Blount v. Clarke , 291 Va. 198 ( 2016 )


Menu:
  • PRESENT: All the Justices
    TRAVION BLOUNT
    OPINION BY
    v. Record No. 151017                                      JUSTICE CLEO E. POWELL
    FEBRUARY 12, 2016
    HAROLD W. CLARKE, DIRECTOR
    OF THE VIRGINIA DEPARTMENT
    OF CORRECTIONS
    UPON QUESTIONS OF LAW CERTIFIED BY THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT
    FOR THE EASTERN DISTRICT OF VIRGINIA
    Pursuant to Article VI, Section 1 of the Constitution of Virginia, we accepted the
    following certified questions from the United States District Court for the Eastern District of
    Virginia, restated for the ease of presentation, pursuant to Rule 5:40(d):
    (1) Is the document which emanated from the Executive Department [on January 10,
    2014 and signed by then-Governor Robert F. McDonnell] to be considered [(a)] a . . . pardon or
    [(b)] a commutation?
    (2) Were the actions taken by the Governor of Virginia in [the aforementioned
    document] valid under the Virginia State Constitution?
    (Letter designators and alterations added). 1
    I. Background
    1
    Pursuant to Rule 5:40(d), we may restate a certified question as originally posed, when
    doing so will aid in “produc[ing] a determinative answer in the[] proceedings.” VanBuren v.
    Grubb, 
    284 Va. 584
    , 589, 
    733 S.E.2d 919
    , 921 (2012). As originally stated, both certified
    questions refer to a document appended to the District Court’s certification order and designated
    only as “Attachment A.” See Blount v. Clarke, Dir. of the Va. Dep’t of Corr., Civil Action No.
    2:12cv699, slip op. at 3 (E.D. Va. July 1, 2015). We have restated the certified questions to
    clarify that these references are to the January 10, 2014 executive order signed by then-Governor
    Robert F. McDonnell and have deleted the qualifier “conditional” before the word “pardon” to
    aid in producing a determinative answer.
    1
    In September 2006, then-fifteen-year-old Travion Blount participated with Morris
    Downing and David Nichols, both adults, in the armed robbery of numerous attendees of a house
    party in Norfolk, Virginia. Blount was indicted on 51 felony charges stemming from the
    robbery. Downing entered a guilty plea and was sentenced under a plea bargain to 10 years.
    Nichols similarly pleaded guilty and was sentenced to 13 years. Blount pleaded not guilty.
    On March 12, 2008, the Circuit Court for the City of Norfolk (“trial court”) found Blount
    guilty of 49 counts, including multiple robbery, attempted robbery, conspiracy to commit
    robbery, abduction, and firearm charges. Blount was sentenced to 118 mandatory years in prison
    for 24 firearm convictions and to six consecutive life terms for three abduction convictions and
    three robbery convictions. Blount unsuccessfully appealed his convictions to the Court of
    Appeals of Virginia and to this Court.
    The United States Supreme Court later ruled in Graham v. Florida, 
    560 U.S. 48
    , 82
    (2010), that “[t]he Constitution prohibits the imposition of a life without parole sentence on a
    juvenile offender who did not commit homicide” without offering a meaningful opportunity for
    release. Blount’s habeas petition and subsequent habeas appeals were refused, with our courts
    relying upon Angel v. Commonwealth, 
    281 Va. 248
    , 273-75, 
    704 S.E.2d 386
    , 401-02 (2011), in
    holding that Code § 53.1-40.01, which permits inmates to apply for conditional release at age
    sixty, provides “an appropriate mechanism” for compliance with Graham.
    On December 21, 2012, Blount filed a “Petition for Habeas Corpus By Prisoner In State
    Custody” pursuant to 28 U.S.C. § 2254 (“federal habeas petition”) in the United States District
    Court for the Eastern District of Virginia (“the District Court”), contending that his six life
    sentences without parole for the non-homicide offenses he had committed as a juvenile were
    unconstitutional under Graham and that this Court incorrectly held in Angel that Code § 53.1-
    2
    40.01 offered him a meaningful opportunity for release in his lifetime. The District Court denied
    the Commonwealth’s motion to dismiss Blount’s federal habeas petition. While discovery was
    pending in the District Court, Blount’s counsel filed a request for a conditional pardon with the
    Governor’s office on December 30, 2013. In his letter, Blount requested that then-Governor
    McDonnell grant him a conditional pardon of his six life sentences and 118-year sentence and
    modify his term of imprisonment “to a more appropriate amount of time for the crimes he
    committed, which many believe might be somewhere between ten and twenty years’
    incarceration.”
    On January 10, 2014, Governor McDonnell issued an executive order stating:
    NOW THEREFORE, in light of the record before me and in the
    interest of justice based on Blount’s young age at the time of the
    crime, his multi-life sentences compared to the sentences of his
    older co-conspirators without the possibility of parole, and in light
    of his complete criminal history and conduct while incarcerated in
    accordance with the provisions of the powers granted to me under
    Article V, Section 12 of the Constitution of Virginia, I Robert F.
    McDonnell, do hereby immediately grant Travion Blount, a
    COMMUTATION OF SENTENCE, reducing his term of
    incarceration for a total of forty (40) years for his offenses.
    ****
    Pardon granted: January 10, 2014
    On January 15, 2014, the Commonwealth filed a “Notice of Pardon” with the District
    Court and thereafter contended that the Governor’s “commutation” of Blount’s sentence made
    Blount’s petition for habeas corpus moot. In response, Blount filed a supplemental motion for a
    continuance, claiming that the Governor’s executive order may be construed only as a
    “conditional pardon” because the Governor has no power to commute non-capital offenses under
    Article V, Section 12 of the Constitution of Virginia as this Court construed that provision in Lee
    v. Murphy, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) 789 (1872).
    3
    The District Court entered an Order on August 6, 2014 granting Blount’s motion to
    continue and ordering further discovery, holding that the Governor did not have the authority to
    commute a non-capital offense as argued by Blount. In response, the Commonwealth filed a
    motion for reconsideration claiming that the District Court did not have the authority to decide
    this question of state constitutional law, that Lee was wrongly decided, and that, as a matter of
    practice for the past 143 years, the Governors of the Commonwealth have regularly exercised
    their power to commute non-capital offenses without contest.
    II. ANALYSIS
    A. Certified Question (1)
    1. Executive Clemency in Virginia
    Article V, Section 12 of the Constitution of Virginia provides:
    The Governor shall have power to remit fines and penalties
    under such rules and regulations as may be prescribed by law; to
    grant reprieves and pardons after conviction except when the
    prosecution has been carried on by the House of Delegates; to
    remove political disabilities consequent upon conviction for
    offenses committed prior or subsequent to the adoption of this
    Constitution; and to commute capital punishment.
    He shall communicate to the General Assembly, at each
    regular session, particulars of every case of fine or penalty
    remitted, of reprieve or pardon granted, and of punishment
    commuted, with his reasons for remitting, granting, or commuting
    the same.
    In construing constitutional provisions, the Court is “not permitted to speculate on what
    the framers of [a] section might have meant to say, but are, of necessity, controlled by what they
    did say.” Harrison v. Day, 
    200 Va. 439
    , 448, 
    106 S.E.2d 636
    , 644 (1959). If there are “no
    doubtful or ambiguous words or terms used, we are limited to the language of the section itself
    and are not at liberty to search for meaning, intent or purpose beyond the instrument.” 
    Id. 4 “Constitutions
    are not esoteric documents and recondite
    learning ought to be unnecessary when we come to interpret
    provisions apparently plain. They speak for the people in
    convention assembled, and must be obeyed.
    It is a general rule that the words of a Constitution are to be
    understood in the sense in which they are popularly employed,
    unless the context or the very nature of the subject indicates
    otherwise.”
    Lipscomb v. Nuckols, 
    161 Va. 936
    , 945, 
    172 S.E.2d 886
    , 889 (1934) (internal quotation marks
    and citation omitted) (quoting Quesinberry v. Hull, 
    159 Va. 270
    , 274, 
    165 S.E. 382
    , 383 (1932)).
    The words of Article V, Section 12 are unambiguous. Pursuant to its language, the
    Governor is vested with the power to (1) grant reprieves; (2) grant pardons; and (3) commute
    capital punishment. Nothing in the plain language of the Constitution purports to give the
    Governor power to commute sentences imposed for convictions on non-capital offenses.
    However, a brief review of the history surrounding the terms “pardon” and “commutation” is
    necessary to answer the certified questions propounded by the District Court.
    2. Pardon
    A pardon may be full or partial, absolute or conditional. In some
    of the States this is so by the express words of the constitution; and
    where the words are not express, the same result flows from the
    doctrine that with us a power general in its terms takes the
    construction given it in the English common law, whence our law
    is derived.
    Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 794.
    A pardon is defined as “[t]he act or an instance of officially nullifying punishment or
    other legal consequences of a crime.” Black’s Law Dictionary at 1286 (10th Ed. 2014). A
    conditional pardon is “[a] pardon that does not become effective until the wrongdoer satisfies a
    prerequisite or that will be revoked upon the occurrence of some specified act.” 
    Id. A partial
    5
    pardon is “[a] pardon that exonerates the offender from some but not all of the punishment or
    legal consequences of a crime.” 
    Id. A pardon
    in our days is not a private act of grace from an
    individual happening to possess power. It is a part of the
    Constitutional scheme. When granted it is the determination of the
    ultimate authority that the public welfare will be better served by
    inflicting less than what the judgment fixed. See Ex parte
    Grossman, 
    267 U.S. 87
    , 120, 121 [(1925)]. Just as the original
    punishment would be imposed without regard to the prisoner’s
    consent and in the teeth of his will, whether he liked it or not, the
    public welfare, not his consent, determines what shall be done. So
    far as a pardon legitimately cuts down a penalty, it affects the
    judgment imposing it. No one doubts that a reduction of the term
    of an imprisonment or the amount of a fine would limit the
    sentence effectively on the one side and on the other would leave
    the reduced term or fine valid and to be enforced, and that the
    convict’s consent is not required.
    Biddle v. Perovich, 
    274 U.S. 480
    , 486-87 (1927).
    3. Commutation
    A commutation is defined as “1. An exchange or replacement. 2. Criminal law. The
    executive’s substitution in a particular case of a less severe punishment for a more severe one
    that has already been judicially imposed on the defendant.” Black’s Law Dictionary at 339.
    When the General Assembly adopted the proposed and ratified Constitution of 1851, the term
    “commutation” signified a change or substitution “in kind” of punishment, a substitution of a
    “lesser” form for a “greater” form. Thus, a reduction in the term of imprisonment at that time
    would not have been understood as a “commutation,” but only a “partial pardon,” because it did
    not concern a change in the kind of punishment.
    Initially, the Executive Committee recommended imbuing the Governor with the power
    to “commute the punishment” generally. Register of the Debates and Proceedings of the Va.
    Reform Convention 71-72 (1851). Subsequently, the word “capital” was inserted to modify
    punishment, along with the clause requiring the Governor to communicate the “particulars of
    6
    every case of fine or penalty remitted, of reprieve or pardon granted, and of punishment
    commuted.” Debates and Proceedings of the Va. Reform Convention, Supplement. No. 82-1,
    Richmond Enquirer (July 14, 1851) (on file at the Library of Virginia).
    Then, during the debate on the provision at issue, Delegate Stanard spoke in opposition to
    giving the Governor the power “to commute capital punishment.” In his speech he articulates an
    understanding that a commutation is a change in the kind of punishment and is distinct from a
    pardon.
    It ought not to be left to the executive to say that he shall not be
    pardoned and that he shall be punished, not in the mode prescribed
    by law for a crime of which he has been guilty, but by some other
    mode which the executive may think more proper to be applied.
    Debates and Proceedings of the Va. Reform Convention, Supp. No 82-2, Richmond Enquirer
    (July 15, 1851) (on file at the Library of Virginia) (emphasis added).
    Delegate Stanard’s understanding of the term “commutation” as a change in the kind of
    punishment finds support from Justice McLean in Ex parte Wells, 
    59 U.S. 307
    , 319-20 (1856)
    (McLean, J., dissenting). In dissent, Justice McLean distinguished between the power to pardon
    and the power to commute while explaining why the executive order at issue was actually an
    unauthorized commutation, not a conditional pardon. Justice McLean wrote regarding the power
    to pardon:
    I have no doubt the President, under the power to pardon, may
    remit the penalty in part, but this consists in shortening the time of
    imprisonment, or reducing the amount of the fine, or in releasing
    entirely from the one or the other. This acts directly upon the
    sentence of the court, under the law, and is strictly an exercise of
    the pardoning power in lessening the degree of punishment . . . .
    
    Id. at 319-20.
    In contrast,
    [t]he power of commutation overrides the law and the judgments
    of courts. It substitutes a new . . . punishment for that which the
    7
    law prescribes a specific penalty. It is, in fact, a suspension of the
    law, and substituting some other punishment which, to the
    executive, may seem to be more reasonable and proper.
    
    Id. at 319
    (emphasis added). Clearly, they were distinguishing commutations from partial
    pardons, supporting the proposition that the two are separate and independent, though closely
    related, acts of clemency. One lessens the punishment by degrees (partial pardon) the other
    changes the kind of punishment from death to life imprisonment (commutation).
    Other states addressing the issue in the timeframe of our constitutional amendment
    recognized a similar distinction between pardons and commutations. See Ogletree v. Dozier, 
    59 Ga. 800
    , 802 (1877) (“In its legal sense, to commute would mean to change from a higher to a
    lower punishment — to change a penalty from the hard work of a chain-gang to work on a farm,
    for instance . . . .”); People ex rel. Smith v. Jenkins, 
    156 N.E. 290
    , 292 (Ill. 1927)
    (“[Commutation] is defined in Bouvier’s Law Dictionary as ‘the change of a punishment to
    which a person has been condemned into a less severe one,’ and in Anderson’s Law Dictionary
    as ‘the substitution of a less for a greater penalty or punishment; the change of the punishment
    for another and different punishment, both being known to the law.’”); Rich v. Chamberlain, 
    65 N.W. 235
    , 235 (Mich. 1895) (citations omitted) (“To commute is defined: ‘to exchange one
    penalty or punishment for another, less severe. . . . [t]he change of a punishment to which a
    person has been condemned into a less severe one.’”); Ex parte Parker, 
    17 S.W. 658
    , 660 (Mo.
    1891) (“Commutation is defined . . . to be ‘the change of punishment to which a person has been
    condemned into a less severe one.’”); Ex parte William Janes, 
    1 Nev. 319
    , 321 (1865) (“A
    commutation is the change of one punishment known to the law for another and different
    punishment also known to the law.”); State v. Hildebrand, 
    95 A.2d 488
    , 489 (N.J. Super. 1953)
    (“This constitutional grant of the pardoning power carried with it the lesser powers of granting
    8
    remission of part of the penalty, of granting commutation of sentence, and of granting a limited
    or partial pardon, although none of these lesser powers is specifically mentioned.”); State ex rel.
    Attorney-General v. Peters, 
    4 N.E. 81
    (Ohio 1885) (citation omitted) (“A pardon discharges the
    individual designated from all or some specified penal consequences of his crime. It may be full
    or partial, absolute or conditional. . . . [C]ommutation is ‘the change of a punishment to which a
    person has been condemned into a less severe one.’”).
    4. The January 10, 2014 Executive Order
    “It is well settled that no technical words or terms are necessary to constitute a pardon.”
    Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 799. Here, because the Governor’s order does not purport to change
    the kind of punishment, but rather it changes the degree or length of Blount’s incarceration, it is
    a partial pardon and not a commutation. Blount argues that because the executive order says
    “COMMUTATION OF SENTENCE” the Governor’s actions were invalid because the Governor
    is only vested with the power to issue commutations in capital cases. Blount further asserts at
    most that the Executive Order is only valid as a conditional pardon, which he does not accept.
    We disagree with Blount’s assertions for two reasons.
    Blount is correct that the executive order says “COMMUTATION OF SENTENCE.”
    However, as recognized in Lee, the courts should operate to “effectuate rather than defeat the
    intention of the State.” 
    Id. at 801.
    Lee also recognized that the same interpretation of the law as
    applied to acts of the king should apply to that of the Governor:
    if the king’s grant admits of two interpretations, one of which will
    make it utterly void and worthless, and the other will give it a
    reasonable effect, then the latter is to prevail, for the reason, says
    the common law, that it will be more for the benefit of the subject
    and the honor of the king; which is more to be regarded than his
    profit.
    And the same rule should be held to apply to the grants of a
    State.
    9
    
    Id. (citation omitted).
    We also disagree with Blount’s contention that if not invalid as a commutation of a
    noncapital crime, the executive order is a conditional pardon. Blount argues as if there are only
    two alternatives, either a commutation or a conditional pardon. As was the case in Wells, the
    question here is not one of practice or even a habitual mislabeling of an act, rather it is purely
    one of constitutional interpretation. See Ex parte 
    Wells, 59 U.S. at 309
    . The Constitution does
    not restrict pardons to conditional pardons. However, there are various kinds of pardons.
    “[A] pardon may be full or partial, absolute or conditional. A
    pardon is full when it freely and unconditionally absolves the
    person from all the legal consequences of a crime and of the
    person’s conviction, direct and collateral, including the
    punishment, whether of imprisonment, pecuniary penalty, or
    whatever else the law has provided; it is partial where it remits
    only a portion of the punishment or absolves from only a portion of
    the legal consequences of the crime. A pardon is absolute where it
    frees the criminal without any condition whatsoever; and it is
    conditional where it does not become operative until the grantee
    has performed some specified act, or where it becomes void when
    some specified event transpires.”
    People ex rel. Madigan v. Snyder, 
    804 N.E.2d 546
    , 557 (Ill. 2004) (quoting 67A C.J.S. Pardon &
    Parole § 2, at 6 (2002)). These distinctions have been acknowledged both in Lee, 63 Va. (22
    Gratt.) at 794 (observing that “[a] pardon may be full or partial, absolute or conditional”), and in
    Ex parte 
    Wells, 59 U.S. at 310
    (“[E]very pardon has its particular denomination. They are
    general, special, or particular, conditional or absolute, [or] statutory.”).
    Here, Blount requested that the Governor grant him a conditional pardon. Governor
    McDonnell did not attach any conditions to the reduction in the degree of punishment for Blount.
    Because there were no conditions attached to the pardon and Governor McDonnell did not
    include anything that would signal the need for Blount’s consent (unlike the Governor in Lee,
    who included a signature line for the defendant’s consent), Blount did not receive a conditional
    10
    pardon. Blount also did not receive a commutation. As we stated above, the Governor is only
    vested with the power to commute capital punishment. Also, the reduction to Blount’s
    punishment was in degree, not in kind. 2 That is a distinction that was recognized at the time the
    Constitution was amended.
    Accordingly, we hold that the answer to certified question (1) is that the executive order
    from Governor McDonnell constitutes a partial pardon because it exonerated him from some but
    not all of the punishment for his crimes. As the executive order is a partial pardon, it is self-
    executing, and its efficacy does not depend on whether Blount would accept it or reject it.
    B. Certified Question (2)
    Because we find that the executive order from Governor McDonnell constitutes a partial
    pardon, we answer certified question (2) in the affirmative. The Commonwealth concedes on
    brief that the Governor has the power to issue a conditional pardon or a partial pardon as those
    are lesser powers subsumed within the general pardoning power granted by Article V, Section 12
    of the Constitution of Virginia. As we have previously held, “[a] pardon may be full or partial,
    absolute or conditional.” Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 794.
    III. CONCLUSION
    For the reasons stated above, certified question (1), alternative (a) is answered in the
    affirmative, as the executive order constitutes a partial pardon. Certified question (2) is likewise
    answered in the affirmative.
    Certified question (1), alternative (a) answered in the affirmative.
    Certified question (2) answered in the affirmative.
    2
    In Lee, the executive order purported to change the sentence from imprisonment in the
    penitentiary to imprisonment in the city jail — a change in the form of imprisonment.
    11
    JUSTICE KELSEY, with whom JUSTICE McCLANAHAN and JUSTICE ROUSH join,
    dissenting.
    Our opinion in Lee v. Murphy, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) 789 (1872), has been on the books for
    over a century. Applying Lee to this case, I would hold that Governor Robert F. McDonnell
    issued exactly what he said he issued — a commutation of the criminal sentences imposed on
    Travion Blount. We could judicially construe it to be a conditional pardon, as we did in Lee, but
    that would require Blount’s acceptance, something he has steadfastly refused to give. Without
    Blount’s assent, the Governor’s act of clemency has no legal effect because the Constitution of
    Virginia does not authorize non-consensual commutations of noncapital sentences.
    I.
    In 2013, while his federal habeas case was pending, Blount requested that then-Governor
    McDonnell “commute” his sentences to a lesser period of incarceration. J.A. at 35. Blount
    acknowledged that the power to do so depended upon the characterization of his request as a
    “conditional pardon.” 
    Id. at 27,
    32, 35, 36. On January 10, 2014, Governor McDonnell issued
    an executive order. The order stated that Blount had requested a “conditional pardon.” 
    Id. at 38.
    The Governor granted it as follows:
    NOW THEREFORE, in light of the record before me and in the
    interest of justice based on Blount’s young age at the time of the
    crime, his multi-life sentences compared to the sentences of his
    older co-conspirators without the possibility of parole, and in
    light of his complete criminal history and conduct while
    incarcerated in accordance with the provisions of the powers
    granted to me under Article V, Section 12 of the Constitution of
    Virginia, I, Robert F. McDonnell, do hereby immediately grant
    Travion T. Blount, a COMMUTATION OF SENTENCE,
    reducing his term of incarceration for a total of forty (40) years
    for his offenses.
    ....
    Pardon granted: January 10, 2014
    12
    On January 15, 2014, the Commonwealth filed a “Notice of Pardon” with the United
    States District Court, which stated that the Governor “pardoned” Blount and “commuted” his
    prior sentences. 
    Id. at 40.
    Also included was an affidavit from an official with the Virginia
    Department of Corrections affirming that she had received the “Commutation” from the
    Governor that had “commuted” Blount’s sentences. 
    Id. at 43.
    The Commonwealth argued that the Governor’s clemency rendered moot Blount’s
    federal petition for habeas corpus. In response, Blount claimed that the Governor’s executive
    order may be construed only as a conditional pardon because the Governor has no power to
    commute noncapital offenses under Article V, Section 12 of the Constitution of Virginia as this
    Court construed that provision in Lee. The federal habeas petition was not moot, Blount argued,
    because his pardon was conditioned upon his acceptance — which he refused to give.
    The United States District Court certified two questions to us concerning the legal nature
    and validity of the executive clemency offered to Blount. The first question asks whether the
    “document” issued by Governor McDonnell to Blount was a “conditional pardon” or a
    “commutation.” J.A. at 103. The second question asks if it was legally valid under the
    Constitution of Virginia. See 
    id. 1 On
    these issues, both the Commonwealth and Blount have
    advocated with clarity and precision. The majority, however, rejects both parties’ arguments and
    adopts a novel theory not advanced by either party. In short, the majority holds that
    commutations of noncapital offenses violate the Constitution of Virginia (as Lee held), but,
    1
    Rule 5:40(d) authorizes us to restate a certified question as originally posed, when
    doing so will aid in producing a “determinative answer” in the proceedings. VanBuren v. Grubb,
    
    284 Va. 584
    , 589, 
    733 S.E.2d 919
    , 921 (2012). The majority uses that authority to excise the
    word “conditional” from the District Court’s first certified question, which originally asked
    whether Governor McDonnell’s act of clemency should be considered a “conditional pardon” or
    a “commutation.” Ante at 1 & n.1. The excision of that one word summarizes the majority’s
    entire opinion and lays bare its principal conceptual flaw.
    13
    regardless, Governor McDonnell did not issue a commutation to Blount — indeed, he could not
    have done so, because commutations by definition do not include a mere reduction in a convict’s
    term of incarceration. Because I know of no legal precedent supporting that view, I respectfully
    dissent.
    II.
    A. ABSOLUTE & CONDITIONAL PARDONS
    The executive power of clemency “reveals a consistent pattern of adherence to the
    English common-law practice.” Schick v. Reed, 
    419 U.S. 256
    , 262 (1974); see also Lee, 63 Va.
    (22 Gratt.) at 791-92. Historically, Anglo-American common law has included several related,
    but conceptually distinct, subsets of executive clemency.
    Early precedents described an absolute pardon as reaching “both the punishment
    prescribed for the offence and the guilt of the offender; and when the pardon is full, it releases
    the punishment and blots out of existence the guilt, so that in the eye of the law the offender is as
    innocent as if he had never committed the offence.” Ex parte Garland, 
    71 U.S. 333
    , 380 (1867). 2
    In this respect, an absolute pardon constituted a “complete remission of any legal consequences
    emanating from a particular crime,” Stanley Grupp, Some Historical Aspects of the Pardon in
    England, 7 Am. J. Legal Hist. 51 (1963), and restored “the competency of the offender and
    remove[d] the infamy of the conviction,” Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 799. 3 This principle tracked
    the common-law view that “the effect of such pardon by the king [was] to make the offender a
    2
    An “absolute pardon” must be distinguished from a “simple pardon,” which “forgives
    the legal violation, but does not erase the individual’s criminal record; nor does it restore his civil
    rights unless such relief is specifically given in the pardoning document.” Walter A. McFarlane,
    The Clemency Process in Virginia, 27 U. Rich. L. Rev. 241, 246 (1993).
    3
    “There is only this limitation to its operation: it does not restore offices forfeited, or
    property or interests vested in others in consequence of the conviction and judgment.” Ex parte
    
    Garland, 71 U.S. at 381
    .
    14
    new man” and “to acquit him of all corporal penalties and forfeitures annexed to that offence for
    which he obtain[ed] his pardon.” 4 William Blackstone, Commentaries *402. Compare
    Edwards v. Commonwealth, 
    78 Va. 39
    , 41-42 (1883), with Prichard v. Battle, 
    178 Va. 455
    , 465-
    66, 
    17 S.E.2d 393
    , 397 (1941).
    A conditional pardon required the satisfaction of a condition “whether precedent or
    subsequent” upon “the performance whereof the validity of the pardon will depend.” 2 William
    Hawkins, A Treatise of the Pleas of the Crown § 45, at 547 (8th ed. 1824); see also 4 
    Blackstone, supra
    , at *401; 1 Joseph Chitty, A Practical Treatise on the Criminal Law 533 (1819). A pardon
    is subject to a condition precedent “if by its terms some event is to transpire before it takes
    effect,” and the pardon’s “operation is deferred until the event occurs.” 1 Joel P. Bishop, New
    Commentaries on the Criminal Law § 914, at 555 (8th ed. 1892). “If the condition is subsequent,
    the pardon goes into operation immediately, yet becomes void whenever the condition is
    broken.” 
    Id. There is
    high authority for the proposition that all pardons, absolute or conditional,
    required the assent of the convict. 1 Bishop, supra, § 907, at 550. As Chief Justice John Marshall
    explained:
    A pardon is a deed, to the validity of which delivery is essential,
    and delivery is not complete without acceptance. It may then be
    rejected by the person to whom it is tendered; and if it be rejected,
    we have discovered no power in a court to force it on him.
    It may be supposed that no being condemned to death would reject
    a pardon; but the rule must be the same in capital cases and in
    misdemeanours. A pardon may be conditional; and the condition
    may be more objectionable than the punishment inflicted by the
    judgment.
    United States v. Wilson, 
    32 U.S. 150
    , 161 (1833); see also Burdick v. United States, 
    236 U.S. 79
    ,
    90-91 (1915). Chief Justice Marshall’s maxim held sway until another titan of the law, Justice
    15
    Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., rejected it in Biddle v. Perovich, 
    274 U.S. 480
    , 486-87 (1927).
    We have never been put to the unenviable task of trying to choose between the views of
    these two great jurists on the question of whether pardons generally (both conditional and
    unconditional) must be accepted by the convict to be effective. But in Lee we made clear our
    agreement with Chief Justice Marshall’s consent requirement on the effectiveness of conditional
    pardons: “A conditional pardon is a grant, to the validity of which acceptance is essential. It
    may be rejected by the convict; and if rejected, there is no power to force it upon him.” Lee, 63
    Va. (22 Gratt.) at 798. 4
    B. COMMUTATIONS: LESSENING A LAWFUL PUNISHMENT
    A pardon should be distinguished from a mere commutation. “A commutation is the
    substitution of a less for a greater punishment, by authority of law,” Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at
    798 (emphasis added), or “a change of punishment from a higher to a lower degree, in the scale
    of crimes and penalties fixed by the law,” In re Victor, 
    31 Ohio St. 206
    , 207 (1877) (emphasis
    added). In other words, a commutation is a “change of a punishment to which a person has been
    condemned into a less severe one,” 1 John Bouvier, A Law Dictionary 258 (5th ed. 1854),
    accomplished by substituting “a smaller for a greater punishment,” Willard H. Humbert, The
    Pardoning Power of the President 27 (1941).
    4
    As applied to conditional pardons, these consent principles likely developed in response
    to the concern that “[a]buses of the pardoning power in England as elsewhere have existed since
    the earliest times.” 
    Grupp, supra, at 58
    . Conditional pardons were issued by English kings to
    recruit soldiers for war, 1 Luke Owen Pike, History of Crime in England 294-95 (1873), to
    banish criminals to colonies and plantations in America, 11 William Holdsworth, A History of
    English Law 570 (1938), to force criminals into periods of hard labor, 
    Schick, 419 U.S. at 261
    n.3 (citing 4 
    Blackstone, supra
    , at *401), and even to extort money from criminals by cash-
    strapped monarchs using the pardon as “a means of financial exploitation,” 
    Grupp, supra, at 59
    (citing 1 F. W. Maitland, Select Pleas of the Crown 85-86 (1888)).
    16
    We have adopted the traditional definition of commutations. “Commutation is simple,”
    we have said, because it is nothing more than “the substitution of a less for a greater penalty or
    punishment.” Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 799. It applies when “the original punishment is
    remitted, and a milder sentence is substituted.” 
    Id. As the
    Attorney General of Virginia
    correctly opined over a half-century ago:
    I am in receipt of your letter . . . asking for the authority of the
    Governor to commute a life sentence to a term of years.
    Under constitutional provisions substantially similar to those now
    in existence, the [Supreme] Court of Appeals had this question
    before it in Lee v. Murphy, 
    22 Gratt. 789
    . The majority opinion in
    that case provides that the Governor has power, with the consent of
    the prisoner, to substitute a milder sentence for the original
    punishment.
    1932 Op. Atty. Gen. 102, 102; see also 1916 Op. Atty. Gen. 203, 203 (describing a reduction in a
    sentence from 90 days to 30 days incarceration as “in the nature of a commutation” which, if
    accepted by the convict, constitutes a lawful “conditional pardon”). 5
    In addition, while a commutation reduces the legally prescribed punishment for the
    crime, it does so without vacating the conviction of the crime or canceling the collateral
    consequences that accompany it. By “merely substitut[ing] lighter for heavier punishment,” a
    commutation “removes no stain, restores no civil privilege, and may be effected without the
    5
    Because a commutation can reduce a sentence both in degree and in kind, an executive
    can “commute a sentence to the time already served or a death penalty to a life sentence.”
    Kathleen Dean Moore, Pardons: Justice, Mercy, and the Public Interest 5 (1989); see also
    
    Humbert, supra, at 27
    (giving, as examples of commutations, changing “the form of punishment
    from a penalty of death to one of life imprisonment” or “reduc[ing] a sentence of twenty-five
    years to one of fifteen years”). “The word [commutation] is a term of art and means, and long
    has meant, the change of one punishment for another and different punishment.” United States
    ex rel. Brazier v. Commissioner of Immigration, 
    5 F.2d 162
    , 165 (2d Cir. 1924). It thus follows
    that “[a] punishment by imprisonment for one year is a different punishment from the fulfillment
    of a two-year sentence, and this is true even though the change is made when the two-year
    sentence is half served.” 
    Id. 17 consent
    and against the will of the prisoner.” In re Charles, 
    222 P. 606
    , 608 (Kan. 1924).
    “Whereas commutation is a substitution of a milder form of punishment, pardon is an act of
    public conscience that relieves the recipient of all the legal consequences of the conviction.”
    
    Schick, 419 U.S. at 273
    n.8 (Marshall, J., dissenting). Thus, unlike a pardon, a mere
    commutation does not “make the offender a new man” in the eyes of the law. 4 
    Blackstone, supra
    , at * 402. His conviction stands untouched legally, and only his sentence is mitigated.
    Unlike a pardon, a true commutation is imposed upon, not offered to, the convict. A
    commutation intends, in general, to satisfy the collective public conscience personified in the
    clement executive and, in particular, to tailor a more measured justice in a case that sometimes
    appears clear only in hindsight. See 
    Biddle, 274 U.S. at 486
    (“[I]t is the determination of the
    ultimate authority that the public welfare will be better served by inflicting less than what the
    judgment fixed.”); 
    Humbert, supra, at 68-69
    (citing 
    Biddle, 274 U.S. at 486
    ). A commutation,
    therefore, “may be imposed upon the convict without his acceptance, and against his consent.”
    Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 798. 6
    C. CONDITIONAL COMMUTATIVE PARDONS
    Over a century ago in Lee, we recognized a hybrid act of clemency that fused the
    attributes of conditional pardons and true commutations. In that case, a Virginia governor issued
    what he titled a “commutation” to Lawrence Murphy that “commuted” his sentence from three
    6
    “It is urged that the exercise of the power of commutation is but the exercise of the
    pardoning prerogative in a lesser degree, and that, if the gift of a pardon is incomplete without
    acceptance, the lesser grant is surely so.” Chapman v. Scott, 
    10 F.2d 156
    , 159 (D. Conn. 1925),
    aff’d, 
    10 F.2d 690
    (2d Cir. 1926). “We may acknowledge the premise without acceding to the
    conclusion, because the fact is that a distinction does exist between a pardon and a commutation,
    and the legal principles applicable are no longer open to question,” and thus, “[t]he rule of law is
    well settled that a commutation does not need acceptance by the convict in order to be
    operative.” 
    Id. at 159-60
    (relying on Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 798); see also In re 
    Victor, 31 Ohio St. at 207
    .
    18
    years to twelve months. We acknowledged that the governor’s warrant did “not purport to be a
    pardon of any sort, but a mere commutation of punishment.” 
    Id. at 799.
    The commutation did
    not vacate the conviction upon the completion of the reduced sentence, reduce the charge of
    conviction to a lesser charge, or purport to affect in any way the collateral consequences of the
    conviction. The only thing it did was “remit the punishment imposed by the law” and
    “substitute[d] another in its place.” 
    Id. at 801.
    This presented quite a problem because the Constitution of Virginia, both then and now,
    authorized the governor to issue commutations only to those sentenced to death. Compare Va.
    Const. art. V, § 12, with Va. Const. art. IV, § 5 (1870). 7 In Virginia, “the executive is only
    authorized to commute capital punishment.” Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 798. “The implication is
    almost irresistible that commutation, in other than capital cases, is forbidden by the constitution
    of 1851.” 
    Id. at 811
    (Bouldin, J., dissenting). As an Attorney General of Virginia has explained:
    If the executive had been granted the general power to pardon
    without more, it is well settled that such a grant would have
    included the lesser power of commutation upon the theory that, if
    the whole offense may be pardoned, a fortiori a part of the
    punishment may be remitted or the sentence commuted. But the
    section has expressly defined the power to commute sentences by
    saying that the executive has the power to “commute capital
    punishment.” The implication is plain that commutation in other
    than capital cases is excluded. . . . My conclusion is that in
    Virginia the Governor does not have the power to commute
    sentences except in capital cases.
    1943 Op. Atty. Gen. 126, 127 (citing Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 798); see also 1916 Op. Atty.
    Gen. at 203.
    7
    Pardons, on the other hand, could be issued to any convict convicted of capital or
    noncapital crimes. Va. Const. art. IV, § 5 (1870). The same is true in the current Constitution of
    Virginia. Va. Const. art. V, § 12.
    19
    Relying on settled principles, we concluded in Lee that the commutation given to Murphy
    was merely “the substitution of a less for a greater punishment” and that the governor’s
    commutation merely “remitted” Murphy’s “original punishment” and substituted in its place a
    “milder sentence.” Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 799. These observations led us to a delicate
    question in Lee. Should the governor’s clemency “be regarded as an attempted commutation of
    punishment,” which would have been an unconstitutional, ultra vires act, or “as a conditional
    pardon,” which would have been constitutionally authorized? 
    Id. at 798.
    If the governor
    intended to issue a true commutation, the inference might arise “that he was either ignorant of his
    constitutional functions, or that it was his purpose to transcend them.” 
    Id. at 801.
    We fought off that inference by presuming that the governor intended “to exercise just
    such powers as are vested in him by the constitution,” and thus, “we should give his official acts
    a fair and liberal interpretation, so as to make them valid if possible.” 
    Id. Giving the
    governor
    the benefit of the doubt, we reasoned that his commutation, “[i]f followed by the acceptance of
    the convict . . . practically amounts to the same thing as a conditional pardon.” 
    Id. at 799.
    We
    dismissed the contention that the governor’s commutation could not “be considered a conditional
    pardon, because neither the word ‘pardon’ nor any equivalent phrase is used therein.” 
    Id. 8 “Upon
    the whole,” Lee concluded, the governor’s putative commutation should be
    judicially construed “as a conditional pardon, if not of the offence, certainly of the punishment
    imposed by the law.” 
    Id. at 802
    (emphasis added). Murphy’s pardon was conditioned upon his
    acceptance of the lesser, “substituted punishment.” 
    Id. While that
    may seem odd, we
    8
    We understood that it would not be a full pardon, which “restores the competency of the
    offender and removes the infamy of the conviction.” Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 799. Instead, it
    had the “operation and effect” of a partial pardon that, like a commutation, “merely remitt[ed] or
    releas[ed] the punishment without removing the guilt of the offender,” and “[i]f followed by the
    acceptance of the convict, it practically amounts to the same thing as a conditional pardon.” 
    Id. 20 emphasized
    that the governor “is authorized to substitute, with the consent of the prisoner, any
    punishment recognized by statute or the common law as enforced in this State.” 
    Id. (emphasis added).
    Because Murphy had already signed the commutation to denote his acceptance, we
    construed it to be a conditional pardon, rather than a true commutation, and thus constitutionally
    valid. Lee recognizes the constitutional authority of a Virginia governor “to impose a lesser
    punishment than that under which the prisoner stands sentenced, which is in the nature of a
    commutation, if done with the consent of the prisoner,” because this act of executive clemency
    can be judicially construed “to be a conditional pardon and not a commutation of punishment.”
    1916 Op. Atty. Gen. at 203. This rather generous construction, however, depended entirely on
    “the condition of the convict’s voluntarily submitting to the lesser punishment.” 
    Id. In short,
    the
    analytical structure of Lee rests upon a simple syllogism:
     A commutation is merely a lesser punishment and, in Virginia, can
    only be issued to convicts with death sentences.
     A commutation of a noncapital sentence will be judicially construed
    to be a lawful conditional pardon if it is conditioned upon the
    convict’s acceptance of the lesser punishment.
     Thus, a conditional pardon can be rejected by the convict.
    This approach remains faithful to the Constitution of Virginia while acknowledging that, in
    Virginia, “the pardon power has been used for commutation of a sentence for a term of years.”
    William F. Stone, Jr., Pardons in Virginia, 26 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 307, 309 n.15 (1969); see
    also 1932 Op. Atty. Gen. at 102; 1916 Op. Atty. Gen. at 203.
    Applied to this case, the logic of Lee confirms Blount’s view that his commutation could
    be constitutionally valid only if we construed it as a conditional pardon — the condition being
    that he accept the lesser, substituted punishment. He has expressly refused to do so, however.
    21
    As a result, even if we inferred a condition of acceptance in the commutation issued to Blount,
    that implied condition has not been satisfied. I thus would hold that the commutation — whether
    or not construed as a conditional pardon — is not legally binding on Blount and that his original
    sentences are still in effect. 9
    D. THE NEW COMMUTATION PARADIGM
    The majority’s reasoning takes a very different path. Lee is briefly mentioned but then
    quickly sidelined by the conclusory statement that Blount did not receive either a “conditional
    pardon” or a “commutation.” Ante at 10-11. I find this hard to understand given that Governor
    McDonnell treated Blount’s request as one seeking a “conditional pardon” and granted that
    request by issuing a “COMMUTATION OF SENTENCE” followed by the notation, “Pardon
    granted: January 10, 2014.” 
    Id. at 38-39
    (capitalization in original). 10
    By refusing to recognize this executive order as either a conditional pardon or a
    commutation, the majority’s reasoning has the intended effect of extinguishing Blount’s ability
    to reject Governor McDonnell’s clemency, a right recognized by Lee. The majority’s holding
    also will have the unintended, but easily foreseeable, effect of restructuring longstanding
    constitutional principles governing executive clemency in Virginia. All this is accomplished,
    remarkably so, without overruling Lee.
    9
    I am aware that Blount’s reason for rejecting his conditional commutative pardon is to
    set up a challenge in federal court against his life sentences based upon Graham v. Florida, 
    560 U.S. 48
    (2010) — a subject that we have already addressed in Angel v. Commonwealth, 
    281 Va. 248
    , 
    704 S.E.2d 386
    (2011). But see LeBlanc v. Mathena, No. 2:12cv340, 2015 U.S. Dist.
    LEXIS 86090, at *30-31 (E.D. Va. July 1, 2015). Even so, Blount’s strategic reasons for
    rejecting the conditional commutative pardon are legally irrelevant.
    10
    As noted earlier, the Commonwealth presented to the United States District Court an
    affidavit from an official with the Virginia Department of Corrections affirming that she had
    received the “Commutation” from the Governor that had “commuted” Blount’s sentences. J.A.
    at 43.
    22
    1.
    Let me begin by addressing the majority’s assertion that Blount did not receive a
    “conditional pardon.” Ante at 10-11. If that were true, then the only proper response would be
    for us to hold his commutation legally ineffectual as a matter of law. The essential task in Lee,
    after all, was to determine whether an apparent commutation of a term of incarceration was
    invalid due to the constitutional provision limiting commutations to death sentences. The
    governor’s action in Lee did not “purport to be a pardon of any sort, but a mere commutation of
    punishment.” Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 799. There was no express condition mentioned in the
    governor’s commutation in Lee, much less a condition anything like the historical examples of
    conditions, such as banishment from the kingdom, servitude in the king’s army, or hard labor for
    a specific period of time. 11
    In Lee, we nonetheless asked “whether the acceptance by the convict of the terms
    imposed by the executive does not give to the [putative commutation] the operation and effect of
    a conditional pardon.” 
    Id. (emphasis added).
    Our affirmative answer to that question was the
    very holding of Lee. It was this condition of “acceptance” that justified the judicial “construing”
    of the putative commutation to be, in practical if not technical terms, a “conditional pardon.” 
    Id. at 799,
    802; see also 1916 Op. Atty. Gen. at 203 (interpreting the “condition” in Lee to be “the
    condition of the convict’s voluntarily submitting to the lesser punishment”). Because it was a
    conditional pardon and not a mere commutation, we found it within the definitional boundaries,
    albeit the outer edges, of the executive clemency power.
    In Blount’s case, we face a nearly identical situation. He was not on death row. The only
    way his putative commutation could be constitutionally valid would be to construe it judicially,
    11
    See supra note 4.
    23
    as we did in Lee, to be a conditional pardon in its “operation and effect” and to recognize an
    implied condition of “acceptance.” 
    Id. The end
    of this analysis gives Blount, as it gave the
    convict in Lee, the right to refuse Governor McDonnell’s clemency offer — which, of course, he
    has done.
    The majority bypasses this reasoning with the observation that the commutation issued to
    Blount did not have a “signature line” for him to acknowledge his acceptance, unlike the
    commutation issued to the convict in Lee. See ante at 10. I do not think the constitutionality of
    an act of executive clemency should turn on whether or not the transmittal document includes a
    signature line. The issue in Lee was not whether a signature line was printed on the
    commutation, but whether the convict had a right to reject the clemency offer. In a footnote, the
    majority adds that the convict in Lee got to spend his commuted sentence in a local jail instead of
    a state penitentiary. Ante at 11 n.2. 12 Here again, nothing in Lee intimates that this fact had any
    analytical significance. The majority cites no court, attorney general, or legal scholar in the 143
    years since Lee that has intimated as much. If these are the only distinctions being drawn
    between Lee and this case, they appear to be so analytically thin as to suggest that Lee has been
    overruled sub silentio.
    12
    The majority asserts that, in Lee, the executive clemency order changed the sentence
    “from imprisonment in the penitentiary to imprisonment in the city jail — a change in the form
    of imprisonment.” Ante at 11 n.2 (emphasis in original). The apparent relevance of that
    assertion is to contrast the situation in Lee to the clemency given to Blount, which the majority
    says constitutes a change “in degree, not in kind.” Ante at 11. The majority never explains how
    an act of clemency reducing a sentence from three years to twelve months (as in Lee) constitutes
    a change in kind but reducing six life sentences, plus 118 years imprisonment, to a mere forty
    years (as in Blount’s case) is a mere reduction in degree.
    24
    2.
    An even greater change in our law is the majority’s unprecedented revision of the
    definition of “commutation.” See ante at 6. Under the revised definition, “the term
    ‘commutation’ signified a change or substitution ‘in kind’ of punishment, a substitution of a
    ‘lesser’ form for a ‘greater’ form. Thus, a reduction in the term of imprisonment at that time
    would not have been understood as a ‘commutation,’ but only a ‘partial pardon.’” Ante at 6
    (emphasis added) (commenting on the term “commutation” at the time of the adoption of the
    1851 Constitution of Virginia); see also ante at 11.
    I know of no legal authority supporting this novel assertion. The majority cites none. 13
    No litigant in this case has mentioned, much less advocated, this thesis. The idea is inconsistent
    with over a thousand self-styled commutations issued by Virginia governors over the years that
    reduced terms of incarceration, see Br. of Resp’t Attach. 2 (listing 1,640 executive commutations
    13
    The majority relies on seven cases for this assertion. Six of them do not at all support
    the majority’s assertion that a commutation, by definition, does not include the reduction of a
    term of incarceration. See Ogletree v. Dozier, 
    59 Ga. 800
    , 802 (1877) (holding that only the
    governor has the power to commute a sentence “from a higher to a lower punishment,” including
    “from the hard work of a chain-gang to work on a farm”); Rich v. Chamberlain, 
    65 N.W. 235
    ,
    235 (Mich. 1895) (holding only that the governor could commute a sentence from state prison to
    a city house of correction under authority “imposed by law”); Ex parte Parker, 
    17 S.W. 658
    , 660
    (Mo. 1891) (holding that a statute permitting the substitution of alternate punishment instead of a
    fine for an impecunious defendant did not “interfere with the governor’s power” to commute);
    State v. Hildebrand, 
    95 A.2d 488
    , 490 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. Div. 1953) (holding only that
    “power of parole” must be distinguished from an executive’s prerogative of pardons); Ex parte
    Janes, 
    1 Nev. 319
    , 321-22 (1865) (holding that the governor had no power to commute the
    prisoner’s death sentence to one of life imprisonment); State ex rel. Att’y-Gen. v. Peters, 
    4 N.E. 81
    , 88 (Ohio 1885) (holding only that a statutory system of credits authorizing “parole” of
    prisoners does not interfere with executive’s general power of clemency). The seventh case,
    moreover, appears to undermine the majority’s assertion. People ex rel. Smith v. Jenkins, 
    156 N.E. 290
    , 292 (Ill. 1927) (upholding the commutation of a life sentence to a term of eight years
    and three months).
    25
    of noncapital sentences issued between 1873 and 2014), and is similarly inconsistent with the
    longstanding view of the Attorney General of Virginia, see 1932 Op. Atty. Gen. at 102.
    The reason for the revised definition is to avoid the conclusion that clemency offered by
    Governor McDonnell to Blount — which identifies itself as “COMMUTATION OF
    SENTENCE,” J.A. at 38 (capitalization in original) — is actually that: a true commutation. If it
    were, it would violate Article V, Section 12 of the Constitution of Virginia. That is not a
    problem here, the majority reasons, because reducing a term of incarceration from a higher to a
    lower degree is not a commutation. A commutation only exists, under this view, when a
    punishment is changed not merely in degree but rather in kind. Ante at 6, 11.
    This narrow view of commutations appears to rest on two grounds: (a) a brief quote
    extracted from the extensive remarks of a single delegate to the 1851 Constitutional Convention;
    and (b) a speculative supposition based on a dissenting opinion issued by a single Justice on the
    United States Supreme Court in a case decided after the commutation provision in the 1851
    Constitution of Virginia had been ratified. Neither of these grounds support the majority’s
    revised definition of commutations in Virginia.
    (a)
    In support of its assertion that “a reduction in the term of imprisonment” could not
    constitute a commutation, ante at 6, the majority quotes Delegate Stanard at the Constitutional
    Convention of 1851, who said: “It ought not to be left to the executive to say that he shall not be
    pardoned and that he shall be punished, not in the mode prescribed by law for a crime of which
    he has been guilty, but by some other mode which the executive may think more proper to be
    applied,” ante at 7. Stanard’s use of the word “mode,” the majority contends, proves that Stanard
    believed a commutation could only be legally valid if it changed the kind of the punishment, but
    26
    not the severity or degree of the punishment. In context, however, the Stanard quote proves just
    the opposite.
    At the 1851 Constitutional Convention, the original proposal addressing executive
    clemency permitted the governor to issue commutations for punishments generally. See Register
    of the Debates and Proceedings of the Va. Reform Convention 71-72 (1851). Stanard and other
    delegates sharply objected to this power. “I regard the power to commute punishment as a
    dangerous one,” he argued. Debates and Proceedings of the Va. Reform Convention, Richmond
    Enquirer, Supp. No. 82, at 2 [hereinafter 1851 Va. Reform Convention Supp. No. 82] (publishing
    debates and proceedings from July 12-15, 1851) (on file with the Library of Virginia). 14
    The reason why Stanard felt this way had nothing to do with the supposed expansion of
    the executive’s commutation power from changes in kind to a sentence to mere reductions in the
    degree of a sentence. Rather, his point was that executive clemency should address only “the
    question of guilt or innocence.” 
    Id. If a
    convict was truly guilty, Stanard believed that “the
    law,” not the chief executive, “ought to prescribe the punishment.” 
    Id. Stanard’s point
    cannot be understood without taking into account that, in 1851, Virginia
    was among the first states to reform its criminal code to eliminate statutorily predetermined
    sentences and to authorize juries to fix the sentence within a statutory range. See Jenia
    Iontcheva, Jury Sentencing as Democratic Practice, 
    89 Va. L
    . Rev. 311, 317 (2003) (recognizing
    14
    Due to “difficulties in the publication of the Register,” only one published volume of
    the Register of the Debates and Proceedings of the Virginia Reform Convention exists, which
    covered the sessions held in January and February 1851. 2 Earl G. Swem, A Bibliography of
    Virginia 449-50 (1917) (naming the “unavoidable delay on the part of many members in revising
    and correcting their speeches” and confusion over payment for the publication as the two main
    difficulties). Additionally, “the Debates were published in full as supplements to the regular
    issues” of several Richmond newspapers, and due to the difficulty in printing the Register, these
    supplements are the only official record of much of the 1851 Constitutional Convention. 
    Id. 27 that
    “Virginia was the first state to formally adopt jury sentencing for all criminal sentences”).
    “[T]his substitution of discretionary terms of imprisonment in the penitentiary for former modes
    of punishment was soon to sweep the nation.” Nancy J. King, Lessons from the Past: The
    Origins of Felony Jury Sentencing in the United States, 78 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 937, 963 (2003)
    (emphasis added). In this context, anything other than a jury fixing the criminal sentence, using
    Stanard’s rhetoric, would be punishing a convict “not in the mode prescribed by law for the
    crime of which he has been [found] guilty.” 1851 Va. Reform Convention Supp. No. 
    82, supra, at 2
    (emphasis added).
    To be sure, Stanard believed all commutations (not just commutations of death sentences)
    were improper because they allowed an executive to avoid his “responsibility of exercising the
    prerogative of pardon” and gave him “the dangerous prerogative” of leaving the conviction
    untouched but reducing the sentence “for such length of time as [the chief executive] shall decide
    to be correct.” 
    Id. It was
    anomalous, Stanard thought, to encourage the executive to “avoid the
    responsibility of pardoning the criminal” and assume “the responsibility of changing the
    punishment.” 
    Id. In short,
    no contextual reading of Stanard’s comments suggests that he believed a
    commutation was legally valid only if it changed the “kind of punishment,” ante at 6, such as
    changing a death sentence to life imprisonment. Stanard, after all, rose in opposition to the
    provision allowing for commutations from a sentence of death to life imprisonment and moved
    to strike it from the draft. His main point was that changing a death sentence to anything other
    than death was the paradigmatic example of a legally invalid change from “the mode prescribed
    by law for a crime” that the convict committed. 1851 Va. Reform Convention Supp. No. 
    82, supra, at 2
    (emphasis added).
    28
    (b)
    Equally unpersuasive is the assertion that “Stanard’s understanding of the term
    ‘commutation,’” as the majority construes it, “finds support” from Justice McLean’s dissent in
    Ex parte Wells, 
    59 U.S. 307
    , 319-20 (1856). Ante at 7. In Ex parte Wells, a convict sentenced
    to death received a “conditional pardon” that “commuted” the sentence to life 
    imprisonment. 59 U.S. at 308
    . After accepting the conditional pardon, the convict filed a habeas petition
    claiming that he should be set free because the condition (his acceptance of a substituted life
    sentence) was unlawful.
    The United States Supreme Court rejected this argument, holding that a “conditional
    pardon” may commute a death sentence to life imprisonment if the condition is “accepted by the
    convict.” 
    Id. at 315.
    It did not matter that a death sentence was different in kind than a life
    sentence, the Court explained, because the conditional nature of the pardon gave the convict the
    choice to accept or reject the “substitution” of one kind of sentence for another. 
    Id. The conditional
    pardon included “a condition, without ability to enforce its acceptance, when
    accepted by the convict, is the substitution, by himself, of a lesser punishment than the law has
    imposed upon him, and he cannot complain if the law executes the choice he has made.” 
    Id. 15 In
    his dissent, Justice McLean recognized that many courts had approved the practice of
    granting “conditional pardons by commuting the punishment.” 
    Id. at 318
    (McLean, J.,
    dissenting). The “power of commutation” being exercised in those conditional pardons, McLean
    15
    In this respect, Ex parte Wells resembles the situation facing Blount. “[B]y calling his
    clemency a conditional pardon, the President allowed (according, at least, to present practice)
    Wells to decide whether or not he would accept the proffered clemency. Had the President
    called his act of clemency a commutation, what it was in fact, Wells would not have had,
    according to existing law an opportunity of accepting or rejecting the proffered clemency.”
    
    Humbert, supra, at 35-36
    n.12.
    29
    understood, was broad enough to include the power to impose a “substitute” sentence (such as
    life imprisonment) in cases where the law “prescribes a specific penalty” (such as the death
    penalty for certain types of murder). 
    Id. at 319
    .
    McLean, however, did not suggest that commutations were invalid unless they changed
    the kind, rather than merely the degree, of punishment. What he objected to was the use of
    executive clemency power to reduce a punishment to a kind or degree that could not have been
    lawfully imposed. “If the law controlled the exercise of this power, by authorizing solitary
    confinement for life, as a substitute for the punishment of death, and so of other offences, the
    power would be unobjectionable,” McLean explained. 
    Id. at 319
    . “But where this power rests in
    the discretion of the executive, not only as to its exercise, but as to the degree and kind of
    punishment substituted, it does not seem to be a power fit to be exercised over a people subject
    only to the laws.” 
    Id. (emphasis added).
    In other words, McLean’s point had nothing to do with the majority’s distinction between
    “in kind” punishment versus “in degree” punishment. Ante at 11. Rather, he was distinguishing
    between legitimate commutations (reducing a sentence, in kind or degree, to a punishment
    authorized by law for the crime) and illegitimate commutations (reducing a sentence, in kind or
    degree, to a punishment not authorized by law for the crime). Ex parte 
    Wells, 59 U.S. at 319
    .
    What offended him all the more was the use of conditional pardons to make legitimate what he
    believed to be illegitimate. “To speak of a contract, by a convict, to suffer a punishment not
    known to the law, nor authorized by it, is a strange language in a government of laws.” 
    Id. “Where the
    law sanctions such an arrangement, there can be no objection; but when the
    obligation to suffer arises only from the force of a contract, it is a singular instrument of
    executive power.” 
    Id. (emphasis added).
    30
    I do not understand how any of this can be read to suggest that McLean defined
    commutations as excluding the power to reduce the degree of punishment and as including only
    the power to change the kind of punishment. Exactly the opposite inference is warranted.
    Executive clemency, McLean thought, could extend to “the degree and kind of punishment
    substituted” so long as the reduced punishment was “known to the law.” 
    Id. Only when
    executive clemency “overrides the law and the judgments of the court,” 
    id., would McLean
    consider it illegitimate.
    As the Solicitor General correctly argues on brief, “Justice McLean took it as given that a
    noncapital sentence could be commuted” and instead argued only “that death sentences were
    categorically different.” Br. of Resp’t at 20 (emphasis in original). As McLean saw it, the
    executive clemency power did not permit a substituted punishment that “the law does not
    authorize.” 
    Id. (quoting Ex
    parte 
    Wells, 59 U.S. at 323
    ). McLean believed the underlying
    criminal law did not authorize “solitary confinement for life, as a substitute for the punishment of
    death,” Ex parte 
    Wells, 59 U.S. at 319
    , and thus, the executive had no power to make that change
    even with the convict’s consent. The justices in the Ex parte Wells majority did not contest this
    assumption because it made no difference to them. If the convict accepted the conditional
    pardon, they reasoned, the executive’s clemency could substitute an otherwise unlawful
    punishment for a lawful punishment. 
    Id. at 315.
    Even if I agreed with my colleagues’ reading of McLean’s opinion in Ex parte Wells,
    there are still reasons to discount its relevance. It was, after all, a dissent. No United States
    Supreme Court precedent has adopted McLean’s views. It was also a dissent addressing an issue
    that McLean said had “never come before [that] court for decision.” 
    Id. at 318
    . To make matters
    worse, it was a dissent on a novel issue issued five years after the Virginia Constitutional
    31
    Convention of 1851. I find it hard to believe that the delegates at the Convention of 1851 were
    prescient enough to anticipate an opinion on a novel issue offered by a dissenting United States
    Supreme Court justice in 1856. I find it even harder to accept that we should be relying on it
    when we have Virginia precedent directly on point to guide our decision in this case.
    3.
    The majority’s revised definition of commutations is a dramatic restructuring of
    clemency law in Virginia. In over a century from Lee until today, a Virginia governor could
    issue a non-consensual commutation only to prisoners on death row. For every other convict, a
    governor’s effort to commute a noncapital sentence to a lesser term of incarceration could be
    valid only if judicially “constru[ed]” as a conditional pardon, Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 802, see
    also 1932 Op. Atty. Gen. at 102, which necessarily required either the express or implied
    condition of the convict’s acceptance. The majority’s reasoning removes the need for that
    condition by allowing all future commutations (now designated “partial pardons,” ante at 6, 9,
    11) to be issued in non-death penalty cases without the convict’s acceptance — the very thing
    that Article V, Section 12 of the Constitution of Virginia clearly forbids.
    My point is best illustrated by contrasting the Commonwealth’s argument in this case to
    the majority’s holding, which ironically is in the Commonwealth’s favor. The Solicitor General
    understands that a “partial pardon” (when not characterized as a conditional pardon under Lee)
    “is functionally the same as a commutation.” Br. of Resp’t at 40. With skilled advocacy, the
    Solicitor General attempts to solve this problem by arguing that Governor McDonnell in fact
    issued a commutation to Blount, but, no matter, commutations of noncapital sentences (Lee
    notwithstanding) do not violate the Constitution of Virginia. In contrast, the majority solves this
    problem by inverting the Commonwealth’s argument. The majority holds that commutations of
    32
    noncapital offenses do violate the Constitution of Virginia (as Lee held), but, no matter,
    Governor McDonnell did not issue a commutation — indeed, he could not have done so, because
    commutations by definition do not include a mere reduction in a convict’s term of incarceration.
    III.
    If Lee is to remain the law of Virginia, it should be applied to this case. If Lee is not to
    remain the law of Virginia, we should overrule it. Given that two major constitutional revisions
    have taken place since Lee, 16 without any suggestion that Lee misconstrued the executive
    clemency power, the latter approach would take a lot of explanation — far more than we have
    been offered in this case. But those are the only two options.
    I would apply Lee and hold that Governor McDonnell issued exactly what he said he
    issued — a commutation of a criminal sentence — which would be constitutionally invalid if it
    could not be judicially construed as a conditional pardon. 17 I believe it should be, but that would
    16
    2 A.E. Dick Howard, Commentaries on the Constitution of Virginia 642 (1974) (stating
    that “[o]nly stylistic changes” were made to current Article V, Section 12 in the 1902
    Constitution of Virginia); 
    id. at 644
    (noting only “one stylistic change” in Article V, Section 12
    as a result of the 1971 revision of the Constitution of Virginia leaving the governor “with exactly
    those powers in this area given to him by the 1870 Constitution”).
    17
    I do not share the Solicitor General’s fear that applying Lee “would bring into doubt
    the validity of the 1,640 commutations granted by Virginia governors since Lee was decided” or
    that “it would hobble future uses of the commutation power and insult the dignity of the
    Governor’s actions.” Br. of Resp’t at 42. The only practical impact of applying Lee is to give
    convicts the right to reject a governor’s offer of a conditional commutative pardon. No evidence
    has been presented that any of the prior 1,640 “commutations” issued over the years were
    rejected by the convicts that received them. Nor do I believe that the dignity of our chief
    executive will suffer in the slightest if Blount, or any other criminal convict, refuses an offer of
    clemency. The executive’s dignity, unassailably demonstrated by his offer of commutative
    grace, remains untouched by the response given to it.
    I also acknowledge, but find unpersuasive, the Solicitor General’s reliance on Professor
    A.E. Dick Howard’s statement that “the effect of the Governor’s power to pardon must be
    determined by the same rules applicable to a pardon by the British Crown or the United States
    President.” Br. of Resp’t at 13, 22 (quoting 2 Howard, supra note 16, at 646); see also 
    id. at 27.
    33
    require Blount’s acceptance, something that he has refused to give. Because the reasoning and
    holding of Lee requires us to honor his right to do so, I respectfully dissent.
    For this statement, Professor Howard cites Wilborn v. Saunders, 
    170 Va. 153
    , 161, 
    195 S.E. 723
    ,
    726 (1938), which in turn quotes 
    Edwards, 78 Va. at 44
    .
    For three reasons, I do not believe Professor Howard’s observation suggests that we
    should overrule Lee. First, Wilborn cited Lee with approval and made no suggestion that any
    aspect of Lee should be reconsidered. 
    Wilborn, 170 Va. at 158-59
    , 195 S.E.2d at 725. Second,
    Edwards dealt only with the “effect” of the “pardoning 
    power,” 78 Va. at 44
    , and not the scope
    of the power of commutation. Third, neither Professor Howard nor the Solicitor General
    addresses the longstanding opinion of the Attorney General “that in Virginia the Governor does
    not have the power to commute sentences except in capital cases.” 1943 Op. Atty. Gen. at 127
    (citing Lee, 63 Va. (22 Gratt.) at 798).
    34