality
    standard embraced by the dissent. Instead, the terms of this
    provision appear to be directed at a standard focused on the
    question whether a punishment is one that is both ―barbarous‖ or
    ―disposed to give pain‖ and ―uncommon‖ or ―rare.‖
    B. Original Public Meaning of ―Cruel and
    Unusual Punishments‖
    ¶ 166 This view is confirmed by evidence of the original
    public meaning of the Utah Cruel and Unusual Punishments
    Clause and of its federal and English antecedents. Article I,
    section 9 traces its roots to a parallel provision in the U.S.
    Constitution‘s Eighth Amendment.209 And the federal provision,
    in turn, was based on a parallel clause in the English Bill of Rights.
    ¶ 167 This background highlights three additional historical
    sources that inform my understanding of the meaning of article I,
    section 9: (1) the English origins of the principle of cruel and
    unusual punishments, (2) the original understanding of the
    federal Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause, and (3) the
    understanding prevailing at the time of the adoption of the Utah
    Constitution. All three sources are incompatible with the principle
    of proportionality endorsed by the dissent, and point instead
    209 The two clauses are nearly identical. Compare U.S. CONST.
    amend. VIII (―Excessive bail shall not be required, nor excessive
    fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments inflicted.‖),
    with UTAH CONST. art. I, § 9 (―Excessive bail shall not be required;
    excessive fines shall not be imposed; nor shall cruel and unusual
    punishments be inflicted. Persons arrested or imprisoned shall not
    be treated with unnecessary rigor.‖).
    76
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                          A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    toward a prohibition of modes of punishment that are
    unprecedented in their barbarous nature.
    a. The English origins of protection against
    ―cruel and unusual punishments‖
    ¶ 168 I do not doubt that the ―maxim that the punishment
    must fit the crime‖ is a matter ―foundational‖ to any ―reasoned
    system of criminal justice.‖ Infra ¶ 214. But the question presented
    does not concern the wisdom or general applicability of this
    ―venerable principle,‖ infra ¶ 214, as a matter of aspirational
    public policy. Instead, the question is whether and to what extent
    this principle is incorporated in the terms of the Cruel and
    Unusual Punishments Clause. And that question must be
    answered by reference to the original meaning of the operative
    terms of the constitution.
    ¶ 169 The quest for original meaning is not simply a search
    for deeply embedded historical values. Again, the premise of
    originalism is not that a dusty tome is more worthy of respect
    than a modern one, but that a written constitution is aimed at
    cementing established principles in place unless and until they are
    repealed or amended. See supra ¶¶ 148–152. So the venerable
    historical sources cited in the dissent—see infra ¶¶ 214–15 (quoting
    the Code of Hammurabi, Leviticus, Plato, and Cicero)—are
    ultimately beside the point. The fact that sages of centuries past
    embraced proportionality in sentencing tells us little about the
    doctrine embedded in the U.S. Constitution in 1789, or the Utah
    Constitution in 1896. (And, in any event, the quoted provisions
    speak only to general aspirational policy of proportionality in
    criminal punishment; we undoubtedly have long embraced that
    general policy in the United States, but that doesn‘t mean that our
    constitutional law requires our judges to enforce such a principle
    as against legislatively endorsed punishments.)
    ¶ 170 To derive an original understanding of the constitution,
    we must consider its text and legal underpinnings. The Cruel and
    Unusual Punishments Clause borrows terms and concepts from
    the English Bill of Rights. Compare An Act Declaring the Rights
    and Liberties of the Subject and Settling the Succession of the
    Crown, 1 W. & M., 2d sess., ch. 2 (Dec. 16, 1689) (―That excessive
    bail ought not be required, nor excessive fines imposed, nor cruel
    and unusual punishments inflicted.‖), with U.S. CONST. amend.
    VIII (―Excessive bail shall not be required, nor excessive fines
    77
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments inflicted.‖). So the
    starting point for any historical study of the Eighth Amendment is
    an inquiry into the understanding of that provision that prevailed
    historically.
    ¶ 171 In its initial invocations of the principle of
    proportionality, the United States Supreme Court proceeded in
    open disdain for the original meaning of the Eighth Amendment.
    In Weems v. United States, for example, the Court openly
    acknowledged that it was embracing a ―progressive‖ legal
    standard that was ―not fastened to the 
    obsolete.‖ 217 U.S. at 378
    .
    Thus, far from attempting to connect up its view with original
    meaning, the Weems Court endorsed a principle that could
    ―acquire meaning as public opinion becomes enlightened by a
    humane justice.‖ 
    Id. Trop v.
    Dulles, 
    356 U.S. 86
    (1958), is to the
    same effect. There the Court formulated the principle endorsed by
    the dissent in this case—a proportionality inquiry rooted in
    ―evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a
    maturing society.‖ Infra ¶ 213 (quoting 
    Trop, 356 U.S. at 101
    ).
    ¶ 172 More recent decisions give at least a nod to history. In
    Solem v. Helm, a majority of the Supreme Court purported to base
    its standard of proportionality on an original understanding of the
    Eighth 
    Amendment. 463 U.S. at 284
    ; see infra ¶ 218 (citing Solem
    for the proposition that ―the Eighth Amendment‘s explicit
    prohibitions of ‗[e]xcessive bail‘ and ‗excessive fines‘ must extend
    to bar excessive terms of imprisonment‖). But the Solem court‘s
    textual and historical analysis was sparse. While invoking the
    English Bill of Rights, the Solem court gave no consideration to
    that provision‘s differential treatment of ―bail‖ and ―fines,‖ on
    one hand, and ―punishments inflicted,‖ on the other. Nor did it
    examine historical practice in England under this provision in
    pursuit of any serious assessment of the question whether the
    standard of excessiveness (as applied to bail and fines) had been
    extended more broadly to ―punishments.‖ Instead, the Solem court
    simply cited historical precedent of the English courts in
    condemning ―a ‗fine of thirty thousand pounds‘‖ as ―‘excessive
    and 
    exorbitant.‘‖ 463 U.S. at 285
    (emphasis added) (quoting Earl of
    Devon’s Case, 11 State Trials 133, 136 (1689)). And, from there, the
    Solem court blithely asserted that the Eighth Amendment must
    have ―adopted the English principle of proportionality,‖ which it
    presumed would extend to punishments in the form of prison
    sentences. 
    Id. at 285–86.
    78
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 173 The Solem majority, like the dissent in this case, infra
    ¶ 215, also cited Blackstone in support of its conclusion that the
    Eighth Amendment incorporated a principle of proportionality.
    
    Id. at 285.
    Yet although it is true that Blackstone favored a
    principle under which the designated ―‗punishment ought always
    to be proportioned to the particular purpose it is meant to serve,‘‖
    infra ¶ 215 (quoting 4 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES ON
    THE LAWS OF ENGLAND *12 (facsimile ed. 1979) (1765–69)), the
    quoted provisions simply articulated aspirational legislative policy.
    See 4 
    BLACKSTONE, supra
    at *11 (indicating Blackstone‘s intent
    simply ―to suggest a few hints for the consideration of such as are,
    or may hereafter become, legislators‖). They do not purport to
    limit the discretion of the legislature or to indicate that the
    legislature might lack the power to impose a sentence that a court
    might later deem to be excessive or disproportionate. To the
    contrary, Blackstone went out of his way to emphasize the ―right
    of the legislature in any country to [e]nforce it[]s own laws by the
    death of the transgressor.‖ 
    Id. And he
    even highlighted a key
    element of the case against judicial enforcement of a constitutional
    principle of proportionality—asserting that ―the quantity of
    punishment can never be absolutely determined by any standing
    invariable rule; but it must be left to the arbitration of the
    legislature to inflict such penalties as are warranted by the laws of
    nature and society, and such as appear to be the best calculated to
    answer the end of precaution against future offences.‖ 
    Id. at *12.
       ¶ 174 These and other shortcomings of the originalist case for
    an Eighth Amendment principle of proportionality were
    highlighted in the lead opinion in Harmelin v. Michigan. In
    Harmelin, the lead opinion chides the Solem majority for
    ―assum[ing], with no analysis‖ that the English Declaration of
    Rights‘ prohibition on ―excessive‖ bail and fines extended also to
    
    ―punishments.‖ 501 U.S. at 967
    . And, citing the ―historical context
    and contemporaneous understanding of the English guarantee,‖
    the Harmelin opinion concludes that the excessiveness limitation
    was historically understood to be limited to bail and fines, and
    that the restriction on ―punishments‖ was defined by what was
    ―cruel and unusual‖ in the sense of a form of punishment aimed
    at inflicting pain (―cruel‖) and also contrary to precedent
    (―unusual‖).
    ¶ 175 The Harmelin opinion‘s basis for this conclusion was the
    1685 case of Titus Oates, which was decided the year after the
    79
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    adoption of the English Bill of Rights. Oates was a ―Protestant
    cleric whose false accusations had caused the execution of 15
    prominent Catholics for allegedly organizing a ‗Popish Plot‘ to
    overthrow King Charles II in 1679.‖ 
    Id. at 969.
    Oates was ―tried
    and convicted before the King‘s Bench for perjury.‖ 
    Id. His crime,
    of ―bearing false witness against another, with an express
    premeditated design to take away his life, so as the innocent
    person be condemned and executed,‘ had, at one time, been
    treated as a species of murder, and punished with death.‖ 
    Id. at 969–70.
    Yet
    [a]t sentencing, [Lord Chief Justice] Jeffreys
    complained that death was no longer available as a
    penalty and lamented that ―a proportionable
    punishment of that crime can scarce by our law, as it
    now stands, be inflicted upon him.‖ Second Trial of
    Titus Oates, 10 How. St. Tr. 1227, 1314 (K.B. 1685).
    The law would not stand in the way, however. The
    judges met, and, according to Jeffreys, were in
    unanimous agreement that ―crimes of this nature are
    left to be punished according to the discretion of this
    court, so far as that the judgment extend not to life or
    member.‖ 
    Ibid. Another justice taunted
    Oates that ―we
    have taken special care of you,‖ 
    id., at 1316.
    The court
    then decreed that he should pay a fine of ―1000 marks
    upon each Indictment,‖ that he should be ―stript of
    [his] Canonical Habits,‖ that he should stand in the
    pillory annually at certain specified times and places,
    that on May 20 he should be whipped by ―the
    common hangman‖ ―from Aldgate to Newgate,‖ that
    he should be similarly whipped on May 22 ―from
    Newgate to Tyburn,‖ and that he should be
    imprisoned for life. 
    Ibid. Harmelin, 501 U.S.
    at 970 (third alteration in original).
    ¶ 176 Oates challenged his sentence in the House of Lords,
    and the Lords‘ opinions form the basis of the Harmelin opinion‘s
    sense of the content of the English Bill of Rights‘ protection
    against ―cruell and unusuall Punishments.‖ 
    Id. ―‗Not a
    single peer
    ventured to affirm that the judgment was legal: but much was
    said about the odious character of the appellant,‘ and the Lords
    affirmed the judgment.‖ 
    Id. ―A minority
    of the Lords dissented,
    however, and their statement sheds light on the meaning of the
    80
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                          A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ‗cruell and unusual Punishments‘ clause.‖ 
    Id. Specifically, as
    the
    lead opinion in Harmelin indicated, the dissenting Lords asserted
    that the King‘s Bench, ―‗being a Temporal Court,‘‖ had no
    authority to divest Oates ―‗of his canonical and priestly Habit‘‖;
    that there was ―‗no Precedent to warrant the Punishments of
    whipping and committing to Prison for Life, for the Crime of
    Perjury‘‖; and that ―‗said Judgments were contrary to Law and
    ancient Practice,‘‖ and thus ―contrary to the Declaration . . . that
    excessive Bail ought not to be required, nor excessive Fines
    imposed, nor cruel nor unusual Punishments afflicted.‘‖ 
    Id. at 971.
         ¶ 177 In further support of this understanding of the English
    Bill of Rights proscription on cruel and unusual punishments, the
    Harmelin opinion also quoted from the discussion in connection
    with a bill passed by the House of Commons, which would have
    annulled Oates‘s sentence. 
    Id. That discussion
    again ―confirm[ed]
    that the ‗cruell and unusuall Punishments‘ clause was directed at
    the Oates case (among others) in particular, and at illegality,
    rather than disproportionality, of punishment in general.‖ 
    Id. ―In all
    these contemporaneous discussions,‖ the Harmelin opinion
    noted that ―a punishment [was] not considered objectionable
    because it [was] disproportionate, but because it [was] ‗out of the
    [Judges‘] Power,‘ contrary to Law and ancient practice,‘ without
    ‗Precedents‘ or ‗express Law to warrant,‘ ‗unusual,‘ ‗illegal,‘ or
    imposed by ‗Pretence to a discretionary Power.‘‖ 
    Id. ―Moreover,‖ the
    opinion noted that ―the phrase ‗cruell and unusuall‘ [was]
    treated as interchangeable with ‗cruel and illegal,‘‖ such that ―the
    ‗illegal and cruell Punishments‘ of the Declaration‘s prologue . . .
    are the same thing as the ‗cruell and unusual Punishments‘ of its
    body.‖ 
    Id. at 973
    (fourth alteration in original).
    ¶ 178 The dissent takes issue with this description of the
    history of Oates‘s trial, highlighting statements in the House of
    Lords that all thought ―such an extravagant Judgment ought not
    to have been given, or a Punishment so exorbitant inflicted on an
    English Subject,‖ or in the House of Commons that members
    described the sentence as ―excessive‖ and ―extravagant.‖ Infra
    ¶ 234. It also cites the work of one legal scholar who has
    concluded, in part based upon his reading of the Oates materials,
    that the ―English Cruell and Unusuall Punishments Clause was
    originally understood to prohibit new punishments that were
    excessive in light of prior practice.‖ Infra ¶ 233 (quoting John F.
    Stinneford, Rethinking Proportionality Under the Cruel and Unusual
    81
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    Punishments Clause, 97 VA. L. REV. 899, 937 (2011)). There are
    several problems with the dissent‘s take on the Oates case.
    ¶ 179 First, it is not true that Oates‘s punishment was
    ―unprecedented in its severity,‖ as the dissent puts it. Infra ¶ 234.
    It is simply not the case that parts of Oates‘s sentence (like the
    flogging that would probably have resulted in death) would have
    been seen as disproportionate to his crime—perjury with the
    intent (and the result) of having fifteen innocent people executed.
    See 
    Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 973
    n.4 (Scalia, J.); see also Anthony F.
    Granucci, ―Nor Cruel and Unusual Punishments Inflicted:‖ The
    Original Meaning, 57 CALIF. L. REV. 839, 859 n.97 (1969) (citing 4
    THE DIARY OF JOHN EVELYN 445 (E. DeBeer ed. 1955) (noting
    contemporary opinion that Oates‘s ―punishment was but what he
    well deserved‖)); 3 THOMAS BABINGTON MACAULAY, THE HISTORY
    OF ENGLAND FROM THE ACCESSION OF JAMES II 304 (1898) (noting
    that Oates‘s ―sufferings, great as they might seem, had been
    trifling when compared with his crimes‖). Indeed, the reason
    Lord Chief Justice Jeffreys complained that ―a proportionable
    punishment of that crime can scarce by our law, as it now stands,
    be inflicted upon [Oates],‖ Second Trial of Titus Oates, 10 How. St.
    Tr. 1227, 1314 (K.B. 1685), is that the crime of which Oates was
    convicted used to be punishable by death. See 4 
    BLACKSTONE, supra
    at
    *196 (noting that under ―the antient [sic] common law‖ it was ―a
    species of killing held to be murder‖ to ―bear[] false witness
    against another, with an express premeditated design to take
    away his life, so as the innocent person be condemned and
    executed‖). But such punishment was discontinued and had no
    statutory authorization. Thus, the problem with Oates‘s sentence,
    in the view of the dissenting Lords and the House of Commons,
    was its unusualness or illegality.
    ¶ 180 Second, the Lords‘ and Commons‘ references to
    ―excessive[ness]‖ may well have referred to the 2,000 marks Oates
    was fined, an amount that ―may have been excessive‖ for the time
    period, Granucci, supra at 859, and which was undoubtedly
    subject to the Excessive Fines Clause of the English Bill of Rights.
    See Earl of Devon’s Case, 11 State Trials 133, 136 (1689)
    (condemning a ―fine of thirty thousand pounds‖ as ―excessive
    and exorbitant.‖).
    82
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 181 Finally, scholars and courts have overwhelmingly
    acknowledged that historical ―English practice‖ was generally
    incompatible with a principle of proportionality.210 After all, ―in
    1791, England punished over 200 crimes with death,‖ and even in
    1830 the ―class of offenses punishable by death‖ encompassed
    ―murder; attempts to murder by poisoning, stubbing, shooting
    210  
    Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 974
    (citing Anthony F. Granucci, ―Nor
    Cruel and Unusual Punishments Inflicted:‖ The Original Meaning, 57
    CALIF. L. REV. 839, 847 (1969)); 
    Weems, 217 U.S. at 391
    –93 (White, J.,
    dissenting, joined by Holmes, J.) (―That in England it was
    nowhere deemed that any theory of proportional punishment was
    suggested by the Bill of Rights, or that a protest was thereby
    intended against the severity of punishments, speaking generally,
    is demonstrated by the practice which prevailed in England as to
    punishing crime from the time of the Bill of Rights to the time of
    the American Revolution.‖); In re Bayard, 
    63 How. Pr. 73
    , 77 (N.Y.
    Gen. Term. 1881) (recognizing that the English Bill of Rights
    ―clearly did not then refer to the degree of punishment, for the
    criminal law of England was at that time disgraced by the
    infliction of the very gravest punishment for the slight offenses,
    even petit larceny being then punishable with death‖).
    A principal source for the dissent‘s view of originalism is the
    research of Professor Stinneford. See infra ¶ 233 (citing John F.
    Stinneford, Rethinking Proportionality Under the Cruel and Unusual
    Punishments Clause, 97 VA. L. REV. 899 (2011)). I find Stinneford‘s
    historical analysis helpful on some points, but deem his thesis
    unsupported by the history that he cites. In any event, it should be
    noted that Stinneford does not endorse the freewheeling approach
    to proportionality endorsed by the dissent. See Stinneford, supra at
    917 (criticizing the U.S. Supreme Court‘s ―proportionality
    jurisprudence‖ as arbitrary and noting ―the lack of a workable
    method for measuring the excessiveness of punishment‖); 
    id. at 968
    (―The evolving standards of decency test has proven itself an
    unreliable and ineffective measure of cruelty. [And] [s]ole reliance
    on the Court‘s ‗independent judgment,‘ on the other hand, would
    be standardless and potentially antidemocratic.‖ (footnote
    omitted)); 
    id. at 969
    (arguing for proportionality as determined by
    ―the bounds‖ of the common law and prior practice).
    83
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    etc.; administering poison to procure abortion; sodomy; rape;
    statutory rape, and certain classes of forgery.‖211
    ¶ 182 Thus, the more careful analysis of the English origins of
    the Eighth Amendment indicates an understanding in line with
    the terms and structure of article I, section 9—that it did not
    impose a principle of proportionality, but only a limitation on
    ―cruel‖ forms of punishment that were ―unusual‖ in the sense of
    being unauthorized by past precedent.
    b. Original understanding of the Eighth Amendment
    ¶ 183 This conclusion is also confirmed by the practice and
    debate that prevailed in the United States at or around the time of
    the federal framing. In state conventions leading to the ratification
    of the United States Constitution, for example, an objection was
    raised that the Constitution (then without a Bill of Rights)
    ―nowhere restrained‖ Congress ―from inventing the most cruel
    and unheard-of punishments, and annexing them to crimes.‖
    2 JONATHAN ELLIOT, DEBATES OF THE FEDERAL CONSTITUTION 111
    (2d ed. 1854). And, in context, the reference to such ―cruel and
    unheard-of punishments‖ was not about proportionality, but
    about form—a concern that without such a ―constitutional check,‖
    Congress might be inclined to turn to cruel punishments such as
    ―racks and gibbets,‖ which ―may be amongst the most mild
    instruments‖ imaginable. Id.212
    
    211Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 975
    (citing 1 JAMES FITZJAMES STEPHEN,
    A HISTORY OF THE CRIMINAL LAW OF ENGLAND 490 (1883), and
    noting that ―during his discussion of English capital punishment
    reform, Stephen does not once mention the Cruell and Unusuall
    Punishments Clause, though he was certainly aware of it,‖ and
    also that ―in his discussion of the suitability of punishments,
    Blackstone [likewise] does not mention the Declaration‖).
    212 See also 3 ELLIOT, supra at 447 (Patrick Henry, in the Virginia
    Convention, speaking of the concern that without a prohibition
    against ―cruel and unusual punishments,‖ like that set forth in the
    Virginia Bill of Rights, Congress could ―loose the restriction of not
    . . . inflicting cruel and unusual punishments,‖ by allowing
    ―tortures, or cruel and barbarous punishment‖); 
    Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 979
    –80 (citing and discussing these sources).
    84
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                              A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 184 ―The actions of the First Congress, which are of course
    persuasive evidence of what the Constitution means, belie any
    doctrine of proportionality.‖ 
    Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 980
    (opinion of
    Scalia, J.) (citation omitted). After all, ―[s]hortly after proposing
    the Bill of Rights, the First Congress‖ extended the punishment of
    ―death by hanging‖ on a range of crimes, including ―forgery of
    United States securities, ‗run[ning] away with [a] ship or vessel, or
    any goods or merchandise to the value of fifty dollars,‘ treason,
    and murder on the high seas.‖ 
    Id. at 980–81
    (second and third
    alterations in original) (quoting 1 Stat. 114). Significantly, ―[t]he
    law books of the time are devoid of indication that anyone
    considered these newly enacted penalties unconstitutional by
    virtue of their disproportionality.‖ 
    Id. at 981.
        ¶ 185 Early American legal commentary is along the same
    lines. One commentator spoke of ―[t]he prohibition of cruel and
    unusual punishments‖ as ―mark[ing] the improved spirit of the
    age, which would not tolerate the use of the rack or stake, or any
    of those horrid modes of torture, devised by human ingenuity for
    the gratification of fiendish passion.‖ JAMES BAYARD, A BRIEF
    EXPOSITION OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES 154 (2d ed.
    1840). Another spoke of the Eighth Amendment‘s Cruel and
    Unusual Punishments Clause as prohibiting ―[t]he various
    barbarous and cruel punishments inflicted under the laws of some
    other countries,‖ such as ―[b]reaking on the wheel, flaying alive,
    rendering asunder with horses, [and] various species of horrible
    tortures inflicted in the inquisition,‖ such as ―maiming, mutilating
    and scourging to death.‖ BENJAMIN L. OLIVER, THE RIGHTS OF AN
    AMERICAN CITIZEN 186 (1832).213
    213   See   also   3
    JOSEPH STORY, COMMENTARIES ON THE
    CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES § 1896 (1833) (asserting that
    the Eighth Amendment was ―adopted as an admonition to all
    departments of the national government, to warn them against
    such violent proceedings, as had taken place in England in the
    arbitrary reigns of some of the Stuarts‖ (emphasis added));
    
    Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 981
    –82 (discussing these and other
    commentaries, and concluding that they ―contain[] no reference to
    disproportionate or excessive sentences‖ and indicate that the
    Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause was understood as
    ―designed to outlaw particular modes of punishment‖).
    85
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 186 This commentary confirms what is indicated by the
    other historical sources cited above: The federal Cruel and
    Unusual Punishments Clause was widely understood not to
    prescribe an assessment of proportionality, but simply to prohibit
    modes of punishment that were ―cruel‖ in the sense of being
    barbaric and ―unusual‖ in the sense of being unprecedented.
    c. The public understanding at the time of the Utah framing
    ¶ 187 This same understanding of ―cruel and unusual
    punishments‖ prevailed at the time of the framing of the Utah
    Constitution. Thus, even if there were doubt about the original
    meaning of the federal Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause,
    the question presented here would yield a straightforward
    answer: Article I, section 9, as originally adopted in 1896, is not a
    license for judicial assessment of the proportionality of criminal
    punishment; it is merely a prohibition of modes of punishment
    that are unprecedented in their barbarousness or tendency to
    inflict pain.
    ¶ 188 State and federal courts consistently conceived of the
    constitutional prohibition of cruel and unusual punishments in
    this way,214 often expressly rejecting the type of proportionality
    214 State v. Williams, 
    77 Mo. 310
    , 312–13 (1883) (holding that
    cruel and unusual does not refer to prison sentences as a mode of
    punishment but only to ―such punishments as amount to torture‖
    such as ―drawing and quartering‖ or ―burning him at the stake‖);
    People ex rel. Kemmler v. Durston, 
    7 N.Y.S. 813
    , 815 (Sup. Ct. Gen.
    Term 1889) (holding that the provision bans modes of punishment
    that ―involve torture and a lingering death‖); In re Kemmler,
    
    7 N.Y.S. 145
    , 149–50 (Co. Ct. 1889) (―[I]t is clearly not against
    [death as a mode of punishment] that the constitution is directed‖
    rather it extends to punishments such as ―crucifixion, boiling in
    water, oil, or lead, blowing from cannon‘s mouth, burning,
    breaking on the wheel, dismemberment, [and] burying alive.‖);
    James v. Commonwealth, 
    12 Serg. & Rawle 220
    , 235 (Pa. 1825)
    (holding that ―the ducking-stool‖ was an illegal punishment
    under ―the humane provisions of the constitutions of the United
    Sates and of [Pennsylvania], as to cruel and unusual
    punishments‖); Ligan v. State, 
    50 Tenn. 159
    , 164 (1871) (upholding
    KKK member‘s conviction and sentence ―for feloniously prowling
    (con‘t.)
    86
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                            A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    analysis advocated by the dissent.215 Throughout the nineteenth
    century, the courts generally understood the prohibition of ―cruel
    and travelling in disguise‖ and holding that ―imprisonment in the
    penitentiary for a longer period, ten to twenty year . . . is neither
    cruel nor unusual, in the sense of the Constitution‖ (internal
    quotation marks omitted)).
    215 See, e.g., Whitten v. State, 
    47 Ga. 297
    , 300–01 (1872) (rejecting
    defendant‘s       argument       that    sentence     was      ―entirely
    disproportionate to the nature and character of the offense‖ and
    holding that ―[s]o long as [legislators] do not provide cruel and
    unusual punishments, such as disgraced the civilization of former
    ages, and make one shudder with horror to read of them, as
    drawing, quartering, burning, etc., the Constitution does not put
    any limit upon legislative discretion‖); State v. White, 
    25 P. 33
    , 35
    (Kan. 1890) (concluding that despite the extreme severity of a
    statutory rape punishment, the court could not ―say that the
    statute is void for that reason‖ and that ―[i]mprisonment in the
    penitentiary at hard labor is not of itself a cruel or unusual
    punishment,‖ but that the Kansas Cruel and Unusual Punishments
    Clause ―relates to the kind of punishment to be inflicted, and not to its
    duration‖ (emphases added)); Foote v. State, 
    59 Md. 264
    , 266–68
    (1883) (upholding defendant‘s sentence jail and lashing because
    ―the people who made [the Maryland] Constitution, and who
    must be presumed to understand the meaning of the terms they
    use, have, from the time these words were first incorporated, in
    1776 down to 1882,‖ never considered ―the punishment of
    whipping‖ to be ―a ‗cruel or unusual punishment‘‖ and that the
    court was ―not dealing with the expediency, justice, or efficacy of
    this punishment, but only with the true interpretation of the terms
    of the Constitution‖); Cummins v. People, 
    3 N.W. 305
    , 305 (Mich.
    1879) (rejecting the argument that a sentence was ―unusually
    severe, and that, in the light of all the facts, it was in violation of
    [the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause,]‖ and holding ―[t]he
    sentence was not in excess of that permitted by statute, and when
    within the statute this court has no supervising control over the
    punishment that shall be inflicted.‖ (emphasis added)); State v.
    Borgstrom, 
    72 N.W. 799
    , 803–04 (Minn. 1897) (rejecting claim that a
    prison sentence ―was altogether disproportionate to the offense
    charged‖ and therefore ―cruel [and] unusual‖ under the state
    (con‘t.)
    87
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    and unusual punishments‖ as a limitation on barbaric methods of
    punishment, while emphasizing that the length of a prison term
    was a matter for legislative discretion.216 In the words of the
    constitution and holding that the punishments ―prohibited by our
    constitution‖ are the ―cruel‖ and ―inhuman‖ punishments such as
    ―loading him with weights,‖ ―drown[ing], disembowel[ment],‖ or
    being ―sewed up in a leather sack with a live dog, a cock, a viper,
    and an ape, and cast into the sea‖); Territory v. Ketchum, 
    10 N.M. 718
    , 718 (1901) (expressing ―great doubt,‖ based on the then-state
    of constitutional law that ―the courts, in any case, have the power
    to review legislative discretion in determining the severity of
    punishment for crime, so long as all forms of torture have been
    avoided‖); Garcia v. Territory, 
    1 N.M. 415
    , 417–19 (1869)
    (upholding sentence of lashing for stealing a mule on the grounds
    that cruel and unusual punishment has reference only to ―the
    process of torture‖ and that it was otherwise ―never designed to
    abridge or limit the selection by the law-making power of such
    kind of punishment as was deemed most effective in the
    punishment and suppression of crime‖); People ex rel. Kemmler v.
    Durston, 
    24 N.E. 6
    , 8 (N.Y. 1890) (―We entertain no doubt in regard
    to the power of the legislature to change the manner of inflicting
    the penalty of death. The general power of the legislature over
    crimes, and its power to define and punish the crime of murder, is
    not and cannot be disputed.‖); State v. Hogan, 
    63 Ohio St. 202
    , 218
    (1900) (―Imprisonment at hard labor is neither cruel nor unusual.
    It may be severe, in the given instance, but that is a question for
    the lawmaking power.‖); State v. Woodward, 
    69 S.E. 385
    , 388–89
    (W. Va. 1910) (holding that ―cruel and unusual punishment‖ does
    ―not affect legislation providing imprisonment for life or years‖
    and that it only applies to ―inhuman, barbarous inflictions‖ but
    nonetheless engaging in proportionality review under the state‘s
    Proportional Punishments Clause).
    216  See Commonwealth v. Hitchings, 
    71 Mass. 482
    , 486 (1855)
    (affirming sentence involving a fine and imprisonment for
    unlawful sale of intoxicating liquor and explaining that the length
    of imprisonment is a matter ―for the legislature to determine‖);
    Barker v. People, 
    20 Johns. 457
    , 459 (N.Y. 1823) (affirming
    punishment of disenfranchisement on conviction of dueling,
    rejecting challenge on cruel and unusual punishments grounds
    (con‘t.)
    88
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                             A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts, ―[t]he question whether
    the punishment is too severe, and disproportionate to the offense,
    is for the legislature to determine.‖217
    ¶ 189 This view prevailed throughout the nineteenth century,
    including in the decade in which our Utah Constitution was
    adopted. An exemplary decision was Hobbs v. State, 
    32 N.E. 1019
    (Ind. 1893). In that case, the Indiana Supreme Court explained that
    ―[t]he word ‗cruel,‘ when considered in relation to the time when
    it found place in the bill of rights, meant, not a fine or
    imprisonment, or both, but such as that inflicted at the whipping
    post, in the pillory, burning at the stake, breaking on the wheel,
    etc.‖ 
    Id. at 1021.
    And, importantly, the Hobbs court went on to
    conclude that the prohibition of ―cruel and unusual punishments‖
    ―does not affect legislation providing imprisonment for life or for
    years.‖ Id.218
    while explaining that ―[t]he disfranchisement of a citizen is not an
    unusual punishment; it was the consequence of treason, and of
    infamous crimes, and it was altogether discretionary in the
    legislature to extend that punishment to other offences‖); Aldridge
    v. Commonwealth, 4 Va. (2 Va. Cas.) 447, 449–50 (Va. Gen. Ct. 1824)
    (upholding sentence on conviction of larceny; rejecting challenge
    under the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause of Virginia
    Declaration of Rights, and explaining that the clause ―was never
    designed to control the Legislative right to determine ad libitum
    upon the adequacy of punishment, but is merely applicable to the
    modes of punishment‖); see also Pervear v. Massachusetts, 
    72 U.S. 475
    , 480 (1866) (upholding sentence involving fine of $50 and
    imprisonment at hard labor for three months on charge of
    maintaining a ―tenement for the illegal sale and illegal keeping of
    intoxicating liquors‖; holding that Eighth Amendment did not
    ―apply to State but to National legislation,‖ while also opining, in
    dicta, that there was ―nothing excessive, or cruel, or unusual‖ in
    this punishment given that the matter was ―wholly within the
    discretion of State legislatures‖).
    217   
    Hitchings, 71 Mass. at 486
    .
    218 See also People v. Smith, 
    54 N.W. 487
    , 487, 488 (Mich. 1893)
    (affirming sentence of five-year term of imprisonment for crime of
    receiving stolen property ―of the value of one dollar‖; rejecting
    (con‘t.)
    89
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ¶ 190 This same approach was reflected in legal commentary
    in the era. ―Punishments‖ were understood as ―cruel when they
    involve[d] torture or a lingering death.‖ 3 BOUVIER‘S LAW
    DICTIONARY 2771 (8th ed. 1914). On the question of ―[w]hat
    punishment is suited to a specified offence,‖ moreover, the
    prevailing view was that that matter ―must in general be
    determined by the legislature.‖ 
    Id. Thus, a
    ―[s]entence for a term
    not exceeding that prescribed by statute‖ was not ―regarded as a
    cruel or unusual punishment.‖ 
    Id. ¶ 191
    It may be a bit of an overstatement to say that the
    nineteenth-century view of the courts on this point was
    ―universal.‖ See 
    Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 984
    (opinion of Scalia, J.)
    (articulating this view); 
    Weems, 217 U.S. at 402
    (White, J.,
    dissenting) (same). At or around the time the Utah Constitution
    was adopted, some courts had endorsed the view that the
    constitutional prohibition of cruel and unusual punishments
    encompassed a standard of review for proportionality of prison
    terms.219 And at least a couple of legal treatises had begun to
    challenge to sentence on the ground that it was ―cruel and
    unusual‖ punishment, particularly in light of the fact that the thief
    himself could only have been sentenced to imprisonment for one
    year; explaining that ―[u]pon the legislature alone is conferred the
    power to fix the minimum and maximum of the punishment for
    all crimes,‖ and that a ―law which provides a greater maximum
    penalty for receiving stolen property than for the larceny of it
    cannot be held to authorize cruel and unusual punishment‖);
    Jackson v. United States, 
    102 F. 473
    , 487 (9th Cir. 1900) (―The general
    rule is well settled that the sentence and punishment imposed
    upon a defendant for any violation of the provisions of the statute,
    which is within the punishment provided for by the statute,
    cannot be regarded as excessive, cruel, or unusual.‖).
    219 See O’Neil v. Vermont, 
    144 U.S. 323
    , 339–40 (1892) (Field, J.,
    dissenting) (asserting that the Eighth Amendment is ―directed,
    not only against punishments‖ of a barbarous or unduly painful
    nature, but also ―against all punishments which by their excessive
    length or severity are greatly disproportioned to the offenses
    charged‖); McDonald v. Commonwealth, 
    53 N.E. 874
    , 875 (Mass.
    1899) (―[I]t is possible that imprisonment in the state prison for a
    long term of years might be so disproportionate to the offense as
    (con‘t.)
    90
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                             A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    embrace this view.220 But in light of the extensive authority cited
    above, this approach would surely have been seen by our Utah
    framers as aberrational.
    ¶ 192 The        dissent    disagrees,  asserting    that     ―the
    preponderance‖ of courts in the nineteenth century adopted the
    approach it takes today. Infra ¶ 244. But in so concluding, the
    dissent ignores—or at least fails to refute or distinguish—a
    significant segment of the body of cases cited above. See supra
    ¶¶ 188–89 & nn.31–35. And in any event the authority it cites does
    not support this conclusion. Before the dissenting opinion in
    O’Neil (1892) and then the majority in Weems (1910), the United
    States Supreme Court had never endorsed proportionality review
    under the Eighth Amendment. Weems and subsequent Supreme
    Court caselaw recognize as much. 
    Weems, 217 U.S. at 378
    (basing
    its holding on a ―progressive‖ legal standard ―not fastened to the
    obsolete‖ but ―acquir[ing] meaning as public opinion becomes
    enlightened by a humane justice‖); Furman v. Georgia, 
    408 U.S. 238
    ,
    at 265–66 (1972) (Brennan, J., concurring) (―Had this historical
    interpretation of the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause
    prevailed, the Clause would have been effectively read out of the
    Bill of Rights. . . . But this Court in Weems decisively repudiated
    the historical interpretation of the Clause‖ (internal quotation
    marks omitted)); 
    id. at 322–25
    (Marshall, J., concurring)
    (concluding that ―the history of the clause clearly establishes that it
    was intended to prohibit cruel punishments,‖ and then noting the
    to constitute a cruel and unusual punishment.‖); State v. Becker, 
    51 N.W. 1018
    , 1022 (S.D. 1892) (―[I]t is certain that it devolves upon
    the legislature to fix the punishment for crime, and that in the
    exercise of their judgment great latitude must be allowed; and the
    courts can reasonably interfere only when the punishment is so
    excessive or so cruel as to meet the disapproval and
    condemnation of the conscience and reason of men generally.‖).
    220 See 3 BOUVIER‘S LAW DICTIONARY 2771 (8th ed. 1914) (―[T]he
    case must be very extraordinary in which [the legislature‘s]
    judgment could be brought in question.‖); OLIVER, supra ¶ 185, at
    186 (asserting that ―imprisonment for an unreasonable length of
    time[] is . . . contrary to the spirit of the constitution . . . [and] must
    be contrary to the intention of the framers of the constitution‖).
    91
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    tide-change in Eighth Amendment law instigated by the O’Neil
    dissent and the Weems majority (emphasis added)). The dissent‘s
    reading of relevant caselaw prior to Weems is, in my view, in error.
    ¶ 193 The dissent derides my reading of Pervear as ―unduly
    strained‖ and somehow meant to sustain the proposition that the
    Supreme Court ―was proclaiming the punishments imposed by
    statute to be immune from constitutional review.‖ Supra ¶ 239.
    First, I am not claiming that a legislative enactment can never be
    cruel and unusual. And no court ever held any such thing.221
    Instead, my point is simply that the prohibition on ―cruel and
    unusual punishments‖ goes to the barbarousness or torturousness
    of the punishment, and not to the length of the term of
    confinement. Second, my reading of Pervear is hardly ―strained‖;
    the Court in that case did hold that ―[t]he mode adopted‖ to
    punish a crime ―is wholly within the discretion of State
    legislatures.‖ 
    Pervear, 72 U.S. at 480
    . Third, it is the dissent that
    stretches the scope of Pervear beyond what it bears by concluding
    that the Court ―implicitly recognized its understanding that
    excessive punishments may be cruel and unusual punishments.‖
    Infra ¶ 238. There is little question why the Court indicated that it
    ―perceive[d] nothing excessive, or cruel, or unusual‖ in Pervear‘s
    sentence. 
    Pervear, 72 U.S. at 480
    . Pervear had argued that the ―fines
    and penalties imposed and inflicted by the State law‖ were
    ―excessive, cruel, and unusual.‖ 
    Id. at 479
    (emphasis added). And
    221 For this reason, the dissent‘s critique of cases like Jackson v.
    United States, infra ¶ 246 n.2 also misses its mark. Neither my
    opinion nor any case upon which it relies ever claimed to
    ―support the extreme proposition that a statute could never
    prescribe a cruel and unusual punishment.‖ Infra ¶ 246 n.2. See,
    e.g., 
    Whitten, 47 Ga. at 301
    (―So long as [legislators] do not provide
    cruel and unusual punishments, such as disgraced the civilization
    of former ages, and make one shudder with horror to read of
    them, as drawing, quartering, burning, etc., the Constitution does
    not put any limit upon legislative discretion.‖); 
    Ketchum, 10 N.M. at 718
    (―It would, indeed, seem to be a matter of great doubt, in
    view of the foregoing expressions of opinion on this subject,
    whether the courts, in any case, have the power to review
    legislative discretion in determining the severity of punishment
    for crime, so long as all forms of torture have been avoided.‖).
    92
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    because the Eighth Amendment expressly prohibits ―excessive
    fines,‖ the quoted language in Pervear is simply a nod to the
    distinction between bail and fines on the one hand and
    punishments on the other.222
    ¶ 194 Of the various cases cited by the dissent purportedly
    establishing the authority of the judiciary to overturn a
    disproportionate sentence, only two of them actually overturned a
    prisoner‘s sentence. See State ex rel. Garvey v. Whitaker, 
    19 So. 457
    (La. 1896); State v. Driver, 
    78 N.C. 423
    (1878). Of the others,
    moreover, none are of any material aid to its thesis. At least one of
    the cited cases appears to be applying proportionality analysis to
    a fine,223 which is expressly subject to the Excessive Fines Clause.
    And in other cases, the courts ultimately upheld the sentence
    under review and alluded to proportionality only as a matter of
    arguendo dicta. In McDonald v. Commonwealth, for example, the
    Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts merely allowed that ―it
    is possible that imprisonment in the state prison for a long term of
    years might be so disproportionate to the offense as to constitute a
    cruel and unusual punishment,‖ while ultimately upholding the
    sentence in question. 
    53 N.E. 874
    , 875 (Mass. 1899) (emphasis
    added).224 The Vermont Supreme Court‘s approach in State v. Four
    222  See State v. Sheppard, 
    32 S.E. 146
    , 148 (S.C. 1899) (―[W]e
    certainly cannot say that such a fine was ‗excessive,‘ or that the
    punishment inflicted was either ‗cruel or unusual.‘‖); Ex parte
    Keeler, 
    23 S.E. 865
    , 868 (S.C. 1896) (―[T]he fine imposed on the
    defendant was not excessive, nor the punishment inflicted cruel
    and unusual.‖).
    223 In re MacDonald, 
    33 P. 18
    , 21 (Wyo. 1893) (explaining that
    the phrase cruel and unusual punishments was aimed ―to prevent
    the imposition of obsolete, painful, and degrading punishments,‖
    and then holding that ―[w]e do not think that the fine imposed upon
    the petitioner by the trial court was excessive, nor the punishment
    growing out of the failure to pay, or secured to be paid, that fine,
    is cruel or unusual‖ (emphasis added)).
    224Even this dictum, moreover, represented a clear departure
    from prior practice. See Sturtevant v. Commonwealth, 
    33 N.E. 648
    ,
    649 (Mass. 1893) (holding that the ―cruel or unusual‖
    punishments clause applied to ―courts, not to the legislature‖);
    (con‘t.)
    93
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    Jugs of Intoxicating Liquor is along similar lines. 
    2 A. 586
    (Vt. 1886).
    There the court simply acknowledged that ―[i]f the penalty were
    unreasonably severe for a single offense, the constitutional
    question might be urged,‖ again while upholding the sentence in
    question. 
    Id. at 59
    3 (second emphasis added).
    ¶ 195 And finally, other cases cited by the dissent cut sharply
    against its position—notwithstanding the dissent‘s attempts to
    discredit them. People v. Smith, 
    54 N.W. 487
    (Mich. 1893),
    unequivocally stated that ―the legislature alone‖ had ―the power
    to fix the minimum and maximum of the punishment for all
    crimes.‖ 
    Id. at 488.
    The dissent views this decision as undermined
    by a case handed down ―just two years later‖—People v. Whitney,
    
    63 N.W. 765
    , 766 (Mich. 1895). Infra ¶ 246. But the Whitney court‘s
    reference to ―cases‖ that ―might arise when the punishment
    imposed by an act is so cruel and unusual that the courts would
    interfere and protect the rights of the party,‖ 
    id., is entirely
    consistent with the original meaning of the principle of cruel and
    unusual punishments as I understand it. The referenced ―cases,‖
    after all, could easily be aimed at encompassing the imposition of
    barbarous modes of punishment.
    ¶ 196 Aldridge v. Commonwealth, 4 Va. (2 Va. Cas.) 447, 449
    (Va. Gen. Ct. 1824), also undermines the dissent‘s view. And the
    case cannot properly be dismissed on the ―racial animus‖ grounds
    charged by the dissent. Infra ¶¶ 248–49. Granted, an element of
    the Aldridge court‘s analysis was based on the notion that the Bill
    of Rights did not apply to African Americans. 
    Aldridge, 4 Va. at 449
    . But the court also articulated an alternative—and
    legitimate—ground: It expressly held that the Cruel and Unusual
    Punishments Clause ―[had no] bearing on th[e] case‖ because the
    provision did not ―control the right to determine . . . the adequacy
    of the punishment, but [wa]s merely applicable to the modes of
    punishment.‖ 
    Id. at 450.
    And, in the subsequent case of
    Commonwealth v. Wyatt, 27 Va. (6 Rand.) 694 (Gen. Ct. 1828), it is
    simply not true—as the dissent charges—that the court held that
    ―sentencing judges were constitutionally restrained from
    
    Hitchings, 71 Mass. at 486
    (―The question whether the punishment
    is too severe, and disproportionate to the offence, is for the
    legislature to determine.‖).
    94
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    sentencing an individual to an excessive number of stripes.‖ Infra
    ¶ 249. Instead, the court concluded that ―[t]he punishment of
    offences by stripes is certainly odious, but cannot be said to be
    unusual.‖ 
    Wyatt, 27 Va. at 701
    . Thus, as far as the discretion of the
    lower court went, it was restrained by ―the discretion always
    exercised by Common Law Courts to inflict fine and
    imprisonment.‖ 
    Id. Accordingly, in
    the same way that Titus
    Oates‘s sentence of flogging multiple times (such that he was
    effectively sentenced to death for a noncapital crime) was illegal
    (unauthorized by statute or common law), so too would a Virginia
    judge be constrained in sentencing someone who operated an
    illegal card game from being lashed so many times that he was
    effectively sentenced to ―death produced by the most cruel
    torture.‖ 
    Id. at 700.
    This analysis is entirely consistent with the
    approach outlined in this opinion. The court confirmed that the
    constitutional restraint was on the mode and legality of the
    punishment and sentence, not a subjective assessment of
    proportionality.
    ¶ 197 Further support for this view can be found in the most
    prominent cruel and unusual punishment case out of Utah in the
    late nineteenth century, People v. Wilkinson, 
    2 Utah 158
    (Utah Terr.
    1877), aff’d sub nom Wilkerson v. Utah, 
    99 U.S. 130
    , 136 (1878). This
    case arose out of a conviction of first-degree murder and a
    sentence of death. The issue on appeal concerned the legality of
    the sentence of death—specifically, the proviso imposed by the
    trial judge that Wilkinson be executed by being ―publicly 
    shot.‖ 2 Utah at 159
    . In challenging that sentence, Wilkinson asserted
    that the judge‘s determination of the ―mode‖ of execution was a
    violation of Utah territorial statutes, the common law, and the
    Eighth Amendment of the U.S. Constitution. On that latter point,
    the Territorial Supreme Court affirmed, in terms in line with the
    approach set forth above:
    The question . . . presents itself: ―Is the manner
    designated in the case before us, that of death by
    shooting, a cruel and unusual punishment?‖ We do
    not think the appellant so considers it, nor do we
    think he could. It is the mode adopted for the army
    in enforcing discipline; it is a mode recognized and
    practised in other civilized countries to enforce
    criminal laws; and, as we have seen, it was approved
    by express statute of this Territory for nearly a
    95
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    quarter of a century, and as history tells us, it is the
    manner of death of which criminals in this Territory
    made choice in preference to other modes, such as
    hanging and beheading. That manner cannot be
    cruel which criminals prefer, and that cannot be
    unusual which is often adopted.
    
    Id. at 164.
        ¶ 198 The Wilkinson court‘s approach is entirely in line with
    the historically accepted view outlined above. Instead of assessing
    the proportionality or excessiveness of the punishment, the
    Wilkinson court‘s analysis deems the element of ―cruel[ty]‖ to go
    to the ―manner‖ of punishment, and that of ―unusual[ness]‖ to be
    addressed to the extent to which a punishment is ―adopted‖ by
    law and common practice.
    ¶ 199 The United States Supreme Court‘s decision affirming
    the Territorial Supreme Court is even clearer. Far from assessing
    proportionality or excessiveness, the Supreme Court directed its
    consideration of ―cruelty‖ to methods of punishment involving
    ―torture,‖ or in other words ―terror, pain, or disgrace.‖ 
    Wilkerson, 99 U.S. at 135
    . Thus, in affirming the sentence of death by firing
    squad, the Supreme Court made reference to modes of barbarous
    punishment such as ―where the prisoner was drawn or dragged to
    the place of execution,‖ or ―where he was embowelled alive,
    beheaded, and quartered.‖ 
    Id. And in
    conceptualizing ―the extent
    of the constitutional provision which provides that cruel and
    unusual punishments shall not be inflicted,‖ the Supreme Court
    held ―that punishments of torture . . . and all others in the same
    line of unnecessary cruelty, are forbidden by that emendment [sic]
    to the Constitution.‖ 
    Id. at 136.
    Because ―[n]othing of the kind‖
    was involved in this case, the Supreme Court affirmed, rejecting
    ―the theory . . . that the court possessed no authority to prescribe
    the mode of execution‖ while holding that ―death by shooting‖
    was by no means cruel and unusual punishment. 
    Id. at 136–37.
        ¶ 200 I suppose it‘s true that the Wilkerson decision did not
    ―define with exactness the [full] extent‖ of the Eighth
    Amendment, but held only that ―punishments of torture . . . are
    forbidden‖ by it. Infra ¶ 242 (quoting 
    Wilkerson, 99 U.S. at 136
    ).
    But the quoted statements are the sum and substance of the
    court‘s analysis of the Eighth Amendment, and they make no
    reference to proportionality. And in any event, any doubts about
    96
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                            A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    Wilkerson were resolved in In re Kemmler, 
    136 U.S. 436
    (1890),
    which unequivocally held that ―[p]unishments are cruel when they
    involve torture or a lingering death; but the punishment of death is not
    cruel within the meaning of that word as used in the constitution.
    It implies something inhuman and barbarous,—something more
    than the mere extinguishment of life.‖ 
    Id. at 447
    (emphasis added).
    ¶ 201 This was the prevailing public understanding of ―cruel
    and unusual punishments‖ at the time of the framing of the Utah
    Constitution. As the author of the dissenting opinion today
    opined previously, ―[l]egal scholars and jurists continued to
    accept this understanding of the phrase [‗cruel and unusual‘]
    throughout the nineteenth century despite occasional attempts to
    expand the cruel and unusual punishments clause to prohibit
    punishments deemed disproportionate to the crime.‖ State v.
    Gardner, 
    947 P.2d 630
    , 636 (Utah 1997) (Durham, J., plurality
    opinion) (citing Granucci, supra at 842). At that time a few isolated
    judges and commentators had alluded to a theory of
    constitutional review for proportionality, but the overwhelming
    majority view was to the contrary—foreclosing only those
    barbarous methods of punishment rejected by law and common
    practice. And the majority approach had been endorsed by our
    Territorial Supreme Court in an opinion affirmed by the U.S.
    Supreme Court.
    3. History of Article I, Section 9
    ¶ 202 The history of article I, section 9 supports this same
    construction. As the dissent indicates, proposed constitutions for
    the State of Deseret (a series of them, from 1849 to 1872) broadly
    provided that ―[a]ll penalties and punishments shall be in
    proportion to the offence.‖ DESERET CONST. art. VII, § 8; infra
    ¶ 216. But this general proviso never became law. By the time we
    became a state, the people of Utah had abandoned the broad
    principle of proportionality in the proposed Deseret constitutions.
    They adopted instead a provision that limits the excessiveness
    inquiry to the imposition of bail and fines. See UTAH CONST. art. I,
    § 9.
    ¶ 203 The dissent interprets this drafting history to preserve a
    broad principle of proportionality. See infra ¶¶ 216–17 & n.1. I see
    no basis for that conclusion. In light of the plain language of
    article I, section 9, I see no way to conclude that our constitution
    embraced a broad principle of proportionality for ―all penalties
    97
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    and punishments.‖ Instead, I would interpret this provision as
    repudiating the general principle and replacing it with a more
    limited standard (restricting review for excessiveness to bail and
    fines).
    ¶ 204 Other state constitutions—including many in place at
    the time of the founding of this state—embrace the formulation in
    the proposed Deseret provision.225 Many of those provisions
    expressly require proportionality in punishment in addition to
    prohibiting the ―cruel and unusual.‖ And courts interpreted them
    in accordance with their terms. In State v. Woodward, 
    69 S.E. 385
    (W. Va. 1910), for example, the West Virginia Supreme Court
    concluded that its Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause did
    ―not affect legislation providing imprisonment for life or years,‖
    but applied only to ―inhuman, barbarous inflictions.‖ 
    Id. at 388–
    89. Yet the court then went on to examine the propriety of a six
    month to one year prison sentence for violations of ―Sunday‖
    laws, noting the West Virginia Constitution commanded that
    ―[p]enalties shall be proportioned to the character and degree of
    225    See, e.g., GA. CONST. art. I, §§ 16, 21 (1868) (―[N]or shall cruel
    and unusual punishments be inflicted.‖; ―All penalties shall be
    proportioned to the nature of the offence.‖); ILL. CONST. art. II, § 11
    (1870) (―All penalties shall be proportioned to the nature of the
    offense. . . .‖); IND. CONST. art. I, § 16 (1851) (―Excessive bail shall
    not be required. Excessive fines shall not be imposed. Cruel and
    unusual punishments shall not be inflicted. All penalties shall be
    proportioned to the nature of the offense.‖); ME. CONST. art. I, § 9
    (1820) (―Sanguinary laws shall not be passed: all penalties and
    punishments shall be proportioned to the offence: excessive bail
    shall not be required, nor excessive fines imposed, nor cruel nor
    unusual punishments inflicted.‖); NEB. CONST. art. I, § 15 (1875)
    (―All penalties shall be proportioned to the nature of the offense
    . . . .‖); OHIO CONST. art. VIII, §§ 13, 14 (1803) (―Excessive bail shall
    not be required; excessive fines shall not be imposed, nor cruel
    and unusual punishment inflicted. . . . All penalties shall be
    proportioned to the nature of the offense.‖); W. VA. CONST. art. III,
    § 5 (1872) (―Excessive bail shall not be required, nor excessive
    fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments inflicted.
    Penalties shall be proportioned to the character and degree of the
    offence.‖).
    98
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    the offense.‖ 
    Id. at 389.
    Significantly, the court emphasized that
    this provision did not ―refer to the mode of punishment, but to
    the degree, extent, and quality.‖ Id.226 With that background, the
    terms of article I, section 9 as adopted are telling.
    ¶ 205 The formulation in other state constitutions—separately
    requiring that ―[a]ll penalties . . . be proportioned to the nature of
    the offense‖ and prohibiting ―cruel and unusual punishments‖—
    presupposes that the two provisions have independent meaning.
    See, e.g., Hi-Country Prop. Rights Grp. v. Emmer, 
    2013 UT 33
    , ¶ 24,
    
    304 P.3d 851
    (interpreting statute ―under the presumption of
    independent meaning (and/or its converse, the presumption
    against surplusage)‖); Vota v. Ohio Copper Co., 
    129 P. 349
    , 353
    (Utah 1912) (―It is our duty to give effect to every word or phrase
    contained in [a] statute. . . .‖). That alone suggests that the
    prohibition of ―cruel and unusual punishments‖ is something
    other than a requirement of proportionality. It also indicates, by
    implication, that the framers of the Utah Constitution rejected a
    principle of proportionality when they declined to include the
    proportionality provision in article I, section 9.
    ¶ 206 I suppose it is conceivable that the framers of the Utah
    Constitution were aware of the outlier cases identified above—
    cases embracing proportionality review as an element of the
    constitutional prohibition of cruel and unusual punishments. See
    supra ¶ 194 & n.40. But the text our framers adopted strikes me as
    a highly unlikely mode of embracing this aberrational theory.
    And if they had intended to buck the prevailing view in other
    jurisdictions operating under parallel clauses, it seems likely they
    would have addressed the matter openly in debate—as they did
    on other such points of dispute.227 Yet the record of the
    226 The court acknowledged that the words ―cruel and
    unusual‖ had been held to ban imprisonment that was ―too long a
    time,‖ but the only authority the court cited was Weems. State v.
    
    Woodward, 69 S.E. at 389
    .
    227 See 1 OFFICIAL REPORT OF THE PROCEEDINGS AND DEBATES OF
    THE CONVENTION 429–92 (1895) (debates over women‘s suffrage);
    
    id. at 326–38
    (debates over the phrase ―or damaged‖ into the
    Takings Clause); 
    id. at 294–97
    (debates over permitting a jury of
    less than twelve to have less-than-unanimous verdicts in civil
    (con‘t.)
    99
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    constitutional convention is silent on article I, section 9. That is
    significant. It suggests, all other things being equal, that our
    framers were endorsing the prevailing approach to ―cruel and
    unusual punishments,‖ and were not embracing a burgeoning
    theory of proportionality.
    ¶ 207 That conclusion is confirmed by the post-ratification
    history of this provision in the wake of the U.S. Supreme Court‘s
    decision in Weems. The Weems decision was the U.S. Supreme
    Court‘s first articulation of a principle of proportionality under
    the Eighth Amendment of the U.S. 
    Constitution. 217 U.S. at 380
    –
    81. As the popular reaction to Weems indicates, however, that
    decision was hardly viewed as confirming an established view of
    ―cruel and unusual punishments.‖ Instead, Weems was seen as
    working an innovation in constitutional law. And the reaction in
    Utah and elsewhere thoroughly undermines the view that the
    concept of ―cruel and unusual punishments‖ was historically
    understood to encompass a principle of proportionality.
    ¶ 208 Local newspaper reports of the Weems decision in Utah
    noted ―agitat[ion] over the action of the supreme court of the
    United States in inaugurating what is designated as a new era in the
    punishment of criminals—that of requiring punishment to be
    proportionate to the offense.‖ New Era in Criminal Penology
    Commences, SALT LAKE HERALD, at 1 (May 9, 1910) (emphasis
    added).228 That account is impossible to square with the notion of
    cases). Yet virtually nothing about article I, section 9 was said
    during the debates over our constitution. See 
    id. at 257
    (noting the
    reading of article I, section 9, one objection to the Unnecessary
    Rigor Clause, some response to that objection, and the striking of
    that clause).
    228 See also New Era in Criminal Penology Commences, SALT LAKE
    HERALD, at 1 (May 9, 1910) (―The court has determined that the
    eighth amendment is not applicable to the states, and hence the
    states will not be compelled to follow the new principles.‖
    (emphasis added)); Supreme Court Arouses Lawyers, OGDEN
    STANDARD, at 7 (May 9, 1910) (―It was admitted that the
    constitution makers have used this phrase only to prohibit the
    resort to inhuman methods for causing bodily torture. It had been
    used to prevent a return . . . to the English custom of
    (con‘t.)
    100
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                            A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    ―cruel and unusual punishments‖ incorporating a longstanding
    principle of proportionality. If the generation that witnessed the
    framing of the Utah Constitution viewed the Weems decision as
    ―inaugurating a new era . . . in the punishment of criminals,‖ they
    certainly would not have viewed article I, section 9 as embracing
    that principle.229
    ¶ 209 At least one other data point cements this conclusion in
    the specific context of a claim like Houston‘s (challenging the
    imposition of a sentence of life without parole on a juvenile): At
    the time of the framing of the Utah Constitution and for many
    disemboweling traitors and burning alive women who committed
    treason. The court decided to regard these precedents as
    milestones in the advance of civilization and not as limitation on
    the phrase.‖); Criminals and Their Punishment, DESERET EVENING
    NEWS, at 7 (May 9, 1910) (―Much speculation exists as to the effect
    of the decision. . . . Most of the states . . . have provisions in their
    constitutions similar to the eighth amendment and it is believed
    the decision will have a powerful influence in the future
    interpretation of these.‖ (emphasis added)); Penalty Must Fit the
    Crime, SALT LAKE TRIBUNE, at 1–2 (May 9, 1910); Holds Punishment
    Cruel: Supreme Court Orders Release of Convicted Philippine Official,
    N.Y. TIMES, at 4 (May 9, 1910) (noting that the Supreme Court had
    ―[f]or the first time in its history‖ overturned a sentence on cruel
    and unusual punishment grounds and that ―the musty precedents
    of the past‖ only used the words ―cruel and unusual‖ to ―prohibit
    a resort to inhuman methods for causing bodily torture‖).
    229 I have no doubt that the founding generation in Utah would
    have bristled at the notion of the death sentence ―for a minor
    infraction such as public intoxication.‖ Infra ¶ 226. And it would
    not be surprising to hear that some of them may have thought of
    such a sentence, colloquially, as ―cruel.‖ Infra ¶ 226. Presumably
    that‘s why they didn‘t adopt such a disproportionate sentence.
    But that ultimately tells us nothing about the original
    understanding of the constitutional construct of ―cruel and
    unusual punishments.‖ That question, instead, requires an
    examination of the founding generation‘s understanding of this
    legal term of art.
    101
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    years thereafter, a juvenile convicted of murder230 would have
    been subject to either the death penalty or to life in prison without
    the possibility of parole.231 This well-established, widely
    applicable sentencing scheme renders Houston‘s claim of
    unconstitutionality highly questionable. Because our founding-era
    justice system clearly and expressly required a juvenile convicted
    of murder to be sentenced to a life-without-parole sentence or
    worse, I find it difficult to believe that such sentence would have
    been viewed as ―cruel and unusual‖ at the time of our
    founding.232
    230 From the time of the founding of the Utah Constitution
    until 1907, Utah had no separate system for adjudicating crimes
    committed by minors. See 1907 Laws of Utah 207–14 (establishing
    the juvenile court system). And even after 1907, a minor who
    committed a felony was tried in the district courts, not the
    juvenile system. See, e.g., 1907 Laws of Utah 208, § 2 (―[Juvenile]
    Court[s] shall have no jurisdiction in cases involving the
    commission of a felony.‖). Thus, a minor like Houston would
    have been ―liable to be punished under the laws of this state.‖
    UTAH COMP. LAWS 1907, § 4072.
    231 See UTAH COMP. LAWS 1907, § 4071 (―All persons are capable
    of committing crimes except . . . . [c]hildren under the age of seven
    years; [c]hildren between the ages of seven years and fourteen
    years, in the absence of clear proof that at the time of committing
    the act charged against them they knew its wrongfulness.‖); 
    id. § 4162
    (―Every person guilty of murder in the first degree shall
    suffer death, or, upon the recommendation of the jury, may be
    imprisoned at hard labor in the state prison for life, in the
    discretion of the court.‖); see also State v. Thorne, 
    117 P. 58
    , 62 (Utah
    1911) (same); In re De Camp, 
    49 P. 823
    , 823 (Utah 1897) (same);
    UTAH COMP. LAWS 1907, § 1686X13 (―The board of pardons is
    hereby authorized to extend to each convict sentenced for any period
    less than life . . . a reduction of the period of sentence, as
    hereinafter provided‖ (emphasis added)); Connors v. Pratt, 
    112 P. 399
    , 400 (Utah 1910) (noting that board of pardons was without
    power to reduce a life sentence).
    232 Cf. 
    Harmelin, 501 U.S. at 980
    (opinion of Scalia, J.) (―[T]he
    actions of the First Congress . . . are persuasive evidence of what
    (con‘t.)
    102
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                          A.C.J. LEE, concurring
    c. Houston‘s Article I, Section 9 Claim
    ¶ 210 For all of the above reasons, the Cruel and Unusual
    Punishments Clause of the Utah Constitution bars only those
    methods of punishment that are ―cruel‖ in the sense of being
    barbaric or torturous and ―unusual‖ in the sense of being contrary
    to law and longstanding practice. Houston‘s state constitutional
    claim fails under this standard.
    ¶ 211 Houston does not—and cannot—complain about any
    torturous or barbarous form of punishment. His claim, instead,
    goes to the alleged excessiveness of his prison term. He alleges,
    specifically, that his ―immaturity, vulnerability, impetuosity, and
    underdeveloped character render him less culpable than an adult
    with fully developed brain and value systems,‖ and as a result his
    sentence constitutes ―disproportionate punishment.‖
    ¶ 212 This is not a cognizable constitutional claim under
    article I, section 9. Because Houston challenges only the
    excessiveness of his prison term, he has not asserted a claim under
    the Utah Constitution as originally understood. I would reject that
    claim on that basis.
    the Constitution means. . . .‖); M’Culloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S.
    (4 Wheat) 316, 401–02 (1819) (relying on the fact that the power to
    establish a national bank ―was exercised by the first congress‖ and
    that ―[a]n exposition of the constitution, deliberately established
    by legislative acts . . . ought not to be lightly disregarded‖).
    103
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    JUSTICE DURHAM, dissenting:
    ¶ 213 I disagree with the majority‘s conclusion that
    sentencing juveniles to life without the possibility of parole
    (LWOP) is not cruel and unusual under article I, section 9 of the
    Utah Constitution. In my view, the diminished culpability of
    juveniles, combined with the exceeding harshness and irreversible
    nature of LWOP, makes this sentence unconstitutionally
    disproportionate and inconsistent with the ―evolving standards of
    decency that mark the progress of a maturing society.‖ Trop v.
    Dulles, 
    356 U.S. 86
    , 101 (1958).
    I. UTAH‘S CRUEL AND UNUSUAL PUNISHMENTS
    CLAUSE AND PROPORTIONAL SENTENCING
    A. The Principle of Proportionality
    ¶ 214 Perhaps no theory of punishment is more foundational
    to a reasoned system of criminal justice than the maxim that the
    punishment must fit the crime. This venerable principle can be
    traced back to the Code of Hammurabi and the Mosaic codes
    found in the Old Testament. CODE OF HAMMURABI § 196 (c. 1770
    B.C.E.) (―If a man destroy the eye of another man, one shall
    destroy his eye.‖); Leviticus 24:20 (―Breach for breach, eye for eye,
    tooth for tooth: as he hath caused a blemish in a man, so shall it be
    done to him again.‖); see MORRIS RAPHAEL COHEN, REASON AND
    LAW 53 (1950) (―But if . . . an eye for an eye or a tooth for a tooth[]
    sounds too barbaric today, may we not . . . put it thus: Everyone is
    to be punished alike in proportion to the gravity of his offense
    . . . ?‖). The ancient Greeks and Romans also acknowledged
    punishments in a just society must be proportional to the crime.
    PLATO, LAWS bk. XI, at 934, in 5 THE DIALOGUES OF PLATO 323 (B.
    Jowett trans., New York, MacMillan & Co. 3d ed. 1892) (c. 350
    B.C.E.) (―[T]he law, like a good archer, should aim at the right
    measure of punishment, and in all cases at the deserved
    punishment.‖); CICERO, DE OFFICIIS bk. I, ch. XXV, at 91 (Walter
    Miller trans., Harvard Univ. Press 1997) (44 B.C.E.) (―We should
    take care also that the punishment shall not be out of proportion
    to the offense . . . .‖).
    ¶ 215 Consequently, ―[t]he principle that a punishment
    should be proportionate to the crime is deeply rooted and
    frequently repeated in common-law jurisprudence.‖ Solem v.
    Helm, 
    463 U.S. 277
    , 284 (1983). Indeed, the Magna Carta of 1215
    guaranteed rights to proportional punishment: ―A free man shall
    104
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           J. DURHAM, dissenting
    not be [fined] for a trivial offence, except in accordance with the
    degree of the offence; and for a serious offence he shall be [fined]
    according to its gravity . . . .‖ J.C. HOLT, MAGNA CARTA 457 (2d ed.
    1992). Blackstone later elaborated that ―[t]he method . . . of
    inflicting punishment ought always to be proportioned to the
    particular purpose it is meant to serve, and by no means to exceed
    it.‖ 4 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *12; see also Thomas A.
    Balmer, Some Thoughts on Proportionality, 87 OR. L. REV. 783, 787–
    88 (2008). Thus, Blackstone reasoned that the application of a
    disproportionately severe punishment is a form of malpractice
    performed by the state:
    It is a kind of quackery in government, and argues a
    want of solid skill, to apply the same universal
    remedy, the ultimum supplicium [the death penalty],
    to every case of difficulty. It is, it must be owned,
    much easier to extirpate than to amend mankind: yet
    that magistrate must be esteemed both a weak and a
    cruel surgeon, who cuts off every limb, which
    through ignorance or indolence he will not attempt
    to cure. It has been therefore ingeniously proposed,
    that in every state a scale of crimes should be
    formed, with a corresponding scale of punishments,
    descending from the greatest to the least . . . .
    4 WILLIAM      BLACKSTONE,     COMMENTARIES       *17–*18   (footnote
    omitted).
    ¶ 216 The early settlers of the Utah Territory intended that the
    ―deeply rooted‖ common law principle of proportional
    punishment be constitutionally protected. In 1849, residents of
    what would become the Utah Territory prepared a proposed state
    constitution guaranteeing that ―[a]ll penalties and punishments
    shall be in proportion to the offence.‖ CONSTITUTION OF THE STATE
    OF DESERET 10 (Kanesville, Orson Hyde 1849). Constitutional
    conventions held in 1856 and 1862 produced proposed state
    constitutions containing identical guarantees of proportional
    punishment. Constitution of the State of Deseret, DESERET NEWS,
    April 2, 1856, at 30; SEN. MISC. DOC. No. 35–240, at 2, 4 (1858); H.R.
    MISC. DOC. NO. 37–78, at 5 (1862).
    ¶ 217 The fundamental principle of proportional punishment
    was carried forward into Utah‘s cruel and unusual punishments
    clause. The draft constitutions of 1872 and 1882 and the state
    105
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    constitution adopted in 1895 replaced the more explicit guarantee
    of proportional punishment found in prior draft constitutions
    with language drawn from the Eighth Amendment of the U.S.
    Constitution:1 ―Excessive bail shall not be required; excessive fines
    shall not be imposed; nor shall cruel and unusual punishments be
    inflicted.‖ UTAH CONST. art. I, § 9; accord H.R. MISC. DOC. NO. 42–
    165, at 5 (1872); CONSTITUTION OF THE STATE OF UTAH 20 (Salt Lake
    City, DESERET NEWS CO. 1882). The Supreme Court has long held
    that identical language found in the Eighth Amendment prohibits
    disproportionate punishments. 
    Solem, 463 U.S. at 290
    (―[A]
    criminal sentence must be proportionate to the crime for which
    the defendant has been convicted.‖); Weems v. United States, 
    217 U.S. 349
    , 367 (1910) (―[I]t is a precept of justice that punishment
    for crime should be graduated and proportioned to offense.‖);
    O’Neil v. Vermont, 
    144 U.S. 323
    , 331–32, 339–40 (1892) (Field, J.,
    dissenting) (although the majority declined to address the issue of
    proportionality under the Eighth Amendment because it was not
    briefed and because the amendment had not yet been extended to
    the states, the dissent reasoned that the Eighth Amendment
    1  The 1872 draft constitution was modeled after the recently
    approved Nevada Constitution as part of the Utah Territory‘s
    ongoing efforts to obtain statehood despite national opposition to
    the practice of polygamy. Soc’y of Separationists, Inc. v. Whitehead,
    
    870 P.2d 916
    , 928 n.31 (Utah 1993) (―In 1872 the constitutional
    convention borrowed the constitution of Nevada as the basis for
    its proposed constitution.‖ (internal quotation marks omitted)); see
    H.R. MISC. DOC. NO. 42–165, 42d at 4 (1872) (―The constitution of
    the proposed State, which is presented [to Congress] herewith,
    looks to the development of those improvements of political
    science which elsewhere excite public attention; for it will be
    observed that it provides for minority representation, impartial
    suffrage, and equal public educational facilities, without
    distinction of race, color, religion, or citizenship.‖) The cruel and
    unusual punishments clause contained in the 1872 draft is
    identical to the corresponding clause found in the Nevada
    Constitution. Compare H.R. MISC. DOC. NO. 42–165, at 5 (1872),
    with NEV. CONST. art. I, § 6. The language found in the Nevada
    Constitution was taken from the Eighth Amendment of the U.S.
    Constitution.
    106
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           J. DURHAM, dissenting
    proscribes ―all punishments which by their excessive length or
    severity are greatly disproportioned to the offenses charged‖).
    ¶ 218 Courts have cited two principal reasons for interpreting
    the text of the Eighth Amendment to guarantee proportional
    punishment. Some courts have held that the Eighth Amendment‘s
    explicit prohibitions of ―[e]xcessive bail‖ and ―excessive fines‖
    must extend to bar excessive terms of imprisonment as ―cruel and
    unusual.‖ 
    Solem, 463 U.S. at 289
    . Other courts have held that
    disproportionately harsh sentences are both ―cruel‖ and
    ―unusual‖ within the meaning of those terms. 
    Weems, 217 U.S. at 364
    , 377 (A sentence of twelve years of ―hard and painful labor‖
    for making false entries in an official document was ―cruel in its
    excess of imprisonment and that which accompanies and follows
    imprisonment. It is unusual in its character. Its punishments come
    under the condemnation of the Bill of Rights, both on account of
    their degree and kind.‖).
    ¶ 219 Other states that have similar cruel and unusual
    punishments clauses in their constitutions have interpreted this
    clause to protect against disproportionate sentences. See, e.g.,
    McDonald v. Commonwealth, 
    53 N.E. 874
    , 875 (Mass. 1899); In re
    Lynch, 
    503 P.2d 921
    , 930 (Cal. 1972). Although the interpretation
    given to similar or even identical language found in the federal
    Constitution or the constitutions of our sister states is not binding,
    we may look to these interpretations when construing Utah‘s
    Constitution. Soc’y of Separationists, Inc. v. Whitehead, 
    870 P.2d 916
    ,
    921 n.6 (Utah 1993).
    ¶ 220 This court has also recognized that the cruel and
    unusual punishments clause of the Utah Constitution provides
    protections against disproportionate punishments similar to the
    safeguards provided by the Eighth Amendment. Thus, ―[a]
    criminal punishment is cruel and unusual under article I, section 9
    if it is so disproportionate to the offense committed that it shock[s]
    the moral sense of all reasonable men as to what is right and
    proper under the circumstances.‖ State v. Lafferty, 
    2001 UT 19
    ,
    ¶ 73, 
    20 P.3d 342
    (second alteration in original) (internal quotation
    marks omitted). Given the deference we afford sentencing judges
    and the right of the legislature to mandate the maximum sentence
    for a given offense—so long as it does not stray beyond
    constitutional      bounds—this         type   of      individualized
    proportionality review is justifiably limited.
    107
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    B. Utah’s Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause
    Prohibits Disproportionate Punishments
    ¶ 221 In his concurring opinion, Justice Lee argues that we
    should abandon our caselaw affirming that the cruel and unusual
    punishments clause of the Utah Constitution forbids
    disproportionate sentences. The concurrence asserts that both the
    text of this clause and the historical understanding of the
    language adopted in the Utah Constitution point to a more
    limited understanding of ―cruel and unusual punishments.‖
    Under this interpretation, the Utah Constitution bans methods of
    punishment that are barbaric, but does not prohibit an excessive
    application of an otherwise permissible mode of punishment.
    ¶ 222 I, along with a majority of this court, disagree. The text
    of the cruel and unusual punishments clause demonstrates that
    disproportionate punishments—not just barbaric methods of
    punishment—are        prohibited.    Moreover,      the    historical
    understanding of the term ―cruel and unusual punishments‖ at
    the time Utah adopted its constitution affirms, rather than detracts
    from, this reading of the text.
    1. Text of Utah‘s Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause
    ¶ 223 Article I, section 9 of the Utah Constitution provides:
    ―Excessive bail shall not be required; excessive fines shall not be
    imposed; nor shall cruel and unusual punishments be inflicted.‖
    This section contains three parallel clauses. The first two clauses
    prohibit ―[e]xcessive bail‖ and ―excessive fines‖ and expressly
    incorporate the principle of proportionality. They require the
    amount of money a defendant may be required to deposit in
    security to remain free, as well as the amount in fines that a
    convicted individual may be required to pay, to be commensurate
    with the crime. The third prohibition against ―cruel and unusual
    punishments‖ does not contain an explicit reference to
    proportionality.
    ¶ 224 Invoking the canon of independent meaning, the
    concurrence asserts that this structure indicates that the framers of
    the Utah Constitution intended to protect citizens from
    disproportionate fines, but not excessive prison sentences or the
    disproportionate application of the death penalty (both accepted
    methods of punishment in Utah). Supra ¶¶ 158–65. This structural
    reading of article I, section 9, however, produces an unnatural and
    incongruous result. A more appropriate canon of construction to
    108
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                            J. DURHAM, dissenting
    apply to a parallel list of items is that of noscitur a sociis, or ―it is
    known from its associates,‖ which ―requires that the meaning of
    doubtful words or phrases be determined in the light of and take
    their character from associated words or phrases.‖ Heathman v.
    Giles, 
    374 P.2d 839
    , 840 (Utah 1962) (internal quotation marks
    omitted). This concept of drawing meaning from the context of
    associated terms has been adopted by the United States Supreme
    Court in interpreting the nearly identical Eighth Amendment:
    We have recognized that the Eighth Amendment
    imposes ―parallel limitations‖ on bail, fines, and
    other punishments, and the text is explicit that bail
    and fines may not be excessive. It would be
    anomalous indeed if the lesser punishment of a fine
    and the greater punishment of death were both
    subject to proportionality analysis, but the
    intermediate punishment of imprisonment were not.
    
    Solem, 463 U.S. at 289
    (citation omitted).
    ¶ 225 The noscitur a sociis canon is also more appropriate
    because of its long-standing application to this constitutional
    language. It was first used in Justice Field‘s influential 1892
    dissent in O’Neil v. Vermont, where he reasoned: ―The whole
    inhibition is against that which is excessive either in the bail
    required, or fine imposed, or punishment 
    inflicted.‖ 144 U.S. at 340
    (quoted in 
    Weems, 217 U.S. at 371
    ). Because this canon was
    applied before Utah adopted article I, section 9, it is more
    appropriate to apply the noscitur a sociis canon to this
    constitutional provision.
    ¶ 226 The plain meaning of ―cruel and unusual punishments‖
    reinforces this structural interpretation. The concurrence looks to
    several nineteenth century definitions of the word ―cruel‖ and
    argues that because none of these dictionary definitions do not
    expressly incorporate the concept of proportionality, Utah citizens
    would have understood ―cruel‖ to exclude this notion. Supra
    ¶ 161. Under this logic, Utahns in 1895 would not have
    understood a death sentence imposed for a minor infraction such
    as public intoxication as a ―cruel‖ punishment because the death
    penalty was not deemed to be an inherently barbarous penalty.
    This cannot be the case. The definition of ―cruel‖ is broad enough
    to include grossly disproportionate punishments. Such
    punishments can be said to be ―inhuman;‖ ―destitute of pity,
    109
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    compassion or kindness;‖ or ―hard-hearted.‖ WEBSTER‘S
    AMERICAN DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE 210 (3d ed.
    1830) (defining ―cruel‖). As noted by the California Supreme
    Court:
    A contrary view leads to the astounding result
    that it is impossible to impose a cruel and unusual
    punishment so long as none of the old and discarded
    modes of punishment are used; and that there is no
    restriction upon the power of the legislative
    department, for example, to prescribe the death
    penalty by hanging for a misdemeanor, and that the
    courts would be compelled to impose the penalty.
    Yet such a punishment for such a crime would be
    considered extremely cruel and unusual by all right-
    mined people.
    Cox v. State, 
    181 N.E. 469
    , 471 (Ind. 1932) (internal quotation marks
    omitted).
    2. Historical Understanding           of   ―Cruel   and     Unusual
    Punishments‖
    ¶ 227 The concurrence also argues that the framers of the
    Utah Constitution would not have understood article I, section 9‘s
    prohibition of ―cruel and unusual punishments‖ to forbid
    disproportionate punishments. Supra ¶¶ 166–67. Most of the
    historical evidence cited by the concurrence, however, merely
    supports the conclusion that this phrase was traditionally
    understood to include barbaric modes of punishment. This
    evidence does not advance the theory advocated by the
    concurrence: that the term ―cruel and unusual punishments‖
    traditionally excluded cruelly disproportionate applications of
    otherwise acceptable modes of punishment. A proper historical
    understanding of ―cruel and unusual punishments‖ includes both
    the method and the severity of punishment imposed.
    a. The English Bill of Rights
    ¶ 228 As noted by the concurrence, supra ¶ 170, the language
    for Utah‘s cruel and unusual punishments clause originated in the
    English Bill of Rights of 1689, which provides ―[t]hat excessive
    Baile ought not to be required nor excessive Fines imposed nor
    cruell and unusuall Punishments inflicted,‖ An Act Declareing the
    Rights and Liberties of the Subject and Setleing the Succession of
    110
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                          J. DURHAM, dissenting
    the Crowne, in 6 STATUTES OF THE REALM 143 (1819). The
    concurrence also correctly notes that we may glean some
    understanding of the original meaning of ―cruel and unusual
    punishments‖ from the Titus Oates case.
    ¶ 229 When King James II ascended to the throne, he had
    Oates tried for perjury for falsely accusing prominent English
    Catholics of organizing a ―Popish Plot‖ to overthrow his brother,
    King Charles II. Harmelin v. Michigan, 
    501 U.S. 957
    , 969 (1991)
    (opinion of Scalia, J.). These accusations resulted in the execution
    of fifteen individuals. 
    Id. Oates was
    found guilty, and the court
    sentenced him to life imprisonment and to annually stand in
    pillory and be whipped through the streets of London. 
    Id. at 970.
    Shortly after James II was deposed in the Glorious Revolution of
    1688 and the English Bill of Rights was passed, Oates petitioned
    the House of Lords to overturn his sentence. 
    Id. Even though
    the
    Lords considered the judgment of sentence to be ―erroneous‖ and
    ―exorbitant,‖ a majority of the House of Lords declined to
    overturn the sentence. 10 H.C. Jour. 249 (1689). Instead, the Lords
    deemed it sufficient to introduce a bill to ―prevent . . . like
    Judgments for the future.‖ 
    Id. Members of
    the House of Commons
    took up Oates‘s cause, however, and passed a bill urging the
    House of Lords to reconsider. 
    Id. at 251.
        ¶ 230 The record of the proceedings before the House of
    Lords and the House of Commons reveals that the debate over
    Oates‘s fate was largely driven by the sectarian politics and
    prejudices of the time. Members of the House of Commons
    argued that Oates‘s conviction should be set aside as corrupt
    because the trial was called for by the recently deposed ―Papist‖
    King James II after ―partial, corrupt, and unqualified Persons
    were returned, and served on Juries.‖ 
    Id. at 248.
    House Members
    also asserted that the Jesuit novices who gave testimony against
    Oates could not be trusted to honor their oaths as witnesses
    because their superiors would have instructed them to lie in order
    ―to discredit the Evidence of the Popish Plot; and disparage those
    Parliaments who had prosecuted it with so much Vigour.‖ 
    Id. The House
    of Commons further urged the House of Lords to consider
    whether denying Oates‘s petition would be ―interpreted a great
    Step towards disavowing the Popish Plot,‖ as it had already been
    understood by rival powers ―beyond Sea,‖ and to contemplate
    whether this tacit admission would ―be so much for the Honour
    of our Nation, or our Religion.‖ 
    Id. at 247.
    Members of the House
    111
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    of Lords, on the other hand, seemed to view Oates and his
    improbable conspiracy theories (including committing perjury ―in
    other Matters‖ such as accusing the former Queen of conspiring to
    kill the King, ―which nobody could believe of her‖) as something
    of an international embarrassment to be swept under the rug. 
    Id. at 249.
    Although the Lords conceded that Oates‘s sentence was
    improper, they declined to reverse it, explaining that the Oates
    case ―was a Matter of great Expectation: That the Eyes of all
    Europe were upon it: And that it would be the Occasion of great
    Censures, if he should be set up for a Witness again, without a full
    Examination of the whole Affair.‖ 
    Id. ¶ 231
    As noted by the concurrence, both members of the
    House of Commons and the dissenting Lords also proffered a
    legal argument for overturning Oates‘s sentence based upon the
    recently passed English Bill of Rights. Supra ¶¶ 176–77. Given the
    extent to which national and religious politics pervaded this
    debate, however, it is somewhat difficult to discern the degree to
    which these political concerns colored the legal reasoning found
    in the record. But the comments preserved in the legislative
    record undoubtably provide some insight into the original
    meaning of the prohibition against ―cruel and unusual
    punishments‖ contained in the English Bill of Rights.
    ¶ 232 The dissenting Lords argued that the sentence imposed
    upon Oates should be overturned under the cruel and unusual
    punishments clause of the English Bill of Rights because there
    were ―no Precedents to warrant the Punishments of whipping and
    committing to Prison for Life, for the Crime of Perjury.‖ 14 H.L.
    Jour. 228 (1689). Thus, they asserted that the judgment against
    Oates was ―contrary to Law and ancient Practice, and therefore
    erroneous, and ought to be reversed.‖ 
    Id. Members of
    the House
    of Commons likewise decried the unprecedented nature of
    punishment, calling the sentence ―illegal‖ and ―against Law.‖ 10
    H.C. Jour. 247 (1689).
    ¶ 233 The lesson that the concurrence takes from these
    statements is that certain members of Parliament objected only to
    the illegal and unprecedented nature of Oates‘s sentence, and not
    the disproportionality of the punishment. Supra ¶ 177. But this is a
    false distinction. The punishments prescribed were unsupported
    by ―Precedents‖ and were ―contrary to Law and ancient Practice‖
    because they exceeded the punishments previously meted out for
    similar crimes. As one legal commentator put it: ―Titus Oates’ Case
    112
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                          J. DURHAM, dissenting
    demonstrates that the English Cruell and Unusuall Punishments
    Clause was originally understood to prohibit new punishments
    that were excessive in light of prior practice.‖ John F. Stinneford,
    Rethinking Proportionality Under the Cruel and Unusual Punishments
    Clause, 97 VA. L. REV. 899, 937 (2011).
    ¶ 234 This concern that Oates‘s sentence was cruel and
    unusual because it was unprecedented in its severity is reflected
    in the Parliamentary record. The dissenting Lords, who argued
    that Oates‘s sentence should have been overturned, asserted that
    the sentence was ―barbarous, inhuman, and unchristian‖ because
    ―there is no Precedents to warrant the Punishments of whipping
    and committing to Prison for Life, for the Crime of Perjury.‖ 14
    H.L. Jour. 228 (1689). Even the Lords in the majority, who
    affirmed Oates‘s sentence in order to prevent ―so ill a Man‖ from
    serving as witness in the future, conceded that ―there was not one
    Lord, but thought the Judgments erroneous, and was fully
    satisfied, That such an extravagant Judgment ought not to have
    been given, or a Punishment so exorbitant inflicted upon an English
    Subject.‖ 10 H.C. Jour. 249 (1689) (first and second emphases
    added). Members of the House of Commons likewise described
    the sentence as ―cruel and ignominious,‖ ―excessive,‖ ―severe and
    extraordinary,‖ and ―an extravagant Judgment‖—all descriptions
    of the disproportionate nature of the sentence. 
    Id. at 247,
    248.
    ¶ 235 Thus the Parliamentary debates over the sentence of
    Titus Oates, which were conducted in the context of the recently
    passed English Bill of Rights, demonstrate an original
    understanding of ―cruel and unusual punishments‖ that includes
    the concept of proportionality.
    b. The understanding of the cruel and unusual punishments
    clause contemporaneous to the adoption of the Utah
    Constitution
    ¶ 236 Of course, the meaning assigned to ―cruel and unusual
    punishments‖ in the English Bill of Rights does not control the
    question of what this phrase means in the context of the Utah
    Constitution. The relevant issue is what these words meant when
    our Constitution was drafted and ratified in 1895. The
    contemporaneous precedents of (1) the U.S. Supreme Court in
    examining the Eighth Amendment, which is nearly identical to
    the relevant language of article I, section 9 and (2) state supreme
    courts that examined similar constitutional clauses reveal that the
    113
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    phrase ―cruel and unusual punishments‖ was generally
    interpreted in line with its plain meaning: that disproportionately
    harsh punishments were cruel and unusual punishments.
    (i)   Contemporaneous U.S. Supreme Court precedent
    ¶ 237 Although the majority of the U.S. Supreme Court did
    not squarely address the question of whether the Eighth
    Amendment prohibited disproportionately harsh punishments
    prior to the adoption of the Utah Constitution, Supreme Court
    precedent indicates that the Court had assumed that a
    disproportionately harsh sentence was a cruel and unusual
    sentence.
    ¶ 238 The Court first addressed a proportional punishments
    argument under the Eighth Amendment in Pervear v.
    Massachusetts, 72 U.S. (5 Wall.) 475 (1866). The defendant in that
    case argued that his sentence of a fifty dollar fine and three
    months imprisonment at hard labor for the illegal sale of
    intoxicating liquors was ―excessive, cruel, and unusual‖ under the
    Eighth Amendment. 
    Id. at 479
    –80. The Court declined to resolve
    this claim because it held that the Eighth Amendment did not
    apply to state legislation. 
    Id. The Court
    went on to opine,
    however, that even if the defendant could invoke the Eighth
    Amendment, the defendant‘s argument would fail on its merits
    because the sentence was not excessive: ―We perceive nothing
    excessive, or cruel, or unusual in [the defendant‘s sentence].‖ 
    Id. at 480.
    Thus, the Court implicitly recognized that excessive
    punishments may be cruel and unusual punishments.
    ¶ 239 The concurrence, however, draws a different conclusion
    from this opinion. The concurrence focuses on the Court‘s
    subsequent observation that the objective of liquor licencing laws
    is ―to protect the community against the manifold evils of
    intemperance‖ and that ―[t]he mode adopted, of prohibiting
    under penalties the sale and keeping for sale of intoxicating
    liquors, without license, is the usual mode adopted in many,
    perhaps, all of the States. It is wholly within the discretion of State
    legislatures.‖ 
    Id. The concurrence
    interprets this language to mean
    that the ―mode‖ of enforcing liquor licensing laws is completely
    within the discretion of the state legislature and could never be
    deemed cruel and unusual so long as the legislature does not
    employ inherently cruel methods of punishment. Supra ¶ 188 n.33.
    This reading is unduly strained. There is no indication that when
    114
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                          J. DURHAM, dissenting
    the Court stated that liquor licensing laws were ―wholly within
    the discretion of State legislatures‖ that it was proclaiming the
    punishments imposed by a statute to be immune from
    constitutional review. Moreover, there is no textual justification
    for drawing a distinction between inherently cruel methods of
    punishment and disproportionately cruel sentences such that the
    former is constitutionally prohibited while the latter is not.
    ¶ 240 In 1892, just three years before the Utah Constitution
    was ratified, the Supreme Court again addressed a challenge to
    the proportionality of a sentence under the Eighth Amendment.
    The defendant in O’Neil challenged a sentence amounting to fifty-
    four years of imprisonment at hard labor for the unauthorized
    sale of intoxicating liquor as unconstitutionally 
    excessive. 144 U.S. at 327
    , 339. Once again, the majority of the court declined to
    address a claim under the Eighth Amendment because it
    concluded that this amendment did not apply to punishments
    applied by the states. 
    Id. at 331–32.
    Justice Field, however,
    authored a lengthy dissent in which he squarely addressed the
    issue, stating that the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause
    is directed, not only against punishments of the
    character mentioned [the rack, thumb-screws, iron
    boots, and stretching of limbs], but against all
    punishments which by their excessive length or
    severity are greatly disproportioned to the offenses
    charged. The whole inhibition is against that which
    is excessive either in the bail required, or fine
    imposed, or punishment inflicted.
    
    Id. at 339–40.
    A separate dissenting opinion authored by Justice
    Harlan and joined by Justice Brewer expressed a similar view,
    declaring that a sentence of fifty-four years ―inflicts punishment
    which, in view of the character of the offenses committed, must be
    deemed cruel and unusual.‖ 
    Id. at 371.
        ¶ 241 For the purpose of the inquiry at issue here—the
    prevailing understanding of the phrase ―cruel and unusual
    punishments‖ when the Utah Constitution was drafted and
    ratified in 1895—it is of little importance that the opinions of
    Justices Field, Harlan, and Brewer are not binding precedent. The
    unchallenged opinion of three Supreme Court justices that a
    disproportionate sentence is also a cruel and unusual sentence just
    three years before Utah adopted its constitution is convincing
    115
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    evidence of how contemporaries would have understood this
    phrase.
    ¶ 242 The U.S. Supreme Court case that the concurrence relies
    upon, Wilkerson v. Utah, 
    99 U.S. 130
    (1878), does not contradict this
    understanding of ―cruel and unusual punishments.‖ See supra
    ¶¶ 197–99. The defendant in that case challenged the manner in
    which he was sentenced to be executed for first-degree murder in
    the Supreme Court of the Territory of Utah, arguing that the
    statutes in force at the time did not permit him to be executed by
    firing squad. People v. Wilkinson, 
    2 Utah 158
    , 160 (Utah Terr. 1877).
    The territorial supreme court considered sua sponte whether the
    manner of carrying out the execution, ―death by shooting,‖ was
    cruel and unusual. 
    Id. at 164.
    The court concluded that death by
    firing squad was not cruel and unusual because it was not an
    unusual method and it was not any less humane than other
    accepted forms of execution. 
    Id. The U.S.
    Supreme Court granted
    certiorari and considered the same constitutional question.
    
    Wilkerson, 99 U.S. at 130
    . The Court conceded that ―[d]ifficulty
    would attend the effort to define with exactness the extent of the
    constitutional provision which provides that cruel and unusual
    punishments shall not be inflicted.‖ 
    Id. at 135–36.
    It nonetheless
    concluded that, at minimum, ―it is safe to affirm that punishments
    of torture . . . are forbidden by‖ the Eighth Amendment. Id at 136.
    The Court, therefore, determined that the method of execution—
    firing squad—was constitutional because it was not in the vein of
    barbarous methods of execution sometimes used in the past, such
    as disembowelment or being burned alive. 
    Id. at 135–36.
        ¶ 243 While Wilkerson and the preceding territorial opinion
    certainly affirm the principle that inherently cruel methods of
    punishment are proscribed by the Eighth Amendment, these
    opinions do not provide that this is the outer limit of the
    protections afforded by this amendment. The Court did not
    consider whether execution was a disproportionately harsh
    punishment for first-degree murder for the simple reason that this
    claim was never raised. Indeed, such an argument certainly
    would have been deemed frivolous in 1878.
    (ii)   Contemporaneous state supreme court precedent
    ¶ 244 The preponderance of state courts that addressed the
    proportional punishments question under identical state
    constitutional provisions agreed with the reading of ―cruel and
    116
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           J. DURHAM, dissenting
    unusual punishments‖ expressed by Justices Field, Harlan, and
    Brewer in O’Neil v. Vermont. State courts that rendered opinions
    on this subject either prior to or soon after the Utah Constitution
    was drafted and ratified in 1895 indicated that disproportionate
    punishments may be unconstitutionally cruel and unusual.
    McDonald v. Commonwealth, 
    53 N.E. 874
    , 875 (Mass. 1899) (―[I]t is
    possible that imprisonment in the state prison for a long term of
    years might be so disproportionate to the offense as to constitute a
    cruel and unusual punishment [under the Massachusetts
    Constitution].‖); State ex rel. Garvey v. Whitaker, 
    19 So. 457
    , 457, 459
    (La. 1896) (citing Justice Field‘s dissent in O’Neil v. Vermont and
    overturning a near six-year sentence for trespassing in a public
    park under Louisiana‘s cruel and unusual punishments clause
    because of the severity of the punishment); People v. Whitney, 
    63 N.W. 765
    , 766 (Mich. 1895) (noting that although ―[u]pon the
    legislature alone is conferred the power to fix the minimum and
    maximum of the punishment for all crimes,‖ nevertheless ―[i]t is
    true that cases might arise when the punishment imposed by an
    act is so cruel and unusual that the courts would interfere and
    protect the rights of the party‖); In re MacDonald, 
    33 P. 18
    , 20–21
    (Wyo. 1893) (noting that a punishment is not ―cruel or unusual‖
    under the Wyoming constitution unless ―the punishment
    provided by the law is so disproportionate to the offense as to
    shock the moral sense of the people‖ (internal quotation marks
    omitted)); State v. Becker, 
    51 N.W. 1018
    , 1022 (S.D. 1892) (noting
    that a punishment may be set aside as unconstitutional ―in very
    extreme cases, where the punishment proposed is so severe and
    out of proportion to the offense as to shock public sentiment and
    violate the judgment of reasonable people‖); State v. Four Jugs of
    Intoxicating Liquor, 
    2 A. 586
    , 593 (Vt. 1886) (rejecting a claim that
    the aggregate prison sentence for numerous separate offenses
    constituted a cruel and unusual punishment, but conceding that
    ―[i]f the penalty were unreasonably severe for a single offense, the
    constitutional question might be urged‖); State v. Driver, 
    78 N.C. 423
    , 426, 430 (1878) (overturning a sentence of imprisonment of
    five years and payment of a $500 security for assault and battery
    as unconstitutionally ―‗excessive, cruel and unusual‘‖ because the
    sentence was ―greater than [had] ever been prescribed or known
    or inflicted‖ for the same or similar offense).
    ¶ 245 The state cases cited by the concurrence do not
    significantly undermine these contemporaneous pronouncements
    117
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    that a disproportionate sentence may be a cruel and unusual
    sentence. The concurring opinion cites several older state opinions
    that state the general proposition that the severity of a sentence is
    left to the legislature. See Commonwealth v. Hitchings, 71 Mass.
    (5 Gray) 482, 486 (1855) (―The question whether the punishment is
    too severe, and disproportionate to the offence, is for the
    legislature to determine.‖); Barker v. People, 
    20 Johns. 457
    , 459
    (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1823) (―[I]t was altogether discretionary in the
    legislature to extend [the punishment of disenfranchisement] to
    other offences.‖). These broad pronouncements that the
    legislature has the discretion to determine the severity of
    sentences do not directly lead to the conclusion that a sentence
    authorized by statute could never be unconstitutionally
    disproportionate. Indeed, courts in both Massachusetts and New
    York later announced that a disproportionately severe sentence
    could be set aside as cruel and unusual. McDonald v.
    
    Commonwealth, 53 N.E. at 875
    ; In re Bayard, 
    63 How. Pr. 73
    , 77
    (N.Y. Gen. Term 1881) (holding that ―cruel and unusual
    punishments‖ may include ―punishments so disproportioned to
    the offense as to shock the sense of the community‖).
    ¶ 246 In a terse opinion, the Michigan Supreme Court also
    rejected a claim that a sentence was cruel and unusual by stating
    that ―[u]pon the legislature alone is conferred the power to fix the
    minimum and maximum of the punishment for all crimes.‖ People
    v. Smith, 
    54 N.W. 487
    , 488 (Mich. 1893). But just two years later the
    court clarified that the state legislature‘s power was not absolute.
    While acknowledging the legislature‘s authority to ―fix the
    minimum and maximum of the punishment for all crimes,‖ the
    court concluded that the legislative prerogative of determining
    the appropriate amount of punishment for a particular crime was
    limited by the cruel and unusual punishments clause of the
    Michigan Constitution: ―It is true that cases might arise when the
    punishment imposed by an act is so cruel and unusual that the
    courts would interfere and protect the rights of the party . . . .‖
    
    Whitney, 63 N.W. at 766
    .2
    2 The concurrence also cites a federal Ninth Circuit case, which
    states that ―[t]he general rule is well settled that the sentence and
    punishment imposed upon a defendant for any violation of the
    provisions of the statute, which is within the punishment
    (con‘t.)
    118
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           J. DURHAM, dissenting
    ¶ 247 The concurrence cites several cases decided before Utah
    adopted its constitution that directly support the proposition that
    the phrase ―cruel and unusual punishments‖ refers exclusively to
    the mode and not the degree of punishment. Supra ¶¶ 188–89. But
    these cases are of limited utility in determining the commonly
    understood meaning of this constitutional term, and they do not
    outweigh the Supreme Court and state precedent supporting
    proportionality review.
    ¶ 248 In Aldridge v. Commonwealth, 4 Va. (2 Va. Cas.) 447, 447–
    48 (Va. Gen. Ct. 1824), a defendant challenged the
    constitutionality of a Virginia statute authorizing his punishment
    as a ―‗free man of color‘‖ convicted of larceny to be whipped with
    thirty-nine lashes, sold into slavery, and transported beyond the
    provided for by the statute, cannot be regarded as excessive, cruel,
    or unusual.‖ Jackson v. United States, 
    102 F. 473
    , 487 (9th Cir. 1900).
    But none of the cases cited by the Jackson court support the
    extreme proposition that a statute could never prescribe a cruel
    and unusual punishment. In Ligan v. State, 50 Tenn. (3 Heisk.) 159,
    164 (1871), the court simply determined that the punishment was
    not cruel and unusual given the ―character of acts‖ committed by
    the defendant and stated that it would ―feel no hesitancy in
    enforcing sternly the penalties provided by the statute.‖ Likewise,
    in Jones v. Territory, 
    43 P. 1072
    , 1074 (Okla. Terr. 1896), the court
    noted that because there was nothing in the record from which
    the court could determine the defendant‘s age, ―previous
    character,‖ or ―the circumstances under which the crime was
    committed,‖ it could not ―say, as a matter of law, that a sentence
    of 50 years in the territorial prison for the crime of manslaughter
    in the first degree is per se cruel and inhuman.‖ Finally, as noted
    above, the remaining cases cited by the Jackson court—Pervear, 72
    U.S. (5 Wall.) at 480; 
    Becker, 51 N.W. at 1022
    ; and 
    Whitney, 63 N.W. at 766
    —actually support the proposition that courts may reverse a
    disproportionately cruel and unusual sentence authorized by
    statute. Supra ¶¶ 238, 244. Moreover, the claim made in Jackson
    that a sentence imposed pursuant to a statute can never be cruel
    or unusual is plainly wrong. Even under the interpretation of the
    cruel and unusual punishments clause advocated by the
    concurrence, a statute providing for a barbaric mode of
    punishment would be unconstitutional.
    119
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    borders of the United States. The court denied the defendant‘s
    constitutional challenge, arguing that the Eighth Amendment was
    never intended to extend to slaves or ―free blacks and mulattoes.‖
    
    Id. at 449.
    The court went on to opine in dicta, however, that the
    constitutional prohibition against cruel and unusual punishments
    ―was never designed to control the Legislative right to determine
    ad libitum upon the adequacy of punishment, but is merely
    applicable to the modes of punishment.‖ 
    Id. at 449–50.
        ¶ 249 The reasoning of Aldridge, however, does not reflect the
    common understanding of ―cruel and unusual punishments‖ and
    may best be explained by racial animus. Indeed, just four years
    later a Virginia court contradicted Aldridge. In Commonwealth v.
    Wyatt, 27 Va. (6 Rand.) 694, 698 (Va. Gen. Ct. 1828), the court
    examined a statute permitting a judge to sentence a person guilty
    of operating an illegal card game to be whipped any number of
    times, so long as only thirty-nine stripes were inflicted at a time.
    Addressing an argument that the statute permitted cruel and
    unusual punishments, the court concluded that the statute was
    not unconstitutional on its face, but suggested that sentencing
    judges were constitutionally restrained from sentencing an
    individual to an excessive number of stripes. 
    Id. at 700–701.
        ¶ 250 Hobbs v. State, 
    32 N.E. 1019
    (Ind. 1893) is likewise of
    limited usefulness in determining the generally accepted meaning
    of ―cruel and unusual punishments.‖ In addressing a challenge to
    a prison sentence under the Indiana Constitution, that state‘s
    supreme court stated that it had not previously analyzed the cruel
    and unusual punishments clause in any depth. 
    Id. at 1020.
    The
    court therefore cited Joseph Story‘s treatise for the proposition
    that the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause of the U.S.
    Constitution prohibits the violent methods of punishment that
    ―had taken place in England in the arbitrary reigns of the Stuarts.‖
    
    Id. at 1021
    (internal quotation marks omitted). The Indiana
    Supreme Court then took this thesis one step further and
    independently concluded that ―cruel and unusual punishments‖
    should be read to exclusively prohibit barbaric methods of
    punishment and that this language ―does not affect legislation
    providing imprisonment for life or for years.‖ 
    Id. This holding,
    however, does not represent a common understanding of this
    constitutional language because the court did not cite any caselaw
    supporting this proposition. The Indiana Supreme Court came to
    this conclusion on its own. Indeed, the court seemed to be entirely
    120
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           J. DURHAM, dissenting
    unaware of the numerous cases holding that a disproportionate
    prison sentence could be an unconstitutionally cruel sentence.
    Supra ¶ 244.
    3. Conclusion
    ¶ 251 Under its plain meaning, ―cruel and unusual
    punishments‖ includes disproportionately harsh punishments.
    And an examination of how this phase was understood in 1895
    does not reveal an interpretation that diverges from this plain
    meaning. At minimum, however, this court should adhere to
    prior precedents where we have recognized that article I, section 9
    of the Utah Constitution prohibits disproportionate sentences. See
    Lafferty, 
    2001 UT 19
    , ¶ 75; State v. Herrera, 
    1999 UT 64
    , ¶ 37, 
    993 P.2d 854
    . An identical interpretation has long been applied by
    federal courts to the Eighth Amendment. 
    Weems, 217 U.S. at 377
    .
    In light of this long-standing interpretation given to identical
    language, we should not depart from our prior holdings because
    it is not ―clearly convinc[ing] that the rule was originally
    erroneous or is no longer sound because of changing conditions.‖
    State v. Menzies, 
    889 P.2d 393
    , 399 (Utah 1994) (internal quotation
    marks omitted).
    II. PROPORTIONALITY OF JUVENILE LWOP
    A. Proportionality in Relation to Juveniles
    as a Defined Class
    ¶ 252 Because Utah has recognized that article I, section 9 of
    the Utah Constitution protects against disproportionately cruel
    and unusual punishments, I now examine whether sentencing a
    juvenile to LWOP violates this constitutional protection. As we
    have previously recognized in State v. Lafferty that ―[a] criminal
    punishment is cruel and unusual under article I, section 9 if it is so
    disproportionate to the offense committed that it shock[s] the
    moral sense of all reasonable men as to what is right and proper
    under the circumstances.‖ 
    2001 UT 19
    , ¶ 73, 
    20 P.3d 342
    (second
    alteration in original) (internal quotation marks omitted). But an
    individualized proportionality review under the Lafferty standard
    is not the only kind of constitutional proportionality analysis.
    Article I, section 9 also requires courts to consider whether a
    particular punishment is unconstitutionally disproportionate
    when applied to a less culpable class of individuals—in this case,
    juveniles.
    121
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    ¶ 253 The Supreme Court has recognized that the Eighth
    Amendment embodies two distinct types of proportionality
    review. First, courts may determine that a sentence is
    unconstitutionally disproportionate, given all of the particular
    circumstances of an individual case. Graham v. Florida, 
    560 U.S. 48
    ,
    59–60 (2010). This kind of review is similar to Utah‘s ―shocks the
    conscience‖ standard. Second, the Court has recognized that
    certain sentences are categorically disproportionate when applied
    to a particular class of individuals. 
    Id. at 60–61;
    see also Roper v.
    Simmons, 
    543 U.S. 551
    , 575 (2005) (prohibiting the death penalty
    for juveniles); Atkins v. Virginia, 
    536 U.S. 304
    , 321 (2002)
    (prohibiting the death penalty for persons with mental
    disabilities). This second type of proportionality review does not
    evaluate a particular sentencing decision, but assesses whether a
    specific sentence may be applied to a group of individuals with a
    defining characteristic that makes members of that group less
    culpable than the general population. 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 61
    –62.
    ¶ 254 A categorical proportionality analysis is likewise
    warranted under article I, section 9 of the Utah Constitution. 3 At
    least one other state has engaged in a similar class-based
    examination under its state constitution. Workman v.
    Commonwealth, 
    429 S.W.2d 374
    , 377–78 (Ky. 1968) (holding that an
    LWOP sentence for rape categorically violated the Kentucky
    Constitution‘s ban on ―cruel punishment‖ when applied to
    juveniles). And, as already noted, because Utah‘s cruel and
    unusual punishments clause is rooted in the Eighth Amendment,
    it is highly persuasive that the federal language has been
    interpreted to include such a categorical analysis.
    ¶ 255 In conducting a categorical proportionality analysis,
    courts have addressed two questions: (1) whether ―community
    consensus‖ favors or disfavors the application of a given penalty
    3 In State v. Gardner, a plurality of this court reasoned that
    Utah‘s cruel and unusual punishments clause categorically
    prohibited the death penalty for the crime of aggravated assault
    while in prison. 
    947 P.2d 630
    , 645 (Utah 1997) (plurality opinion).
    A majority of the court, however, based its holding that the
    sentence was unconstitutionally disproportionate on the Eighth
    Amendment. 
    Id. at 653
    (Zimmerman, A.C.J., concurring).
    122
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           J. DURHAM, dissenting
    to a particular group and (2) whether that penalty is
    disproportionate based on a court‘s independent assessment.
    First, courts have asked whether statutory enactments or
    sentencing practices disfavor a particular punishment, indicating
    a consensus that the penalty is disproportionate when applied to a
    particular class. 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 66
    –67 (finding a consensus
    against juvenile LWOP for nonhomicide offenses); 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 567
    (consensus against the death penalty for juveniles); 
    Atkins, 536 U.S. at 316
    (consensus against the execution of persons with
    mental disabilities). Indicia of society‘s disapproval of a
    punishment suggest the penalty is disproportionate and
    ―unusual‖     under    the    Eighth    Amendment.      However,
    ―[c]ommunity consensus, while entitled to great weight, is not
    itself determinative of whether a punishment is cruel and
    unusual.‖ 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 67
    (internal quotation marks
    omitted). The ultimate responsibility for determining whether a
    punishment violates constitutional protections remains the
    province of the courts, which must exercise ―independent
    judgment.‖ 
    Id. As the
    Nevada Supreme Court has noted:
    More than any other provision in the Constitution
    the prohibition of cruel and unusual punishment
    depends largely, if not entirely, upon the
    humanitarian instincts of the judiciary. We have
    nothing to guide us in defining what is cruel and
    unusual apart from our consciences. . . . Our decision
    must necessarily spring from the mosaic of our
    beliefs, our backgrounds and the degree of our faith
    in the dignity of the human personality.
    Naovarath v. State, 
    779 P.2d 944
    , 947 (Nev. 1989) (internal quotation
    marks omitted). ―The judicial exercise of independent judgment
    requires consideration of the culpability of the offenders at issue
    in light of their crimes and characteristics, along with the severity
    of the punishment in question.‖ 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 67
    .
    B. Independent Assessment of the Proportionality
    of Juvenile LWOP
    ¶ 256 ―To be constitutionally proportionate, punishment must
    be tailored to a defendant‘s personal responsibility and moral
    guilt.‖ Harmelin v. Michigan, 
    501 U.S. 957
    , 1023 (1991) (White, J.,
    dissenting); accord Williams v. New York, 
    337 U.S. 241
    , 247 (1949)
    (―[T]he punishment should fit the offender and not merely the
    123
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    crime.‖); United States v. Barker, 
    771 F.2d 1362
    , 1365 (9th Cir. 1985)
    (―In each case, a criminal sentence must reflect an individualized
    assessment of a particular defendant‘s culpability rather than a
    mechanistic application of a given sentence to a given category of
    crime.‖). The Supreme Court has recognized that certain
    categories of individuals, such as persons with mental disabilities
    and juveniles, must be treated differently when evaluating the
    constitutionality of a sentence because members of these classes
    are less culpable than other individuals.4 
    Atkins, 536 U.S. at 311
    ,
    317, 321 (prohibiting the death penalty for persons with mental
    disabilities because of the reduced ―relative culpability of
    mentally retarded offenders‖); 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 571
    , 578
    (prohibiting the death penalty for juveniles because of their
    ―diminished culpability‖). In the context of offenders under the
    age of eighteen, ―imposition of a State‘s most severe penalties on
    juvenile offenders cannot proceed as though they were not
    children.‖ Miller v. Alabama, __ U.S. __, 
    132 S. Ct. 2455
    , 2466
    (2012).
    ¶ 257 In several recent cases, the Supreme Court has
    recognized that sentences appropriate for adult offenders may not
    be applied to juveniles. In Roper v. Simmons, the Court held that
    juveniles may not be subjected to the death penalty because it is
    ―disproportionate punishment for offenders under 
    18.‖ 543 U.S. at 575
    . The Court subsequently held in Graham v. Florida that a
    juvenile could not be sentenced to LWOP for a nonhomicide
    
    crime. 560 U.S. at 82
    . Finally, in Miller v. Alabama, the Court held
    that LWOP may not be imposed on a minor under a mandatory
    sentencing statute. __ U.S. at __, 132 S. Ct. at 2469. The Miller
    4  The law has also, for example, long recognized serious
    mental illness as a source of diminished capacity and tailored both
    concepts of culpability and sentencing accordingly. See, e.g., UTAH
    CODE § 76-2-305(1)(b) (―Mental illness . . . may be evidence in
    mitigation of the penalty in a capital felony . . . and may be
    evidence of special mitigation reducing the level of a criminal
    homicide or attempted criminal homicide offense . . . .‖); Archuleta
    v. Galetka, 
    2011 UT 73
    , ¶ 95, 
    267 P.3d 232
    (―[E]vidence of physical
    and sexual abuse and diminished mental capacities compose the
    kind of troubled history that may diminish moral culpability.‖
    (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    124
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           J. DURHAM, dissenting
    Court explicitly declined to consider, however, whether the
    Eighth Amendment categorically bars an LWOP sentence for
    juveniles, leaving that question open under the federal
    constitution. 
    Id. ¶ 258
    Roper, Graham, and Miller are founded upon the special
    circumstances of childhood that make juveniles less culpable and
    constitutionally different from adults. Miller, __ U.S. at __, 132
    S. Ct. at 2464 (―[C]hildren are constitutionally different from
    adults for purposes of sentencing. Because juveniles have
    diminished culpability and greater prospects for reform . . . they
    are less deserving of the most severe punishments.‖ (internal
    quotation marks omitted)); see also Thompson v. Oklahoma, 
    487 U.S. 815
    , 835 (1988) (plurality opinion) (―[L]ess culpability should
    attach to a crime committed by a juvenile than to a comparable
    crime committed by an adult.‖). These cases rely upon three
    fundamental characteristics of juveniles that separate them from
    adults: (1) a lack of maturity, (2) a greater vulnerability to negative
    influences, and (3) the fact that a juvenile‘s character is less fixed
    than an adult. Miller, __ U.S. at __, 132 S. Ct. at 2464. The
    mitigating characteristics of youth must also inform a
    proportionality analysis under the Utah Constitution.
    ¶ 259 First, juveniles are less culpable because they exhibit ―a
    lack of maturity and an underdeveloped sense of responsibility.‖
    
    Id. (internal quotation
    marks omitted). The underdeveloped
    nature of a juvenile‘s moral compass is not merely a matter of
    common-sense that ―any parent knows‖—it is rooted in the
    science of brain development. 
    Id. (internal quotation
    marks
    omitted). Due to a lack of maturity, ―‗adolescents are
    overrepresented statistically in virtually every category of reckless
    behavior.‘‖ 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 569
    (quoting Jeffrey Arnett, Reckless
    Behavior in Adolescence: A Developmental Perspective, 12
    DEVELOPMENTAL REV. 339, 339 (1992)).5 An adolescent‘s
    propensity for reckless and criminal activity is attributable, at
    5 See also Jeffrey Arnett, Reckless Behavior in Adolescence: A
    Developmental Perspective, 12 DEVELOPMENTAL REV. 339, 343 (―Even
    when factors such as education, occupation, family size, and
    quality of home life are taken into account, the association of age
    with criminal behavior is preeminent . . . .‖).
    125
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    least in part, to an underdeveloped brain: ―[D]evelopments in
    psychology and brain science continue to show fundamental
    differences between juvenile and adult minds. For example, parts
    of the brain involved in behavior control continue to mature
    through late adolescence.‖ 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 68
    . ―Scientists have
    found clear evidence that the brain continues to mature through
    adolescence and into the early twenties, with large scale structural
    change taking place during this period in the frontal lobes, most
    importantly within the prefrontal cortex, . . . . [which] is central to
    . . . advanced thinking processes that are employed in planning
    ahead and controlling impulses, and in weighing the costs and
    benefits of decisions before acting.‖ ELIZABETH S. SCOTT &
    LAURENCE STEINBERG, RETHINKING JUVENILE JUSTICE 44 (2008); see
    also 
    id. at 45
    (―Recent studies show substantial changes during
    [adolescence and early adulthood] in brain regions and systems
    associated with impulse control, the calibration of risk and
    reward, and the regulation of emotions.‖).
    ¶ 260 ―In recognition of the comparative immaturity and
    irresponsibility of juveniles, almost every State prohibits those
    under 18 years of age from voting, serving on juries, or marrying
    without parental consent.‖ 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 569
    ; accord 
    Thompson, 487 U.S. at 823
    (plurality opinion) (―Examples of this distinction
    [between juveniles and adults] abound in our law: in contracts, in
    torts, in criminal law and procedure, in criminal sanctions and
    rehabilitation, and in the right to vote and to hold office.‖ (internal
    quotation marks omitted)). The same markers of immaturity
    underlying the denial of certain rights to juveniles that are
    enjoyed by adults support the conclusion that juveniles are
    comparatively less blameworthy for crimes they may commit.
    
    Thompson, 487 U.S. at 835
    (plurality opinion).
    ¶ 261 Second, juveniles are more vulnerable to negative
    influences and are generally unable to extricate themselves from
    crime-ridden environments. 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 569
    . ―[Y]outh is
    more than a chronological fact. It is a time and condition of life
    when a person may be most susceptible to influence and to
    psychological damage.‖ Eddings v. Oklahoma, 45
    5 U.S. 1
    04, 115
    (1982). This susceptibility to negative influences is almost
    invariably coupled with a juvenile‘s inability to change his or her
    environment. Juveniles are dependent upon their parents or
    guardians for support and are unable to choose the neighborhood
    in which they live or, to great extent, the peers with whom they
    126
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                          J. DURHAM, dissenting
    associate. ELIZABETH S. SCOTT & LAURENCE STEINBERG, RETHINKING
    JUVENILE JUSTICE 135 (2008). Nor do juveniles choose abusive,
    neglectful, or chaotic family lives that are all too often associated
    with criminal behavior in minors. Given their increased
    susceptibility to influences they cannot control, ―juveniles have a
    greater claim than adults to be forgiven for failing to escape
    negative influences in their whole environment.‖ 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 570
    .
    ¶ 262 Third, a juvenile‘s character is less fixed than an adult
    and is less likely to be mired in irretrievable depravity and
    psychological damage. 
    Id. Studies have
    shown that a majority of
    juvenile offenders ―age out‖ of criminal behavior as they mature
    into adulthood. Laurence Steinberg & Elizabeth S. Scott, Less
    Guilty by Reason of Adolescence: Developmental Immaturity,
    Diminished Responsibility, and the Juvenile Death Penalty, 58 AM.
    PSYCHOLOGIST 1009, 1014 (2003) (―For most teens, [antisocial]
    behaviors are fleeting; they cease with maturity as individual
    identity becomes settled. Only a relatively small proportion of
    adolescents who experiment in risky or illegal activities develop
    entrenched patterns of problem behavior that persist into
    adulthood . . . .‖); Terrie E. Moffitt, Adolescence-Limited and Life-
    Course-Persistent Antisocial Behavior: A Developmental Taxonomy,
    100 PSYCHOL. REV. 674, 675 (1993) (―The majority of criminal
    offenders are teenagers; by the early 20s, the number of active
    offenders decreases by over 50%, and by age 28, almost 85% of
    former delinquents desist from offending . . . .‖). Given the often
    fleeting nature of juvenile criminal tendencies, ―[i]t is difficult
    even for expert psychologists to differentiate between the juvenile
    offender whose crime reflects unfortunate yet transient
    immaturity, and the rare juvenile offender whose crime reflects
    irreparable corruption.‖ 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 573
    . Because the adult
    who serves a life sentence will likely not be the same person who
    committed even a heinous crime while in their youth, juveniles
    are less deserving of the harsh sentence of LWOP.
    ¶ 263 The characteristics of youth that make juveniles less
    culpable than adults undermine the penological justifications for
    an LWOP sentence. ―A sentence lacking any legitimate
    penological justification is by its nature disproportionate to the
    offense.‖ 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 71
    ; accord 
    Atkins, 536 U.S. at 318
    –20
    (the death penalty for persons with mental disabilities is excessive
    because it does not further legitimate penological goals). Thus, a
    127
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    penalty that does not adequately serve at least one of the
    legitimate     social    goals     of  punishment—rehabilitation,
    incapacitation, deterrence, and retribution—is nothing more than
    the ―unnecessary and wanton infliction of pain‖ and violates
    Utah‘s cruel and unusual punishments clause. State v. Gardner, 
    947 P.2d 630
    , 634 (Utah 1997) (plurality opinion) (internal quotation
    marks omitted). Juvenile LWOP does not adequately further these
    traditional justifications for punishment.
    ¶ 264 LWOP serves no rehabilitative purpose, because the
    defendant will never be allowed to participate in society. Miller,
    __ U.S. at __, 132 S. Ct. at 2465 (―Life without parole forswears
    altogether the rehabilitative ideal.‖ (internal quotation marks
    omitted)). Indeed, individuals serving LWOP are often denied
    access to rehabilitation programs in prison for the simple reason
    they will never be released. Ashley Nellis, The Lives of Juvenile
    Lifers: Findings from a National Survey, THE SENTENCING PROJECT
    23–24 (Mar. 2012), http://sentencingproject.org/doc/publications
    /jj_The_Lives_of_Juvenile_Lifers.pdf.
    ¶ 265 On the other hand, an LWOP sentence does serve the
    penological goal of incapacitating the individual from committing
    future crimes—at least outside of prison. The incapacitation
    rationale, however, is only valid if the confined individual would
    commit additional crimes but for his or her incarceration. ―To
    justify life without parole [under an incapacitation theory] on the
    assumption that the juvenile offender forever will be a danger to
    society requires the sentencer to make a judgment that the
    juvenile is incorrigible.‖ 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 72
    . As noted above,
    however, making a determination that an individual will always
    be a danger to society based on crimes committed while a juvenile
    is very difficult given the often transient nature of juvenile
    criminal tendencies. Supra ¶ 262. Absent reliable indicators that a
    juvenile will forever be dangerous, the goal of incapacitation is
    severely undermined.
    ¶ 266 Juvenile LWOP likewise does not adequately serve the
    penological goal of deterrence. ―Because juveniles‘ lack of
    maturity and underdeveloped sense of responsibility . . . often
    result in impetuous and ill-considered actions and decisions, they
    are less likely to take a possible punishment into consideration
    when making decisions.‖ 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 72
    (alteration in
    original) (citation omitted) (internal quotation marks omitted); see
    also 
    Atkins, 536 U.S. at 319
    –20 (the death penalty for persons with
    128
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           J. DURHAM, dissenting
    mental disabilities does not further the goal of deterrence because
    they often have a diminished ability to control their conduct based
    upon potential legal penalties). Thus, potential juvenile offenders
    are not likely to be deterred by the possibility of an LWOP
    sentence.
    ¶ 267 The goal of retribution also does not justify juvenile
    LWOP. ―The heart of the retribution rationale is that a criminal
    sentence must be directly related to the personal culpability of the
    criminal offender.‖ Tison v. Arizona, 
    481 U.S. 137
    , 149 (1987).
    Because juveniles are inherently less culpable than adults, ―the
    case for retribution is not as strong with a minor as with an
    adult.‖ Miller, __ U.S. at __, 132 S. Ct. at 2465 (internal quotation
    marks omitted). Juveniles are less blameworthy because of their
    immaturity, susceptibility to negative influences they cannot
    control, and increased capacity to reform. Supra ¶¶ 259–62. This
    greatly weakens society‘s claim to retribution—especially where
    the punishment involves permanent incarceration. Thus,
    retribution is a weak justification for juvenile LWOP. Absent
    sufficient justification within any of the traditional rationales for
    punishment, juvenile LWOP constitutes the ―unnecessary and
    wanton infliction of pain.‖ See 
    Gardner, 947 P.2d at 634
    (Durham,
    J., plurality) (internal quotation marks omitted).
    ¶ 268 Finally,      when       conducting      a    constitutional
    proportionality analysis, courts must weigh the culpability of a
    particular class of individuals against the severity of the penalty.
    In this case, juveniles are not only less culpable than adults; an
    LWOP sentence is disproportionate because it is a harsher penalty
    for juveniles than it is for adults. LWOP sentences ―share some
    characteristics with death sentences that are shared by no other
    sentence[]‖ because ―[i]mprisoning an offender until he dies alters
    the remainder of his life by a forfeiture that is irrevocable.‖ Miller,
    __ U.S. at __, 132 S. Ct. at 2466 (internal quotation marks omitted).
    An LWOP sentence for juveniles ―means denial of hope; it means
    that good behavior and character improvement are immaterial; it
    means that whatever the future might hold in store for the mind
    and spirit of [the convict], he will remain in prison for the rest of
    his days.‖ 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 70
    (alteration in original) (internal
    quotation marks omitted). ―Under this sentence a juvenile
    offender will on average serve more years and a greater
    percentage of his life in prison than an adult offender.‖ 
    Id. An 129
                             STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    adult and a juvenile sentenced to LWOP ―receive the same
    punishment in name only.‖ 
    Id. ¶ 269
    Thus, in weighing the reduced culpability of juveniles
    against the severity of juvenile LWOP, I conclude such a sentence
    is unconstitutionally disproportionate under Utah‘s cruel and
    unusual punishments clause.
    C. Community Consensus
    ¶ 270 Although       community       consensus     regarding      a
    punishment is not determinative, it is relevant to an analysis of
    the constitutionality of juvenile LWOP. In gauging community
    consensus, the Supreme Court has looked to whether ―objective
    indicia of society‘s standards, as expressed in legislative
    enactments and state practice, show a national consensus against
    a sentence for a particular class of offenders.‖ Miller, __ U.S. at __,
    132 S. Ct. at 2470 (internal quotation marks omitted).
    ¶ 271 The first indication of society‘s standards—legislation
    regarding juvenile LWOP—is inconclusive. In a vast majority of
    states and in the federal criminal system, sentencing laws permit
    juvenile LWOP.6 
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 62
    (―Six jurisdictions do not
    allow life without parole sentences for any juvenile offenders [as
    of 2010].‖); State-By-State Legal Resource Guide, UNIV. OF S.F.
    PROJECT TO END JUVENILE LIFE WITHOUT PAROLE (Nov. 28, 2012),
    6   Unlike interpretations of the United States Constitution,
    which affect laws promulgated by the state legislatures of all fifty
    states, when we address a Utah constitutional question, only Utah
    laws are implicated. When analyzing legislative enactments to
    gauge community consensus regarding a particular punishment,
    however, it is still appropriate to analyze laws from other states to
    gauge national consensus. 
    Gardner, 947 P.2d at 640
    (plurality
    opinion) (in evaluating the constitutionality of a punishment
    under a state constitutional provision, courts should compare ―the
    challenged penalty with the punishments prescribed for the same
    offense in other jurisdictions‖ (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    Indeed, if we confined our analysis to Utah legislative enactments,
    this measure of community consensus would be circular and
    always favor the State because in order for a convict to challenge
    the constitutionality of a sentence, the Utah Legislature must have
    first authorized the punishment.
    130
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           J. DURHAM, dissenting
    https://www.usfca.edu/law/jlwop/resource_guide/ (juvenile
    LWOP prohibited in eight states and the District of Columbia as
    of November 2012). Simply tallying the jurisdictions that permit
    or prohibit this penalty, however, ―present[s] a distorted view.‖
    Miller, __ U.S. at __, 132 S. Ct. at 2472. Most state legislation
    permitting juvenile LWOP does so only indirectly. Statutes
    typically authorize certain juveniles to be tried as adults and
    receive an adult sentence, but transfer statutes typically do not
    address whether a particular sentence is appropriate when
    applied to a juvenile.7 Id. at __, 132 S. Ct. at 2472–73. Statutes that
    determine the conditions under which a juvenile may be
    transferred to the adult criminal system tells us that the states
    considered the juvenile ―to be old enough to be tried in criminal
    court for serious crimes (or too old to be dealt with effectively in
    juvenile court), but tells us nothing about the judgment these States
    have made regarding the appropriate punishment for such youthful
    offenders.‖ 
    Thompson, 487 U.S. at 826
    n.24 (plurality opinion). Thus,
    ―the statutory eligibility of a juvenile offender for life without
    parole does not indicate that the penalty has been endorsed
    through deliberate, express, and full legislative consideration.‖
    
    Graham, 560 U.S. at 67
    .
    ¶ 272 In this case, the second consideration when measuring
    community consensus—actual sentencing practices—provides a
    more definite indication of consensus. ―Actual sentencing
    practices are an important part of [an] inquiry into consensus.‖ 
    Id. at 62.
    Thus, even in jurisdictions where legislative enactments
    permit a particular penalty, infrequent imposition of the
    punishment may nonetheless indicate popular disapproval of the
    punishment. 
    Id. (infrequent imposition
    of juvenile LWOP for
    nonhomicide crimes in jurisdictions where the penalty ―is
    permitted by statute discloses a consensus against its use‖); 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 567
    (infrequent imposition of the death penalty on
    7 Until recently, Utah was among the states that only permitted
    juvenile LWOP through its transfer statutes. See UTAH CODE
    §§ 78A-6-602(3), 78A-6-702. In 2013, however, the legislature
    amended the aggravated murder statute to specify that juvenile
    defendants are not subject to the death penalty, but may be
    sentenced to either twenty-five years to life or LWOP. 2013 Utah
    Laws 317.
    131
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    juvenile offenders contributed to the Court‘s conclusion that
    society disapproved of the practice); 
    Atkins, 536 U.S. at 316
    (infrequent imposition of the death penalty on persons with
    mental disabilities indicated community disapproval). A rarely
    imposed sentence may also indicate the punishment is ―unusual‖
    within the meaning of the constitutional ban on cruel and unusual
    punishments.8 
    Atkins, 536 U.S. at 316
    .
    ¶ 273 Thus, the extreme infrequency of a juvenile LWOP
    sentence in Utah indicates societal disapproval of the punishment
    and that the sentence is ―unusual‖ within the meaning of Utah‘s
    cruel and unusual punishments clause. Indeed, prior to
    Mr. Houston receiving an LWOP sentence for a crime he
    committed while he was a juvenile, the punishment was more
    hypothetical than real. Mr. Houston is the only person serving a
    juvenile LWOP sentence in Utah. Juvenile Life Without Parole
    (JLWOP), NAT‘L CONFERENCE OF STATE LEGISLATURES 14 (Feb.
    2010), http://www.ncsl.org/documents/cj/jlwopchart.pdf; State
    Distribution of Estimated 2,589 Juvenile Offenders Serving Juvenile Life
    Without       Parol,     HUMAN        RIGHTS       WATCH        (2004),
    http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/related_material/upda
    tedJLWOP10.09.pdf. And there is every indication that despite the
    fact that juvenile LWOP, as well as the death penalty before the
    Supreme Court declared it unconstitutional, has long been
    available through the juvenile transfer statute, Mr. Houston is the
    only juvenile offender to ever receive such a harsh sentence in
    Utah. Jesse Fruhwirth, To Die in Prison, STANDARD-EXAMINER,
    May 6, 2007, at 1A. A sentence so rarely imposed despite its
    availability through legislative enactment demonstrates this
    punishment has never garnered wide-spread approval in Utah.
    ¶ 274 Finally, the international consensus against juvenile
    LWOP confirms my conclusion that this sentence is cruel and
    8 The deterrent effect of an infrequently imposed sentence is
    also greatly reduced, undermining this justification for imposing
    the penalty in the first instance. See Furman v. Georgia, 
    408 U.S. 238
    , 311 (1972) (White, J., concurring) (―[T]he death penalty could
    so seldom be imposed that it would cease to be a credible
    deterrent or measurably to contribute to any other end of
    punishment in the criminal justice system.‖).
    132
    Cite as: 
    2015 UT 36
                           J. DURHAM, dissenting
    unusual. International consensus regarding a particular penalty
    may be relevant in determining whether the punishment is cruel
    and unusual. 
    Roper, 543 U.S. at 575
    (―[A]t least from the time of
    the Court‘s decision in Trop, the Court has referred to the laws of
    other countries and to international authorities as instructive for
    its interpretation of the Eighth Amendment‘s prohibition of ‗cruel
    and unusual punishments.‘‖); 
    Thompson, 487 U.S. at 830
    n.31
    (plurality opinion) (―We have previously recognized the relevance
    of the views of the international community in determining
    whether a punishment is cruel and unusual.‖).
    ¶ 275 In the case of juvenile LWOP, the international
    consensus against the penalty is all but unanimous. The United
    States is the only country in the world that currently sentences
    juveniles to a life imprisonment with no chance of release. Connie
    de la Vega & Michelle Leighton, Sentencing Our Children to Die in
    Prison: Global Law and Practice, 42 U.S.F. L. REV. 983, 989 (2008).
    Only ten other counties have laws allowing a juvenile LWOP
    sentence: Antigua and Barbuda, Argentina, Australia, Belize,
    Brunei, Cuba, Dominica, Saint Vincent and the Grenadines, the
    Solomon Islands, and Sri Lanka. 
    Id. at 990.
    But researchers have
    been unable to identify any juveniles serving an LWOP sentence
    in these countries, indicating that, in practice, the United States is
    the only nation to actually impose irreversible life-long
    imprisonment on minors. 
    Id. at 990,
    1004–07.
    ¶ 276 International treaties confirm the international
    community‘s condemnation of juvenile LWOP. The U.N.
    Convention on Rights of the Child (CRC), adopted by almost
    every nation in the world, provides that ―[n]either capital
    punishment nor life imprisonment without possibility of release
    shall be imposed for offences committed by persons below
    eighteen years of age.‖ GA Res. 44/25, Annex, U.N. GAOR, 44th
    Sess., Supp. No. 49 at 167, U.N. Doc. A/44/49, at art. 37(a) (Nov.
    20, 1989). The United States and Somalia are the only countries
    that have not ratified the CRC. Connie de la Vega & Michelle
    Leighton, Sentencing Our Children to Die in Prison: Global Law and
    Practice, 42 U.S.F. L. REV. 983, 1009 (2008); Lisa S. Yun, The United
    States Stands Alone: An International Consensus Against Juvenile Life
    Without Parole Sentences, 20 S. CAL. INTERDISC. L.J. 727, 732 (2011);
    Jelani Jefferson & John W. Head, In Whose ―Best Interests‖?—An
    International and Comparative Assessment of US Rules on Sentencing
    of Juveniles, 1 HUM. RTS. & GLOBALIZATION L. REV. 89, 103 (2008).
    133
    STATE v. HOUSTON
    J. DURHAM, dissenting
    D. Conclusion
    ¶ 277 I agree with the majority‘s holding that Utah Rule of
    Criminal Procedure 22(e) requires this court to review
    Mr. Houston‘s unpreserved constitutional challenges to his
    sentence. I also agree with the majority that the cruel and unusual
    punishments clause of the Utah Constitution forbids
    disproportionate punishments—not just methods of punishment
    that are barbaric. Both this court‘s prior caselaw and an analysis of
    the text and history of this clause confirm that a disproportionate
    sentence may be both cruel and unusual.
    ¶ 278 I disagree, however, with the majority‘s conclusion that
    juvenile LWOP is not unconstitutionally disproportionate. Both
    the extreme infrequency of a juvenile LWOP sentence in Utah and
    global rejection of permanent incarceration for crimes committed
    before adulthood confirm my independent assessment that
    juvenile LWOP is cruel and unusual under the Utah Constitution.
    I would remand with instructions to administer the only other
    sentence available at the time of Mr. Houston‘s conviction: twenty
    years to life in prison. See UTAH CODE § 76-5-202(2) (2005); 
    id. § 76-3-207(5)(a)–(c)
    (2005). Mr. Houston may well prove to be an
    irretrievably depraved individual, and a parole board may never
    deem him fit to rejoin society. Under this scenario, Mr. Houston
    would justifiably spend the rest of his days behind bars. I find it
    cruel and unusual, however, to make an irreversible
    determination that he should die in prison based upon even a
    heinous crime committed while he was a minor.9 The special
    circumstances of youth, which make juveniles less blameworthy
    and more capable of reform than adults, require the justice system
    to treat children differently.
    9  I note that the record is replete with evidence that
    Mr. Houston suffers from mental illness and the psychological
    damage created by a history of abuse and neglect. With the option
    of eventual release, his access to treatment and services would be
    enhanced, and perhaps, therefore, his ability and motivation to
    transform his life.
    134