State v. Leevan Roundtree ( 2021 )


Menu:
  •                                                               
    2021 WI 1
    SUPREME COURT          OF   WISCONSIN
    CASE NO.:              2018AP594-CR
    COMPLETE TITLE:        State of Wisconsin,
    Plaintiff-Respondent,
    v.
    Leevan Roundtree,
    Defendant-Appellant-Petitioner.
    REVIEW OF DECISION OF THE COURT OF APPEALS
    Reported at 
    387 Wis. 2d 685
    ,
    928 N.W.2d 806
    (2019 – unpublished)
    OPINION FILED:         January 7, 2021
    SUBMITTED ON BRIEFS:
    ORAL ARGUMENT:         September 11, 2020
    SOURCE OF APPEAL:
    COURT:              Circuit
    COUNTY:             Milwaukee
    JUDGE:              William S. Pocan & David A. Hansher
    JUSTICES:
    ANN WALSH BRADLEY, J., delivered the majority opinion of the
    Court, in which ROGGENSACK, C.J., ZIEGLER, DALLET, and KAROFSKY,
    JJ., joined. DALLET, J., filed a concurring opinion, in which
    ANN WALSH BRADLEY and KAROFSKY, JJ., joined. REBECCA GRASSL
    BRADLEY, J., filed a dissenting opinion. HAGEDORN, J., filed a
    dissenting opinion.
    NOT PARTICIPATING:
    ATTORNEYS:
    For the defendant-appellant-petitioner, there were briefs
    filed by Kaitlin A. Lamb assistant state public defender. There
    was an oral argument by Kaitlin A. Lamb.
    For the plaintiff-respondent, there was a brief filed by
    Sarah L. Burgundy¸ assistant attorney general; with whom on the
    brief was Joshua L. Kaul, attorney general. There was an oral
    argument by Sarah L. Burgundy.
    
    2021 WI 1
    NOTICE
    This opinion is subject to further
    editing and modification.   The final
    version will appear in the bound
    volume of the official reports.
    No.    2018AP594-CR
    (L.C. No.   2015CF4729)
    STATE OF WISCONSIN                         :            IN SUPREME COURT
    State of Wisconsin,
    Plaintiff-Respondent,
    FILED
    v.
    JAN 7, 2021
    Leevan Roundtree,
    Sheila T. Reiff
    Defendant-Appellant-Petitioner.                  Clerk of Supreme Court
    ANN WALSH BRADLEY, J., delivered the majority opinion of the
    Court, in which ROGGENSACK, C.J., ZIEGLER, DALLET, and KAROFSKY,
    JJ., joined.   DALLET, J., filed a concurring opinion, in which
    ANN WALSH BRADLEY and KAROFSKY, JJ., joined.      REBECCA GRASSL
    BRADLEY, J., filed a dissenting opinion. HAGEDORN, J., filed a
    dissenting opinion.
    REVIEW of a decision of the Court of Appeals.             Affirmed.
    ¶1    ANN    WALSH   BRADLEY,   J.       The    petitioner,          Leevan
    Roundtree, seeks review of an unpublished per curiam decision of
    the court of appeals affirming his judgment of conviction and
    No.    2018AP594-CR
    the denial of his motion for postconviction relief.1                        He asserts
    that       the    felon-in-possession             statute     under   which     he   was
    convicted is unconstitutional as applied to him.
    ¶2        Specifically,     Roundtree         contends      that     Wisconsin's
    lifetime         firearm    ban   for   all       felons    is   unconstitutional     as
    applied to him because his conviction over ten years ago for
    failure to pay child support does not justify such a ban.                             He
    maintains that the conviction was for a nonviolent felony and
    that no public safety objective is served by preventing him from
    owning a firearm.
    ¶3        The parties disagree as to the level of scrutiny that
    we   should        employ    to   resolve     this     constitutional       challenge.
    Roundtree advances that we should subject the statute to the
    requirements of a strict scrutiny review.                        The State counters
    that the application of intermediate scrutiny is consistent with
    precedent.
    ¶4        We determine that Roundtree's challenge to the felon-
    in-possession         statute      (
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2)     (2013-14)2)
    requires the application of an intermediate level of scrutiny.
    State v. Roundtree, No. 2018AP594-CR, unpublished slip op.
    1
    (Wis. Ct. App. Apr. 4, 2019) (per curiam) (affirming the
    judgment and order of the circuit court for Milwaukee County,
    William S. Pocan and David A. Hansher, Judges).
    All subsequent references to the Wisconsin Statutes are to
    2
    the 2013-14 version unless otherwise indicated.
    Although Roundtree was convicted pursuant to 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2), that subsection has since been repealed, with the
    substance of the former § 941.29(2) now residing in 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m) (2017-18). See 2015 Wis. Act 109, §§ 6, 8.
    2
    No.    2018AP594-CR
    Under such an intermediate scrutiny analysis, we conclude that
    his challenge fails.           The statute is constitutional as applied
    to Roundtree because it is substantially related to important
    governmental objectives, namely public safety and the prevention
    of gun violence.
    ¶5     Accordingly, we affirm the decision of the court of
    appeals.
    I
    ¶6     In 2003, Roundtree was convicted of multiple felony
    counts of failure to support a child for more than 120 days. 3                        As
    a consequence of these felony convictions, Roundtree was, and
    continues     to   be,     permanently          prohibited     from     possessing     a
    firearm.
    ¶7     Milwaukee         police    executed          a   search        warrant   at
    Roundtree's    home      on   October   30,       2015.       Under    his    mattress,
    officers located a revolver and ammunition.                     A record check of
    the recovered gun revealed that it had been stolen in Texas.
    Roundtree claimed that "he purchased the firearm from a kid on
    the street about a year ago, but that he did not know it was
    stolen."
    ¶8     The State charged Roundtree with a single count of
    possession    of   a     firearm   by   a       felon   contrary      to    
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2).       He pleaded guilty and was subsequently sentenced
    to 18 months of initial confinement and 18 months of extended
    supervision.
    3   See 
    Wis. Stat. § 948.22
    (2) (2003-04).
    3
    No.     2018AP594-CR
    ¶9        Roundtree   moved     for    postconviction          relief,      arguing
    that 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2), the felon-in-possession statute,
    was unconstitutional as applied to him.                   The circuit court held
    the motion in abeyance pending the United States Supreme Court's
    decision in Class v. United States, 
    138 S. Ct. 798
    , 803 (2018),
    which     determined    that    a    federal      criminal    defendant          does    not
    waive a constitutional challenge to the statute of conviction on
    direct appeal by entering a guilty plea.4
    ¶10       After the issuance of the Class opinion, the circuit
    court      ultimately       determined          that    Roundtree           waived       his
    constitutional         challenge       by        entering      a      guilty         plea.
    Consequently, the circuit court denied Roundtree's motion for
    postconviction relief.5
    ¶11       Roundtree appealed, and the court of appeals affirmed,
    albeit on different grounds.            State v. Roundtree, No. 2018AP594-
    CR,   unpublished      slip    op.   (Wis.      Ct.    App.   Apr.    4,     2019)      (per
    curiam).        Instead of resting on the guilty plea waiver rule, the
    court      of    appeals    determined          that   "regardless          of    whether
    Roundtree forfeited the constitutional argument by entering a
    guilty plea, . . . the argument fails on its merits."                            Id., ¶5.
    4The "guilty plea waiver rule" refers to the general rule
    that a guilty, no contest, or Alford plea waives all
    nonjurisdictional defects, including constitutional claims.
    State v. Kelty, 
    2006 WI 101
    , ¶18, 
    294 Wis. 2d 62
    , 
    716 N.W.2d 886
    ; see North Carolina v. Alford, 
    400 U.S. 25
     (1970).
    5The order denying the postconviction motion was entered by
    the Honorable David A. Hansher. The Honorable William S. Pocan
    accepted   Roundtree's   plea  and   entered   the  judgment   of
    conviction.
    4
    No.    2018AP594-CR
    By   way    of    explanation       on       the       merits,       the    court        of    appeals
    expounded, "Roundtree's notion that his particular nonviolent
    felony matters is incorrect.                  Rather, it is settled law that the
    firearm     ban    applies       regardless            of    the     defendant's         particular
    felony."          Id.,    ¶7.       Like      the       court        of    appeals,       we,       too,
    determine that Roundtree's argument fails on its merits, and
    therefore         we     need     not        address          whether         he        waived       his
    constitutional challenge.6
    II
    ¶12    Roundtree           asks    us    to           review        whether       
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2) is unconstitutional as applied to him.                                        Examining
    the constitutional application of a statute presents a question
    of   law     that         this     court       reviews             independently              of     the
    determinations           rendered       by    the       circuit           court     or    court       of
    appeals.         State v. McGuire, 
    2010 WI 91
    , ¶25, 
    328 Wis. 2d 289
    ,
    
    786 N.W.2d 227
    .
    ¶13    In our review, we must also determine the appropriate
    level of scrutiny to guide our analysis.                                  This issue likewise
    presents a question of law that we determine independently.                                          See
    6Roundtree contends that Wisconsin's use of the guilty plea
    waiver rule was altered by the Court's recent decision in Class
    v. United States, 
    138 S. Ct. 798
     (2018).         The Class Court
    determined that a guilty plea by itself does not bar a federal
    criminal defendant from challenging the constitutionality of the
    statute of conviction on direct appeal. 
    Id. at 803
    . Roundtree
    asserts that, like the defendant in Class, he should be allowed
    to challenge the government's power to criminalize his conduct
    in spite of his guilty plea. The State disagrees, arguing that
    Class applies in federal court only and that it does not extend
    to as-applied challenges.
    5
    No.     2018AP594-CR
    Brandmiller      v.   Arreola,      
    199 Wis. 2d 528
    ,       536-37,       540-41,   
    544 N.W.2d 894
     (1996).
    III
    ¶14   We   begin      by   setting   forth    Roundtree's        argument      and
    some necessary background regarding the individual right to bear
    arms.    Subsequently, we determine the level of scrutiny under
    which we examine the felon-in-possession statute.                          Finally, we
    apply the appropriate level of scrutiny.
    A
    ¶15   Roundtree was convicted of possession of a firearm by
    a felon contrary to 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2)(a), which provides
    that a person convicted of a felony in this state "is guilty of
    a Class G felony if he or she possesses a firearm under any of
    the     following       circumstances . . . ."                 The         circumstance
    applicable    here     is    that    "[t]he     person   possesses          a   firearm
    subsequent to the conviction for the felony or other crime, as
    specified in sub. (1)(a) or (b)."               § 941.29(2)(a).
    ¶16   This statute, as Roundtree correctly observes, bars a
    person convicted of any felony from firearm possession after
    that conviction without exception, with no time limitation, and
    with no mechanism for restoration of the right to possess a
    firearm.      The     statute    does     not   draw   any    distinctions        among
    felonies.     Those convicted of less serious felonies are banned
    from possessing firearms just as are those convicted of the most
    serious felonies.
    ¶17   In Roundtree's estimation, this statutory scheme is
    unconstitutional as applied to him.                There are two major types
    6
    No.   2018AP594-CR
    of constitutional challenges:            facial and as-applied.               Michels
    v. Lyons, 
    2019 WI 57
    , ¶11, 
    387 Wis. 2d 1
    , 
    927 N.W.2d 486
    .                           A
    party challenging a law as unconstitutional on its face must
    show that the law cannot be constitutionally enforced under any
    circumstances.     
    Id.
     (citation omitted).
    ¶18    In    contrast,     in   an   as-applied      challenge,     the     court
    assesses the merits of the challenge by considering the facts of
    the particular case before it.               State v. Wood, 
    2010 WI 17
    , ¶13,
    
    323 Wis. 2d 321
    , 
    780 N.W.2d 63
    .               For an as-applied challenge to
    succeed, the challenger must demonstrate that the challenger's
    constitutional rights were actually violated.                    
    Id.
        If such a
    violation occurred, the operation of the law is void as to the
    facts presented for the party asserting the claim.                        
    Id.
          We
    presume   that    the   statute     is    constitutional,         and   the     party
    raising   a      constitutional      challenge       must       prove   that     the
    challenged    statute    has    been     applied    in     an    unconstitutional
    manner beyond a reasonable doubt.             Id., ¶15.
    ¶19    Roundtree's       as-applied        challenge    is    based    on     the
    contention that his conviction for failure to pay child support
    is a nonviolent felony and thus is insufficient to curtail his
    constitutional right to bear arms.               He argues that "[d]isarming
    [him] does not in any way advance public safety, but deprives
    him of his right to keep and bear arms for self-defense."                          As
    this is an as-applied challenge, he must demonstrate that his
    constitutional rights specifically were violated, not that the
    statute is unconstitutional in all applications.
    7
    No.    2018AP594-CR
    B
    ¶20    We begin our assessment of Roundtree's claim with some
    background on the right to bear arms.             Both the United States
    and Wisconsin Constitutions provide for this right.              U.S. Const.
    amend. II; Wis. Const. art. I, § 25.7
    ¶21    The United States Supreme Court has made clear that
    "[l]ike most rights, the right secured by the Second Amendment
    is not unlimited."       District of Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 626 (2008).      The same is true of the right provided by our
    State Constitution.      Moran v. DOJ, 
    2019 WI App 38
    , ¶48, 
    388 Wis. 2d 193
    ,    
    932 N.W.2d 430
    .       Indeed,    the   Second    Amendment
    secures "the right of law-abiding, responsible citizens to use
    arms in defense of hearth and home."         Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 635
    .
    ¶22    In Heller, the Court struck down a regulation barring
    residential    handgun   possession     as    contrary    to     the   Second
    Amendment.     
    Id.
        In doing so, the Court observed "that the
    Second Amendment conferred an individual right to keep and bear
    arms."     
    Id. at 595
    .   It was careful, however, to delineate the
    reach of its analysis:
    [N]othing in our opinion should be taken to cast doubt
    on longstanding prohibitions on the possession of
    firearms by felons and the mentally ill, or laws
    forbidding the carrying of firearms in sensitive
    7 The Second Amendment to the United States Constitution
    provides:   "A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the
    security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and
    bear Arms, shall not be infringed." Its Wisconsin counterpart,
    art. I, § 25, sets forth:   "The people have the right to keep
    and bear arms for security, defense, hunting, recreation or any
    other lawful purpose."
    8
    No.    2018AP594-CR
    places such as schools and government buildings, or
    laws imposing conditions and qualifications on the
    commercial sale of arms.
    Id. at 626-27.
    ¶23     The         Court         identified             such        regulations         as
    "presumptively lawful," id. at 627 n.26, and reiterated the same
    assessment two years later in McDonald v. City of Chicago, 
    561 U.S. 742
    , 786 (2010) ("We made it clear in Heller that our
    holding    did    not    cast     doubt      on    such       longstanding        regulatory
    measures    as    'prohibitions         on    the       possession        of     firearms   by
    felons and the mentally ill,' 'laws forbidding the carrying of
    firearms    in    sensitive      places      such       as    schools      and    government
    buildings, or laws imposing conditions and qualifications on the
    commercial sale of arms.'                We repeat those assurances here.")
    (internal citations omitted).
    ¶24     It is the juxtaposition of the United States Supreme
    Court's stated limitations on the Second Amendment individual
    right to bear arms, as well as the felon-in-possession statute's
    presumed lawfulness, that guides our analysis.
    IV
    A
    ¶25     With    this        necessary         background        in    hand,     we     next
    identify    the    appropriate         level       of    scrutiny        that     frames    our
    analysis.
    ¶26     The parties here disagree as to the level of means-end
    scrutiny that should be applied.                        Roundtree contends that we
    should subject 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2) to strict scrutiny.                                    He
    bases     this    argument       on    language         in    the    Seventh       Circuit's
    9
    No.     2018AP594-CR
    decision in Ezell v. City of Chicago which indicates that "the
    rigor of . . . judicial review will depend on how close the law
    comes to the core of the Second Amendment right and the severity
    of the law's burden on the right."                       Ezell v. City of Chicago,
    
    651 F.3d 684
    ,    703   (7th       Cir.    2011).           Under   this    framework,
    Roundtree argues that § 941.29(2) severely burdens the core of
    the Second Amendment right because it completely restricts the
    right to bear arms, thus necessitating strict scrutiny review.
    ¶27     In order to survive strict scrutiny, a statute must
    be narrowly tailored to advance a compelling state interest.
    Monroe Cnty. Dep't of Human Servs. v. Kelli B., 
    2004 WI 48
    , ¶17,
    
    271 Wis. 2d 51
    , 
    678 N.W.2d 831
    .                   Strict scrutiny is an exacting
    standard, and it is the rare case in which a law survives it.
    State v. Baron, 
    2009 WI 58
    , ¶48, 
    318 Wis. 2d 60
    , 
    769 N.W.2d 34
    .
    ¶28    The State disagrees and advocates for the application
    of    intermediate     scrutiny.             In    the    State's      view,     such   an
    application would be consistent with the language of Heller and
    its interpretation by both the court of appeals of this state
    and the Seventh Circuit.              See State v. Pocian, 
    2012 WI App 58
    ,
    ¶11, 
    341 Wis. 2d 380
    , 
    814 N.W.2d 894
     (citing United States v.
    Skoien, 
    614 F.3d 638
    , 639, 641-42 (7th Cir. 2010) (en banc) ("In
    a case decided after Heller and McDonald, the Seventh Circuit
    Court of Appeals utilized an 'intermediate scrutiny' analysis
    and applied it to a constitutional challenge to a federal law
    prohibiting     an    individual        convicted         of    misdemeanor      domestic
    violence     from    carrying     a    firearm      in    or    affecting      interstate
    commerce.").        Pursuant to an intermediate scrutiny analysis, we
    10
    No.        2018AP594-CR
    ask    whether       a    law    is    substantially         related     to    an     important
    governmental objective.                
    Id.
    ¶29     We agree with the State that intermediate scrutiny is
    the appropriate inquiry to guide our analysis.                                First, Heller
    clearly requires more than mere rational basis review of laws
    that are alleged to burden Second Amendment rights.                                Heller, 
    554 U.S. at
    628 n.27.                "If all that was required to overcome the
    right to keep and bear arms was a rational basis, the Second
    Amendment would be redundant with the separate constitutional
    prohibitions on irrational laws, and would have no effect."                                   
    Id.
    ¶30     Second,          the    intermediate          scrutiny     approach          lends
    vitality       to         the      Heller       court's       statement            that     felon
    dispossession statutes are "presumptively lawful."                                   Kanter v.
    Barr,    
    919 F.3d 437
    ,      448     (7th    Cir.    2019).          To    subject     a
    "presumptively            lawful"      statute       to   strict    scrutiny          would    in
    effect remove the operation of such a presumption.                                  As stated,
    strict scrutiny is a steep hill to climb.
    ¶31     Our conclusion is consistent with that of other courts
    that    have    considered            the    question.         Indeed,    federal          courts
    around   the     country         have       interpreted      the   above-cited            language
    from Heller as indicative of requiring an intermediate scrutiny
    analysis when examining Second Amendment challenges.                                See, e.g.,
    Skoien, 
    614 F.3d at 641-42
    ; Kanter, 919 F.3d at 448; United
    States v. Marzzarella, 
    614 F.3d 85
    , 97 (3d Cir. 2010).
    ¶32     The       Wisconsin      Court    of    Appeals     has    taken       the    same
    approach.       In both Pocian, 
    341 Wis. 2d 380
    , ¶¶11-12, and State
    v. Culver, 
    2018 WI App 55
    , ¶37, 
    384 Wis. 2d 222
    , 
    918 N.W.2d 103
    ,
    11
    No.    2018AP594-CR
    the court of appeals applied intermediate scrutiny to as-applied
    challenges to the felon-in-possession statute.                Support for the
    use of intermediate scrutiny is thus plentiful in the case law
    and accepting Roundtree's position would necessitate overruling
    both Pocian and Culver, which we decline to do.
    ¶33    In contrast, Roundtree points us to no case in which
    an    appellate   court   has    applied    strict   scrutiny   to    a   Second
    Amendment challenge to a felon-in-possession statute.8                    Absent
    any    such    application      of   strict   scrutiny   in     Wisconsin     or
    elsewhere in this type of case, we decline to break new ground.9
    We acknowledge that strict scrutiny has been applied to
    8
    related federal statutes, but none of those cases finds purchase
    here. In United States v. Engstrum, 
    609 F. Supp. 2d 1227
    , 1231-
    32 (D. Utah 2009), the District Court applied strict scrutiny to
    the federal statute prohibiting firearm possession by a person
    convicted of a "misdemeanor crime of domestic violence." See 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(9).    Similarly, in Tyler v. Hillsdale Cnty.
    Sheriff's Dep't, 
    775 F.3d 308
    , 328-29 (6th Cir. 2014), reh'g en
    banc granted, opinion vacated (Apr. 21, 2015), the Sixth Circuit
    applied strict scrutiny to 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g)(4)'s dispossession
    of a person "who has been committed to a mental institution."
    Tyler largely based its application of strict scrutiny on
    citation to separate writings in other cases, and in any event
    the opinion has been vacated.       Id. at 328-29.   Likewise,
    Engstrum is of little value here because the restriction it
    addressed was based on a misdemeanor, not a felony.
    Justice Rebecca Grassl Bradley's dissent would apply
    9
    strict scrutiny, citing this court's decision in Mayo v.
    Wisconsin Injured Patients and Families Compensation Fund, 
    2018 WI 78
    , ¶28, 
    383 Wis. 2d 1
    , 
    914 N.W.2d 678
    .      Justice Rebecca
    Grassl   Bradley's  dissent,   ¶¶73-74.     However,   Mayo  is
    inapplicable here.
    12
    No.   2018AP594-CR
    ¶34   We are likewise unpersuaded by the argument Roundtree
    makes pursuant to the Seventh Circuit's decision in Ezell, 651
    In   Mayo,   an   equal  protection   case  regarding   the
    constitutionality of medical malpractice damage caps, the
    majority of the court overruled the "rational basis with teeth"
    standard from Ferdon ex rel. Petrucelli v. Wisconsin Patients
    Compensation Fund, 
    2005 WI 125
    , 
    284 Wis. 2d 573
    , 
    701 N.W.2d 440
    .
    Mayo, 
    383 Wis. 2d 1
    , ¶32.     The "rational basis with teeth"
    standard from Ferdon, although similar, is different from
    intermediate scrutiny.
    The Ferdon court set forth that "rational basis with teeth"
    "focuses on the legislative means used to achieve the ends.
    This standard simply requires the court to conduct an inquiry to
    determine whether the legislation has more than a speculative
    tendency as the means for furthering a valid legislative
    purpose." Ferdon, 
    284 Wis. 2d 573
    , ¶78. Intermediate scrutiny,
    on the other hand, asks whether a law is "substantially related
    to an important governmental objective." State v. Pocian, 
    2012 WI App 58
    , ¶11, 
    341 Wis. 2d 380
    , 
    814 N.W.2d 894
     (citation
    omitted).
    Importantly, the Ferdon court explicitly disclaimed that it
    was applying intermediate scrutiny.     It stated that rational
    basis was the "appropriate level of scrutiny in the present
    case," clearly evidencing a distinction between intermediate
    scrutiny and "rational basis with teeth."       See Ferdon, 
    284 Wis. 2d 573
    , ¶¶63-65.
    Further, the Mayo court specifically stated that it was
    addressing levels of scrutiny for equal protection challenges.
    Mayo, 
    383 Wis. 2d 1
    , ¶28. Roundtree's challenge is not based on
    the equal protection clause, but on a purported abridgement of
    his Second Amendment rights.
    The intermediate scrutiny standard thus is well established
    and retains vitality. In 1996, a unanimous court first adopted
    and applied the intermediate scrutiny analysis in a challenge to
    a cruising ordinance as violative of the constitutional right to
    travel.   See Brandmiller v. Arreola, 
    199 Wis. 2d 528
    , 540-41,
    
    544 N.W.2d 894
     (1996). More recently, in State v. Culver, 
    2018 WI App 55
    , ¶37, 
    384 Wis. 2d 222
    , 
    918 N.W.2d 103
    , the court of
    appeals, post-Mayo, addressed the same question at issue here
    and applied intermediate scrutiny.
    13
    No.       2018AP594-CR
    F.3d 684.      He bases this argument on the Ezell court's statement
    that   "the    rigor        of . . . judicial          review    will     depend      on   how
    close the law comes to the core of the Second Amendment right
    and the severity of the law's burden on the right."                            Id. at 703.
    In Roundtree's view, the felon-in-possession statute implicates
    the core Second Amendment right and severely burdens such a
    right, necessitating the most rigorous level of scrutiny.
    ¶35    However, this argument rests on a faulty premise.                             As
    the    Seventh     Circuit         explained      in    Kanter,    less        than    strict
    scrutiny review is appropriate here because "the weight of the
    historical evidence . . . suggests that felon dispossession laws
    do not restrict the 'core right of armed defense,' but rather
    burden 'activity lying closer to the margins of the right.'"
    Kanter,      919     F.3d     at    448    n.10.        Instead,        the    core     right
    identified in Heller is "the right of a law-abiding, responsible
    citizen to possess and carry a weapon for self-defense . . . ."
    United States v. Chester, 
    628 F.3d 673
    , 683 (4th Cir. 2010)
    (emphasis removed).
    ¶36    Like    the     Seventh       Circuit     in      Kanter,       we    need   not
    conclusively determine the scope of the historical protections
    of the Second Amendment.                  Kanter, 919 F.3d at 447; see infra,
    ¶41.    But also like the Seventh Circuit in Kanter, we are not
    persuaded that the core Second Amendment right is implicated so
    as to require strict scrutiny review.
    14
    No.   2018AP594-CR
    ¶37    Accordingly, we determine that Roundtree's challenge
    to   
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2)    requires        the    application    of    an
    intermediate level of scrutiny.10
    B
    ¶38    We next apply intermediate scrutiny to the felon-in-
    possession statute considering the facts of this case.
    ¶39    Generally,   Second   Amendment       challenges     require      this
    court to undertake a two-step approach.             State v. Herrmann, 
    2015 WI App 97
    , ¶9, 
    366 Wis. 2d 312
    , 
    873 N.W.2d 257
    .                  We ask first
    "whether the challenged law imposes a burden on conduct falling
    within the scope of the Second Amendment's guarantee."                         
    Id.
    (quoting Marzzarella, 
    614 F.3d at 89
    ).               If the answer is no,
    then the inquiry ends.     
    Id.
    ¶40    If the first inquiry is answered in the affirmative,
    then the court proceeds to inquire into "the strength of the
    government's    justification     for       restricting   or   regulating     the
    exercise of Second Amendment rights."              
    Id.
     (quoting Ezell, 651
    F.3d at 703).
    10We observe that defendants around the country who raise
    as-applied challenges to felon-in-possession statutes will face
    an uphill climb.   See Pocian, 
    341 Wis. 2d 380
    , ¶12 (explaining
    that as of the writing of that opinion, "[n]o state law banning
    felons from possessing guns has ever been struck down").
    Of those federal circuits that have not foreclosed such
    challenges entirely, only one has ever upheld an as-applied
    Second Amendment challenge to the federal statute banning
    firearm possession by certain individuals convicted of crimes.
    See Binderup v. Att'y Gen. U.S., 
    836 F.3d 336
     (3d Cir. 2016); 
    18 U.S.C. § 922
    (g); see also Kanter v. Barr, 
    919 F.3d 437
    , 442-44
    (7th Cir. 2019).
    15
    No.     2018AP594-CR
    ¶41     The      Seventh   Circuit     has    described        the       historical
    evidence as to whether felons were categorically excluded from
    the Second Amendment's scope as "inconclusive."                                Kanter, 919
    F.3d    at     445.        Accordingly,     when     faced     with       an    as-applied
    challenge to the federal felon-in-possession statute, the court
    declined to resolve the first step of the inquiry and instead
    relied    on      the    dispositive     second     step——the       application         of   a
    means-end scrutiny analysis.                Id. at 447.         We take a similar
    approach here.
    ¶42     Like the court in Kanter, we assume that the felon-in-
    possession statute burdens conduct falling within the scope of
    the     Second       Amendment's        guarantee    in   order          to     reach    the
    dispositive issue.            Our inquiry, then, focuses on whether the
    statute      at    issue     is   substantially       related       to     an     important
    governmental objective.
    ¶43     As other courts in this state and elsewhere have done,
    we     recognize        public    safety     generally,       and     preventing         gun
    violence       specifically,       as    important     governmental             objectives.
    See    Pocian,       
    341 Wis. 2d 380
    ,      ¶15;    Kanter,    919       F.3d     at   448.
    Indeed, "[p]ublic safety and the protection of human life is a
    state interest of the highest order."                        State v. Miller, 
    196 Wis. 2d 238
    , 249, 
    538 N.W.2d 573
     (Ct. App. 1995).
    ¶44     Roundtree protests that he should not be prohibited
    from firearm possession because his felony conviction did not
    involve violence.           He claims that the nature of his conviction
    and the fact that it is remote in time weigh in favor of a
    16
    No.    2018AP594-CR
    determination that 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2) is unconstitutional as
    applied to him.
    ¶45   We    are     not   persuaded         that   the    specific      facts   of
    Roundtree's    case     compel     such     a   conclusion.          Roundtree      was
    convicted of failure to support a child for over 120 days.                          In
    his view, this is different in kind from the crime at issue in
    Pocian, where the defendant was convicted of uttering a forgery
    as the underlying felony.            Put frankly, he suggests that failing
    to pay child support is not as bad as "physically taking a
    victim's property."
    ¶46   But       failure   to     pay   child    support    is    every    bit   as
    serious as uttering a forgery if not more so.                  Those who fail to
    make support payments deprive the very people they should be
    protecting     most,    their      own     children,    from    receiving       basic
    necessities.        Roundtree chose to keep money for himself that
    rightly belonged to his children.                  And, to further add to the
    egregiousness of his offense, he committed this crime repeatedly
    by failing to support for at least 120 days.                     By all accounts
    this is a serious offense.
    ¶47   Simply because his crime was not physically violent in
    nature, it does not follow that the felon-in-possession statute
    cannot be constitutionally applied to Roundtree.                          The Seventh
    Circuit determined as much in Kanter when it concluded that "the
    government    has    shown    that    prohibiting      even    nonviolent      felons
    like Kanter from possessing firearms is substantially related to
    its interest in preventing gun violence."                    Kanter, 919 F.3d at
    17
    No.     2018AP594-CR
    448.     The legislature did not in 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2) create a
    hierarchy of felonies, and neither will this court.
    ¶48    Even    in    the    case    of    those    convicted      of    nonviolent
    felonies, "someone with a felony conviction on his record is
    more likely than a nonfelon to engage in illegal and violent gun
    use."        United States v. Yancey, 
    621 F.3d 681
    , 685 (7th Cir.
    2010).        Thus,    even    if    a    felon    has    not    exhibited       signs    of
    physical violence, it is reasonable for the State to want to
    keep    firearms      out     of   the    hands    of    those    who    have     shown    a
    willingness to not only break the law, but to commit a crime
    serious enough that the legislature has denominated it a felony,
    as Roundtree has here.
    ¶49    The     State    has   cited        an    abundance   of        research    to
    support this conclusion.                 "Other courts addressing this issue
    have observed that nonviolent offenders not only have a higher
    recidivism rate than the general population, but certain groups—
    —such as property offenders——have an even higher recidivism rate
    than violent offenders, and a large percentage of the crimes
    nonviolent recidivists later commit are violent."                              Kaemmerling
    v. Lappin, 
    553 F.3d 669
    , 683 (D.C. Cir. 2008) (citing Ewing v.
    California, 
    538 U.S. 11
    , 26 (2003)).
    ¶50    As the Kanter court noted, several studies "have found
    a connection between nonviolent offenders . . . and a risk of
    future violent crime."             Kanter, 919 F.3d at 449.
    For example, one study of 210,886 nonviolent offenders
    found that about one in five were rearrested for a
    violent crime within three years of his or her
    release. See U.S. Dep't of Justice, Bureau of Justice
    18
    No.     2018AP594-CR
    Statistics Profile of Nonviolent Offenders Exiting
    State Prisons 2, 4 (2004).      A separate study found
    that 28.5 percent of nonviolent property offenders——a
    category   that   includes    fraud   convictions——were
    rearrested for a violent offense within five years of
    their release.   See Matthew R. Durose, et al., U.S.
    Dep't of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics,
    Recidivism of Prisoner Released in 30 States in 2005:
    Patterns from 2005 to 2010, at 9 (2014). Yet another
    study found that "even handgun purchasers with only 1
    prior misdemeanor conviction and no convictions for
    offenses involving firearms or violence were nearly 5
    times as likely as those with no prior criminal
    history to be charged with new offenses involving
    firearms or violence."    Garen J. Wintemute, et al.,
    Prior Misdemeanor Convictions as a Risk Factor for
    Later Violent and Firearm-Related Criminal Activity
    Among Authorized Purchasers of Handguns, 280 J. Am.
    Med. Ass'n 2083, 2083 (1998) (emphasis added).
    Id.
    ¶51    Such assertions are echoed by data from the Wisconsin
    Department of Corrections (DOC).                For example, DOC data indicate
    that among recidivists who committed public order offenses, such
    as failure to pay child support, and were released from prison
    in    2011,    21.4     percent       recidivated    with       a     violent     offense.
    Joseph R. Tatar II & Megan Jones, Recidivism after Release from
    Prison,       Wis.    Dep't      of   Corrections,        at     14     (August     2016),
    https://doc.wi.gov/DataResearch/InteractiveDashboards/Recidivism
    AfterReleaseFromPrison_2.pdf.              As the State strikingly observes
    in its brief, "the 21.4 percent rate of public order offenders
    recidivating         with   a    violent   crime     was       higher    than     that   of
    property       offenders        (16   percent)      and    drug       offenders      (17.9
    percent).       And it was just seven percentage points lower than
    the rate of violent offenders (28.3 percent)."                            This data is
    surely    sufficient        to   support    a    substantial          relation     between
    19
    No.    2018AP594-CR
    keeping      firearms       out       of    the        hands    of     those     convicted      of
    nonviolent         felonies          and    the        public        safety     objective       of
    preventing gun violence.
    ¶52    Further, the fact that Roundtree's conviction occurred
    over   ten    years      ago     does      not     affect       the    result.         Roundtree
    asserts that he poses no danger to public safety and should be
    able to possess a firearm as a result.                                 However, the record
    indicates         that   the    gun        Roundtree         possessed        was    stolen    and
    purchased off the street.                   Supporting street level gun commerce
    is hardly the benign action Roundtree would have us believe it
    is.
    ¶53    In sum, we determine that Roundtree's challenge to the
    felon-in-possession            statute       (
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2))        requires
    the application of an intermediate level of scrutiny.                                      Under
    such an intermediate scrutiny analysis, we conclude that the
    felon-in-possession             statute       is       constitutional          as    applied    to
    Roundtree         because      the    statute          in    question     is     substantially
    related      to    important         governmental            objectives,        namely    public
    safety and the prevention of gun violence.
    ¶54    Accordingly, we affirm the decision of the court of
    appeals.
    By    the    Court.—The         decision         of     the    court    of    appeals    is
    affirmed.
    20
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rfd
    ¶55    REBECCA    FRANK    DALLET,       J.        (concurring).           I     write
    separately    to     address    the    unanswered        question        of   whether       by
    pleading guilty Roundtree waived his as-applied challenge to the
    constitutionality of 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2).                       I conclude that,
    following Class v. United States, 583 U.S. ___, 
    138 S. Ct. 798
    (2018), he did not.
    ¶56    Generally,    a    defendant      who       pleads    guilty       with       the
    assistance of reasonably competent counsel waives his right to
    later raise an independent claim related to a deprivation of his
    constitutional       rights     that     occurred        prior     to     his    pleading
    guilty.      See Tollett v. Henderson, 
    411 U.S. 258
    , 267 (1973).
    The rationale behind this "guilty-plea-waiver rule" is that a
    counseled    guilty     plea    admits    "all      of    the     factual       and    legal
    elements necessary to sustain a binding, final judgment of guilt
    and   a     lawful     sentence."         United         States     v.        Broce,       
    488 U.S. 563
    , 569 (1989).1
    ¶57    In order to balance efficient judicial administration
    with the rights protected by the United States Constitution, the
    United    States     Supreme    Court    has   developed          exceptions          to   the
    guilty-plea-waiver rule for claims that implicate the State's
    very power to prosecute the defendant, provided that a court can
    resolve those claims without venturing beyond the record.                                  See
    
    id. at 574-76
    ; Menna v. New York, 
    423 U.S. 61
    , 63 n.2 (1975)
    We have interpreted this rule, like other waiver rules, to
    1
    be one of judicial administration that does not deprive an
    appellate court of jurisdiction.     See State v. Riekoff, 
    112 Wis. 2d 119
    , 123-24, 
    332 N.W.2d 744
     (1983).
    1
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rfd
    (per     curiam)    (guilty        plea       did    not       waive    a     constitutional
    challenge under the Double Jeopardy Clause when the claim could
    be resolved on the existing record);                           see also       Blackledge v.
    Perry, 
    417 U.S. 21
    , 30-31 (1974) (guilty plea did not foreclose
    a   defendant's           habeas       petition          alleging       "unconstitutional
    vindictive prosecution" because the Due Process Clause precluded
    the State from even prosecuting the defendant).
    ¶58    Although      the    guilty-plea-waiver              rule       arose     in    the
    federal      context,       this       court       has     steadfastly         adopted       that
    precedent.        See, e.g., State v. Kelty, 
    2006 WI 101
    , ¶42, 
    294 Wis. 2d 62
    ,          
    716 N.W.2d 886
    ;                Hawkins            v.          State,      
    26 Wis. 2d 443
    , 448, 
    132 N.W.2d 545
     (1965).                         Wisconsin courts have
    broadened the federal exceptions, recognizing that a guilty plea
    does not waive facial challenges to the constitutionality of the
    statute      of   conviction.            See,       e.g.,      State    v.     Molitor,       
    210 Wis. 2d 415
    , 419 n.2, 
    565 N.W.2d 248
     (Ct. App. 1997).                                        This
    court,    however,        has    not    yet    extended        that     exception       to    as-
    applied      constitutional        challenges.             See    State       v.    Cole,    
    2003 WI 112
    ,      ¶46,    
    264 Wis. 2d 520
    ,             
    665 N.W.2d 328
    ;          State     v.
    Trochinski,        
    2002 WI 56
    ,     ¶34       n.15,       
    253 Wis. 2d 38
    ,       
    644 N.W.2d 891
    .        But following Class, the application of the guilty-
    plea-waiver rule should no longer depend upon whether an appeal
    challenging the constitutionality of a statute is classified as
    facial or as-applied.
    ¶59    In Class, the United States Supreme Court applied an
    exception to the guilty-plea-waiver rule to allow a defendant to
    challenge the constitutionality of the statute of conviction on
    2
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rfd
    appeal.      
    138 S. Ct. at 803-05
    .         Class    pleaded     guilty      to
    unlawfully carrying a firearm on U.S. Capitol grounds, contrary
    to 
    40 U.S.C. § 5104
    (e)(1), after the police had found three guns
    in his car in a Capitol parking lot.                  On appeal, Class argued
    that the statute violated his due-process rights since he did
    not have fair notice that a parking lot was part of the Capitol
    "grounds."     Id. at 802.           Class also claimed that the statute
    violated his Second Amendment rights because "Capitol Grounds"
    included so broad an area that it was practically impossible to
    lawfully     carry    a    firearm    anywhere       within     the     District     of
    Columbia.     Id.     In allowing both claims to proceed, the Court
    rested its decision on its 150-year-old understanding of the
    nature of a guilty plea:
    The plea of guilty is, of course, a confession of all
    the facts charged in the indictment, and also of the
    evil intent imputed to the defendant. It is a waiver
    also of all merely technical and formal objections of
    which the defendant could have availed himself by any
    other plea or motion.    But if the facts alleged and
    admitted do not constitute a crime against the laws of
    the Commonwealth, the defendant is entitled to be
    discharged.
    Id. at 804 (quoting Commonwealth v. Hinds, 
    101 Mass. 209
    , 210
    (1869)).     The Court held that Class's guilty plea did not waive
    his claims challenging the constitutionality of the statute of
    conviction because those claims involved the State's ability to
    constitutionally      prosecute      Class     and    did    not      contradict     the
    terms of the indictment or the written plea agreement.                               Id.
    at 805.
    ¶60     Given    the    Court's    analysis       in     Class,     there   is    no
    justification for continuing to treat as-applied challenges to
    3
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rfd
    the     constitutionality             of        the    statute          of     conviction         any
    differently than facial challenges.                           After all, Class did not
    hinge on the type of constitutional challenge being raised.                                        See
    United States v. Alarcon Sanchez, 
    972 F.3d 156
    , 166 n.3 (2d
    Cir. 2020) ("Pursuant to the holding in Class, defendants have a
    right      to     raise        on     appeal          both     as-applied             and      facial
    constitutional          challenges         to    the    [statute         of    conviction].").
    Indeed,      when      addressing      the       merits      of    Class's          challenges     on
    remand, the D.C. Circuit Court of Appeals treated both of his
    claims       as   as-applied          challenges.                 See    United          States    v.
    Class, 
    930 F.3d 460
        (D.C.       Cir.    2019).           But       see    State     v.
    Jackson, 
    2020 WI App 4
    , ¶¶8-9, 
    390 Wis. 2d 402
    , 
    938 N.W.2d 639
    (noting that it was "not clear . . . whether Class'[s] challenge
    was   an     as-applied        or    facial       challenge").               Second,       and    more
    importantly, the Court's reasoning in Class must apply equally
    to    facial      and    as-applied          challenges           because      both       types    of
    challenges        "call       into     question         the       Government's            power    to
    'constitutionally prosecute'" the defendant.                                 Class, 
    138 S. Ct. at 805
     (quoting Broce, 
    488 U.S. at 575
    ) (adding that whether a
    constitutional challenge can be classified as "jurisdictional"
    is also not dispositive).
    ¶61      This     court      should       therefore         adopt      the     holding      in
    Class, not only to remain consistent with United States Supreme
    Court      precedent      but       also    to    continue         to    strike          the   proper
    balance      between         efficient          judicial       administration               and   the
    protection        of     a     defendant's            constitutional               rights.         See
    Kelty, 
    294 Wis. 2d 62
    , ¶27.                     It should be the law in Wisconsin
    4
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rfd
    that       a   guilty       plea   does    not       waive   a    defendant's         right   to
    challenge             the    statute      of     conviction's           constitutionality,
    facially or as applied, provided the challenge can be resolved
    without contradicting the record.                       We should withdraw language
    from       Cole       and   Trochinski    and    clarify         the    court    of   appeals'
    holding in Jackson to the extent that those decisions hold that
    a defendant who pleads guilty waives his right to later raise an
    as-applied             constitutional          challenge         to     the      statute      of
    conviction.2
    ¶62        For the foregoing reasons, I respectfully concur.
    ¶63        I    am   authorized     to    state       that      Justices     ANN    WALSH
    BRADLEY and JILL J. KAROFSKY joins this concurrence.
    See State v. Cole, 
    2003 WI 112
    , ¶46, 
    264 Wis. 2d 520
    , 665
    
    2 N.W.2d 328
    ; State v. Trochinski, 
    2002 WI 56
    , ¶34 n.15, 
    253 Wis. 2d 38
    , 
    644 N.W.2d 891
    ; State v. Jackson, 
    2020 WI App 4
    ,
    ¶¶8-9, 
    390 Wis. 2d 402
    , 
    938 N.W.2d 639
    .
    5
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    ¶64   REBECCA GRASSL BRADLEY, J.              (dissenting).       The Second
    Amendment provides:
    A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the
    security of a free State, the right of the people to
    keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed.
    U.S.   Const.     amend.   II.      St.       George   Tucker,     a     pre-eminent
    constitutional law scholar during the founding era, described
    the Second Amendment as "the true palladium of liberty . . . .
    The right of self defence is the first law of nature:                         in most
    governments it has been the study of rulers to confine this
    right within the narrowest limits possible.                  Wherever standing
    armies are kept up, and the right of the people to keep and bear
    arms is, under any colour or pretext whatsoever, prohibited,
    liberty,     if   not   already     annihilated,        is   on    the       brink   of
    destruction."       St. George Tucker, Blackstone's Commentaries 1:
    App. 300 (1803).        In plainer words, the Second Amendment is the
    people's ultimate protection against tyranny.
    ¶65   Applying the original public meaning of this bulwark
    of liberty, the United States Supreme Court more than a decade
    ago finally dispelled the prevalent, but historically ignorant
    notion that the Second Amendment protects merely a collective,
    militia member's right.          The Supreme Court declared the right to
    keep and bear arms is "exercised individually and belongs to all
    Americans"; accordingly, "the District [of Columbia]'s ban on
    handgun      possession     in      the       home     violates        the      Second
    Amendment . . . ."         District of Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 581, 635 (2008) (emphasis added).                  See also Letter from
    Thomas Jefferson to James Madison (Dec. 20, 1787), in The Papers
    1
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    of Thomas Jefferson, XII, 438-40 (Julian Boyd ed., 1950) ("Let
    me add that a bill of rights is what the people are entitled to
    against every government on earth, general or particular, [and]
    what no just government should refuse or rest on inference.")
    (emphasis added).            Any encroachment upon this fundamental right
    must withstand strict judicial scrutiny.                   Wisconsin Carry, Inc.
    v. City of Madison, 
    2017 WI 19
    , ¶9, 
    373 Wis. 2d 543
    , 
    892 N.W.2d 233
     (declaring the right to keep and bear arms to be "a species
    of right we denominate as 'fundamental'"); Mayo v. Wisconsin
    Injured Patients & Families Comp. Fund, 
    2018 WI 78
    , ¶28, 
    383 Wis. 2d 1
    ,       
    914 N.W.2d 678
        ("Strict      scrutiny       is   applied     to
    statutes that restrict a fundamental right.").
    ¶66     Ignoring       conclusive         historical      evidence       to    the
    contrary,       the      majority        upholds     the   constitutionality            of
    Wisconsin's categorical ban on the possession of firearms by any
    person convicted of a felony offense,1 regardless of whether that
    individual is dangerous.             Under the majority's vision of what is
    good for society, "even if a felon has not exhibited signs of
    physical violence, it is reasonable for the State to want to
    keep       firearms    out    of   the    hands    of   those    who    have    shown   a
    willingness       to . . . break          the      law."        Majority       op.,   ¶48
    (emphasis added).            It may be "reasonable" to the majority but it
    surely isn't constitutional.               "The very enumeration of the right
    takes out of the hands of government——even the Third Branch of
    Government——the power to decide on a case-by-case basis whether
    the right is           really worth       insisting upon.          A constitutional
    1   See 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m).
    2
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    guarantee       subject          to     future          judges'     assessments              of    its
    usefulness is no constitutional guarantee at all."                                     Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 634
     (emphasis in original).                           Centuries of history warned
    the Founders that governments certainly wanted to keep arms out
    of the hands of the citizenry in order to ease the establishment
    of   tyranny——and         they    often        succeeded.           It    is     for     this     very
    reason that the Framers insisted on preserving the individual
    right to keep and bear arms for all Americans.
    ¶67    Under       
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m),          the     State    deprives
    Leevan Roundtree of his fundamental constitutional right to keep
    and bear arms, based solely on his failure to pay child support
    more than ten years ago, with no showing that he poses a danger
    to society.       Applying the wrong standard of review, the majority
    sidelines      the    United          States       Constitution,         demotes       the    Second
    Amendment to second-class status,2 and endorses a blanket ban on
    one of our most fundamental constitutional liberties.                                     In doing
    so, the majority contravenes the original public meaning of the
    Second Amendment.           I dissent.
    I
    ¶68    The Constitution takes precedence over any statute,
    and any statute in conflict with the Constitution cannot stand.
    "The       [C]onstitution         is     either         a     superior,         paramount         law,
    unchangeable         by   ordinary        means,         or    it   is     on     a    level      with
    See McDonald v. City of Chicago, 
    561 U.S. 742
    , 780 (2010)
    2
    ("[R]espondents, in effect, ask us to treat the right recognized
    in Heller as a second-class right, subject to an entirely
    different body of rules than the other Bill of Rights guarantees
    that we have held to be incorporated into the Due Process
    Clause.").
    3
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    ordinary legislative acts, and, like other acts, is alterable
    when the legislature shall please to alter it.                         If the former
    part of the alternative be true, then a legislative act contrary
    to the [C]onstitution is not law; if the latter part be true,
    then written [C]onstitutions are absurd attempts on the part of
    the people to limit a power in its own nature illimitable."
    Marbury v. Madison, 
    5 U.S. 137
    , 177 (1803).                         Bearing in mind
    that the Second Amendment protects the "first law of nature"——
    the right to defend oneself——any infringement of the right must
    be concordant with the Constitution and may replicate only those
    restrictions       society   accepted         at   the    founding.        Permitting
    restraints on the right to keep and bear arms that were never
    contemplated by the Framers lends an illimitable quality to the
    legislative    power    to     regulate       a    fundamental      right,    thereby
    deflating the primacy of the Constitution and imperiling the
    liberty of the people.
    ¶69     Wisconsin    Stat.     § 941.29(1m)           bans   all     felons   from
    possessing a firearm in this state:                "[a] person who possesses a
    firearm is guilty of a Class G felony if any of the following
    applies:     (a) [t]he person has been convicted of a felony in
    this state, [or] (b) [t]he person has been convicted of a crime
    elsewhere that would be a felony if committed in this state."
    This felon dispossession statute draws no distinction between an
    individual     convicted     of    first-degree           homicide      and   someone
    convicted     of    "failing      to     comply      with     any      record-keeping
    requirement for fish" (a felony in this state).                           
    Wis. Stat. § 29.971
    (1)(c).         Rather         than    the       historically      recognized
    4
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    revocation      of        Second       Amendment      rights      predicated           on   an
    individual's dangerousness to society, the Wisconsin Legislature
    instead    rescinds         those       rights       based     merely       on   a     felony
    conviction, irrationally preserving the right to keep and bear
    arms for both violent and dangerous citizens.
    ¶70     In 2003, Roundtree failed to pay child support for
    more than 120 consecutive days, resulting in his conviction for
    a felony under 
    Wis. Stat. § 948.22
    (2).                       Roundtree was sentenced
    to four years of probation and later paid his past due child
    support.        Nearly      13     years     later,    while     executing       a     search
    warrant    on   Roundtree's            property,     the     police    found     a   handgun
    tucked beneath his mattress.                   The State charged Roundtree with
    violating 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m).3                    The majority concludes that
    Roundtree's felony conviction for failure to timely pay child
    support more than a decade earlier permanently forecloses his
    individual Second Amendment rights.                    Although the United States
    Supreme Court has never opined on the constitutionality of felon
    dispossession        laws,       the    majority     reflexively        follows      federal
    jurisdictions        in    upholding         these   laws,     neglecting        (as    other
    courts have) to conduct the historical analysis necessary to
    ascertain the original public meaning of the Second Amendment in
    this regard.
    ¶71     Troublingly,               the    majority         applies       intermediate
    scrutiny to a statute that demands strict scrutiny review, while
    3  Roundtree  was   actually  convicted  under   
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (2), but sub. (2) was subsequently repealed and replaced
    with 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m).     For consistency and to avoid
    confusion, I use sub. (1m) throughout.
    5
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    declining to discern whether the people who ratified the Bill of
    Rights consented to the removal of the Second Amendment right
    from non-violent felons.               While legislatures have always had the
    power    to     prohibit       people    who       are    dangerous      from    possessing
    firearms, the Second Amendment does not countenance collectively
    depriving       all    felons     of     their       individual         Second    Amendment
    rights.       Such laws sweep too broadly, disarming those who pose
    no danger to society.               And if the professed purpose of felon
    dispossession laws is "public safety and the prevention of gun
    violence" as the majority describes,4 then Wisconsin's lawmakers
    need to adjust their aim; 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m) leaves violent
    misdemeanants free to keep and bear arms.
    ¶72        Since     the    founding       of    our     nation,        Americans    have
    understood their right to keep and bear arms as fundamental to
    the people's self-preservation and defense.                        Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 593-94
     ("By the time of the founding, the right to have arms had
    become fundamental             for English subjects," citing Blackstone's
    description of "the right of having and using arms for self-
    preservation       and    defence").           In    Wisconsin     Carry,        this    court
    expressly recognized the right to keep and bear arms to be "a
    species of right we denominate as 'fundamental,' reflecting our
    understanding that it finds its protection, but not its source,
    in our constitutions."            
    373 Wis. 2d 543
    , ¶9 (citations omitted).
    During    the    ratifying       conventions,            "there   was    broad    consensus
    between Federalists and their opponents on the existence and
    nature    of     the     'natural       right'      to     keep   and     bear    arms    for
    4    Majority op., ¶4.
    6
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    defensive purposes."             Binderup v. Atty. Gen. U.S. of America,
    
    836 F.3d 336
    , 367 (3d Cir. 2016) (Hardiman, J., concurring).
    Although we expound only the Second Amendment in this case, this
    court has also deemed the people's right to keep and bear arms
    protected under the Wisconsin Constitution5 to be a fundamental
    right.          State v. Cole, 
    2003 WI 112
    , ¶20, 
    264 Wis. 2d 520
    , 
    665 N.W.2d 328
     ("We find that the state constitutional right to bear
    arms       is    fundamental.").           Because     
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m)
    restricts a fundamental right that predates and is "independent
    of" the Constitution entirely, Wisconsin Carry, 
    373 Wis. 2d 543
    ,
    ¶9, strict scrutiny must apply.
    ¶73       Inexplicably,      but    quite    conveniently,       the    majority
    opinion never mentions Wisconsin Carry, nor does it even utter
    the word "fundamental."               When a challenged statute impairs a
    fundamental right, this court must apply a heightened level of
    scrutiny.         Very recently, this court articulated that "[s]trict
    scrutiny        is   applied   to   statutes       that   restrict     a    fundamental
    right."         Mayo, 
    383 Wis. 2d 1
    , ¶28.            Not only does the majority
    disregard the nature of the right to keep and bear arms, it also
    fails to apply Mayo, which hardly imposed a novel approach to
    examining laws restricting fundamental rights.                        Strict scrutiny
    has    never      been   limited     to    equal    protection    challenges.       We
    recently         reiterated    that       "[a]     statute    which    directly    and
    substantially infringes upon a fundamental liberty interest must
    withstand strict scrutiny:                 it must be narrowly tailored to
    See Article 1, Section 25 of the Wisconsin Constitution:
    5
    "The people have the right to keep and bear arms for security,
    defense, hunting, recreation or any other lawful purpose."
    7
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    serve a compelling state interest."                   Matter of Visitation of
    A.A.L., 
    2019 WI 57
    , ¶18, 
    387 Wis. 2d 1
    , 
    927 N.W.2d 486
    .                               See
    also    Burson      v.   Freeman,   
    504 U.S. 191
    ,    199    (1992);     Reno   v.
    Flores, 
    507 U.S. 292
    , 301-02 (1993).                   Strict scrutiny applies
    "when a statute impinges on a 'fundamental right' or creates a
    classification that 'operates to the peculiar disadvantage of a
    suspect class.'"           Metropolitan Associates v. City of Milwaukee,
    
    2011 WI 20
    , ¶60 n.20, 
    332 Wis. 2d 857
    , 
    96 N.W.2d 717
     (emphasis
    added).        In Larson v. Burmaster, 
    2006 WI App 142
    , ¶42, 
    295 Wis. 2d 333
    , 
    720 N.W.2d 134
    , the Wisconsin Court of Appeals held
    that    "strict          scrutiny   is    applied"         when     a    "fundamental
    constitutional right is violated."
    ¶74     Without explanation, the majority altogether ignores
    its holding in Wisconsin Carry and refuses to apply Mayo, two
    cases     we      recently   decided.         The    majority      threatens      every
    Wisconsin citizen's right to keep and bear arms by failing to
    acknowledge the right as fundamental and accordingly using the
    wrong level of review.              In electing to apply an intermediate
    level of scrutiny, the majority misconstrues the nature of the
    infringement of Roundtree's Second Amendment right.                           Its error
    stems from mischaracterizing the person who seeks to exercise
    his Second Amendment right as an "activity lying closer to the
    margins      of    the   right."     Majority       op.,   ¶35    (emphasis      added)
    (citing Kanter v. Barr, 
    919 F.3d 437
    , 448 n.10 (7th Cir. 2019)).
    Of course, a person is not an "activity" and in this case,
    Roundtree wishes to exercise what Heller pronounced to be the
    "core   lawful       purpose   of   armed     defense,"      which      the   State   of
    8
    No.       2018AP594-CR.rgb
    Wisconsin totally denies him.                      
    554 U.S. at 630
    .                   "[A] lifetime
    ban    on       any    felon    possessing         any          firearm"    undoubtedly        "does
    impair the 'core conduct' of self-defense in the home——at least
    for    a    felon      who     has   completed         his       sentence,       or    someone       who
    shares his household."                     C. Kevin Marshall, Why Can't Martha
    Stewart Have a Gun?, 
    32 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol'y 695
    , 697 (2009).
    Such       "broadly      prohibitory         laws          restricting       the       core   Second
    Amendment             right . . . are          categorically                unconstitutional."
    Ezell v. City of Chicago, 
    651 F.3d 684
    , 703 (7th Cir. 2011).
    Roundtree's core right to possess a firearm in his own home is
    not merely restricted, it is extinguished.                                 This alone warrants
    strict scrutiny.
    ¶75       Ultimately,         the    level          of    scrutiny     applied         is    not
    dispositive; 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m) fails under either level of
    review.         More importantly, the statute is inconsistent with the
    historical understanding of the scope of the Second Amendment
    right and who possesses it.                  For this reason, Heller declined to
    adopt       a    particular      level       of    scrutiny.6              The     Supreme         Court
    expressed only that "'rational basis' . . . could not be used to
    evaluate         the    extent       to    which       a    legislature          may    regulate      a
    District of Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 581, 628
    6
    (2008).    See also State v. Sieyes, 
    225 P.3d 995
    , ¶34 (Wash.
    2010) ("We follow Heller in declining to analyze [Washington's
    statute restricting the rights of children to keep and bear
    arms] under any level of scrutiny.       Instead we look to the
    Second    Amendment's   original    meaning,    the  traditional
    understanding of the right, and the burden imposed on children
    by upholding the statute.        See generally Eugene Volokh,
    Implementing the Right to Keep and Bear Arms for Self-Defense:
    An Analytical Framework and a Research Agenda, 
    56 UCLA L. Rev. 1443
    , 1449 (2009).").
    9
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    specific, enumerated right" such as "the right to keep and bear
    arms."     Heller, 
    554 U.S. at
    628 n.27 ("If all that was required
    to overcome the right to keep and bear arms was a rational
    basis, the Second Amendment would . . . have no effect.").                                      If
    anything, Heller signals that courts should approach challenges
    to   statutes       infringing          the     Second      Amendment          right     with    a
    rigorous       review       of     history,          rather       than     the        inherently
    subjective consideration of whether the government's interest in
    curtailing      the     right      outweighs         the    individual's             interest    in
    exercising it.          "As to the ban on handguns[,] . . . the Supreme
    Court    in    Heller       never       asked    whether         the     law    was     narrowly
    tailored      to    serve     a    compelling         government         interest        (strict
    scrutiny) or substantially related to an important government
    interest      (intermediate         scrutiny).             If    the    Supreme        Court    had
    meant to adopt one of those tests, it could have said so in
    Heller   and       measured       D.C.'s      handgun      ban    against        the    relevant
    standard.       But the Court did not do so; it instead determined
    that handguns had not traditionally been banned and were in
    common        use——and        thus        that        D.C.'s           handgun         ban      was
    unconstitutional."               Heller v. District of Columbia, 
    670 F.3d 1244
    , 1273 (D.C. Cir. 2011) (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting).                                        The
    majority      in    this    case     should      have       conducted          the    historical
    analysis       necessary           to      determine            whether         felons         were
    traditionally         dispossessed         of    their      weapons.            They    weren't,
    unless they were dangerous to society.                          Accordingly, Wisconsin's
    categorical dispossession of all felons irrespective of whether
    they pose a danger to the public is unconstitutional.
    10
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    ¶76    Although the United States Supreme Court has declined
    to   pronounce       the        appropriate         level   of     review       for     statutes
    burdening the fundamental right to keep and bear arms in favor
    of     discerning     the        traditional         understanding         of     the     Second
    Amendment, this court (as it must) has recognized the right to
    keep    and   bear     arms        to   be     fundamental,        and     this       court   has
    declared strict scrutiny to be the appropriate level of scrutiny
    "applied to statutes that restrict a fundamental right."                                   Mayo,
    
    383 Wis. 2d 1
    , ¶28.                At the very least, the majority should
    explain why it now subordinates the fundamental, constitutional
    right to keep and bear arms.
    II
    ¶77    Statutes subject to strict scrutiny rarely survive.
    Burson v. Freeman, 
    504 U.S. 191
    , 211 (1992) ("[I]t is the rare
    case     in   which        we    have        held    that    a     law    survives       strict
    scrutiny.").          In    order       to    survive,      "a   statute       must     serve   a
    compelling state interest[,] . . . be necessary to serving that
    interest[,]     and . . . be             narrowly       tailored         toward       furthering
    that    compelling         state    interest."           Mayo,     
    383 Wis. 2d 1
    ,         ¶28.
    Historically,        laws       that    dispossessed         the    violent       served      the
    compelling state interest in public safety.                              Wisconsin's felon
    dispossession law,              however, ensnares the non-violent, thereby
    detaching itself from the statute's ostensible purpose.
    ¶78    Even assuming Wisconsin's felon dispossession statute
    serves the unquestionably compelling state interest in public
    11
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    safety,7 the statute is not "narrowly tailored" toward advancing
    that interest because it applies to any individual convicted of
    a   felony     offense,    even      if   that      person    poses      no   danger   to
    society.       For example:       "One man beats his wife, harming her
    physically and emotionally and traumatizing their children who
    witness      the     assault.   He    may,      however,     only     have     committed
    battery, a misdemeanor."              State v. Thomas, 
    2004 WI App 115
    ,
    ¶47, 
    274 Wis. 2d 513
    , 
    683 N.W.2d 497
     (Schudson, J., concurring)
    (emphasis       in     original).             The     legislature        allows     this
    undisputedly violent man to possess a firearm.                            "Another man
    enters     a   garage     to    steal     a     shovel;      he    has    committed    a
    burglary," which is a felony offense.                        
    Id.
         The legislature
    forever prohibits him from possessing a firearm.                              "One woman
    drives while intoxicated, threatening the lives of countless
    citizens.      Under Wisconsin's drunk driving laws——the weakest in
    the nation——she has committed a non-criminal offense if it is
    her first, or only a misdemeanor unless it is her fifth (or
    subsequent) offense."           Id., ¶48.        Wisconsin's legislature deems
    this woman fit to possess a firearm.                    "Another woman, however,
    forges a check; she has committed a felony."                       Id.    As a result,
    Wisconsin's legislature forever prohibits her from possessing a
    firearm.       Despite the utterly ineffectual distinctions drawn by
    the   legislature,        the     majority          allows   the      legislature      to
    permanently dispossess non-dangerous individuals of their Second
    Amendment rights while allowing violent citizens to retain them.
    7State v. Pocian, 
    2012 WI App 58
    , ¶12, 
    341 Wis. 2d 380
    , 
    814 N.W.2d 894
       (quoted   source   omitted)  (holding   that   felon
    dispossession statutes are a "matter of public safety").
    12
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    Even intermediate scrutiny cannot save a statute that purports
    to serve an important government interest——protecting society
    from violent criminals——but fails so miserably to achieve it.
    ¶79      In considering an as-applied challenge to a law "that
    entirely bars the challenger from exercising the core Second
    Amendment         right,       any    resort           to     means-end        scrutiny        is
    inappropriate"          when    the    challenger             falls    outside         of    "the
    historical justifications supporting the regulation."                               Binderup,
    836 F.3d at 363 (Hardiman, J., concurring).                           Instead, "such laws
    are   categorically        invalid         as    applied      to     persons    entitled       to
    Second     Amendment       protection."               Id.     In     Binderup,     a    federal
    statute       dispossessing          all        individuals        convicted       of        state
    misdemeanors punishable by more than two years in prison went
    "even      further      than   the    'severe          restriction'       struck       down    in
    Heller:       it completely eviscerate[d] the Second Amendment right"
    as    to   an     entire   group      of    individuals         who    were     historically
    proven to retain it.                 Id. at 364.              So too with Wisconsin's
    categorical ban on the possession of firearms by non-dangerous
    felons.           The    original      meaning          of     the     Second     Amendment,
    encompassing a traditional understanding of the scope of the
    rights       it   protects      as    well        as    the    range     of     historically
    recognized           restrictions,               establishes            this        statute's
    unconstitutionality,            independent            of    the     application        of    any
    standard of scrutiny.
    III
    ¶80      At its inception, the right to keep and bear arms
    protected under the Second Amendment was never understood to
    13
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    countenance the categorical exclusion of felons that 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m)          endorses.       Historically,            legislatures        prohibited
    only     dangerous          people    from        possessing         a    firearm,      not    an
    individual like Roundtree who, although convicted of a felony
    offense, poses no demonstrable risk to the public.                                    This more
    narrowly drawn restriction reflects the nature of the right as
    an individual, rather than a merely collective or civil one.
    ¶81    In drafting the Second Amendment, "both Federalists
    and Anti-Federalists accepted an individual right to arms; the
    only debate was over how best to guarantee it."                                 Don B. Kates,
    Jr., Handgun Prohibition and the Original Meaning of the Second
    Amendment,       
    82 Mich. L. Rev. 204
    ,     223      (1983).         The    Founders
    settled on the following language:                     "A well regulated Militia,
    being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of
    the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed."                                    U.S.
    Const. amend. II.            When judges interpret constitutional text, we
    give words their original public meaning.                                Judges who instead
    inject       a      modern      gloss        over      constitutional              provisions
    impermissibly         change    their    meaning,          a    right      reserved     to     the
    people    through       the    process       of    constitutional           amendment.         In
    interpreting          the    Second   Amendment,        we      accordingly         apply     the
    particular meaning of the words "militia" and "right of the
    people" as they were understood at the time of ratification.
    ¶82    At the time of the founding, "militia" meant "the body
    of the people"——an adult citizenry "who were not simply allowed
    to keep their own arms, but affirmatively required to do so."
    Letters      from     the     Federal    Farmer       to       the   Republican        123     (W.
    14
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    Bennett ed. 1978) (ascribed to Richard Henry Lee) ("A militia,
    when     properly          formed,      are      in     fact       the      people
    themselves . . . ."); Kates, supra, at 214 (discussing how, in
    the pre-colonial tradition, male citizens were required to keep
    arms for purposes of law enforcement).                 It was the citizenry's
    collection of personally-owned firearms that made possible law
    enforcement and military service during the founding era.                    After
    all, the Founders preserved this right primarily in response to
    the tyranny witnessed in England and its corresponding colonies.
    As George Mason warned, it was the goal of the English monarch
    "to disarm the people," as that was the "best and most effectual
    way to enslave them."          3 J. Elliot, Debates in the Several State
    Conventions 380 (2d ed. 1836).
    ¶83   As a principal means of resisting such tyranny, the
    Founders enshrined the "right of the people" to keep and bear
    arms as an individual right.             As Richard Henry Lee understood,
    "to preserve liberty, it is essential that the whole body of the
    people always possess arms and be taught alike, especially when
    young,   how   to    use     them."     Kates,    supra,   at     221-22    (citing
    Letters from the Federal Farmer, supra, at 124).                    For Lee, the
    right to keep and bear arms formed a bedrock of an independent
    nation and free society.              The Second Amendment "right of the
    people" perfectly mirrors the language found in the First and
    Fourth Amendments.           In each of these provisions, "the people"
    unequivocally       retain    far-reaching       and   fundamental       individual
    rights under the Constitution.                As Heller acknowledged, "the
    people" "refers to a class of persons who are part of a national
    15
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    community or who have otherwise developed sufficient connection
    with this country to be considered part of that community."
    Heller,      
    554 U.S. at
       580    (citing    United    States       v.   Verdugo-
    Urquidez, 
    494 U.S. 259
    , 265 (1990)).                       It is within the context
    of this broad protection of individual liberty that the Second
    Amendment must be understood.                     While the Constitution permits
    certain restrictions, regulations, and forfeitures of the right
    to keep and bear arms, any curtailing of such a fundamental
    liberty interest requires close judicial inspection.
    ¶84    In a case also concerning a constitutional challenge
    to 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m), Seventh Circuit Court of Appeals
    Judge Amy Barrett undertook the "exhaustive historical analysis"
    of the Second Amendment as applied to felons, an issue left
    unexamined          in      Heller,          which      did      not         consider     the
    constitutionality of felon dispossession laws.                           In that seminal
    opinion,       then-Judge            Barrett     concluded       that        "[h]istory    is
    consistent with common sense:                   it demonstrates that legislatures
    have   the     power       to    prohibit      dangerous      people     from    possessing
    guns[,]      [b]ut       that        power    extends    only    to     people      who    are
    dangerous."          Kanter v. Barr, 
    919 F.3d 437
    , 451 (7th Cir. 2019)
    (Barrett,          J.,     dissenting).              Founding-era       state       ratifying
    conventions         and     contemporaneously-enacted             legislation           reveal
    that the Second Amendment never empowered legislatures to disarm
    non-dangerous felons.
    ¶85    Language protecting the right to bear arms proposed
    during       the     New    Hampshire,         Massachusetts,          and     Pennsylvania
    ratifying conventions is frequently cited as evidence of the
    16
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    constitutionality of felon disarmament.                            Kanter, 919 F.3d at 455
    (Barrett, J., dissenting).                   All three proposals, however, would
    have    excluded       from     the      Second        Amendment's           protections        only
    people who were dangerous.                   Id. at 456.           The New Hampshire state
    convention       proposed       that         "Congress          shall    never        disarm    any
    Citizen unless such as are or have been in Actual Rebellion."                                      2
    Bernard Schwartz, The Bill of Rights: A Documentary History 761
    (1971)    (emphasis       added).             At      the    time,       "[t]his       limitation
    targeted a narrow group because 'rebellion' was a very specific
    crime" denoting treason.                 Kanter, 919 F.3d at 455 (Barrett, J.,
    dissenting)      (citing        Rebellion,            2     New    Universal         Etymological
    English Dictionary (4th ed. 1756)).                             Nothing in the historical
    record suggests New Hampshire would have extended disarmament to
    common criminals, much less individuals who posed no risk to
    public safety.
    ¶86     The    same     can      be    said        for     the    proposal        from   the
    Massachusetts convention.                    Samuel Adams suggested limiting the
    right    to    bear     arms       to    "peaceable          citizens."              Id.   (citing
    Schwartz, supra, at 681).                     In the founding era, "'peaceable'
    meant     '[f]ree        from        war;        free        from       tumult';         '[q]uiet;
    undisturbed'; '[n]ot violent; not bloody'; '[n]ot quarrelsome;
    not     turbulent.'"           Kanter,         919        F.3d     at   455        (Barrett,     J.,
    dissenting)          (citing    1       Samuel     Johnson,         A    Dictionary        of    the
    English      Language     (5th       ed.     1773)).            Each    of    the    antonyms     of
    "peaceable" connote some form of danger to the public at large.
    In     other    words,       the        Massachusetts             convention         couched    its
    proposed Second Amendment limitation within the context of one's
    17
    No.      2018AP594-CR.rgb
    propensity for violence; nothing in the language purports to
    exclude criminals as a class.
    ¶87       Lastly, although the Pennsylvania convention offered
    ostensibly the strongest restriction on Second Amendment rights,
    a more careful reading of this proposal suggests otherwise.                               The
    Pennsylvania Minority proposed:                      "That the people have a right
    to bear arms . . . and no law shall be passed for disarming the
    people      or    any     of   them    unless    for    crimes    committed,         or   real
    danger of public injury from individuals."                        Schwartz, supra, at
    665 (emphasis added).                 There are two potential interpretations
    of this language:              one that would exclude both criminals as well
    as the otherwise dangerous, and another that would exclude those
    who pose a danger to society, irrespective of whether they have
    committed         crimes.         Kanter,    919      F.3d   at   456     (Barrett,       J.,
    dissenting).             Given the absence of any historical indications
    that the founding generation contemplated the dispossession of
    all criminals, the latter interpretation is the more reasonable
    one, under which "the catchall phrase limiting the rights of
    individuals who pose a 'real danger of public injury' would be
    an    effort      to     capture      non-criminals      whose    possession         of   guns
    would pose the same kind of danger as possession by those who
    have committed crimes" namely, "a subset of crimes" involving
    "real danger of public injury."                  Id. (emphasis in original).
    ¶88       Of course, none of the limiting language proposed by
    any    of        these     states'      conventions       appears       in     the    Second
    Amendment.          Id.        This omission provides further textual proof
    that Second Amendment rights extend to every citizen, unless
    18
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    restricted or removed for constitutionally-permissible reasons,
    which    were      uniformly      rooted        in     concerns       over    dangerousness
    rather than general criminality.                      An examination of legislation
    in the American colonies predating the Second Amendment confirms
    this    understanding.            Concerned           at    the   time      with     impending
    threats of English tyranny, the founding generation dispossessed
    individuals        "who     refused        to    pledge       their      loyalty      to    the
    Revolution,        state,    or    nation."            Binderup,       836     F.3d    at    368
    (Hardiman,       J.,   concurring).             Early       Americans        grounded      their
    disarmament laws in quelling the "potential danger" posed by
    those who were disloyal, although they had committed no crime.
    Id. (citing Nat'l Rifle Ass'n of Am., Inc. v. Bureau of Alcohol,
    Tobacco, Firearms, & Explosives, 
    700 F.3d 185
    , 200 (5th Cir.
    2012)).       At its core, the founding generation enacted these
    types of laws in order to "deal with the potential threat coming
    from armed citizens who remained loyal to another sovereign."
    Kanter, 919 F.3d at 457 (Barrett, J., dissenting) (quoted source
    omitted).          These    laws     were       not       concerned    with     categorical
    distinctions based upon classes of criminals nor an individual's
    prior    legal     transgressions.              Instead,      they     were     designed     to
    disarm       individuals       who     posed          a     danger     to      society      or,
    particularly in the founding era, a danger to the Revolution.
    ¶89    The same can be said about other laws enacted close in
    time    to   the    founding.         In    particular,           colonial     legislatures
    passed       statutes       disarming           Native       Americans         and     slaves,
    purportedly out of fear of their armed "revolt" or other threats
    to "public safety."            Id. at 458 (citing Joyce Lee Malcolm, To
    19
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    Keep and Bear Arms 140-41 (1994)).                           Similarly, a distrust of
    Catholics      prompted        their        disarmament            "on     the        basis     of
    allegiance" rather than faith.                       Id. at 457 (citing Robert H.
    Churchill, Gun Regulation, the Police Power, and the Right to
    Keep Arms in Early America: The Legal Context of the Second
    Amendment, 
    25 Law & Hist. Rev. 139
    , 157 (2007)).                               Although these
    laws would not survive a contemporary constitutional challenge,
    they    nevertheless       reveal         the    limits      the    founding          generation
    contemplated for the right to keep and bear arms.                                The earliest
    Americans enacted them out of a fundamental fear of rebellion
    and public unrest, rather than as a forfeiture for criminal
    conduct.            Constitutionally                 permissible          disarmament          is
    circumscribed by founding-era conceptions of a person's danger
    to society.         In other words, "Heller instructs that the public
    understanding of the scope of the right to keep and bear arms at
    the time of the Second Amendment dictates the scope of the right
    today."      Binderup, 836 F.3d at 367 (Hardiman, J., concurring).
    ¶90    In    contrast         to     its        meaning      under         
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m),        the      word        "felon"        signified        something       quite
    different in the founding era.                       "At early common law, the term
    'felon'      applied    only    to    a     few       very   serious,          very   dangerous
    offenses such as murder, rape, arson, and robbery."                                      Don B.
    Kates   &    Clayton     E.    Cramer,          Second    Amendment        Limitations         and
    Criminological         Considerations,            
    60 Hastings L.J. 1339
    ,       1362
    (2009).       Over time, English Parliament began classifying more
    and more crimes as "capital offenses, some involving trivial
    thefts."      
    Id.
        In colonial America, capital punishment was rare.
    20
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    Kanter, 919 F.3d at 459 (Barrett, J., dissenting).                     Although a
    definitive understanding of what "felony" meant at that time
    remains elusive, a felony conviction unaccompanied by a life
    sentence typically resulted in a suspension of rights, rather
    than a permanent loss.         Id.
    ¶91       Contrary    to   this     overarching        distinction     between
    dangerous and non-dangerous individuals, some courts——and the
    State    in   this   case——claim      that     the   original   meaning    of   the
    Second Amendment is rooted in a "virtuous citizenry" test.                      See,
    e.g., United States v. Yancey, 
    621 F.3d 681
    , 684-85 (7th Cir.
    2010) (citing with approval cases concluding that the right to
    bear arms was tied to the concept of a virtuous citizenry);
    United States v. Carpio-Leon, 
    701 F.3d 974
    , 979-80 (4th Cir.
    2012) ("[F]elons were excluded from the right to arms because
    they were deemed unvirtuous.").                According to this theory, the
    "right to arms was inextricably and multifariously linked to
    that of civic virtue . . . ."                Kates & Cramer, supra, at 1359.
    Because criminals have engaged in unvirtuous conduct, purveyors
    of this notion posit that the Framers intended to limit their
    Second        Amendment    liberties           outright,     irrespective        of
    dangerousness.       See id. at 1360.
    ¶92       The majority alludes to this concept in a selective
    but incomplete citation to Heller, proclaiming that "the Second
    Amendment      secures    'the       right     of    law-abiding,     responsible
    citizens to use arms in defense of hearth and home.'"                     Majority
    op., ¶21 (citing Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 635
    ).                 Of course, far from
    restricting the right to keep and bear arms to a select segment
    21
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    of society, to be exercised only for self-defense in the home,
    Heller instead declared that the Second Amendment right "belongs
    to all Americans" and broadly protects all "defensive purposes"
    regardless of whether the right is exercised within or beyond
    the   home.        
    554 U.S. at 581, 602
    .      This    is    the   core    right
    protected by the Second Amendment.                      The full context of the
    phrase from Heller cited by the majority shows that the Second
    Amendment     is    neither      limited      to     "law-abiding"      citizens         nor
    confined to the "defense of hearth and home."                           Instead, the
    Heller Court reserved other applications of the Second Amendment
    for "future evaluation" while declaring that the Constitution
    "surely     elevates       above      all    other      interests"      the   practice
    prohibited by the District of Columbia's handgun ban:                                   "the
    right of law-abiding citizens to use arms in defense of hearth
    and   home."         
    Id. at 635
    .       While      this    may    constitute         a
    particularly sacrosanct exercise of the Second Amendment right,
    at its core, the Second Amendment protects far more, and nothing
    in an original understanding of its text remotely suggests a
    non-violent        criminal      forfeits         his   Second       Amendment      right
    altogether.
    ¶93     In suggesting that the Second Amendment right belongs
    only to the law-abiding, the virtuous citizen standard is deeply
    intertwined     with     the     collective       rights   interpretation          of    the
    Second Amendment, a reading Heller debunked as contrary to the
    22
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    original meaning of the Second Amendment.8                       While "history does
    show that felons could be disqualified from exercising certain
    rights——like the rights to vote and serve on juries——because
    these rights belonged only to virtuous citizens[,]" such "virtue
    exclusions are associated with civic rights——individual rights
    that       'require[]     citizens      to   act    in    a   collective    manner   for
    distinctly public purposes.'"                Kanter, 919 F.3d at 462 (Barrett,
    J., dissenting) (citation omitted).                       In contrast, the Second
    Amendment          "unambiguously"       protects        "individual     rights,"    not
    collective rights.            Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 579
    .             Given the Supreme
    Court's rightful rejection of the collective rights theory as
    applied       to    the   right    to    keep      and   bear   arms,    the   virtuous
    citizenry          standard   is   entirely        misplaced     in    construing    the
    Second Amendment, particularly considering that its exercise is
    "intimately connected with the natural right of self-defense,
    and not limited to civic participation."                        Kanter, 919 F.3d at
    464 (Barrett, J., dissenting).
    ¶94     The virtuous citizenry standard lacks any foundation
    in the historical backdrop to the Second Amendment.                            For one,
    The "virtuous-citizens-only conception of the right to
    8
    keep and bear arms is closely associated with pre-Heller
    interpretations of the Second Amendment by proponents of the
    'sophisticated collective rights model' who rejected the view
    that the Amendment confers an individual right and instead
    characterized the right as a 'civic right . . . exercised by
    citizens, not individuals . . . who act together in a collective
    manner, for a distinctly public purpose:     participation in a
    well regulated militia.'"      Binderup v. Atty. Gen. U.S. of
    America, 
    836 F.3d 336
    , 371 (3rd Cir. 2016) (Hardiman, J.,
    concurring) (citing Saul Cornell & Nathan DeDino, A Well
    Regulated Right: The Early American Origins of Gun Control, 
    73 Fordham L. Rev. 487
    , 491-92 (2004)).
    23
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    "this supposed limitation on the Second Amendment stems from a
    misreading      of     an         academic        debate         about      'ideological
    interpretation.'"           Binderup,    836       F.3d    at    371      (Hardiman,     J.,
    concurring)    (citation          omitted).         In    advancing        this    theory,
    certain    scholars    divorced       themselves          from     more    authoritative
    historical    sources       and    wrongly       focused     upon      whether     or    not
    particular    Founders       were     civic       republicans       or     libertarians.
    Id.; see also Saul Cornell & Nathan DeDino, A Well Regulated
    Right:     The Early American Origins of Gun Control, 
    73 Fordham L. Rev. 487
    , 492 (2004).             This debate over ideology may inform the
    Framers' motivations for constitutionally preserving the right
    to keep and bear arms, but it has nothing to say about the scope
    of the right or any constitutionally permissible restrictions on
    its exercise.
    ¶95     If the virtuous citizenry test was historically valid,
    we would expect to discover 18th and 19th century laws depriving
    felons of their Second Amendment rights——a class of people that
    would certainly be categorized as "unvirtuous."                             But that is
    simply not the case.              In the decades following ratification,
    "nine states enacted their own right-to-arms provisions in their
    constitutions,"       and     none     of        them     placed       restrictions      on
    criminals.     Kanter, 919 F.3d at 463 (Barrett, J., dissenting)
    (citing Eugene Volokh, State Constitutional Rights to Keep and
    Bear Arms, 
    11 Tex. Rev. L. & Pol. 191
    , 208-09 (2006)).                                   The
    historic     record     affords       the        virtuous        citizenry        test    no
    credibility; in fact, there is "no historical evidence on the
    public meaning of the right to keep and bear arms indicating
    24
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    that 'virtuousness' was a limitation on one's qualification for
    the   right."         Binderup,        836        F.3d   at   373     (Hardiman,       J.,
    concurring).        Instead, as outlined above, the original meaning
    of the Second Amendment contemplates curtailing the rights of
    only those individuals who pose a danger to the public.
    ¶96    The majority's rationale for sanctioning the blanket
    revocation of felons' Second Amendment right is even weaker than
    the   "virtuous      citizen"    justification.               Wisconsin's         citizens
    should be alarmed by the breathtaking scope of the majority's
    conclusion that "it is reasonable for the State to want to keep
    firearms out of the hands of those who have shown a willingness
    to . . . break the law"9 considering the "cancerous growth since
    the 1920s of 'regulatory' crimes punishable by more than a year
    in prison, as distinct from traditional common-law crimes.                            The
    effect of this growth has been to expand the number and types of
    crimes     that   trigger     'felon'    disabilities         to     rope    in    persons
    whose convictions do not establish any threat that they will
    physically harm anyone, much less with a gun."                       Marshall, supra,
    at 697.     As but one example of how the ever-expanding regulatory
    state may eventually make felons of us all, recall that whomever
    fails "to comply with any record-keeping requirement for fish"
    is guilty of a Class I felony under 
    Wis. Stat. § 29.971
    (1)(c)
    (provided the fish are worth more than $1,000).
    ¶97    Only    months     ago,     a     slim      majority     of    this     court
    invalidated       Executive    Order     28,       which   had   been      issued    by   a
    single, unelected bureaucrat who in the name of the COVID-19
    9   Majority op., ¶48.
    25
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    pandemic      "claimed     the     authoritarian      power       to    authorize        the
    arrest and imprisonment of the people of Wisconsin for engaging
    in lawful activities proscribed by the DHS secretary-designee in
    her sole discretion."              Wisconsin Legislature v. Palm, 
    2020 WI 42
    ,    ¶81,    
    391 Wis. 2d 497
    ,     
    942 N.W.2d 900
         (Rebecca        Grassl
    Bradley, J., concurring).             Had the court ruled otherwise, would
    a majority of this court deem it "reasonable" to keep firearms
    out of the hands of those who disobeyed a cabinet secretary's
    decree to "all people within Wisconsin to remain in their homes,
    not to travel and to close all businesses that she declares are
    not   'essential'"?          Palm,    
    391 Wis. 2d 497
    ,         ¶1.        If    so,   the
    court's decision in this case would give the State license to
    disarm a substantial portion of the citizens of Wisconsin based
    on their "willingness to break the law" as unilaterally decreed
    by    an    unelected     bureaucrat,       for    the     unspeakable        crimes      of
    opening their "non-essential" businesses or washing their hands
    for less than 20 seconds.              Palm, 
    391 Wis. 2d 497
    , ¶87 (Kelly,
    J., concurring).          As a general proposition, the judiciary should
    defer to the policy choices of the legislative branch, but when
    those policy choices unconstitutionally infringe the people's
    fundamental rights, it is the duty of the judicial branch to say
    so.        "[T]o   make    an    individual's      entitlement          to   the    Second
    Amendment      right      itself     turn    on    the     predilections           of    the
    legislature . . . is            deference    the    Constitution         won't      bear."
    Binderup, 836 F.3d at 374 (Hardiman, J., concurring).
    ¶98    Underlying the founding generation's reverence for the
    fundamental right to keep and bear arms was the understanding
    26
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    that "[o]ne of the ordinary modes, by which tyrants accomplish
    their purposes without resistance, is, by disarming the people,
    and making it an offence to keep arms."                             Heller, 
    554 U.S. at
    608-09       (citing      Joseph    Story,     A    Familiar         Exposition       of   the
    Constitution         of   the     United    States      §     450    (reprinted       1986)).
    Embodying "the first law of nature" and representing "the true
    palladium       of    liberty,"      the     people's         Second    Amendment       right
    deserves far more respect than the legislature or the majority
    give it.
    IV
    ¶99     Whether      applying       strict       scrutiny       or      some    lesser
    standard, 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m) is unconstitutional as applied
    to     Roundtree,         under    the     original          meaning     of     the    Second
    Amendment.       Even if a compelling state interest underlies the
    statute, it lacks any narrow tailoring tied to the protection of
    the public and therefore the statute unconstitutionally limits
    Roundtree's right to keep and bear arms.                        Nor does § 941.29(1m)
    bear     a    substantial         relation     to       an    important        governmental
    objective.       Section 941.29(1m) bans every felon from possessing
    a firearm in this state, regardless of whether he poses a danger
    to the public.             If the compelling/important state interest is
    protecting the public from dangerous felons, then the statute
    must    actually       do   so.      Instead,       §    941.29(1m)          disarms    every
    citizen convicted of a felony offense, regardless of the nature
    of the crime involved, and irrespective of whether the offender
    is     dangerous.           To    survive     either         strict     or     intermediate
    scrutiny,       § 941.29(1m)        would     need       to    reach     only      dangerous
    27
    No.      2018AP594-CR.rgb
    felons, as determined by the crime committed or the offender's
    personal      characteristics.              Under    the    intermediate          level     of
    scrutiny      applied    by       the   majority,      in   order       to    assess      "the
    strength      of   the   government's         justification        for       restricting"10
    Roundtree's        Second    Amendment       rights——public        safety——the         court
    must    ask    whether      the    public    is     safer   now    that      Roundtree      is
    completely and permanently disarmed.11
    ¶100 Roundtree         committed       a     non-violent         felony     when     he
    failed to pay child support nearly 13 years ago.                          The sentencing
    court did not send Roundtree to prison, indicating he was not
    deemed dangerous to the public.                   The record shows he made full
    restitution by paying what he owed and he did not reoffend.
    Roundtree has never been convicted of a violent crime and the
    State did not introduce any evidence otherwise suggesting that
    Roundtree poses a danger to society.                   Abandoning any pretense of
    conducting      an   individualized          inquiry    into      the     application       of
    Wisconsin's felon disarmament statute to Roundtree specifically,
    the majority instead resorts to nearly decade-old data from the
    Wisconsin Department of Corrections indicating that 21.4 percent
    of those who committed "public order offenses" and spent time in
    prison later committed a violent crime.                     Majority op., ¶51.              Of
    course, Roundtree was never incarcerated for his offense, so the
    only foundation for the majority's declaration of a "substantial
    10   Majority op., ¶40 (citation omitted).
    C. Kevin Marshall, Why Can't Martha Stewart Have a Gun?,
    11
    
    32 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol'y 695
    , 696 (2009) ("Is the public safer
    now   that   Martha  Stewart   is   completely  and  permanently
    disarmed?").
    28
    No.    2018AP594-CR.rgb
    relation" between disarming nonviolent felons and "preventing
    gun violence" collapses when applied to Roundtree and others
    like him who never spent time in prison.
    ¶101 Even    if    Roundtree    had       spent     time    in        prison,    the
    premise that the State may permanently disarm all felons in
    order to protect the public, based on data showing that 21.4
    percent of felons incarcerated for "public order offenses" later
    commit    violent   ones,       presents     a    specious     justification            for
    infringing a fundamental constitutional right.                     Unlike Roundtree
    who was sentenced to probation, Martha Stewart spent five months
    in jail.     Marshall, supra, at 695.                  "Is the public safer now
    that   Martha    Stewart    is    completely       and    permanently          disarmed?"
    Id. at 696.        Of course not, and "it is at least curious how
    Martha Stewart could merit anyone's concern."                      Id. at 735.          The
    same could be said for Roundtree, since the State produced no
    evidence indicating that Roundtree presents a danger to society
    warranting removal of his Second Amendment right.
    ¶102 The Founders never understood legislatures to have the
    power to strip non-dangerous criminals of their Second Amendment
    rights,    which    the    Constitution          protects    for        all    Americans.
    Absent statutory language narrowly tailoring the disarming of
    felons based upon their perceived dangerousness, or even bearing
    a   substantial     relationship       to        the     ostensible          governmental
    objective of protecting society, 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m) cannot
    survive    any   level     of    constitutional        scrutiny         as    applied   to
    Roundtree, much less the hapless possessor of fish who runs
    afoul of the record-keeping requirements of Chapter 29 of the
    29
    No.     2018AP594-CR.rgb
    Wisconsin Statutes.         Without the predictive powers of the mutant
    precogs from "The Minority Report,"12 permanently revoking the
    Second Amendment rights of those who fail to meet their familial
    financial    obligations         or   carelessly     keep   their    fish    records,
    bears no relationship to "public safety" or "the prevention of
    gun violence," majority op., ¶53, much less a substantial one.
    ¶103      Of   particular          constitutional       concern,     
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m)       permanently         disarms    Roundtree     and      other      non-
    dangerous felons, who have no avenue for having their Second
    Amendment rights restored.              In contrast, a convicted felon only
    temporarily loses his right to vote during his incarceration and
    extended     supervision.             
    Wis. Stat. § 6.03
    (1)(b).           Once    he
    completes    the    term    of    his    sentence,    the    State     restores     his
    voting rights.       
    Wis. Stat. § 304.078
    (3).               Similarly, convicted
    felons regain their right to serve as jurors after their civil
    rights have been restored.              
    Wis. Stat. § 756.02
    .         Reviving these
    collective    rights       for    felons     while   permanently       dispossessing
    them of their individual and fundamental Second Amendment rights
    turns the constitutional order on its head.
    12 "The Minority Report is a 1956 science fiction novella by
    American writer Philip K. Dick, first published in Fantastic
    Universe. In a future society, three mutants foresee all crime
    before it occurs. Plugged into a great machine, these 'precogs'
    allow a division of the police called Precrime to arrest
    suspects before they can commit any actual crimes."          The
    philosophical premise underlying the novella "question[s] the
    relationship between authoritarianism and individual autonomy."
    The story was adapted into the 2002 film "Minority Report,"
    directed             by             Steven            Spielberg.
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_Minority_Report.
    30
    No.   2018AP594-CR.rgb
    * * * * *
    ¶104 To   the   extent    
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m)   permanently
    deprives Roundtree of his fundamental, individual right to keep
    and bear arms, with no showing of his dangerousness to society,
    this statute is unconstitutional as applied to Roundtree.           While
    the wisdom of the legislature's policy choices may be fiercely
    debated, "the enshrinement of constitutional rights necessarily
    takes certain policy choices off the table."          Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 636
    .   Permanent dispossession of felons' Second Amendment
    rights is one of them.       "[A]n act of the Legislature repugnant
    to the Constitution is void."             Marbury, 
    5 U.S. at 177
    .       As
    applied to felons who pose no danger to society, Wisconsin's
    felon dispossession statute is repugnant to the Constitution,
    and therefore void.     Because the majority allows statutory law
    to override the fundamental constitutional right to keep and
    bear arms, I dissent.
    31
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    ¶105 BRIAN                HAGEDORN,       J.       (dissenting).                       The     Second
    Amendment             prohibits       the   government            from       infringing             upon    the
    individual             and     fundamental            right       to       keep        and     bear     arms.
    Wisconsin, however, makes possession of firearms a crime for any
    person convicted of a felony.                          
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m)(a) (2017-
    18).1       This complete ban on possessing firearms never expires; it
    lasts for a lifetime.                    It matters not whether the felony was for
    making            unlawful            political            contributions                     (
    Wis. Stat. § 11.1401
    (1)(a)), legislative logrolling (
    Wis. Stat. § 13.05
    ),
    armed       robbery          (
    Wis. Stat. § 943.32
    (2)),              or    here,        delinquent
    child support (
    Wis. Stat. § 948.22
    (2)).
    ¶106 In 2003, Leevan Roundtree was convicted of a felony
    for failure to pay child support for more than 120 days.                                                     In
    2015, a search warrant found him in possession of a firearm
    under his mattress at his home, leading to the charge currently
    before       us        on    appeal.        Roundtree         asks         this        court     to    decide
    whether the Second Amendment permits the State to criminalize
    his     possession             of    a    firearm.            The      majority              answers        yes,
    reasoning that the State may disarm all those who have committed
    a felony of whatever kind.                            I disagree.            I conclude that the
    original              public      meaning        of    the     Second         Amendment              supports
    applying          at        least     intermediate            scrutiny            to     this        type    of
    restriction.                This places the burden on the State to demonstrate
    that        the       law    is     constitutional           as    applied         to        Roundtree       by
    proving           a     substantial         relationship,              a     close           fit,     between
    All subsequent references to the Wisconsin Statutes are to
    1
    the 2017-18 version.
    1
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    criminalizing gun possession for those convicted of any felony
    or of the felony of failure to pay child support and the State's
    interest in preventing gun-related violence.                    The State has come
    nowhere close to meeting its burden.                I respectfully dissent.
    I.    THE SECOND AMENDMENT
    ¶107 We      begin    by    laying    down   the    guiding       principles   of
    constitutional interpretation, and then apply those principles
    to the Second Amendment.2
    A.     Principles of Constitutional Interpretation
    ¶108 In America, the people are sovereign.                         This is the
    bedrock principle of American government.                      Wis. Leg. v. Palm,
    
    2020 WI 42
    , ¶172, 
    391 Wis. 2d 497
    , 
    942 N.W.2d 900
     (Hagedorn, J.,
    dissenting) ("Government has a morally legitimate claim to order
    and command not because it has the biggest guns or because it's
    always been that way, but because the people have given it that
    power.").       When the people established our federal government,
    they granted it only a limited set of enumerated powers.                       United
    States     v.   Morrison,        
    529 U.S. 598
    ,       607    (2000).         States,
    meanwhile,      retained        broad   and    far-reaching        police      powers,
    covering    the    state's      inherent    power    "to      promote    the   general
    welfare," which "covers all matters having a reasonable relation
    2 Roundtree also challenges 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m)(a) under
    Article I, Section 25 of the Wisconsin Constitution.     However,
    he fails to develop this argument in any meaningful way, and we
    will not do so for him. Serv. Emps. Int'l Union, Loc. 1 v. Vos,
    
    2020 WI 67
    , ¶24, 
    393 Wis. 2d 38
    , 
    946 N.W.2d 35
    .      Accordingly,
    this analysis focuses on the Second Amendment alone.
    2
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    to the protection of the public health, safety or welfare."
    State v. Interstate Blood Bank, Inc., 
    65 Wis. 2d 482
    , 490, 
    222 N.W.2d 912
     (1974).
    ¶109 Neither state nor federal power is without limitation,
    however.     The people declared certain areas off limits.                    Many of
    these limits are listed in the federal Constitution's Bill of
    Rights, including the Second Amendment's protection of the right
    "to keep and bear Arms."         U.S. Const. amend. II.
    ¶110 Initially, the Bill of Rights only applied against the
    federal     government.        Timbs   v.    Indiana,     
    139 S. Ct. 682
    ,      687
    (2019).      Following the Civil War, however, the people decided
    that some of the limits on federal power should also constrain
    the exercise of state power.                 
    Id.
        To that end, the people
    adopted     the    Fourteenth   Amendment      which,      among      other   things,
    provides     that    states     may    not    "abridge      the     privileges     or
    immunities of citizens of the United States" or "deprive any
    person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of
    law."      U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 1.                  Over time, the United
    States Supreme Court has construed the Fourteenth Amendment as
    incorporating most of the protections in the Bill of Rights
    against the States——the Second Amendment among them.                          McDonald
    v.   City     of    Chicago,     
    561 U.S. 742
    ,         750     (2010).         Once
    incorporated, the amendment's "protection applies 'identically
    to both the Federal Government and the States.'"                         Timbs, 139
    U.S. at     689     (quoting     McDonald,         
    561 U.S. at
          766     n.14).
    Therefore, no arm of Wisconsin government may infringe upon "the
    3
    No.     2018AP594-CR.bh
    right of the people to keep and bear Arms."                       U.S. Const. amend.
    II.
    ¶111 The Supreme Court's Second Amendment jurisprudence is
    sparse,    establishing        for     our   purposes        only     two    controlling
    propositions:      (1) the Second Amendment is incorporated against
    the States via the Fourteenth Amendment; and (2) the right the
    Second     Amendment    protects        is       an    individual      right,       not    a
    collective right.            McDonald, 
    561 U.S. at 749-50
    ; District of
    Columbia v. Heller, 
    554 U.S. 570
    , 595 (2008).                             While we are
    bound by these holdings, neither offers much assistance in this
    case.      Several federal courts of appeals have opined on the
    intersection    of     the    Second     Amendment          and   felon-dispossession
    laws, but those decisions are merely persuasive, not binding.
    ¶112 In other words, this court is both free and duty-bound
    to do the job of a court——not just to compare and contrast other
    courts'    opinions,     but    to     explore        the   meaning    of     the   Second
    Amendment and apply it afresh.                   Admittedly, this is a difficult
    task.     But we are not without the tools to do the job.                        When the
    people enacted the Constitution, they used words with certain
    meanings,    and   those       words    were       understood——and          meant   to    be
    understood——by the public.              Our job when reading and applying
    the Constitution is to learn how its words were understood by
    the public when they were written, what many call the "original
    public meaning."
    ¶113 The first task in this inquiry is, not surprisingly,
    to read the constitutional text taking into account its context
    and structure.         The people who adopted it, after all, can be
    4
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    presumed to have meant what their words conveyed when they wrote
    and adopted them.             Gibbons v. Ogden, 22 U.S. (9 Wheat.) 1, 188
    (1824) ("[T]he people who adopted [the Constitution], must be
    understood to have employed words in their natural sense, and to
    have intended what they have said."); see also Joseph L. Story,
    1 Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States § 451
    (1833) ("In the first place, then, every word employed in the
    constitution       is    to    be    expounded         in    its   plain,        obvious,        and
    common     sense,       unless      the    context          furnishes       some      ground      to
    control, qualify, or enlarge it.").
    ¶114 However,          sometimes          the     meaning       of       the     text      is
    difficult to determine.               This can be especially true with the
    passage    of    time.         When       that    is    the    case,      we     look       to   the
    historical record for clues as to what the public understood the
    provision to mean when it was adopted.                        Serv. Emps. Int'l Union,
    Loc.   1   v.    Vos,     
    2020 WI 67
    ,       ¶28     n.10,     
    393 Wis. 2d 38
    ,          
    946 N.W.2d 35
           ("[W]here        necessary,            helpful     extrinsic           aids      may
    include the practices at the time the constitution was adopted,
    debates     over        adoption      of     a       given     provision,             and     early
    legislative interpretation as evidenced by the first laws passed
    following       the     adoption.").              The       meaning      of     the     text      as
    enlightened by the historical record is no less binding because
    the historical inquiry is still directed toward discovering what
    the words were understood to convey when written.                               See McPherson
    v. Blacker, 
    146 U.S. 1
    , 27 (1892); Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 592
    .                                       In
    other words, the original public meaning controls, even when we
    have to work a little to find it.
    5
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    ¶115 Judicial application of the original public meaning is
    sometimes quite easy.        A President, for example, must be at
    least 35 years old.       U.S. Const. art. II, § 1, cl. 5.             Putting
    that into practice isn't difficult and requires nothing more
    than analyzing and applying the text.             But other provisions,
    especially the more vaguely worded protections in the Bill of
    Rights, often demand some legal framework or test that enables a
    court to apply the law to the facts of a case.             See, e.g., Ezell
    v. City of Chicago, 
    651 F.3d 684
    , 700-04 (7th Cir. 2011); see
    also Bartlett v. Evers, 
    2020 WI 68
    , ¶¶256-59, 
    393 Wis. 2d 172
    ,
    
    945 N.W.2d 685
     (Hagedorn, J., concurring).               Our law is replete
    with these implementing doctrines that give effect to various
    constitutional provisions.3
    ¶116 A proper legal test must implement and effectuate the
    original public meaning of the law.           Bartlett, 
    393 Wis. 2d 172
    ,
    ¶259 (Hagedorn, J., concurring) (explaining that an appropriate
    implementing doctrine is one "that gets us to the heart of the
    constitution's   meaning").       This   is    not   a    license     for   the
    judiciary   to   engage     in   policy-driven       constitutional         line
    drawing.    Rather, an implementing doctrine must be a faithful
    3 For example, the Fourth Amendment protects against
    unreasonable searches and seizures.     This text is put into
    practice with the default warrant requirement and analytical
    categories such as reasonable suspicion, probable cause, and
    exigent circumstances.   E.g., Terry v. Ohio, 
    392 U.S. 1
    , 27
    (1968); Payton v. New York, 
    445 U.S. 573
    , 590 (1980).      Most
    challenges under the equal protection clause are analyzed under
    a rational basis test. E.g., Gregory v. Ashcroft, 
    501 U.S. 452
    ,
    470 (1991). But government discrimination on the basis of race
    is subject to strict scrutiny.   E.g., Loving v. Virginia, 
    388 U.S. 1
    , 11 (1967). And the list could go on.
    6
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    extension of the lines ascertainable in the provision's text and
    history.     Id., ¶¶257-59.
    ¶117 With these principles in mind, we turn to the text and
    history of the Second Amendment, followed by a discussion of its
    proper application.
    B.   The Text
    ¶118 The    Second    Amendment         provides:          "A     well     regulated
    Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State, the
    right   of   the    people    to    keep       and    bear    Arms,          shall    not   be
    infringed."       U.S. Const., amend. II.
    ¶119 As more extensively discussed in Heller, the Second
    Amendment contains both a prefatory and operative clause, the
    latter of which protects the right to keep arms and to bear
    them.    Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 576-78
    .                   Historical evidence makes
    clear that "'[k]eep arms' was simply a common way of referring
    to possessing arms, for militiamen and everyone else."                                 
    Id. at 583
    .     Similarly,     to    "bear"    arms         meant   to    carry,        as    it   is
    understood today.       
    Id. at 584
    .
    ¶120 The    text's    reference         to    "the    right      of     the    people"
    reflects an understanding that this right——like the Founders'
    understanding of many protections in the Bill of Rights——did not
    create a new right unknown to the people.                     
    Id. at 592
    .             Rather,
    the Second Amendment presumes this right already existed and was
    held by the people.          
    Id.
       The Second Amendment therefore called
    upon a right that had an ascertainable scope and substance, and
    gave it protection in our fundamental law.
    7
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    ¶121 By   adopting    the    Second   Amendment,   then,   the    people
    prohibited the federal government from infringing their right to
    keep and bear arms to the same extent the right existed when the
    Second Amendment was ratified in 1791.               As Heller explained,
    "Constitutional rights are enshrined with the scope they were
    understood to have when the people adopted them, whether or not
    future legislatures or (yes) even future judges think that scope
    too broad."      
    Id. at 634-35
    .
    ¶122 The text, however, leaves many questions unanswered.
    It does not readily reveal the nature of the right as it was
    originally understood, and therefore the power of the state to
    regulate matters touching its protections.           Accordingly, we look
    to the historical record for further assistance.
    C.    The History
    ¶123 In 1689 King William and Queen Mary assured Englishmen
    that they would never be disarmed.              Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 593
    .
    Codified in the English Bill of Rights, the protection provided:
    "That the Subjects which are            Protestants, may have Arms for
    their Defence suitable to their Conditions, and as allowed by
    Law."     
    Id.
     (quoting 1 W. & M., ch. 2, § 7, in 3 Eng. Stat. at
    Large 441 (1689)).          The English right to arms "has long been
    understood to be the predecessor to our Second Amendment."                   Id.
    This     forerunner,   and    its    understanding   leading      up    to   the
    adoption of the Second Amendment in 1791, is our starting point.
    ¶124 But our study of the historical record does not end
    there.     As noted above, the Second Amendment does not operate
    8
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    against the states directly; it does so by incorporation via the
    Fourteenth Amendment, which was ratified in 1868.                           Although this
    issue engenders some debate, the prevailing view is that "when
    state- or local-government action is challenged, the focus of
    the original-meaning inquiry is carried forward in time; the
    Second Amendment's scope as a limitation on the States depends
    on how the right was understood when the Fourteenth Amendment
    was ratified."         Ezell, 651 F.3d at 702 (citing McDonald, 
    561 U.S. at 770-77
    ).          Thus, our study of the historical record does
    not conclude with the close of the Founding Era, but rather
    continues through the Reconstruction Era.                      Id. at 702-03.
    1.   A Positive Right
    ¶125 At its core, the historical record demonstrates that
    the Second Amendment protects the longstanding, natural right to
    self-defense.
    ¶126 From the outset, the English Bill of Rights made this
    point   explicit       by    guaranteeing           the       right    to    "have    Arms
    for . . . Defence."             Heller,      
    554 U.S. at 593
    .        Blackstone,
    reflecting on the English right, noted that it protected the
    "natural     right   of     resistance       and    self-preservation"          and   "the
    right   of    having      and    using       arms    for      self-preservation        and
    defence."        
    Id. at 594
       (quoting           1     William       Blackstone,
    Commentaries on the Laws of England 139-40 (1765)).
    ¶127 Across the Atlantic, after King George III tried to
    disarm American colonists, Americans "invoke[ed] their rights as
    Englishmen to keep arms."              
    Id.
           It was in that context that a
    9
    No.      2018AP594-CR.bh
    New York newspaper said in April 1769 that "[i]t is a natural
    right which the people have reserved to themselves, confirmed by
    the Bill of Rights, to keep arms for their own defence."                                             
    Id.
    (quoted source omitted).                      On the American conception of the
    right to keep and bear arms, Blackstone observed it was "without
    any qualification as to their condition or degree, as [was] the
    case    in    the        British          government."            1     William         Blackstone,
    Commentaries on the Laws of England 143 n.40 (St. George Tucker
    ed. 1803).
    ¶128 In          short,       the      central          component          of    the       Second
    Amendment is the longstanding, natural right to self-defense.
    Heller,      
    554 U.S. at 595
    .      And,       as    Heller      noted,       this     right
    extends      "to    the    home,          where     the    need       for    defense       of     self,
    family, and property is most acute."                           
    Id. at 628
    .
    2.     With Limitations
    ¶129 This         core        right,        however,      was        not     impervious       to
    certain types of government regulation.                                Laws restricting the
    right   to    keep        and    bear       arms     were      rare,     but       they    were     not
    unknown.       Those that existed were largely aimed at persons or
    classes of people who might violently take up arms against the
    government         in    rebellion,           or    at     persons          who    posed      a    more
    immediate danger to the public.
    ¶130 An early instance of this was in 1689, the same year
    the    English      Bill        of    Rights        codified       Protestants'            right     to
    possess arms.            At that time, Catholics were deemed a threat to
    rebel against the Protestant crown and "were not permitted to
    10
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    'keep arms in their houses.'"             Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 582
     (quoting
    4 William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England 55
    (1769)).     A 1695 Irish law disarmed Catholics on the same basis.
    7 Will. III ch. 5, § 3 (1695); see also Joseph G.S. Greenlee,
    The Historical Justifications for Prohibiting Dangerous Persons
    from Possessing Arms, 
    20 Wyo. L. Rev. 249
    , 260 (2020).                         These
    class-based dispossessions of those feared to be disloyal to the
    crown, and therefore likely to take up arms against the crown,
    were renewed multiple times and persisted well into the 18th
    century.     Greenlee, supra at 260-61.
    ¶131 The American colonies adopted similar laws disarming
    those they feared would use them to violent ends.                          In 1736,
    Virginia permitted constables to "take away Arms from such who
    ride,   or   go,    offensively     armed,      in   Terror   of     the   People."
    Id. at 262 (quoting George Webb, The Office of Authority of a
    Justice of Peace 92-93 (1736)).               And in 1756, during the French
    and Indian War, Virginia authorized the seizure of arms from
    Catholics out of fear they were sympathetic to the French cause
    and would take up arms against the colonies.                  Id. at 263.         But
    even that law provided an exception "for the defense of his
    house or person."           Id. (quoting 7 William Waller Hening, The
    Statutes     at    Large;   Being   a    Collection     of    All    the   Laws   of
    Virginia 37 (1820)).           Maryland and Pennsylvania also enacted
    similar laws during the French and Indian War.                Id.
    ¶132 The        revolutionary       years   gave   rise   to     related   laws
    targeting those perceived as disloyal to the American cause and
    therefore at risk to take up arms in violence against it.                          In
    11
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    1775, Connecticut prohibited anyone who defamed acts of Congress
    from       keeping    arms     "until          such    time    as       he    could     prove    his
    friendliness to the liberal cause."                           Id. at 268 (quoting G.A.
    Gilbert, The Connecticut Loyalists in 4 Am. Historical Rev. 273,
    282 (1899)).          One year later, the Continental Congress passed
    the Tory Act, which called for disarming those with "erroneous
    opinions,      respecting           the    American      cause."4             Also     that   year,
    Congress recommended that the colonies disarm those "who are
    notoriously disaffected to the cause of America."                                   4 Journals of
    the    Continental       Congress,             1774-1789      205       (1906).        And,     at    a
    minimum,        Massachusetts,              Pennsylvania,               New    Jersey,        North
    Carolina,      and     Virginia          all    heeded       the    call,      disarming      those
    disaffected with or unwilling to take an oath of allegiance to
    the American cause.            Greenlee, supra at 264-65.
    ¶133 Massachusetts' responded likewise to Shays' Rebellion
    a   decade     later.        Beginning           in    August       1786,      armed     bands       of
    western      Bay     Staters    revolted          against      the       federal      government,
    attacking       government          properties         and,        on    February        2,   1787,
    engaging a Massachusetts militia in a military confrontation.
    Id. at       268-69.           In        response       to     the       violent       rebellion,
    Massachusetts          placed        a     variety       of        restrictions         on    those
    involved, including dispossession of their firearms for three
    years.       1 Private and Special Statutes of the Commonwealth of
    Massachusetts from 1780-1805 145-47 (1805).                                   Notably, the law
    provided that arms given up be kept safe "in order that they may
    4 Journals of the Continental Congress, 1775-1789 18-22
    4
    (1906); https://www.loc.gov/resource/bdsdcc.00801/?st=text.
    12
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    be returned to the person or persons who delivered the same, at
    the expiration of the said term of three years."                                     Id. at 147.
    The    response         to     Shays'     Rebellion          epitomized            the    type    of
    dispossession laws that existed during the Founding Era.                                         They
    were    aimed      at     those       considered         dangerous     to      the       government
    during      a   time    of     war,     and    to    a     more    limited         extent,   those
    considered dangerous to society.
    ¶134 Moving            forward     in        time,        the   Reconstruction            Era
    unsurprisingly reflects the prejudices of the age; most arms
    regulations        targeted       slaves       and        freedmen.           At     a    minimum,
    Mississippi, Indiana, Maryland, Kentucky, North Carolina, and
    Delaware adopted such discriminatory laws.                              Greenlee, supra at
    269 n.133.        Before passage of the Fourteenth Amendment, Congress
    condemned these laws as a violation of the right to keep and
    bear arms in the Freedmen's Bureau Act and the Civil Rights Act,
    both of 1866.             McDonald, 
    561 U.S. at 773-75
    .                       Ratification of
    the    Fourteenth             Amendment,         which       was       widely        viewed        as
    constitutionalizing the Civil Rights Act of 1866, affirmed that
    states      could       not     enact     such       discriminatory           laws       depriving
    persons of their constitutional rights.                           
    Id. at 775
    .
    ¶135 A      Kansas       law     adopted       in    1868,      the     same       year   the
    Fourteenth Amendment was ratified, is quite instructive.                                          See
    Vos, 
    393 Wis. 2d 38
    , ¶64 ("Early enactments following adoption
    of    the   constitution          are    appropriately             given     special       weight.
    This   is       because       these    enactments          are    likely      to     reflect     the
    original public meaning of the constitutional text."                                     (citation
    omitted)).        It provides:
    13
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    Any person who is not engaged in any legitimate
    business,   any   person   under   the   influence  of
    intoxicating drink, and any person who has ever borne
    arms against the government of the United States, who
    shall be found within the limits of this state
    carrying on his person a pistol, bowie-knife, dirk, or
    other deadly weapon, shall be subject to arrest upon
    charge of misdemeanor, and upon conviction shall be
    fined a sum not exceeding one hundred dollars, or by
    imprisonment in the county jail not exceeding three
    months, or both, at the discretion of the court.
    2 General Statutes of the State of Kansas 353 (1897).                This law
    prohibits carrying arms:       (1) while "not engaged in legitimate
    business"; (2) while intoxicated; or (3) for any individual "who
    has ever borne arms against" the United States.                The first two
    restrictions    are   temporarily   imposed     in   circumstances      where
    individuals pose a danger of engaging in arms-related violence.
    The third restriction focuses on those who could be considered a
    threat to rebel against the government because they had done so
    in the past.
    ¶136 Notably the Kansas law prohibited only the "carrying,"
    or "bearing," of arms, and not their possession.           See supra ¶15.
    Therefore, it did not prohibit keeping arms in defense of one's
    home.   The law also did not prohibit long guns, so it was not a
    complete prohibition on carrying weapons.            Greenlee, supra at
    271   (citing   Parman   v.   Lemmon,    
    244 P. 232
    ,   233    (Kan.    1926)
    (holding shotguns were not included in a similarly constructed
    statute)).
    ¶137 Although more historical clarity would be welcome, the
    record sufficiently establishes three key propositions regarding
    the original meaning of the Second Amendment.            First, possession
    of firearms for self-defense and protection of one's home as an
    14
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    individual right was widely accepted as the core of the Second
    Amendment's         protections.          And        the    relative    paucity      of     laws
    prohibiting the possession or carrying of arms shows that this
    fundamental         right       was    subject         to     only     narrow       bands     of
    restrictions.           Second, in at least some circumstances, states
    could permissibly restrict the right to keep and bear arms among
    those posing a danger to take up arms against the government and
    those posing a danger of engaging in arms-related violence.5
    Third, states had some authority to protect against dangerous
    individuals by way of class-based arms restrictions, even when
    not everyone in the class posed a clear danger of putting their
    arms to violent use.
    ¶138 Instead         of    this      relevant        historical        evidence,      the
    majority relies in large part on Heller's declaration that its
    opinion       was     not   meant      to     cast         doubt     about    "longstanding
    prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons," which
    were       presumed     lawful.        
    554 U.S. at 626-27
    .         This   statement
    reflects that Heller was limited in its reach, and at least
    suggests not all such laws would be unconstitutional.                                  But it
    also       does   not    mean    all     such    laws       are    constitutional         (that
    question is reserved), nor does it establish that these laws are
    In addition to the examples provided, see United States v.
    5
    Sheldon, in 5 Transactions of the Supreme Court of the Territory
    of Michigan 337, 346 (W. Blume ed. 1940) ("The constitution of
    the United States also grants to the citizen the right to keep
    and bear arms.     But the grant of this privilege cannot be
    construed into the right in him who keeps a gun to destroy his
    neighbor.").
    15
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    embedded      into    the    original    public       meaning    of     the   Second
    Amendment.
    ¶139 To be sure, felon-dispossession laws laws have been on
    the books for some time.             But these laws are of 20th century
    vintage; they do not date back to the 18th or 19th centuries——
    the   relevant       time    periods    when    the     Second    Amendment       was
    ensconced as an individual constitutional right.                      See generally
    C. Kevin Marshall, Why Can't Martha Stewart Have a Gun?, 
    32 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol'y 695
     (2009) (examining the genesis of
    felon-dispossession laws).           In fact, no historical evidence from
    the   time    the     Second    Amendment     was   adopted      or    incorporated
    against      the    states     demonstrates    broadscale       dispossession      of
    those who have committed certain crimes.                  Kanter v. Barr, 
    919 F.3d 437
    , 454 (7th Cir. 2019) (Barrett, J., dissenting) ("[A]t
    least thus far, scholars have not been able to identify any such
    laws.").
    ¶140 The first felon-dispossession laws appeared in 1923,
    when New Hampshire, North Dakota, and California enacted laws
    forbidding         felons    from   possessing        pistols     or     revolvers.
    Greenlee, supra at 273 & n.160.                In 1927, Rhode Island went a
    step further, barring those convicted of "a crime of violence"
    from possessing "any firearm."                Id. at 274 (quoting 
    1927 R.I. Pub. Laws 257
    ).        The federal felon-dispossession law, meanwhile,
    was not enacted until the Federal Firearms Act of 1938, and even
    then it only applied to those who had committed certain violent
    crimes.       
    Id.
     (citing Federal Firearms Act, ch. 850, §§ 1(6),
    2(f), 
    52 Stat. 1250
    , 1250-51 (1938)).                 It was not until a 1961
    16
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    amendment to the Federal Firearms Act that federal law first
    prohibited      all        felons    nationwide                from    possessing        firearms
    regardless of their underlying felony.                               Marshall, supra at 698
    (citing An Act to Strengthen the Federal Firearms Act, Pub. L.
    No.    87-342,        
    75 Stat. 757
           (1961)).                Wisconsin's           felon-
    dispossession law, meanwhile, dates back only to 1981.                                   Ch. 141,
    Laws of 1981.
    ¶141 Thus,         the    proliferation            of    these    laws     in    the    last
    century——far         removed      from    the    time          the    Second     Amendment      was
    enshrined      in     the       Constitution         and       incorporated       against       the
    states——does         not    support       the    notion           that    these        laws    were
    understood      to    be     permissible        under          the    historic        preexisting
    right to keep and bear arms.                  Such laws may be common today, but
    they do not enlighten the original public meaning of the Second
    Amendment.
    ¶142 Moreover, even if such a law had existed when the
    Second and Fourteenth Amendments were ratified, it is unclear
    how much help that would be.                  This is because the definition of
    a "felon" has greatly expanded since the Founding Era.                                          See
    Kanter, 919 F.3d at 458-62 (Barrett, J., dissenting).                                   In 1791,
    felonies      were    a     narrow   subset          of    crimes       generally       involving
    violence, many of which warranted the death penalty.                                          Id. at
    459.     In    contrast,          today   a     person          can    become     a    felon    for
    possessing certain fish illegally, falsifying a boat title, tax
    fraud, trafficking SNAP benefits, second offense dialing 911 for
    a nonexistent emergency, adultery, and perjury, just to name a
    17
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    few.6       This reality seems to undercut any useful comparisons
    between the treatment of felons in 1791 and today.                              But again,
    the historical record reveals no evidence from the Founding or
    Reconstruction Eras of the kind of broad felon-dispossession law
    like the one here.
    ¶143 Some have justified these laws by applying a so-called
    "unvirtuous     citizenry"      theory        to       the    Second    Amendment.        See
    Greenlee, supra at 275-85.              But this lacks any sound basis in
    historical fact, at least insofar as it would apply to today's
    felon-dispossession laws.
    ¶144 This    theory    is     based       on    the     accurate      premise    that
    founding-era        felons    could     be         disqualified         from     exercising
    certain     civic    rights    because        those          rights    belonged    only   to
    virtuous citizens.            See Thomas M. Cooley, A Treatise on the
    Constitutional       Limitations        29     (1st          ed.   1868)      (noting    that
    certain groups including "the idiot, the lunatic, and the felon,
    on   obvious    grounds,"      were    "almost          universally        excluded"     from
    exercising certain civic rights).                       The problem with extending
    this theory to the Second Amendment, however, is that the right
    to keep and bear arms is not a "civic right" as that term was
    understood at the founding.              "Civic rights" were understood to
    be   just    that——rights      related       to     the       civic    space,    i.e.,    the
    community.       They   included       "individual             rights    that    'require[]
    citizens to act in a collective manner for distinctly public
    purposes.'"      Kanter, 919 F.3d at 462 (Barrett, J., dissenting)
    
    Wis. Stat. § 29.971
    (1)(c); § 30.80(3m); § 71.83(2)(b)(1);
    6
    § 946.92(3)(a); § 256.35(10)(a); § 944.16; § 946.31(1).
    18
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    (quoting Saul Cornell, A New Paradigm for the Second Amendment,
    
    22 Law & Hist. Rev. 161
    , 165 (2004) (alteration in original)).
    Put differently, civic rights were those rights that empowered
    individuals to participate in the enterprise of self-governance—
    —for example, the right to vote and to serve on juries.                                
    Id.
    Although these civic rights are "held by individuals," they are
    exercised "as part of the collective enterprise[s]" of self-
    governance or administration of justice.                    
    Id.
    ¶145 "Heller, however, expressly rejects the argument that
    the Second Amendment protects a purely civic right"; it protects
    a personal, individual right.                  
    Id.
     at 463 (citing Heller, 
    554 U.S. at 595
       ("[T]he       Second      Amendment    confer[s]         an   individual
    right to keep and bear arms.")).                  Because the right to keep and
    bear arms is not a civic right, it was not one of the rights
    that could historically be withdrawn from unvirtuous citizens.
    Indeed, there is "no historical evidence on the public meaning
    of    the    right        to    keep     and      bear      arms     indicating       that
    'virtuousness' was a limitation on one's qualification for the
    right——contemporary insistence to the contrary falls somewhere
    between guesswork and ipse dixit."                   Binderup v. Att'y Gen. U.S.,
    
    836 F.3d 336
    ,       372     (3d   Cir.    2016)    (en    banc)     (Hardiman,      J.,
    concurring).           In short, nothing in the text or history of the
    Second Amendment suggests the right to keep and bear arms could
    be    removed     by    the    government      because      the    government      deemed
    certain kinds of people unvirtuous.
    19
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    ¶146 Putting        all     this    together,              the    historical         record
    reveals the following regarding the original public meaning of
    the Second Amendment:
       The Second Amendment protects an individual right to
    keep and bear arms, especially in the defense of one's
    home;
       The    government       nevertheless            was        understood         to    have
    some ability to dispossess those who posed a danger of
    engaging in arms-related violence, often due to the
    risk of rebellion against the government;
       The government had some flexibility to disarm classes
    of people that posed a high risk of engaging in arms-
    related       violence,       even        if    individuals            within       that
    group might themselves not pose that danger; and
       No     evidence         supports          the         notion          that     felon-
    dispossession          laws     of    the      type        at    issue       here    are
    "longstanding"           in      the           sense        that        they        were
    contemplated when the right to keep and bear arms was
    safeguarded in the Constitution.
    ¶147 With this history in mind, we turn to the task of
    determining what legal framework or test best effectuates the
    Second Amendment's original public meaning.
    D.    An Implementing Doctrine
    ¶148 The application of these principles to the case before
    us   requires     some    additional        work.           We    need       some    judicially
    enforceable       legal        framework,        or    implementing               doctrine,       to
    20
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    effectuate             the        constitutional        provision's          original        public
    meaning.          See supra ¶¶11-12.
    ¶149 For better or for worse, both federal courts and this
    court have created and adopted a tiers of scrutiny approach for
    evaluating some types of constitutional claims, especially those
    dealing with fundamental rights.                        Courts typically employ three
    tiers       of        judicial         scrutiny:        rational       basis,       intermediate
    scrutiny, and strict scrutiny——although these tiers sometimes
    work       more       like    a    sliding    scale.         Some   have      criticized       this
    approach, not without merit.7                       But it has the virtue of putting
    the State to its proof when government attempts to regulate in
    areas the Constitution generally places outside the permissible
    bounds of regulation.                     While a better analytical tool may be
    devised,          I    accept      this    general      construct      in    this     case     as   a
    reasonable approach to the tricky problem of applying the text
    of the Constitution to various kinds of regulations touching the
    Second Amendment.
    ¶150 The          United         States     Supreme     Court    has        described    the
    right to keep and bear arms as "among those fundamental rights
    necessary to our system of ordered liberty."                            McDonald, 
    561 U.S. at 778
    .            This       is    consistent      with     its    inclusion         in    the
    Constitution             alongside          other       basic,      pre-existing          rights,
    including the freedoms of speech and religion.                                Generally, when
    the     government                restricts      the    exercise        of     rights        deemed
    E.g., R. George Wright, What if All the Levels of
    7
    Constitutional Scrutiny Were Completely Abandoned?, 
    45 U. Mem. L. Rev. 165
     (2014) (advocating for abolition of the tiers of
    scrutiny).
    21
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    fundamental, courts apply strict scrutiny.                    See, e.g., State v.
    Post, 
    197 Wis. 2d 279
    , 302, 
    541 N.W.2d 115
     (1995).                      To survive a
    challenge, the "statute must further a compelling state interest
    and be narrowly tailored to serve that interest."                           
    Id.
         This
    burden rests on the state, not the challenger, and will rarely
    succeed.
    ¶151 An         honest     evaluation          of   the    historical         record
    regarding     the     Second        Amendment,      however,        suggests      strict
    scrutiny may not be appropriate for all regulations affecting
    the right it protects.          We must match the doctrine to the scope
    of the right, and do so fairly.                  Prohibiting the possession of
    firearms altogether (especially in the home, as with Roundtree),
    cuts on its face right to the core of the Second Amendment
    right.     That said, as best as I can discern from the historical
    evidence    now     available       and    summarized      above,    the    state   was
    nevertheless      understood        to    have   some   authority      to   dispossess
    those who posed a danger of engaging in arms-related violence,
    and to do so in ways that were at least somewhat over- or under-
    inclusive.
    ¶152 As explained above, in the early English tradition of
    protecting    the    right     to    keep    and    bear    arms,    the    government
    dispossessed an entire class of citizens based on the fear they
    would take up arms in violent rebellion against the Protestant
    crown.     Surely, not every member of that class was predisposed
    to violence against the government, yet the class as a whole was
    restricted.       Similarly, during the Founding Era, states broadly
    dispossessed those unwilling to take an oath to support the
    22
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    cause of independence or otherwise sympathetic to British rule.
    Surely not everyone dispossessed under those laws presented a
    danger    to     public    safety.          Even       the   1868    Kansas      law   that
    dispossessed       anyone      "who    has        ever    borne     arms     against    the
    government of the United States" cannot be said to be narrowly
    tailored in the context of the Civil War's aftermath.                               Former
    confederate soldiers presumably                   comprised a not insignificant
    class of people in Kansas, many of whom no longer would have
    posed a significant risk of violence simply by virtue of their
    past war efforts on behalf of the Confederacy.
    ¶153 As a starting point, then, the individual right to
    keep and bear arms, especially for the protection of one's home,
    is a fundamental and individual right that should be treated as
    such.     But where there is a significant risk of arms-related
    violence,      government      retains      some       authority    to      restrict   this
    right in ways that are not narrowly drawn; it may be over- or
    under-inclusive.          Even though restrictions on the individual and
    fundamental right to keep and bear arms should ordinarily be
    subject to the highest judicial scrutiny, where the risk of gun-
    related    violence       is   at     stake,       a     slightly    more      deferential
    standard    is    appropriate         and    in    keeping     with      the   historical
    record.
    ¶154 Overly-generous deference to the government, however,
    would not be appropriate, especially since the text generally
    carves this right out as an impermissible area of government
    interference.       The State must bear the burden in this context to
    show it is acting within constitutional limits, not the other
    23
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    way around.        When it comes to individuals who pose a danger of
    using a firearm to commit violence, however, strict scrutiny
    would seem to demand too much of the government in ways that do
    not capture the historical understanding of the right.                        A more
    appropriate analysis in this context is therefore a heightened
    scrutiny that still puts the government to its proof.                      Among the
    tools available, intermediate scrutiny best fits the bill.8
    ¶155 This        approach      has    parallels      in    other    areas    of
    constitutional         law.    The    Supreme      Court   applies     intermediate
    scrutiny in some other circumstances where fundamental rights
    are implicated.          In the First Amendment context, for example,
    the Court analyzes content-based restrictions on speech under
    strict scrutiny, but it applies a form of intermediate scrutiny
    to   time,    place,      or   manner      regulations.         Compare    Texas   v.
    Johnson, 
    491 U.S. 397
    , 412 (1989) (applying "the most exacting
    scrutiny"    to    a    flag-burning       statute)      with   United    States   v.
    O'Brien,     
    391 U.S. 367
    ,     376-77        (1968)   (applying     intermediate
    scrutiny to uphold a defendant's conviction for burning a draft
    8I endorse the majority of Justice Rebecca Bradley's
    dissent. However, I believe something less than strict scrutiny
    is more in keeping with the historical record——and therefore the
    original public meaning——for the type of restriction here.     I
    also agree with the majority that our decision in Mayo v.
    Wisconsin Injured Patients and Families Compensation Fund, 
    2018 WI 78
    , 
    383 Wis. 2d 1
    , 
    914 N.W.2d 678
    , is inapplicable. Whatever
    analytical framework this court applies to equal protection
    cases under the Wisconsin Constitution is not, in my view,
    relevant to the framework we should employ to a claim under the
    Second Amendment to the federal Constitution.       The original
    public meaning inquiry should dictate the appropriate legal
    test, regardless of the tests this court has employed in
    analyzing cases under different constitutional provisions.
    24
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    card); McCullen v. Coakley, 
    573 U.S. 464
    , 486 (2014) (applying
    intermediate       scrutiny       to    strike          down    a     statute      establishing
    "buffer zones" around facilities where abortions are performed).
    ¶156 Intermediate scrutiny places the burden on the State
    to show that the law at issue advances an important governmental
    interest     and     is        substantially            related        to     that       interest.
    Gerhardt     v.    Estate       of     Moore,          
    150 Wis. 2d 563
    ,         570-71,        
    441 N.W.2d 734
          (1989).          Even    when          the    governmental         interest       is
    important, a law survives intermediate scrutiny only if it "does
    not    burden      substantially              more       [protected           activity]          than
    necessary to further those interests."                          Turner Broad. Sys., Inc.
    v.    FCC,   
    520 U.S. 180
    ,        189      (1997).           As    now-Justice          Barrett
    explained     in    her     dissent          in    a    case     challenging            this   same
    Wisconsin law, the fit between the means and the ends must be a
    close one.         Kanter 919 F.3d at 465 (Barrett, J., dissenting)
    ("'[A]   very      strong      public-interest               justification         and    a    close
    means-ends      fit'      is    required          before       [the    defendant]          may    be
    constitutionally          subject       to    the       United       States       and    Wisconsin
    dispossession statutes.").
    ¶157 It's     worth       emphasizing            again       that    the    burden      when
    applying intermediate scrutiny is on the State to prove that the
    restriction advances an important interest and is substantially
    related to that interest.                State v. Baron, 
    2009 WI 58
    , ¶14, 
    318 Wis. 2d 60
    , 
    769 N.W.2d 34
    .                    Every federal circuit to consider
    this matter agrees.             See, e.g., Binderup, 836 F.3d at 353; Tyler
    v. Hillsdale Cnty. Sherriff's Dept., 
    837 F.3d 678
    , 693 (6th Cir.
    2016); Heller v. District of Columbia, 
    670 F.3d 1244
    , 1258 (D.C.
    25
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    Cir.   2011).        As     one    court    put     it,     "Strict         and   intermediate
    scrutiny      (which        we     collectively        refer          to     as    'heightened
    scrutiny'     to     distinguish         them       from    the       far    less      demanding
    rational-basis        review)       in      effect     set       up    a     presumption      of
    invalidity that the defendant must rebut."                             Hassan v. City of
    New York, 
    804 F.3d 277
    , 299 (3d Cir. 2015).
    ¶158 To summarize, where the government purports to act in
    ways   the    people        have    made     clear     in    their          constitution      are
    outside the power granted, it is not the citizen who must show
    the    government          has     acted       unconstitutionally;                it    is    the
    government that must demonstrate it has authority to do what it
    wishes.      The Constitution reflects a presumption that government
    action in that zone is unlawful unless proven otherwise.                                      The
    historic     right     to    keep     and    bear     arms       is    an     individual      and
    fundamental right.           But the government has broader authority to
    restrict the right of those who would use arms for gun-related
    violence.          Intermediate            scrutiny——requiring                a     substantial
    connection to the important governmental interest——appears to
    best   capture       and     secure      the    right       in    accordance           with   its
    original public meaning where government acts to protect against
    those who pose a danger of engaging in gun-related violence.
    26
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    II.       APPLICATION
    ¶159 Roundtree            challenges               the         constitutionality                of
    Wisconsin's        felon-dispossession                  law     as     applied           to     him.9
    Wisconsin       Stat.   § 941.29(1m)(a)                 provides:           "Any     person      who
    possesses a firearm is guilty of a Class G felony if any of the
    following       applies:      (a)     The          person     has    been    convicted          of    a
    felony in this state."              "In this context, 'possess' . . . simply
    'means that the defendant knowingly had actual physical control
    of   a   firearm.'"           State           v.    Black,      
    2001 WI 31
    ,       ¶19,    
    242 Wis. 2d 126
    , 
    624 N.W.2d 363
    .                       Thus, for anyone convicted of a
    felony, § 941.29(1m)(a) operates as a lifetime ban on possessing
    firearms    for    self-defense,              hunting,        or     any    other    ordinarily
    lawful purpose.
    ¶160 Roundtree brings two types of as-applied challenges.
    First,     he    argues      that    the           State      may    not     constitutionally
    dispossess       him    because       the          State      has     not    shown        that       he
    personally poses a danger of engaging in gun-related violence.
    To support this challenge, Roundtree notes that his underlying
    felony, besides being nonviolent, occurred more than ten years
    ago, and that nothing he has done since suggests he poses any
    heightened       risk   of   using        a    gun      violently.           But    as    we     have
    discussed, the historical record suggests states may, consistent
    9 As   we    have explained  before,   "Challenges  to  the
    constitutionality of a statute are generally defined in two
    manners:    as-applied and facial."    Vos, 
    393 Wis. 2d 38
    , ¶37.
    Where "[a]s-applied challenges address a specific application of
    the statute against the challenging party," a facial challenge
    argues    a    statute  "operates   unconstitutionally  in   all
    applications." Id., ¶¶37-38.
    27
    No.     2018AP594-CR.bh
    with the right secured by the Second Amendment, dispossess some
    people on a somewhat overbroad class-wide basis.                                  This is so
    even if some individual members of the class demonstrate their
    personal characteristics are inconsistent with a propensity for
    violence.      Moreover,       the   challenged             law   criminalizes           firearm
    possession for committing a felony, not for any of Roundtree's
    personal characteristics or other actions.                         In other words, the
    State    has   charged     Roundtree            with        the   crime      of    illegally
    possessing     a     firearm    on       one        basis    only——his       prior       felony
    conviction.         Therefore,       a    challenge          focused      on      Roundtree's
    personal risk of danger is off the mark.
    ¶161 Roundtree also argues the State may not dispossess him
    simply   for       belonging    to       either       the     class    of      people      that
    committed any felony or the class of people that committed the
    same felony as him.
    ¶162 It is indisputable that public safety is a compelling
    governmental interest.          See State v. Cole, 
    2003 WI 112
    , ¶23, 
    264 Wis. 2d 520
    ,       
    665 N.W.2d 328
    .                This    interest      is      also    well-
    illustrated in the history of the Second Amendment.                                Wisconsin
    Stat. § 941.29(1m)(a) therefore advances an important government
    objective.
    ¶163 Thus, we turn to the second prong of the intermediate
    scrutiny analysis:        whether a law that dispossesses all felons
    is   substantially       related         to     the        government's        interest      in
    preventing     gun-related       violence.                  And   again,        it's      worth
    repeating that the State bears the burden to show a close and
    28
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    substantial connection exists.                      The State tries to meet its
    burden by pointing us to two studies.10
    ¶164 The study most heavily relied on by the State is a
    2016 study on recidivism prepared by the Wisconsin Department of
    Corrections.        See Joseph R. Tatar II & Megan Jones, Recidivism
    After     Release     from    Prison,          Wisconsin      Dep't    of    Corrections
    (August 2016) (hereinafter "DOC Study").                       In its analysis, that
    study     grouped    all     offenses      into       four    categories:            violent
    offenses,    property        offenses,         drug   offenses,     and     public     order
    offenses.     Id. at 14.           Relevant here, the public order offense
    category included failure to pay child support (120 days+) in
    addition     to     crimes    like       operating      while      intoxicated,        bail
    jumping, and operating a vehicle to elude an officer.                            Id.     The
    State primarily relies on the study's conclusion that for those
    who committed a prior public order offense, 21.4 percent                                  of
    recidivists in that category went on to commit a violent offense
    within    three     years.         The    remaining         78.6   percent      of   crimes
    committed     within       three       years    by    recidivists       whose    original
    incarceration       was    for     a   public       order    offense    committed       non-
    violent offenses (either a drug offense, property offense, or
    another public order offense).                 Id.
    10The majority, in a block quote to the majority opinion in
    Kanter v. Barr, 
    919 F.3d 437
    , 449 (7th Cir. 2019), notes two
    additional studies that are not discussed by the State in its
    briefing. Majority op., ¶50. Because it is the State's burden
    to satisfy the substantial relationship prong of intermediate
    scrutiny, its failure to discuss these studies should preclude
    the majority's consideration of them.     This court should not
    attempt to prove the State's case for it.
    29
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    ¶165 The      State      erroneously       cites   this         study   for     a
    proposition       it    most     certainly       does    not     support.            It
    characterizes the DOC Study as concluding that 21.4 percent of
    all those released after committing a public order offense went
    on to commit a violent offense.                  That's simply not what the
    study says, and it is an egregious error in light of its almost
    singular prominence in the State's effort to prove the requisite
    connection.        This 21.4 percent is not the percentage of all
    public    order    offenders     who,    after    release,     committed      violent
    crimes.     Rather, it considers only those who committed another
    crime after committing a public order offense, and conveys the
    percentage    of       those   public     order    offense      recidivists         who
    committed a violent crime.              In other words, this 21.4 percent
    figure has nothing to do with, and makes no reference to, those
    who never recidivate after committing a public order offense.
    It   should   be    obvious,     then,    that    this   statistic        offers     no
    assistance in establishing the relationship between past crime
    and a person's risk to commit gun-related violent crime in the
    future, which is the core inquiry of the intermediate scrutiny
    analysis.
    ¶166 The second study offered by the State surveys "5,923
    authorized purchasers of handguns in California in 1977," 3,128
    of whom had at least one prior misdemeanor conviction at the
    time of purchase.         Garen J. Wintemute et al., Prior Misdemeanor
    Convictions as a Risk Factor for Later Violent and Firearm-
    Related     Criminal      Activity      Among     Authorized      Purchasers         of
    Handguns, 280 J. Am. Med. Ass'n 2083, 2083 (1998) (hereinafter
    30
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    "Wintemute         Study").            Specifically,            the    State    points        to    that
    study's conclusion that "even handgun purchasers with only 1
    prior       misdemeanor          conviction          and    no       convictions       or    offenses
    involving firearms or violence were nearly 5 times as likely as
    those with no prior criminal history to be charged with new
    offenses involving firearms or violence."                                     
    Id.
          Consider me
    unsurprised             that    people        with    criminal         records        who    purchase
    handguns          are    more        likely    to    commit      future       crime        than    those
    without       a     criminal           record.            But    this     correlation             hardly
    demonstrates the close and substantial relationship required to
    justify this law.                While those with a prior criminal record are
    surely more likely to commit future crime, the vast majority of
    people       in    the     study       who    had    prior       criminal      records        did    not
    commit a new violent offense.                          And the State must demonstrate
    that        dispossessing             the     entire        class      that     it     chose        will
    substantially further the State's efforts to remediate the risk
    of   gun-related           violence.11               This    study      falls        far    short     of
    demonstrating             why    those        convicted         of    illegal        possession       of
    certain fish, tax fraud, or failure to pay child support should
    be     dispossessed             in     the    interest          of    preventing       gun-related
    violent crime.
    ¶167 The          State's        correlation-centric             reasoning——that             
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m)(a) substantially furthers the fight against
    gun-related violence simply by virtue of a correlation between
    past crime of any sort and future violent crime——does not meet
    Importantly, the Wintemute Study does not actually
    11
    analyze felons as a class because generally, felons will not be
    authorized handgun purchasers.
    31
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    the mark.         Playing this logic out further, suppose those who
    previously        declared   bankruptcy      are    modestly     more     likely    to
    commit violent crime in the future?12              Or those who do not have a
    bachelor's degree by the time they are 25?13                  How about those who
    were born out of wedlock,14 or who fall below the poverty line?15
    Taking      the   State's    argument   on   its    face,     dispossession       laws
    barring      these   classes    of   persons    (which      impact    not   a    small
    amount of the population) would survive as long as the State
    could prove that these features are correlated with an increased
    risk    of    committing     violent    crime      with   a    firearm.         Modest
    correlation, however, is simply not enough.                    And at best, that
    is all the State has here.
    Gercoline van Beek, Vivienne de Vogel & Dike van de
    12
    Mheen, The Relationship Between Debt and Crime:   A Systematic
    and Scoping Review, European J. of Probation, Oct. 2020, at 1
    (showing "a strong association between debt and crime whereby
    debt is a risk factor for crime").
    Lance Lochner & Enrico Moretti, The Effect of Education
    13
    on Crime:    Evidence from Prison Inmates, Arrests, and Self-
    Reports, 94 The Am. Econ. Rev. 155, 156-57 (2004) ("Instrumental
    variable estimates reveal a significant relationship between
    education and incarceration . . . .").
    Todd D. Kendall & Robert Tamura, Unmarried Fertility,
    14
    Crime, and Social Stigma, 
    53 J.L. & Econ. 185
    , 213 (2010) ("[A]n
    increase of 10 nonmarital births per 1,000 live births is
    associated with an increase in future murder and property crime
    rates between 2.4 and 4 percent.").
    U.S. Dep't of Justice, NCJ 248384, Household Poverty and
    15
    Nonfatal Violent Victimization, 2008-2012, 1 (2014) ("Persons in
    poor households had a higher rate of violence involving a
    firearm (3.5 per 1,000) compared to persons above the FPL (0.8-
    2.5 per 1,000).").
    32
    No.    2018AP594-CR.bh
    ¶168 Including all felonies in 
    Wis. Stat. § 941.29
    (1m)(a)'s
    reach,    no    matter       how    violent        and    no       matter    how    serious,    is
    "wildly overinclusive."                 Kanter, 919 F.3d at 466 (Barrett, J.,
    dissenting).          It is an extraordinarily broad class that lacks a
    substantial relationship to the harm it seeks to remedy.                                       Id.
    The fit between means and ends must be close——not perfect, but
    close.         The     State's          evidence         is    far        from     showing    that
    dispossessing all felons forever bears a close or substantial
    relationship to remediating the danger of gun-related violence.
    ¶169 If the class of all felons is too broad, perhaps the
    State could nonetheless show that criminalizing possession of
    firearms       based    on    the       particular        underlying         felony      survives
    constitutional scrutiny.                But the State does not even purport to
    argue    that    those       who    have      failed          to    pay     child    support    or
    committed other analogous crimes pose any risk of committing
    gun-related       violence         as     a       consequence        of     their     underlying
    felony, nor do its studies support that conclusion.                                    The State
    therefore fails to meet its burden of proof here as well.
    ¶170 The important goal of protecting against gun-related
    violence does not seem to be furthered by dispossessing those
    who have not committed a violent act with a gun, and indeed have
    not committed a violent act at all.                            The State does not meet
    this challenge head on; it has not met its burden to prove a
    close and substantial relationship between the means and ends of
    the     prohibition.           Accordingly,              Roundtree's             conviction    for
    possession       of    a     firearm,         a     criminal        prohibition         triggered
    33
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    because he was convicted of failure to pay child support for 120
    days, violates the Second Amendment and is unconstitutional.
    III.   CONCLUSION
    ¶171 We are bound to interpret and apply the Constitution
    as written.        A careful study of the history surrounding the
    right to keep and bear arms as protected by the Second Amendment
    demonstrates that while the right to keep arms in the home for
    self-defense is within the core of the right, some class-based
    restrictions on firearm possession are permissible to protect
    against the danger of gun-related violence.            Felon-dispossession
    laws may be permissible under this historical protection, but
    only    where     the   State    shows    the   restriction    substantially
    advances the State's interest in protecting against gun-related
    violence.       Here, however, the State did not carry its burden to
    show that Wisconsin's dispossession law satisfies this standard
    as applied to Roundtree.          Therefore, his conviction violates the
    Second Amendment.       I respectfully dissent.
    34
    No.   2018AP594-CR.bh
    1